Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 12

The Growing Pains of a Free Republic

conflict's endemic in the mind:


your job's to hear it in the wind
and compass it in opposites,
and bring the antagonists by your wits

to being one, and that the law


thenceforth, until you change your minds
against and with the shifting winds
that this and that way blow the straw.α

The public attitude toward personal liberty shifted dramatically after the 9/11 terrorist

attacks in New York City and Washington D.C. Before the Twin Towers were wantonly

destroyed, civic liberty, in a universal sense, was virtually sacrosanct. With the passing

of statutes like the Patriot Act in the United States and Bill C-36 in Canada, public and

personal liberty has been wilfully compromised for the sake of public security, and has

brought to bear upon the entire concept of political liberty a burden that has violated the

α
Howard Nemerov, Poem: "To the Congress of the United States, Entering Its Third
Century", from The Selected Poems of Howard Nemerov. © Swallow Press and Ohio
University Press.
D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 2

sanctity of such a public disposition. Without liberty there can be no democracy. But

how is it to be restored? Is it a simple question of reversing policy with an opposing act

of instauration, or does it require civil conflict and disobedience in a struggle to win back,

or, perhaps, to win outright those liberties necessary for a viable democratic union?

The actions and record of the current administration in the United States is

sufficient for a beginning of an answer to these questions. In a recent interview, a former

strategist for the American Republican Party cited the significant reliance the architects of

post 9/11 America had on the political advice of Niccolò Machiavelli, particularly in the

pages of The Prince.1 But where they took violence, deceit and fraud as the means to

achieve the honourable end of maintaining political power, they used the ideas of the

Florentine with a typical understanding of how he understood politics. As a result, an

increasingly wider chasm separates the haves from the growing number of have-nots. It

is no mere irony that the author who proffered the advice to the ruling Medici family to

wrest control of political power, had, in fact, offered the clearest insight to winning

liberty, and this leads to the point of this essay. For civil liberty to be extended, class

conflict must be maximised. It is the job of the government to enacts laws to manage the

social dynamic to maximise, as opposed to suppress, this conflict; to sublimate the

inherent violence in parliament.

Since Karl Marx, it has been widely believed that a harmonious social order can

only be derived from a world without classes and class conflict. Logically, this appears

to be correct, and countless laws have been ratified to even out the playing field, as it

were, in order for citizens to enjoy their pursuit of happiness. But beneath the surface of

the evils of class conflict, and beyond the very human reaction to reconcile the conflict
D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 3

and mitigate the struggle, is this actually so? Contrary to this prevailing opinion,

Machiavelli accepted the class basis of political life and understood it to be the very

dynamic that could be beneficial to a republic. “His own study of history,” writes Kent

Brudney of Machiavelli, “and his own experience of Italian and Florentine politics led

him to conclude that class politics were an immutable characteristic of republican

political life, whose effects would often vitalise (or revitalise) a well-ordered republic.”2

The nature of this dynamic, however, is difficult to pinpoint in Machiavelli’s literature

leaving no sign posts to identify which of the many paths to take to arrive at the

comprehension of this “immutable characteristic of republican life”. The danger is in

taking a wrong turn.

Granted, in the body of Machiavelli’s literature, there are overtones and

generalities from which one can infer this conclusion, still there are problems for one to

encounter in the search for the locus of such conflict. What, for example, was the source

of such conflict? Was it economical, psychological, or religious? Other writers have

thought that Machiavelli admired the republic of ancient Rome, and disdained the

sectarianism of the Florentine republic because the latter was rooted in Christianity,

whereas the former was not.3 This view attributes the political success of the Romans to

a quality of human spirit that the Florentines lacked. This is true so far as it goes, and is

on the verge of cogency. Conceivably, one cannot imagine a warrior spirit to reside in

the heart of somebody who turns the other cheek out of love for his enemies.

Furthermore, in Machiavelli’s The Discourses, he states unequivocally his contempt for

Christianity, and how it weakened the strength and virtù necessary to “make men very

bold”.4 But this leads to a digression. It is not evident in Machiavelli’s published works

D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 4

if he criticised religion as playing a determinant role in class struggle as much as he

criticised its affect as an institutionalised state religion on a citizen’s virtù. Harvey C.

Mansfield, for instance, mistakenly believed that Machiavelli admired the Roman

Republic because the pagan spirit of the Romans allowed their passion and ardour to be

channelled into military endeavours far more easily than that of a Christian people.5

While such conclusions are arguable, it would be more fruitful to follow the line of

thought as that which Machiavelli drew in such statements as “I must not fail to discuss

the tumults that broke out between the death of the Tarquins and the creation of the

tribunes”6 to get to the heart of the matter. It would, moreover, be more rewarding to

separate religion from politics.

Machiavelli was clear in pointing out how the lesson the Roman Republic taught

on public liberty can be obscured by the “quarrels between the nobles and the plebs,” and

how those who attributed the downfall of the Roman Republic to this civil strife had

attributed the wrong effect to the cause. More significantly:

Nor do they realize that in every republic there are two


different dispositions, that of the populace and that of the upper
class and that all legislation favourable to liberty is brought
about by the clash between them.7

One of the motivations for Machiavelli to pursue this line of thought was the endless

factionalism of Florentine society that resulted in violence to the popoloα and the eclipse

of public authority. Here, the difference between Florence and Rome owed more to the

different attitudes of class interest than anything else. Factionalism is no more chaotic,

undemocratic and prone to corruption than party politics is in America.8 A conspicuous

feature in the history of Florence was the absence of a coherent class division that had

α
Italian for ‘people’; the Florentine equivalent to the plebeians in the Roman Republic.
D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 5

characterized ancient Rome beginning with the first secessio plebis circa 494 BC. How

Machiavelli viewed class division is a key component to his conception of liberty, and it

is the nature of this division, more than religion, that he was alluding to in Book I of The

Discourses. The problem, however, as previously mentioned, is his lack of precision

when he defines social classes. His proclivity to use terms loosely notwithstanding, some

writers have established meaning in his use of the term “class” and have concluded that

what he meant by such a term was rooted in economic life. Neal Wood observed that

Machiavelli’s discussion of class behaviour often appears more psychological than

economic, that his treatment of class behaviour was based on an empirical and historical

method.9 But recalling what Brudney hypothesised, that Machiavelli wanted to suggest

the immutability of class conflict and the enduring benefits such conflicts engender, one

can safely assume that his class psychology was rooted in a consistent notion of

economic station and ownership, and that “his argument did not depend on the continuity

of a particular class but on the continuity of class oppositions and their importance to

republics.”10 Embedded in this idea is the belief Machiavelli had in the ultimate

safeguard for a republic’s liberty, that it was held in the hands of the people.

To demonstrate this, it is first necessary to evaluate the dynamic arising from the

relations between the wealthy and the rest of the people. Admittedly, Machiavelli

suggested that class conflict derived from economic inequality, but there are instances

when his is explicit about it. A feudal system, he maintains in a discussion of those

conditions that favoured the establishment of republics, is incompatible with a free

government. Arguing that the gentry “who live in idleness on the abundant revenue

derived from their estates, without having anything to do either with their cultivation or

D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 6

with other forms of labour essential to life,” are “pest[s] in any republic and in any

province; but still more pernicious are those who…have castles under their command and

subjects who are under their obedience.”11 In his time, there were regions in Italy that

were poorly suited for a free republic, like Naples and Lombardy where the reign of the

nobility was left intact. But unlike these fiefdoms, the conditions in Florence were

amenable for the introduction of a free government since neither the ottimati, the landed

wealthy, nor the popolo, were independent from the communal economy or the

communal authority.

The demise of the nobility, marked by the Ordinance of Justice in 1293, set their

social standing as equals to the rest of the Florentine people, all accountable and equally

dependent on the political institutions of the city state for both private protection and

advancement in their lives. In The History of Florence, he analyzed a civic conflict that

took place in 1353 between two rival families, the Albizzi, and the Ricci, and argued that

due to the gradual dissolution of the landed gentry into the communal affairs of the city,

there was an orderly resolution of class differences that rendered the urban wealthy a

social position that no longer posed the problems that the landed gentry did.

And as the citizens, since the ruin of the nobility, were on


such an equality that the magistrates were more respected
now than they had previously been, they designed to proceed
toward the suppression of this disorder with civil authority
alone.12

Another indication of Machiavelli’s understanding of how the struggle between social

classes is rooted in the civil economy is found in Book I of The Discourses, where he

discussed the effects of the Agrarian Law in Rome. It is clear he understood how the

clash of social classes arises from private property, and that any legislation to establish

D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 7

economic equality where none previously existed can bring damaging results. The law had

two chief provisions: first, it limited the acres of land any citizen could own; and second

it regulated the distribution of land and booty won in battle with neighbouring states. He

cited the cause of the discord as being due to the acquisitive nature in which “some desire

to have more and others are afraid to lose what they have already acquired.”13 Therefore,

it is “clear from this that men set much greater store on property than on honours.”14

Keeping in mind that he characterised men essentially as ambitious, restless and self-

interested, at the core of this issue is the defence of property or the craving of property,

and that any law favouring one interest over the other is likely to turn the city topsy-

turvy.

A more accurate appraisal of the human character is achieved when considering the

separate attributes of each class. It bears to be repeated here that the observations

presented thus far were made empirically in the middle of the last millennium, in the case

of Renaissance Florence, and historically two and a half millennia ago in ancient Rome,

and yet they are no less pertinent to the state of modern political liberty than those of

The Prince are to Lee Atwater’s understanding of how to seize and maintain political

power.α The wealthy, either Roman patriciate or Florentine ottimati), according to

Machiavelli were forever ambitious and always jealous of their social station, yet they did

offer their cities the same qualities that were indispensable to the success of the republic,

namely, their skills in politics and the military. One of the primary failures the Florentine

α
Lee Atwater, the adviser to President George H. W. Bush, reputedly reread The Prince
once a year to ‘keep in touch with the Master’ (see Endnote 1).
D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 8

republic endured, out of an irreconcilable animosity to the ottimati on the part of the

people, was the continual exclusion of the wealthy class in all civic and political matters

whenever the people gained control of government. In contrast to the Romans, who,

despite their differences, operated on the principle of inclusion, the republic did not take

advantage of these skills and “invited the political and military amateurism that

characterised the Florentine Republic that Machiavelli served from 1498-1512.”15 For

Machiavelli, the people, who generally were not as ambitious as the wealthy, desired only

not to be oppressed, and as long as they and their families were reasonably secure, they

were content. But where he observed the enduring enmity of one class to the other to the

extent where they considered each other more to be enemies to be defeated rather than

adversaries with whom they had to work out their difficulties, he insisted there be

constitutional checks on aristocratic ambition, and when the common interest is neglected,

the people are required to act politically to restore their freedom.

In the breadth of his political literature, Machiavelli was consistent in thinking

that the characteristics of the social dynamic were timeless, and as such accorded a

reasonable degree of predictability in political life. On the whole, this meant that the

behaviour of the citizenry, and conversely that of the governors of republics, could be

anticipated. When the social role of each class was respected and accepted as a fact of

life, then constitution-making and political leadership became less problematic. What

upsets the balance is the development of factions within societies, as was the case in

Florence.16 Whether it occurred due to family ties, or by guild loyalties, or by the

development of parties, it muted the class interests necessary to the maintenance of


D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 9

liberty. On this note, Machiavelli breaks with traditional political philosophy and affirms

the rightful place of the people in any republic.

This is the issue that has either escaped the attention of, or had been blatantly

ignored by the political wisdom of his day. It was left to Machiavelli even to challenge

the wisdom of Livy as well.

Nothing is more futile and more inconstant than are the


masses. So says our author, Titus Livy, and so say all other
historians….But, however that may be, I think, and always
shall think there can be no harm in defending an opinion by
arguments so long as one has no intention of appealing either
to authority or force. I claim, then, that for the failing for
which writers blame the masses, any body of men one cares to
select may be blamed, and especially princes; for anyone who
does not regulate his conduct by laws will make the same
mistakes as the masses are guilty of.17

Having said this, Machiavelli unveils his argument in favour of the people in a republic

concluding with the remark that “for four hundred years they were enemies to the very

name of king and lovers of glory and of the common good of their country.”18 In leading

to this conclusion, he mentions a specific defence of the formal constitutional role the

people played. Where Livy had attributed the virtue of the Roman constitution to the

authority of the Consuls for its ability to contain the “tribunician storms”, Machiavelli

argued that the creation of the Consuls and the Senate were but the beginning of the

development of Roman greatness.19 If the political system of the Roman Republic did

not accommodate the representation of the people, it would be inadequate. “In a

republic, then,” writes Machiavelli, “at this stage there were the consuls and the senate,

so that as yet it comprised…a Principality and Aristocracy. It remained to find a place

D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 10

for Democracy.”20 If tumults occurred in the city of Rome, it was not due to unruly

behaviour on the part of the plebeians, they happened out of necessity because of the

populace being oppressed, or out of a suspicion that it was about to be oppressed. At

any rate, it provided a public platform for those who discerned wrongful treatment to

appeal to the public to plead their case. The subsequent creation of the Tribunes after the

secessio plebis finally established the sort of mixed constitution that led the way for

Roman liberty. “Hence,” Machiavelli concludes, “if these tumults led to the creation of

the tribunes, tumults deserve the highest praise, since, besides giving the populace a share

in the administration, they served as the guardian of Roman liberties….”21 Clearly, then,

out of social and class conflict were the liberties of not only those who experienced or

suspected to experience oppression, but those of the entire citizenry, were extended. It is

precisely the reason that, owing to their political autonomy were they able to express any

dissatisfaction to be adjudged and redressed by the public body thereby institutionalising

a new way or means to formally give vent to civic discontent.

This strikes at the core of modern political understanding. In the case of Rome, to

propose that its republic owed its health to Roman dissension is a radical proposition.

This was the theme in all of Machiavelli’s published literature. It was his desire to

convince his readers to accept this proposition, for accepting it meant depriving the

governing class in his day one of its most potent arguments, one that has resurfaced over

the centuries to Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, to Mill, Madison, and Walter Lippmann, that

is, popular attempts to share in government are inherently destructive to republics.

D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 11

One of the symptoms of this prevailing misunderstanding in politics is the notorious

stigma popularly given to modern politicians. The fault lies with the perceived role that a

politician has in a democracy. In an age where party politics justifies the means in

governance, too much attention is paid to a candidate’s moral vision, or his steadfast

belief in the incorruptibility of his ideals, or, once being elected, her ability to deflect

blame and publicly vilify her opponent as an enemy, as being evil, and must be beaten and

vanquished. In such a world, when one is implicated in scandal, all his associates are

deemed guilty. This is conflict that has no lightning rod, so to speak, to shunt the high

amperage electricity of social disagreement away safely. Where it leads is to factional

division along abstract lines. What is needed is effective politicians who ply their trade

artfully, who seek to negotiate and know when and how to compromise, who view their

adversaries today as colleagues tomorrow, who, in short, can effectively apprehend

maximised social conflict and direct it through existing, or if need be, new legislation to

augment the liberty of the entire political body, and finally, who realise that conflict is not

dire crisis but merely growing pains in the further development of a healthy republic.

D Camellato
872900228
The Growing Pains of a Free Republic (con’t) 12

NOTES
1
Interview with Kevin Phillips, democracynow.org [cited 29 March 2008].
2
Kent Brudney, “Machiavelli on Social Class and Class Conflict,” Political Theory, Vol.
12, No. 4, (November 1984), p. 509.
3
Harvey Mansfield, Jr., “Party and Sect in Machiavelli’s Florentine Histories,” in Martin
Fleisher, ed., Machiavelli and the Nature of Political Thought, New York, Atheneum,
1972, pp. 209-266.
4
Niccolò Machiavelli, The Discourses, Bernard Crick, ed(s)., Leslie J. Walker, trans.,
Penguin Books, New York, 1987, p. 278.
5
Mansfield, “Party and Sect”, p. 238.
6
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 113.
7
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 113.
8
Thomas E. Mann and Norman J. Ornstein, The Broken Branch : How Congress Is
Failing America And How To Get It Back On Track, Oxford; New York: Oxford
University Press, 2006.
9
Neal Wood, “The Value of Asocial Sociability: Contributions of Machiavelli, Sidney,
and Montesquieu,” in Fleisher, pp. 288-289.
10
Brudney, “Machiavelli on Social Class”, p. 511.
11
Machiavelli, The Discourses, pp. 245-246.
12
Niccolò Machiavelli, History of Florence and of the Affairs of Italy, Felix Gilbert,
trans., Harper Torchbooks, New York, 1960, p. 111.
13
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 200.
14
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 204.
15
Brudney, “Machiavelli on Social Class”, p. 513.
16
Machiavelli, History of Florence, pp. 108-109.
17
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 252.
18
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 254.
19
Titus Livius, The History of Rome, Vol. 1, Rev. Canon Roberts, trans., Ernest Rhys ed.,
J.M. Dent & Sons, Ltd., London, 1905, II.i, p. 79.
20
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 111.
21
Machiavelli, The Discourses, p. 115.

D Camellato
872900228

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi