Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 17

1

Horizons of care: from future imaginaries to responsible research and innovation


Christopher GROVESa,1 a ESRC Centre for the Economic and Social Aspects of Genomics (Cesagen), Cardiff University, 10 Museum Place, Cardiff, United Kingdom CF10 3BG
Abstract. Responsible Research and Innovation (RRI) has emerged as a response to the problem of the unintended consequences of new technologies, one with an agenda shaped by concerns about the impact of technological innovation on issues of procedural and substantive justice. The role of future imaginaries, manifest in texts and images, in shaping innovation and framing what counts as legitimate topics for social debate on technologies has been documented by science and technology studies (STS) scholars, but has not yet been discussed widely in the literature on RRI. In this paper, I argue that the critique of future imaginaries is important for the procedural and substantive justice concerns of RRI, but that missing from the STS literature on imaginaries is an adequate treatment of their nonrepresentational dimensions, including practice and desire, and the role these play in constructing particular future horizons, styles of living the future in the present that are constitutive of subjectivity. I suggest that, without an adequate treatment of these aspects, RRI perspectives will face difficulties in understanding the nature and role of organized irresponsibility within innovation, before proposing that a political imaginary of care offers a possible route to take in thinking about the ethical and political aspects of innovation that permits these aspects to be adequately addressed. Keywords. Care, futures, future imaginaries, responsible research and innovation, uncertainty.

1. Introduction

Responsible innovation or responsible research and innovation (RRI) (Owen et al., 2012) is a concept that has emerged in response to a slow-burning crisis of legitimacy, in which emerging technologies (such as biotechnologies, nanotechnologies and neurotechnologies, for example) are often represented as major drivers. Critical commentators have found in such technologies the threat of disruptive innovation, framing this threat in ethical terms as heralding the erosion of culturally constitutive values (de St. Cameron, 2006) or in political terms as creating the real prospect of an irreversible and anti-democratic redistribution of power (Sparrow, 2008). RRI aims to symbolically and practically re-integrate innovation within political and civil society, by opening it up to democratic questioning and oversight, and by introducing values other than profit and efficiency into decisions about what pathways innovation should follow. At the level of codified norms, RRI may mean adopting codes of conduct or adjusting regulatory statutes to render them adaptive and anticipatory in the face of uncertainty. It also may require the creation and promulgation of new practices that recognize the potential of technological novelty for producing unintended consequences, including the intensification of social problems like alienation or inequality as well as more traditional concerns, such as environmental or health risks. Instead of being characterized by organized irresponsibility (Beck, 1995), innovation under RRI is to be pressed into a virtuous mold, and made to produce the right impacts (Von Schomberg, 2011). RRI thus rests on two basic ideas: that innovation can help make a better world by contributing to substantive ethico-political goals like social justice or the common good, and also
1 Corresponding Author. Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

2 that innovation processes have a procedural justice dimension, insofar as they may trigger processes of social change over which stakeholders (including the public) should have some form of oversight and influence. An important, though often overlooked (there are exceptions, such as Grin and Grunwald (2000)) aspect of innovation in relation to procedural justice is the role played by imaginaries in shaping technological evolution, from basic research to commercialization. Texts and imagery associated with innovation are often interwoven with the imaginative construction of alternative futures. In public rhetoric around innovation, evocations of the future are frequently used in ways that mirror genre conventions of science fiction, as Jose Lopez has noted in relation to nanoscience and nanotechnology. Lopez points out there is a key difference here, however: in science fiction the extrapolated future is a stepping-stone for critical reflection, whereas in rhetoric around innovation, it is the endpoint of the reflection (Lopez, 2004). The power of such future-oriented imagery and narrative is considerable, as has been documented by the sociology of expectations. It can create future imaginaries (Fujimura, 2003) that influence the course of innovation by facilitating the formation of networks, transfer of resources, and dissemination of knowledge (Brown and Michael, 2003), and more broadly, by shaping collective understandings of what kinds of futures are possible, and thus of what kinds of agency are feasible in the present. Their significance for the theme of RRI is therefore considerable (Simakova and Coenen, 2013). For example, the influence of imaginaries of technological determinism has been traced in examples of path dependency in technological development (Mody, 2006; Sparrow, 2007). Promissory rhetoric has also been interpreted as either misdirecting ethical discussions towards highly speculative debates about potential futures that may never happen (Nordmann, 2007), or as encouraging the postponement of ethical debates (Hanson, 2011). As a consequence, technological future imaginaries may help to prevent scrutiny of assumptions about innovation pathways and to exclude alternative visions of the future form discussion, thus making progress on the procedural elements of RRI more difficult. The kinds of critique undertaken by Lopez and others might, therefore, be thought to be an essential contribution to RRI. However, imaginaries in the sense examined by the sociology of expectations are typically interpreted as what Emilio Mordini calls a 'symbolic template' 'that generates a sense of identity and inclusiveness' (Mordini, 2007, p. 30). Imaginaries in this sense are seen as forms of representation that encourage individuals and groups to identify symbolically and imaginatively with them. Critiques of imaginaries generally point to contradictions and inconsistencies within them (e.g. Lopez, 2004). However, such an approach fails to touch on the ways in which identification with particular visions is produced through other, non-representational practices that underlie and influence sensemaking through image or text such as those involved in the production and reproduction of economic relationships, in the formation of desire, and in shaping other elements that, in turn, produce and sustain specific forms of life and their characteristic matters of concern. In this essay, I argue that the procedural dimension of RRI will have to deal, not only with imaginaries and the symbolic dimensions of innovation more widely, but also with these non-representational conditions of their production and reproduction. These constitute key yet overlooked material conditions that shape the values with which innovators and consumers of innovation identify. In the next section, I explore the concept of RRI itself, and relate its emergence to contradictions
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

3 within the imaginaries of modernist ethical and social thought, generated by the relationship between these modernist patterns of thought and natural science. Following this, I examine some of the material conditions under which this contradiction is produced and reproduced against the background of what I term the future horizon of practice and representation. I then explore the antagonistic structure of these conditions, before concluding with a brief sketch of a different future horizon, through which a different relationship with technology and innovation may be imagined, one in which these antagonisms are acknowledged and overcome.
2. Responsible

research and innovation and the contradictions of consequentialism

RRI has taken on currency in discussions around technology policy for a variety of reasons (Owen et al., 2012). Originating within discussions of themes such as that of the knowledge society and the changing nature of the contract between scientific research and wider society (Guston 2006), the concept has since been much discussed in relation to emerging technologies such as nanotechnology and synthetic biology. Debates over the necessity of precaution as a regulatory approach (Mayer and Stirling 2002) for new technologies have emerged over the last three decades in response to specific governance dilemmas that derive from the scarcity of information regarding the potential safety or environmental hazards of emerging technologies (Collingridge 1980). At the same time, participants in these debates have also interpreted precaution as providing opportunities to ask questions about the social impact of technologies that extend more widely than questions of risks versus benefits (Wynne 1996). In particular, precaution has been seen as a theme under which debates over the social and democratic control of technology may be re-activated (Tallacchini 2004). RRI views this opportunity as one for enhancing the social value of new technologies through deliberative public scrutiny of innovation processes, which operates upstream in innovation processes (Wilsdon and Willis 2004), and aims to ensure that innovation produces the right impacts (Von Schomberg, 2011). Beyond this, however, RRI has specified one of its substantive and procedural goals as responsiveness (Macnaghten and Owen, 2011; Von Schomberg, 2011). Wider and earlier engagement is intended to scrutinize the priorities and values that explicitly or implicitly guide innovation activities, and which their enactors (Garud and Ahlstrom, 1997) may take as given and as more or less universally shared. It is hoped that, through engagement, such implicit priorities and values may be made more explicit and opened up to questioning. It is further hoped that enactors (individuals and institutions) will therefore become actively responsive to the other voices admitted into the arenas of expectations in which selection pressures are exerted on new technologies (Bakker et al., 2011). It is intended that one of the central outcomes of responsiveness should be a procedural democratization of innovation, as well as a new substantive focus for innovation on achieving societallyvalued right impacts. However, the demand for these changes which implicitly recognizes that social attitudes toward innovation itself are (as they have perhaps always been) ambivalent may appear to have something of the quality Hegel attributed to the demands of morality in general, which held to possess a reality that only ought to be, and which stubbornly is not (Hegel, 1993: 133-36). If innovation is, as Beck (1995)
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

4 puts it, organised irresponsibility, receiving all its vigor from dynamics of profi t-led creative destruction and the externalization or socialization of risks, then one might entertain a suspicion that RRI may represent a merely verbal solution to a real and persistent contradiction or antagonism. Whereas once the social ought was the recognition of legal or social rights, in what Beck has called risk societies this ought may have been replaced, in the face of reflexive uncertainties created by innovation, by that of being responsible. If RRI is to mean something beyond a mere ought, an impotent verbal solution, then it is necessary to understand the contradictions and antagonisms to which it is a response, which is our task in this chapter.2 Innovation in the sense of creating technological artefacts and associated capabilities with the primary goal of solving instrumental (how to) tasks brings the idea of responsibility to the foreground of ethical debates in a way that was not the case in pre-modern societies (Mitcham, 1994: 107). This is because it is inherently a future-creating activity: by bringing something new into the world, it can change the world itself. Yet the habits of mind that tend to govern how we think about the ethical significance of innovation are largely focused on the past, present and near future and on situations where relationships between proximate individuals are involved rather than relationships between people distant from us in space and/or time (Jonas 1984). Despite this, the increasing economic and cultural importance of technological innovation during the early modern period was itself accompanied by changes in ideas regarding moral conduct, which gave new weight to the future in moral discourse. Modernity, as many sociologists from Weber and Durkheim through to Zygmunt Bauman have argued, involves both social differentiation and reintegration: new divisions of labour and the multiplication of social roles, but also attempts to formulate new overarching moral principles. The purpose of these principles was to fill the gap left by the vanishing moral certainties of medieval Europe, a worldview called by J. B. Schneewind (1984) the divine corporation with God at the head as its CEO, and others occupying fixed offices within this edifice. In the medieval moral frame, what it meant to act responsibly was therefore fixed with regard to the immemorial past, and specifically, to rules that carried the deontological authority of religious revelation. A fixed set of virtues, enshrined in religious traditions and in the ethics of figures like Aquinas, were seen as necessary to fit any individual to the station they were born to occupy in life. But the changes which early modernity brought with it in the 16th and 17th centuries began to loosen these traditional certainties and the bonds they cemented. The rise of the scientific method shaped an increasingly future-oriented world, one that could be improved, and that was structured by an emerging qualitative change in the relationship to historical time itself, a relationship only fully realized after 1870 in the idea of modernity as neue Zeit, a period better than what has gone before (Koselleck, 1985: 295) and distinguished from old time (Rabinow, 2009: 61). It is in the second half of the 17th century that the concepts of antiquity, middle ages and modernity (where one must aim to live) became established for the entirety of historical time (Koselleck, 1985: 17). Such a condition, Peter Osborne suggests, is characterized both by an openness to an indeterminate future and a diminution of the present to the status of a vanishing point, a gap between past and future which constitutes time itself (Osborne, 1992: 31). The deontological morality of the divine corporation is overwritten by emergent consequentialist habits of mind, tied to what Max Weber described as Zweckrationalitt enshrined as an administrative form of
2

The rest of this section summarizes an argument first made in Grinbaum and Groves (2013) Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

5 reason. The mathematics and natural science of the 17th century contributed to this development by helping to redefine the very concept of futurity, constituting it as a domain of finite possibilities, arranged according to their greater or lesser probability, a territory of greater or lesser foreseeable evils rather than the prospect of a single, final division made by deontological religious ethics between Good and Evil through the establishment of a single principle of behavior, confirmed by the Bible and the promise of the Last Judgement (Koselleck, 1985, p. 18). The work of Jacob Bernouilli was a major step forward here in determining how to decide whether a given set of observational data could be a representative basis for estimating probabilities (Bernstein, 1996: 117-19). These shifts in culturally-prevalent understandings of time and futurity were accompanied by the emergence of a new, more minimal concept of virtue. As Henry S. Richardson has pointed out (Richardson, 1999), the ideal moral agent of this emerging consequentialist age was Jeremy Bentham's utilitarian subject as well as Webers diligent Protestant, a subject who strives to assess, with precision, the contribution each act she performs makes to the aggregate happiness of society. Foresight clear vision directed into the geometric space of the probable future (Romanyshyn, 1989) became the badge of the responsible agent. Scientific precision is offered as the benchmark of good foresight, which in turn is the condition of progress, providing both a tool for realizing it and a warrant for pursuing it. Foresight based on predictive techniques is thus the primary tool and virtue of the consequentialist subject. Yet no matter how much past data is available to build risk predictions upon, the perspective of a perfect utilitarian agent is ultimately impossible to adopt. To entirely overcome uncertainty would require foresight capable of covering the entire span of the consequences of any act. The utilitarian philosopher J. J. C. Smart proposed that, in most circumstances, the utilitarian can assume that the remote effects of his actions tend rapidly to zero, like the ripples on a pond after a stone has been thrown into it (Smart and Williams, 1973: 64). Sometimes this will not be so, however. The consequentialist moral agent thus has both first and second order responsibilities. Responsible for assessing the consequences of an action, the agent is also responsible for deciding when s/he has finished performing due diligence, and can make up his/her mind to act. Sometimes, as Smart notes, in situations that are relatively routine, this second order responsibility is undemanding. With respect to other activities, however, the opposite is true and technological innovation, due to the unwanted surprises that may accompany it, is one such. Data, by itself, is not enough to determine when one has performed ones second-order responsibility adequately. Certain evaluative commitments are needed to interpret the data, and therefore cannot themselves be drawn from data. These are required in order to determine which potential consequences of an action should be treated as salient or not, how far into the future ones foresight should be extended, and how any expected consequences should be weighted depending on their distance from the present. As well as a consequentialist decision framework, then, decision horizons (Hansson, 1996) need to be settled on, along with a positive or negative rate of discounting future outcomes (Feldstein, 1964). But in addition, the agent needs to know what are reasonable standards of prediction? (MacIntyre, 1983). The reasonable standard for such knowledge in modernity is generally provided by scientific knowledge. This intimate connection between science and ethics has, however, proven problematic.
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

6 As Ian Hacking (1986) has pointed out, the potential of advanced technologies for creating unforeseen 'interference effects' is written into the way they are embedded within contemporary societies. Their pervasiveness and proximity to each other, along with the intimacy with which they interact with natural processes (Latour, 2008), creates the likelihood of nasty surprises. Yet, as Luigi Pellizzoni (2004) has observed, according to the legal principle of reasonable foreseeability, an agent can be absolved of liability even if later found to be causally responsible for creating harm, so long as the agent was inescapably ignorant of the potential consequences of his or her actions at the time of acting. If the 'state of the art' in science could not have predicted certain consequences at the time of acting, then how can someone be judged responsible for producing them? Yet at the same time, this condition of ignorance is, on Hacking's account, still a form of culpable ignorance: we are no longer ignorant that, thanks to living in technological societies where phenomena like PCB pollution, asbestosrelated illnesses and BSE are widespread, we can expect the unexpected. Nonetheless, how can we take responsibility for avoiding specific consequences that, even if we suspect they may be in wait, we cannot foresee? The 'state of the art' of scientific knowledge is rooted in the past - it is, if you like, a picture of the world as it has existed up until the point where it makes new innovations possible. From this picture, we can extrapolate what the world may be like in the future. But once scientific knowledge has been translated into technology and innovation actual transformative interventions in the world the world as it has hitherto been framed within the lens of science may no longer exist. New technologies can help to change nature and society so radically that the world for which established regulations (and even moral codes) were created may no longer exist. Our reliance on science prompts us to imagine the future as 'stationary' (Orlan, 2010). We could say that, in the wake of innovation, the future facing us is no longer what it used to be. This is not just a problem of knowledge. Its root is buried within what Hannah Arendt has identified as an inescapable feature of human finitude. Finitude, the foundation of Schneewind's divine corporation, is re-encountered by modernity just at the moment when its achievements encourage us to entertain the prospect of infinite progress. In fact, it is precisely the transformative power of technology and scientific knowledge that, for Arendt, underlines this rediscovery of our finitude. She pointed out that the human condition of finitude is not the same as a fixed, immutable human nature. Rather, it is an inherent aspect of human beings power to remake their world and themselves: what human beings create through subjective effort takes on an objective form that then, in turn, conditions both their existence and their subsequent creative activity (Arendt, 1998: 9-10), leading to unanticipated consequences. So we have now exposed the tension within modern ethical culture to which RRI desires to respond. The social use of science promises the transformation of the future, but in transforming it, depends on foresight that itself relies on hindsight, hindsight that can quickly become out of date thanks to the novelty introduced into the world through the appliance of science. RRI counterposes to the modernist reliance on scientific foresight and clear vision a multiperspectival culture of caution and transparency. It also recognizes, however, that the imperative to innovate is driven by structural, political economic features of contemporary society. The need to extract profit from investment in new technologies is seen as the key driver behind the selection of particular technological options. RRI aims to introduce alongside this driver countervailing social values elicited through deliberative engagement in an expanded public sphere, so that innovation is not only procedurally restrained from
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

7 proceeding along unacceptable pathways, but directed towards priorities that are subject to a wider consensus implying that the uncertainties that will still surround innovation may be more acceptable if goals are chosen on a more transparent, more consensual basis. Creating around technology a more discursively-open public sphere is seen as the cure for the ethical tensions of modernity. In the next section, I examine some aspects of a deeper antagonism at the heart of innovation, one that helps to creates the ethical contradiction I have explored above. I then show that an understanding of this antagonism can help expose some current limitations of the RRI agenda. In the Conclusion, I explore some openings through which these limitations may be overcome.
3. Living

the empty future

In this section, we explore how the future is constructed, not just with texts and images, but also through practices and patterns of desire. Together, representations, practices and patterns of desire constitute assemblages that concretize styles of living the future, future horizons within which forms of subjectivity are constituted. It is against these horizons that social antagonisms are produced and reproduced, as a function of tensions within practices and representations. The future-oriented phenomenon of technological innovation can then be contextualized within a broader analysis of how contemporary technological societies relate to the future. The need to understand how futures are constructed using the concept of future horizons is set out in Adam and Groves (2007). That the construction of futures is more than a representational process or activity has been recognized by some researchers within the sociology of expectations, who have examined the role of affect in shaping how expectations are produced (e.g. Brown, 2005). Nonetheless, critical treatments of the ways imaginaries exert selection pressures upon technologies remain largely concerned with their representational content and inner logics (e.g. Lopez, 2004). It is questionable, I want to suggest, whether a critical stance that remains at the level of how futures are represented goes far enough to expose deeper tensions with within how the future is socially constructed. My point here is similar to Langdon Winners criticism of social constructivism as a way of understanding technology that usually finds it sufficient to gather evidence of social activities most clearly connected to technological change while ignoring the possible existence of deeper cultural, intellectual, or economic origins of social choices about technology or deeper issues surrounding these choices (Winner, 1993: 371). Something that is missing from critiques of how imaginaries represent the future is why the idea of foresight itself and the imagery that accompanies it are so seductive. Future narratives are always constructed around promises connected to particular technological capabilities, but what they share is the gesture of looking ahead itself, which relies on what Robert Romanyshyn (1989) has called the archetypal, fundamental modern metaphor of Cartesian perspective, from which the modern subject (in art, science and ethics) views the world as a geometrically extended both in the three dimensions of space and the fourth dimension of time. From Bentham to contemporary champion of strategic nanoscience Mihail Roco, faith in foresight is reaffirmed: progress is faster with clearer vision (Roco, 2007). As we have seen, there are contradictions at the heart of this allegedly rational faith, yet still it endures. What habits of mind and what practices sustained this faith in the face of these contradictions?
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

8 In the previous section, we explored certain central aspects of the revolution in ethical life brought by modernity. What changed here, to use Foucauldian language, was the ethical problematization of the world, where by problematization is meant the ensemble of discursive and non-discursive practices that make something enter into the play of true and false and constitute it as an object of thought (Foucault, 1966, p. 670, quoted in Rabinow, 2003: 18). The problematization of the future was a key element of the cultural, epistemic, ethical and political shifts initiated within the early modern period. In this period, the future became an object for a variety of regimes of scientific and moral truth, as we saw in the previous section. A future of finite possibilities became, for instance, conceptualizable in terms of counterfactual worlds (Giddens, 1991), a prerequisite for the kinds of imaginaries analyzed by Lopez, or indeed, for any critique of them. Lucian Hlscher has documented how the re-organization of the temporal character of experience in this period, made representations of disjunctive possible future worlds possible in the first place. In medieval European culture, he argues, the future was thought of mostly in terms of the future states or condition of an individual person or thing (Hlscher, 1999, pp. 19-20). From the 16th and 17th centuries onwards, however, European culture manifests the idea of the future as such: a unified realm of potential, interconnected events, of finite possibilities. With this problematization came new styles of living the future, new assemblages of practices and patterns of desire, along with new representational and symbolic regimes. As a result, Peter Osbornes remark, quoted earlier, that modernity is characterized by openness to an indeterminate future is arguably not precise enough. The future is, to a certain extent, always indeterminate for human beings. Yet at particular times and in specific places, humans are cultured by determinate assemblages of techniques, practices, modes of representation, imagination and thought that constitute styles of living the future in the present, ways of cutting out a more or less domesticated future for themselves from purely determinable uncertainty. From within such a style, the future becomes the object of regimes of truth an object of knowledge, of action, and a source of ethical demands. This concept of a constitutive style of living the future is foreshadowed in Reinhardt Koselleck's notion of a 'horizon of expectations' [Erwartungshorizont] (Koselleck, 2002) characteristic of individual texts and particular historical periods, and Lucian Hlscher's notion of a 'future horizon' [Zukunftshorizont] (Hlscher, 1999). Their respective employments of the word horizon resonate with the concepts of horizon found in Heidegger and Gadamer, who deploy it in describing a feature of subjectivity not present to the subject itself but nonetheless constitutive of its perspective on the world. As Niklas Luhmann writes, the essential characteristic of a horizon is that we can never touch it, never get at it, never surpass it, but that in spite of that, it contributes to the definition of the situation (Luhmann, 1976: 140). Barbara Adam and I (2007) have suggested that with modernity evolved a number of distinctive, divergent styles of living the future, a variety of assemblages of practices, patterns of desire and forms of representation. These emerged gradually (rather than signaling a punctual break with the past) from within the fissures that social change opened up within medieval habits of mind. It is these new horizons within which future imaginaries begin to populate the future with counterfactual possibilities. We taxonomized these horizons as a set of ideal types: for example, an abstract future emerging in the 17th century, where the future was interpreted as the deterministic product of Newtonian physical laws, an open future, in which the future was the horizon of collective political action, and as the 18th century passed into the
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

9 19th, an empty future horizon. It is this empty future horizon, I want to suggest, which ultimately makes the promises of foresight so seductive and readily reproducible even in the face of contradiction as the basis of making sense of the future. Hlscher (1999) documents how such a future horizon emerges within Europe and the United States towards the end of the 19th century, and then begins to coalesce in new imaginaries, patterns of representation and imagery. He names this new ethos the mechanization of the future [Technisierung der Zukunft], with the growth of railways being a major influence. New practices of travel and the distribution of goods reshaped conceptions of progress, enabling them to be thought and imagined, for the first time, in terms of quantitative measure: faster speeds, greater numbers of passengers carried, whole nations crossed in a single day. The Enlightenment had dreamed of the moral perfection of humanity and the realization of its inner nature. By contrast, the late 19th century dreamed of abundance, realized through myriad avenues of technological ingenuity, having become habituated to the technologically-assisted crossing of frontiers. Hlscher identifies the development of certain technologies as a driving force behind the mechanization of the future. But contributing to their development, and rippling out beyond it to affect a wide range of institutions was a wider confluence of knowledge practices, modes of action and ethical life, within which new forms of expert knowledge had significant influence. The future increasingly became constructed to fit within the grids made available by the systematic and mathematized forms of knowledge that had begun their growth in the 17th century physics (especially thermodynamics), engineering, and economics. The future was increasingly projected through these practices as an empty field, empty of actuality the geometric, Cartesian temporal space we encountered above, which is empty yet full of infinite counterfactual possibilities from which specific finite possibilities can be selected and realized at will. Emerging in the middle of the century, cost-benefit analysis (CBA) exemplified such counterfactual, future-oriented expert knowledge. Quantifying potential outcomes, in order to render them commensurable with each other, became an increasingly influential way for State actors to justify policy choices and build consensus for political decisions, as Theodor Porter (1995) has argued. Pioneered by figures such as Jules Dupuit, the epistemological and ethical goal for such thinkers was to dissolve the conflicts of politics into bureaucratized routines of administrative decision-making. Custom treats [politics] as a moral science: time, we are convinced, will make it an exact one, borrowing its methods of reasoning from analysis and geometry, to give its demonstrations a precision they now lack. (Jules Dupuit, Titres scientifiques de M. J. Dupuit (1857), p. 31, cited in Porter, 1995) CBA shaped new practices for the governance of public works, such as the actuarial practices of risk accounting that became part of the emergent social state (Donzelot, 1988), and which, in Nikolas Rose's words, 'brought the future into the present and made it calculable' (Rose, 1999, p. 247). Such practices also accelerated the evolution of new economic institutions and practices built around the trading of futures options. Later, in the 20th century, the dominance of such practices extended to shaping how wars were fought (Edwards, 1996). Similar, quasi-scientific approaches to assessing indicators of progress (such as formalized, consensus-based foresight
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

10 and horizon scanning exercises, innovation scoreboards and integrated assessment models) were developed in the second half of the century as ways of laying down a road into the future along which innovation could proceed. The accretion of capabilities for using new knowledge practices to exercise foresight and plan ahead of the present, and new ways of organizing action to maximize options and adaptive flexibility meant that those social actors, including states, that possessed such capabilities were able to increase their political legitimacy. Further, they gained the advantage of being able to decisively and speedily shape the future territory on which less agile and capable others would later have to make decisions and deal with consequences. In the age of the empty future, all were equally able to imagine new possible futures, but in the end, some of these futures were created more equal than others. Such foresight practices helped the consequentialist ethical imperatives of modernity to be more widely manifest in public policy and to accrue legitimacy as ways of ordering policy priorities. Utilitarianism informed the basis of neo-classical microeconomics, before being translated, as the 19th century passed into the 20th, into the new sub-discipline of welfare economics. Maximizing material well-being through an increased satisfaction of individual preferences, became the measure of all social progress, with utility curves and cost-benefit profiles shaping the social imaginaries of progress. As we noted in the previous section, consequentialist morality manifests contradictions in the face of innovation. For their part, the empty futures consequentialist tools have faced widespread criticisms of the presuppositions on which their extensive policy use rests, along with demonstrations of their systematic failure in practice (Mitchell, 2002; Flyvbjerg et al., 2003). Yet despite this, they retain legitimacy, a fact that has led to a kind of religious character being attributed to the ethos of the empty future. CBA has been called a secular sacrament (Hammond, 1966: 196), a form of ritual observance undertaken through practices of precise quantification. Walter Benjamin notes how utilitarianism, as the centre of the ethical life of industrial capitalist societies, takes on a religious coloring that is cultic in nature concerned with external affirmations of belief and associated practices rather than with theology or scripture becoming a form of observance for which there is no day that would not be a holiday in the awful sense of exhibiting all sacred pomp the extreme exertion of worship (Benjamin, 1996: 288). The ubiquity of quantification is attested to by Georg Simmel, writing in 1903 of the centrality of [p]unctuality, calculability and exactness (Simmel, 2002: 14) to the normative and moral texture of even everyday life in the capitalist metropolis. The use of tools like CBA does not, therefore, purify politics of the symbolic reasoning and argumentation that is characteristic of morality and politics, and, as Dupuit desired, transform it into an exact science. Instead, the rituals of CBA and welfare economics retain a supplementary symbolic and even aesthetic significance in the face of even complex and reflexive uncertainty, enabling demarcations to be made between the pure and impure, the risky yet calculable and the merely dangerous and unpredictable (Crawford, 2004). This combination of the scientific, symbolic and aesthetic within the empty future requires further analysis. We have not yet discussed the patterns of desire that characterize it, and which, in the face of antagonism and contradiction, ensure its reproduction as a style of living the future. Hlscher shows that what he calls the mechanization of the future shapes specific varieties of future imaginary that become prevalent around the turn of the 20th
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

11 century, ones in which novel techniques and technologies are depicted that bring ease, comfort, speed and abundance. Yet the forms of desire that typify the empty future are not simply fixated on the accumulation of quantities of luxuries and the diminution of annoyances. I noted above that the chief advantage conferred by the knowledge practices that map the vacant terrain of the empty future is flexibility an increase in the autonomy of people and/or organizations, a decrease in their reliance on the explicit consent of others in carrying out their policies, and an ability to secure their own future by displacing uncertainty and insecurity onto others (Vail, 1999: 14). Such an increase in autonomy promises to make the future more secure and controllable. Yet at the same time, the mapping of the future, precisely because it increases autonomy and flexibility, can also increase uncertainty. For example, basing decisions about innovation pathways and products at each stage on the basis of information about narrowly-define potential benefits and costs can produce unforeseeable consequences, exactly because of the conviction that the benefits are so certain or so great the product in question must be deployed as widely as possible. As we saw in Section Two, the lack of fit between territory and map between the future that is created and the predictions that justified the acts that led to it being created points up an ethical contradiction. At the same time, however, this contradiction can be traced back to an underlying tension within the empty future between what, in psychoanalytical terminology, can be distinguished as desires and drives. On the one hand, the desire to see ahead, to exercise foresight and have ones autonomy affirmed is fulfilled in the production of the map and the fantasy of a future unified under the rule of the imperium of technical control. The precision of utilityfunctions, cost-benefit analyses and trend forecasts reassure us that a boundary exists between ways of acting that are risk aware and rational, and others which are unruly, risk-blind, and dangerous. However, the desire for uncertainty to be at least symbolically tamed goes along with a conflicting impulse, one which enjoins us to transgress the boundary between risk and danger in order to open up new territories of possibility. The existence of prediction becomes at the same time a license to seek out uncertainty, to create new futures on the basis of rules of thumb, in ways similar to how participants in extreme sports conduct themselves (O'Malley, 2008). This impulse can be related to the Freudian/Lacanian concept of death drive, in the sense of a compulsion so powerful that it makes one indifferent to death (Fisher, 2011), which Marshall Berman (1983) identifies at the heart of modernity in his reading of Goethe's Faust: In the worlds more advanced industrial countries, development has followed more authentically Faustian forms. Here the tragic dilemmas that Goethe defined have remained urgently in force. It has turned out and Goethe could have predicted it that under the pressures of the modern world economy the process of development must itself go through perpetual development. (p. 78) The empty future is sustained by a modern frontier spirit: the positing of new certainties in order to transgress them. Ian Welsh (2000) has noted the affective charge associated with the colonisation of the future, which drives innovation beyond the limits of socially ratified rationality, beyond the strictures of cost-benefit analysis, and which saturates even the most measured language of advocates of, for example, nuclear power. Welsh (p. 13) quotes the head of the UK Atomic Energy Authority, Sir John Hill, speaking in 1971:
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

12 I hope we will not lose all sense of striving for the future or of interest in the undiscovered, nor refuse to make any journey unless every step can be counted and measured in advance. The road to successful and economic power stations is uncharted. I hope we can maintain our resolve to continue the exploration. The need for a rationalized measure of progress, embodied in the search for more efficient techniques of manipulating nature, is inseparable from an impulse to use the map as a launching platform for an erratic quest for novelty for its own sake, even if it is costly and a step into 'uncharted territory'. This two-sided dynamic can be seen, once again, at work in relation to radical nanotechnology visions, in which nano is conceived of as the 'new new thing', in Richard Jones' words (Jones 2007), carrying both the promise of ultimate certainty (in the shape of the capability to engineer out of human life natural uncertain, fragility and vulnerability) and the promise of infinitely disruptive potential for transforming the world. This twin dynamic finds expression, for example, in the future imaginaries of radical visions of nanotechnology, such as molecular engineering (Amato, 1999) and technological convergence (Roco and Bainbridge, 2003). The empty future tries to bring manifest unity and order to the future in the form of ordered assessments of risk, yet simultaneously seeks to recreate the empty field of possibilities it has just caught within the nets of reason.
4. Conclusion:

Horizons of Care

In Section Two, we saw how a central contradiction within the ethical life of modernity results from its reliance on scientifically-guided foresight to assess the potential consequences of innovation. This contradiction began to emerge alongside a style of living the future that develops around industrial technological innovation as an engine of modernization and rationalization, and which reshapes a variety of practices across a wide variety of aspects of social life. Within this style of living the future, this future horizon, there is a deep antagonism that creates the conditions for the contradiction analyzed in Section Two. The modern emphasis on foresight, I have suggested, clouds the reality of how uncertainty is experienced but also of how it is, at the same time, a seductive source of value in industrial and post-industrial societies. As we saw in Section Two, technological societies characterized by the pervasiveness of advanced technologies confirm the reality of human finitude. In Section Three, we have seem how this confirmation of finitude is a dialectical result of the lure of infinity of living an empty future, of continually recreating the future as a vacant space of pure potential. The uncertainty caused by the quest for certainty is, though troubling, an excess produced from within the patterns of practice we have examined above that have come, across history, to characterize modernization. Despite destabilising its results, this excess nonetheless also sustains its forward momentum. It may not be enough, then, to simply point out contradictions, expose the determinist logics of technological imaginaries, or even admit a multiplicity of voices into arenas of expectations in order to ensure that innovation drives at the right impacts. If the empty future is a seductive and compulsive way of living the counterfactual futures that Giddens and Hlscher see as characterizing modernity, then replacing irresponsibility with responsibility cannot simply a matter of employing precaution, or of re-organising institutions to be more responsive. The material basis of this style of living the future, rooted in practice and desire and how
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

13 social patterns are reproduced across time, needs also to be the subject of analysis for RRI. As we saw towards the beginning of this essay, responsible innovation contains a constitutive tension. The empty future, the source of this tension, is an ethos, a style of living, with, in turn, its own characteristic style of aesthetics, of epistemology, politics and ethics. Responsible innovation, if properly conscious of the tension to which it is a response, must consciously aim to culture an alternative ethos, a style of living the future that is more appropriate to our rediscovered finitude one that counterposes its own aesthetics to the aesthetics of the empty future, a remodeled epistemology to its epistemology, a different politics to its politics and a recalibrated ethics to its ethics. The use of the concept of 'responsiveness' (von Schomberg 2011), as we saw above in Section Two, has been a way of articulating RRI as rooted in a kind of ethics of mutual recognition and an epistemology of multiple perspectives on uncertainty. Both these dimensions are represented as intrinsically important parts of the central thread of RRI, to direct innovation towards the right impacts, defined through extensive and inclusive deliberation and debate. Part of the goal of employing such an approach is to interrogate the imaginaries invoked by enactors of new technologies in order to expose the assumptions about social priorities and ideological tropes that underlie and reinforce them and which reproduce within them particular styles of living the future. Yet RRI has not, to date, addressed the need for a new ethos for living with technology more fully than this. The call for responsiveness expresses what its advocates see as a radical demand for innovation to be opened up to the influence of stakeholders, including publics, beyond the charmed circle of the usual suspects. Yet this call, by focusing on reciprocity, fails to recognize central aspects of our relationship to the future generations who will inhabit the world shaped by innovation. This relationship is characterized by non-reciprocity (Groves 2009), by the inequality of power between living and potential people. It has been recognized by some advocates of RRI that a kind of implicitly non-reciprocal care for the future must be an ingredient within RRI (Owen, Macnaghten, and Stilgoe 2012). But the question that remains is how the different elements of RRI might hang together, in the context of how futures are lived in practice, and how RRI can be cultured as part of a different future horizon. If the phenomenon of organized irresponsibility emerges from out of the empty future, is there a corresponding ethos or style of living the future in which RRI could be anchored, one that brings together practice, desire, aesthetics, knowledge, ethics and politics? I have argued elsewhere (Groves 2011) that such an ethos might be sketched out as a political imaginary of care, drawing on phenomenological traditions of thought as well as feminist ethics. This would develop an account of care as a relation to the future with particular aesthetic, ethical and epistemological orientations, and as associated with modes of subjectivity that contrast strongly with those shaped by the empty future. Rather than basing a concept of RRI on a thin account of procedural or substantive justice (based on, say, concepts of rights) that aims to rein in organized irresponsibility, what this position would require is a commitment to and justification of a thick account of human flourishing that places the concept of a good life at the heart of its ethical (and aesthetic, and political) elements. In addition, what would be unique about this approach (making it distinct from, for example, a capabilities-based approach) is how it makes the subjective experience of meaning and agency of what matters to individuals and the groups of which they are part (Sayer 2011)
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

14 into necessary ingredients of its characteristic concepts of flourishing and harm, and also how it recognizes that such experiences are dependent upon intersubjective and psychosocial conditions. The connection of care with forms of life rather than principles divorced from such forms has been made by a range of feminist ethicists, notably Sara Ruddick (1980) and Joan Tronto (1993). They have both argued that ethics viewed through a lens of care is less a question of finding different foundations for morality, and more a matter of changing the relationship between moral theory and practice. Ethics for such theorists and politics, for that matter becomes less about how and why to apply moral principles and more about cultivating attitudes and dispositions that are suited to protecting and sustaining valuable human relationships in the face of uncertainty and insecurity. A future horizon of care is a different way of bringing the future into the present than that which characterizes the quantifying and instrumentalizing projections of the empty future. It domesticates uncertainty by beginning from within relationality and connection rather than by beginning from an assumed position of autonomy. In beginning with relationality, care begins with the experience of attachment and how it contributes to flourishing (Groves 2011). The developmental contribution of good attachment is the building of reliable relationships through which the uncertain future that arises from human vulnerability and finitude can be tamed in ways that acknowledge the emotional, as well as practical, dependence of people on each other. Human needs which include the need for meaning and influence over ones fate and over the fates of those one cares about are the primary source of human vulnerability and thus the primary object of care, but the circles of attachment spread more widely than just ones human significant others. Places, objects, nonhumans, institutions and ideals can all be objects of attachment and thus become constitutive values that also have needs (even ideals can flourish or decay) and which contribute to the meaningfulness of individual lives and collective histories. To be able to deal with ones attachments as an active subject of care requires the cultivation of certain capabilities, among which feminist theorists such as Sara Ruddick (1980) highlight the role of listening, intuition, attentiveness to what others need in order to flourish, and tending to these needs. In this sense, a political imaginary of care can be linked to the capabilities approach to an ethics of flourishing championed, in different forms, by Martha Nussbaum (2003) and Amartya Sen (1993). A key difference between the two approaches is, however, that for the former active care on the part of those in need must be a constitutive part of how all human needs/capabilities are provided for, except perhaps in cases of emergency or genuine helplessness. Needs may be fulfilled generically and instrumentally as a precondition of survival (think of refugees being provided with a certain number of calories a day in staple foods by an aid agency at a feeding station) or they can be fulfilled in ways that are constitutively valuable over time as an ingredient in human flourishing (think of an extended family celebrating Eid-ul-Fitr, Pesach or Christmas with an appropriate meal). In this way, it can be seen that care, when directed at other subjects, is always ultimately care for their capacity to care both for themselves and others, to form attachments, to make sense of their world based on these relationships and the biographical or historical narratives to which these relations contribute, and to act within these narratives to shape and influence their futures. To care is not simply an interpersonal endeavor. Enabling others for whom we care to flourish also requires the construction of broader socio-political and economic structures that embody solidarity and mutual risk-sharing across space time, as Joan
Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

15 Tronto (1993) and other theorists who have written on the political significance of care, such as Eva Kittay (2001), Fiona Robinson (1999) and Daniel Engster (2007) have argued. It also requires human-nature relations that honor the dependency of human flourishing on the non-human world (Groves 2009). The political imaginary of care connects the experience of attachment to the social (and natural) conditions necessary to support and sustain flourishing across time. In doing so, it points to an ethos in and for which the future is constructed as the totality of the singular futures of others we care about, together with the conditions of their flourishing very different to an untenanted future of pure possibility to be seized and colonized at will. While there is no space here to fully develop the political imaginary of care as the basis for a new ethos of technological innovation (or to properly anticipate the criticisms that such a thick account of flourishing will attract), some possible linkages can be indicated. In relation to technology, the idea of care offers a starting point for thinking about responsibility that connects with the analysis of technological artefacts offered by, for example, Peter-Paul Verbeek (2011). Verbeek, echoing Arendt's account of finitude, sees technology as morally significant because of the ways in which it conditions human agency. Design, for Verbeek, is therefore an inherently moral activity as it aims to embed within technological artefacts qualities that are actively designed to positively enhance specific forms of human life, including the capacity of technological objects to create and sustain forms of attachment across time, creating a relationship between humans and technologies which circles around care (in the sense outlined above) rather than latching onto the compulsion to seek novelty. Verbeek presents his ethics as a kind of 'good life' ethics of technology, a technologically-mediated vision of eudaimonia, that awakens a different aesthetic and ethical relationship to the future. Viewed as part of a political imaginary of care, the right impacts of innovation would not just be impacts that address material needs, but ones that enhance human capacities to flourish in the face of uncertainties and surprises, by contributing to the social relationships that are necessary to support these capacities. In place of the coupled impulses of future-mapping and the desire for the new new thing, we might find a desire for the qualitative enhancement of values that stand for the resilience and flourishing of richer forms of life. Examining a technology within the context of a 'good life' ethics of care suited to human finitude would base itself on the recognition technology is not, in and of itself, essentially alienating, destructive or dehumanising. Equally, it would be wary of the will to transgression embodied by the empty future. It would respond to the new problematic of the future awakened by the experience of reflexive uncertainty by asking not only what a given technology might contribute to the fulfillment of human needs, but how it will affect the agency and identity of its users. The point here would perhaps be not to view technological artefacts as tools for satisfying abstract needs, but as participating with human users in reshaping our sense of who we are and what we can do. References
Adam, B. and Groves, C. (2007) Future Matters: Action, Knowledge, Ethics, Leiden: Brill. Amato, I. (1999) Nanotechnology: Shaping the World Atom by Atom. Washington D.C, National Science and Technology Council. Arendt, H. (1998) The human condition, Chicago: Chicago University Press. Bach, U. E. (2011) Seeking Emptiness: Theodor Hertzka's Colonial Utopia Freiland (1890), Utopian Studies, 22(1): 74-90. Bakker, S., Van Lente, H. and Meeus, M. (2011) 'Arenas of expectations for hydrogen technologies', Technological Forecasting and Social Change 78(1): 152-162. Beck, U. (1992) Risk society : towards a new modernity, London: Sage Publications. Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

16
Beck, U. (1995) Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk, Cambridge: Polity Press. Benjamin, W. (1996) Capitalism as religion Selected Writings, vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Berman, M. (1983) All that is solid melts into air : the experience of modernity, London: Verso. Bernstein, P. (1996) Against the Gods: The Remarkable Story of Risk, Chichester: Wiley. Brown, N. (2005) Shifting Tenses: Reconnecting Regimes of Truth and Hope, Configurations 13: 331Brown, N. and Michael, M. (2003) 'A sociology of expectations: retrospecting prospects and prospecting retrospects', Technology Analysis & Strategic Management 15(1): 3-18. Campbell, C. (1977) 'Clarifying the Cult', The British Journal of Sociology 28(3): 375-388. Collingridge, D. (1980) The Social Control of Technology. New York: St Martins Press. Crawford, R. (2004) 'Risk Ritual and the Management of Control and Anxiety in Medical Culture', Health: 8(4): 505-528. de S. Cameron, N. M. (2006) 'Biotechnology and the future of humanity', J Contemp Health Law Policy 22(2): 413-23. Edwards, P. N. (1996) The closed world: computers and the politics of discourse in Cold War America , Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Engster, D. (2007) The Heart of Justice: Care Ethics and Political Theory . Oxford: Oxford University Press. Feldstein, M. S. (1964) 'The Social Time Preference Discount Rate in Cost Benefit Analysis', The Economic Journal 74(294): 360-379. Fisher, M. (2011) The privatisation of stress, http://www.newleftproject.org/index.php/site/article_comments/the_privatisation_of_stress, accessed 25 May 2013. Flyvbjerg, B., Bruzelius, N. and Rothengatter, W. (2003) Megaprojects and Risk: An Anatomy of Ambition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fortun, M. and Schweber, S. S. (1993) 'Scientists and the Legacy of World War II: The Case of Operations Research (OR)', Social Studies of Science 23(4): 595-642. Fujimura, J. (2003) Future imaginaries: genome scientists as cultural entrepreneurs. in A. H. Goodman D. Heath and S. M. Lindee (eds.) Genetic Nature/Culture. Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press. Garud, R. and Ahlstrom, D. (1997) 'Technology assessment: a socio-cognitive perspective;, Journal of Engineering and Technology Management, 14(1): 25-48. Grin, J. and Grunwald, A. (2000) Vision Assessment: Shaping Technology in 21st Century Society, Heidelberg: Springer Verlag. Grinbaum, A. and Groves, C. (2013), What is responsible about Responsible Innovation? Understanding the ethical issues, i n R. Owen, J, Beasant and M. Heintz (eds.), Responsible Innovation: Managing the Responsible Emergence of Science and Innovation in Society, Chichester: John Wiley and Sons. Groves, C. (2009) Future Ethics: Risk, Care and Non-reciprocal Responsibility, Journal of Global Ethics 5 (1): 1731. Groves, C. (2011) The Political Imaginary of Care: Generic Versus Singular Futures, Journal of International Political Theory 7 (2): 165189. Guston, D. H. (2006) Responsible Knowledge-based Innovation, Society 43 (4): 1921. Hacking, I. (1986) Culpable Ignorance of Interference Effects, in D. MacLean (ed.) Values at Risk. Totowa NJ: Rowman and Allanheld: 136-154. Hammond, R. J. (1966) 'Convention and Limitation in Benefit-Cost Analysis', Natural Resources Journal 6(2): 195-222. Hanson, V. (2011) 'Envisioning Ethical Nanotechnology: The Rhetorical Role of Visions in Postponing Societal and Ethical Implications Research', Science as Culture 20(1): 1-36. Hansson, S. O. (1996) 'Decision Making Under Great Uncertainty', Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26: 369-386. Hegel, G. W. F. (1993) The Science of Logic, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. Hoffmann-Riem, H. and Wynne, B. (2002) 'In risk assessment, one has to admit ignorance', Nature 416(6877): 123-123. Hlscher, L. (1999) Die Entdeckung der Zukunft, Frankfurt a. M.: Fischer. Jones, R. (2007). The new new thing. Soft Machines, 9th July, http://www.softmachines.org/wordpress/?p=312, accessed 13 March 2011. Kittay, E. F. (2001) When Caring Is Just and Justice Is Caring: Justice and Mental Retardation, Public Culture 13 (3): 557579. Koselleck, R. (1985) Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time: Kegan Paul International, Limited. Koselleck, R. (2002). The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts, Stanford, Stanford University Press. Latour, B. (2008) Its development, stupid ! or How to Modernize Modernization, http://espacestemps.net/document5303.html, accessed 9 September 2011. Lopez, J. (2004) 'Bridging the Gaps: Science Fiction in Nanotechnology', Hyle 10(2): 129-152. Luhmann, N. (1976). The future cannot begin: temporal structures in modern society. Social Research 43(1): 130-152. MacIntyre, A. C. (1983) Utilitarianism and cost-benefit analysis: an essay on the relevance of moral philosophy to bureaucratic theory. in D. Scherer and T. Attig (eds.) Ethics and the environment. Englewood CLiffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Macnaghten, P. and Owen, R. (2011) 'Environmental science: Good governance for geoengineering', Nature 479(7373): 293-293. Mayer, S. and Stirling, A. (2002) Finding a Precautionary Approach to Technological Developments Lessons for the Evaluation of GM Crops, Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 15 (1): 5771. Mitcham, C. (1994) Thinking Through Technology: The Path Between Engineering and Philosophy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Mitchell, T. (2002) Rule of Experts: Egypt, Techno-Politics, Modernity, Berkeley: University of California Press. Mody, C. M. (2006) Small, but determined: technological determinism in nanoscience. in J. Schummer and D. Baird (eds.) Nanotechnology Challenges: Implications for Philosophy, Ethics and Society . Singapore: World Scientific Publishing. Nordmann, A. (2007) 'If and Then: A Critique of Speculative NanoEthics', Nanoethics 1(1): 31-46. Nussbaum, M. C. (2003) Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. O'Malley, P. (2008) Governmentality and Risk. in J. O. Zinn (ed.) Social theories of risk and uncertainty. London: Blackwell. Orlan, A. (2010) The impossible evaluation of risk, Prisme 18. Paris: Cournot Centre. Osborne, P. (1992) Modernity Is a Qualitative, Not a Chronological, Category: Notes on the Dialectics of Differential Historical Time, in F. Barker P. Hulme and M. Iversen (eds.) Postmodernism and the Re-reading of Modernity. Manchester: Manchester University Press: 65-84. Owen, R., Macnaghten, P. and Stilgoe, J. (2012) 'Responsible research and innovation: From science in society to science for society, with society', Science and Public Policy 39(6): 751-760. Pellizzoni, L. (2004) 'Responsibility and Environmental Governance', Environmental Politics 13(3): 541-565. Porter, T. M. (1995) Trust in numbers: the pursuit of objectivity in science and public life, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Rabinow, P. (2003) Anthropos Today: Reflections on Modern Equipment, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

17
Richardson, H. S. (1999) 'Institutionally Divided Moral Responsibility', Social Philosophy and Policy 16(2): 218-249. Roco, M. C. (2007) 'Progress in Governance of Converging Technologies Integrated from the Nanoscale', Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1093(1): 1-23. Roco, M. C. and W. S. Bainbridge (2003) Converging technologies for improving human performance: nanotechnology, biotechnology, information technology and cognitive science, Dordrecht/London, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Robinson, F. (1999) Globalizing Care: Ethics, Feminist Theory, and International Relations . Oxford: Westview Press. Romanyshyn, R. D. (1989) Technology as symptom and dream, London: Routledge. Ruddick, S. (1980) Maternal Thinking, Feminist Studies 6 (2) (July 1): 342367. Sayer, A. (2011) Why Things Matter to People: Social Science, Values and Ethical Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sen, A. (1993) Capability and Well-being, in A. Sen and M. C. Nussbaum (eds.), The Quality of Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Simakova, E. and Coenen, C. (2013) Vision, hype and expectations: a place for responsibility. In R. Owen J. Beasant and M. Heintz (eds.) Responsible innovation: managing the responsible emergence of science and innovation in society . Chichester: John Wiley and Sons: 241-268. Simmel, G. (2002) The metropolis and mental life. in G. Bridge and S. Watson (eds.) The Blackwell City Reader. Oxford and Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, B. A. O. (1973) Utilitarianism; for and against, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sparrow, R. (2007) 'Revolutionary and Familiar, Inevitable and Precarious: Rhetorical Contradictions in Enthusiasm for Nanotechnology', Nanoethics 1: 57-68. Sparrow, R. (2008) 'Talkin Bout a (Nanotechnological) Revolution', Ieee Technology and Society Magazine 27(2): 37-43. Tallacchini, M. (2004) Before and Beyond the Precautionary Principle: Epistemology of Uncertainty in Science and the Law , Toxicology and Applied Pharmacology 197 (3): 174174. Tronto, J. C. (1993) Moral Boundaries: a Political Argument for an Ethic of Care. New York: Routledge. Vail, J. (1999) Insecure times: conceptualizing insecurity and security. In J. Vail, J. Wheelock and M. Hill (eds.) Insecure times: living with insecurity in contemporary society. London: Routledge: 1-20. Verbeek, P-P. (2011) Moralizing Technology: Understanding and Designing the Morality of Things. Chicago; London: University of Chicago Press. Von Schomberg, R. (2011) Towards Responsible Research and Innovation in the Information and Communication Technologies and Security Technologies Fields Research and Innovation Policy. Brussels: European Commission. Welsh, I. (2000) Mobilising modernity: the nuclear moment, London: Routledge. Wilsdon, J., and Willis, R. (2004) See-through Science: Why Public Engagement Needs to Move Upstream. London: Demos. Winner, L. (1993) 'Upon Opening the Black Box and Finding It Empty: Social Constructivism and the Philosophy of Technology', Science, Technology, & Human Values 18(3): 362-378. Wynne, B. (1996) May the Sheep Safely Graze? A Reflexive View of the Expert-lay Knowledge Divide, in S. Lash, B. Szerszynski, and B. Wynne (eds.) Risk, Environment and Modernity: Towards a New Ecology. London: Sage.

Christopher Groves 2013 DRAFT VERSION DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORIAL PERMISSION

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi