Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 15

Journal of Visual Culture http://vcu.sagepub.

com/

What Makes an Image Singular Plural? Questions to Jean-Luc Nancy


Hagi Kenaan Journal of Visual Culture 2010 9: 63 DOI: 10.1177/1470412909354256 The online version of this article can be found at: http://vcu.sagepub.com/content/9/1/63

Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com

Additional services and information for Journal of Visual Culture can be found at: Email Alerts: http://vcu.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://vcu.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://vcu.sagepub.com/content/9/1/63.refs.html

>> Version of Record - May 27, 2010 What is This?

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

journal of visual culture

What Makes an Image Singular Plural? Questions to Jean-Luc Nancy Hagi Kenaan

Abstract

This article examines the connection between Jean-Luc Nancys thinking of images and his radical ontology of the singular plural. It shows how Heideggers conception of Dasein becomes operative in Nancys understanding of the visual and examines the implications which Nancys critique of Heidegger carries for a new ontology of the image. The articles central concern is the question of what it means for a philosophy of the visual to embrace the singular plural? In what senses is the singular plural the foundation of an images being? How should the singular plural play itself out in a thinking of the image? Focusing on Nancys interpretation of paintings origins, the article questions the manner in which the ethical consequences of Nancys ontology are brought to bear on his understanding of art.
Keywords

art being-with Heidegger image Jean-Luc Nancy Lvinas origins of painting singular plural

The gure proves itself to be capable of opening onto the with as its border, the very limit of its outline. (J-L. Nancy, Being Singular Plural, 2000)

Being-an-Image
One of the unique features of Nancys thinking about the visual is the ontological character of his investigation. Nancy thinks of images in an ontological manner.
journal of visual culture [http://vcu.sagepub.com] SAGE Publications (Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore and Washington DC) Copyright The Author(s), 2010. Reprints and permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalspermissions.nav Vol 9(1): 6376 DOI 10.1177/1470412909354256

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

64

journal of visual culture 9(1)

This primarily means that his treatment of the image is guided by the question of being: being-an-image or the being of an image. In addressing images in terms of their being, Nancy breaks away from a predominant tradition that grounds the conceptualization of the image in the opposition between true being and mere appearance. In this tradition, the image is characteristically understood as that which merely appears, a type of representation that draws its significance from its relation to being, while having no genuine part in it. When construed as a representation, the image gives itself to thought only in terms of that which it is not, i.e. in terms of its relationship to another typically more basic kind of entity whose presence it re-presents. As such, the image is commonly relegated by the tradition to a secondary, derivative, domain of existence: a copy, a double, a substitute. Hence, Nancy s methodological starting point is, in itself, an expression of an understanding that images are not actually copies (Nancy, 2006: 214), that the image is not the double of a thing in the world (p. 73). Nancy thus underscores the need to recognize the images ontological autonomy but, at the same time, he also emphasizes that we should be careful not to turn the image into yet another kind of object. Images, for him, are not re-presentations; they embody their own unique form of presence but this presence is not thinglike. Images are neither copies nor are they objects. And, in fact, they call for a thinking that resists the binary opposition between object and copy. For Nancy, in other words, it is crucial that we learn how to think of images as sui generis and, in particular, that we think of them in ways that resist not only the more traditional rhetoric of imitation and copy, but also the more contemporaneous tendencies of integrating the image into a language of identity and objecthood. The image, Nancy (2005) writes, is neither the thing nor the imitation of the thing (p. 8). And this may be taken as the first distinction of the image, the initial sense in which Nancy can speak of The Image The Distinct. The distinct stands apart from the world of things considered as a world of availability (p. 2). The image is distinct from its being-there in the sense of the Vorhanden, its simple presence in the homogeneity of the world and in the linking together of natural and technological operations What is distinct in being-there is being-image (p. 9). The clear Heideggerian resonance that we can hear in Nancys language is not a coincidence, but reflects, rather, an ongoing dialogue with Heidegger which is constantly present at the background of Nancys thinking about ontology and art. Furthermore, in arguing for the need to distinguish the being of the image from the being of an object (what Heidegger calls the Vorhanden), Nancy is, in fact, borrowing importing from Heidegger a wholly distinctive interpretational scheme that is central to Being and Time: the analytics of Dasein. For Heidegger, the analysis of Dasein is necessary in order to open up the question that regulates his investigation, the question of the meaning of Being. What is primarily interrogated in the question of the meaning of Being is that being which has the character of Da-sein (Heidegger, 1996[1927]: 37). Dasein is chosen as that necessary point of entry due to its uniqueness:

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Hagi Kenaan What Makes an Image Singular Plural?

65

Dasein itself is distinctly different than other beings Dasein is a being that does not simply occur among other beings. It is ontically distinguished by the fact that in its being this being is concerned about its very being. (p. 10) Dasein is a unique being whose uniqueness lies in the way it relates to its own being. And, since the essence of Dasein lies in its existence, the characteristics to be found in this being are thus not objectively present attributes (p. 40). For Heidegger, in other words, the analysis of Dasein calls for an interpretation that must resist the parameters of objecthood and, instead, develop with a view toward [Daseins] structures of existence (p. 40) such as, for example, its being-in-the-world, being-with-others, temporality, care, being-toward-death. This shift from Daseins objectmodalities to its particular modes of being from categories to existentialia is reproduced by Nancy who, in turning to the image, explicitly brackets the images objectively present attributes and focuses, rather, on its unique structures of being: e.g. the images givenness, its temporality, presence, absence, nitude and transcendence. Hence, taking this analogy further, we may say that if Heidegger is the philosopher who taught us as Lvinas (1985) puts it how to hear the resonance of the verb to be in the concept Being (p. 33), then Nancy can be said to be a philosopher who teaches us how to recognize the presence of that verb in the word image.

Being-With: Nancys Critique of Heidegger


Nancy often acknowledges his debt to Heidegger whose fundamental ontology he regards as that which has put us on the way to where we are, together, whether we know it or not (Nancy, 2000: 26). In this context, one of the most crucial moments in Heideggers Being and Time (1996[1927]) is, for Nancy, the discussion of Daseins relations with others (the Existentiale of being-with). Dasein, according to Heidegger, is never alone in the world and the world is thus typically experienced through the prism of co-presence; however, Daseins being-with is not just one among Daseins traits. It is not a contingent fact, but a constitutive feature of Daseins being-in-the-world. Being-with-Others belongs, according to Heidegger, to the being of Dasein [and] this must be understood as an existential statement as to its essence. In this sense, even when actual, factual Dasein does not turn to others and thinks that it does not need them it is in the mode of being-with (Heidegger, 1996[1927]. Being-with, Mitsein, is, according to Heidegger, a grounding and regulating structure of human existence an Existentiale that, for Nancy, carries significant implications for any understanding of the self (selfhood) and, consequently, of the unfolding, the event, of meaning. In other words, Nancy (2000) identifies a promise in Heideggers Mitsein, a potential for a radical philosophical beginning which he describes in the following way:

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

66

journal of visual culture 9(1)

Heidegger clearly states that being-with is essential to the constitution of Dasein itself. Given this, it must be made absolutely clear that Dasein, far from being either man or subject, is not even an isolated and unique one, but is instead always the one, each one, with one another. If this determination is essential, then it needs to attain to the co-originary dimension and expose it without reservation. (p. 26) What Nancy nds in Heidegger is a lens through which the self can be viewed as an event of multiplicity; and, in a corollary manner, an opening to a new kind of fundamental ontology that will take issue with this co-originary dimension and expose it without reservation. Taking seriously the Heideggerian conception of being-with ultimately implies, according to Nancy, that ego sum = ego cum (p. 26). Yet, this way of putting things should not be regarded as a conclusion as much as it is an opening of an avenue that invites further exploration. In other words, Nancy hears in Heideggers Mitsein the reverberation of a call for a radical beginning, for a philosophy that needs to recommence, to start itself, from itself, against itself. And, in order to do this, philosophy needs to think in principle about how we are us among us, that is, how the consistency of our Being is in being-in-common and how this consists precisely in the in or in the between of its spacing (p. 26). Heideggers Mitsein serves as a mark which indicates to us a place from which first philosophy must recommence (p. 26). Yet, this is also precisely what Heidegger, according to Nancy, fails to see. Heidegger fails to come to terms with the potential of his own thinking because he moves too quickly from thinking about the pole of the one (Dasein) to the pole of the undifferentiated many (das Man) and does so without ever dwelling on how we are us among us, on how the consistency of our Being is in being-in-common.To put this more specifically, instead of dwelling on the phenomenon of being-with, Heidegger hurries to conceptualize this experience as a structural condition en bloc a condition of average anonymity which he sets in opposition to Daseins authentic possibility of individuation. For Nancy, Heideggers affirmative assertion of co-originarity never fulfils itself since Heidegger ultimately gives up on the step to the consideration of Dasein itself and never considers the possibility of an explicit and endless exposition of co-originarity and the possibility of taking account of what is at stake at the togetherness of the ontological enterprise (p. 26). In this respect, there is an important negative lesson to be learned from Heideggers analysis of Dasein, an analysis that brings Heidegger so close and yet leaves him all too distant from the meaning of being-with.

Being Singular Plural


The existential analytic of Being and Time, Nancy writes, is the project from which all subsequent thinking follows, whether this is Heideggers own later thinking or our various ways of thinking against or beyond Heidegger himself (p. 93). Indeed, Nancys Being Singular Plural exemplies such an attempt to think against and beyond Heidegger. Hence, growing out of a critique of Heidegger that

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Hagi Kenaan What Makes an Image Singular Plural?

67

is far more profound than what rst appears to be a simple readjustment of the Heideggerian discourse (p. 26), Nancy takes on the task of redoing the whole of rst philosophy by giving the singular plural of Being as its foundation (p. xv). The starting point for this enterprise for which the form of the ontological treatise ceases to be appropriate (p. xv) is nevertheless formulated in an ontological manner.The givenness of Being, Nancy writes,is a gift that can be summarized as follows: Being itself is given to us as meaning (p. xv, emphases in original). This postulation consists of three focal points: Being, meaning and, in between, an us. The term Being is used here by Nancy in a manner that refers back to and concomitantly breaks away from the Heideggerian vision. Unlike Heidegger, for Nancy, there is no brute givenness of Being Being does not have meaning (p. 2). Nancy explicitly refuses to allow any concept of pure Being to become operative in his first philosophy to serve as grounds for our thinking independently of the actual manifestation of meaning.Being does not have meaning because Being itself, the phenomenon of Being, is meaning (p. 2). But, it should not in any way be understood as something given. It is never simply there in the form of an object, but present only as an incessant unfolding. Meaning is its own communication or its own circulation. How and where does this circulation take place? For Nancy,we are this circulation (p. 2). Meaning is grounded in the human we.The very possibility of having meaning is thus always already a co-possibility, or more clearly put, the fundamental condition of the appearance of meaning is being-with. As suggested, however, this is not a simple condition that could be taken for granted, but one that calls for a radical exposition. Indeed, for Nancy, the question of the ground of meaning the one philosophy needs to think is a question about how we are us among us how the consistency of our Being is in being-in-common and how this consists precisely in the in or in the between of its spacing (p. 26). In other words, the space in which the meaningfulness of things unfolds is one that never stems from and can never be traced back to a single unified origin, but that is constituted, rather, by a constant pluralization and splitting. Meaning begins where presence is not pure presence but where presence comes apart in order to be itself as such.This as presupposes the distancing, spacing, and division of presence (p. 2). Another way to put this is to say that the origin of meaning is neither the individual nor the community. What makes meaning possible is neither the infinitesimality of an undividable selfhood nor the unified homogeneity of a public space but, rather, what Nancy calls a transindividuality, a singularity indissociable from its being-with-many. But, how does all this bear on our understanding of the visual? Returning to our discussion of Nancys ontology of images, let us ask: what would it mean to think an images being as a being-with? In what ways is the singular plural the foundation of an images being? How does the singular plural of the image play itself out? Or, more generally, what are the implications which Nancys Being Singular Plural carries for an understanding of images? What would it mean for a philosophy of the image to come to terms with the condition of transindividuality or with the singular-plural origins of the image?

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

68

journal of visual culture 9(1)

The Origin of the Image


In Nancys writing on the visual, the question of the images plural singular origins is, surprisingly, hardly ever addressed.1 Nancy does often underscore the need to think the image beyond the specicity of a medium, but this preoccupation with the inner plurality of the artistic medium developed, for example, in Why Are There Several Arts and Not Just One? (Nancy, 1996) never leads Nancy back to the question of the co-originarity of our being-with. How should we understand the apparent forgetfulness of the singular plural in Nancys writing on the visual arts? I am not sure how to answer this question. But, in order to get a better view of its signicance, let us turn rst to a text in which Nancy explicitly reects on the origins of the image. In Painting in the Grotto, Nancy (1996) addresses the question of the origin of painting by responding to a primal image a primal scene of creation: the image of the making of the first image. Let us imagine the unimaginable, the gesture of the rst imager His hand advances onto a void, hollowed out at the very instant that separates him from himself instead of prolonging his being in his act. But this separation is the act of his being. Here he is outside of self even before having his own self, before having been a self ... the animal that stands in the grotto and that makes this gesture knows things, beings, different kinds of matter, structures, signs and actions. But it is ignorant of form, the rising up of a gure or a rhythm in its presentation For the rst time, he touches the wall not for support nor as an obstacle or something to lean on, but as a place, if one can touch a place. The rock wall makes itself merely spacious: the event of dimension and of the line, of the setting aside and isolation of a zone that is neither a territory of life nor a region of the universe, but a spacing in which to let come coming from nowhere and turned towards nowhere all the presence of the world. From the painter to the wall the hand opens up a distance that suspends the continuity and the cohesion of the universe, in order to open up a world (Nancy, 1996: 745). Nancy describes (imagines) the birth of painting as a drama for one actor: a solitary painter who, facing a wall in the depth of a dark cave, encounters a new kind of freedom that allows him to open up, for the first time ever, a space in which meaning can reverberate. Unlike Plato, for whom the cave signifies a human condition that is radically severed from the origins of meaning, Nancy interprets the cave as the cradle of the meaningful.2 Following Bataille to whom Painting in the Grotto is an homage Nancy approaches the first image in terms of the agency and the act involved in its creation.The prehistoric image on which Nancy focuses is one of a human hand. Hand stencils and hand prints are indeed typically dated among the most early images of the upper Paleolithic, but Nancy reflects neither on the specificity of a given hand-print nor on the different types different techniques involved in the making of such images. He seems to bracket a discussion of the images objective traits since, for him, the image qua object is only a trace of that primordial act that generates the very possibility of the image which is co-originary

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Hagi Kenaan What Makes an Image Singular Plural?

69

with the possibility of selfhood. In this respect, Nancys text is not only a drama in one act, but also a drama of an act, a singular gesture, an event that allows the emerging self of the painter to be itself by relating to itself, by presenting and seeing itself through what in Being Singular Plural is described as a constant distancing, spacing, and division of presence (Nancy, 2000: 2). Indeed, if we reread Nancys description of the first imager in the light of our discussion of Being Singular Plural, the presence of his ontology and, in particular, of his claim about meanings split origins, becomes evident. The painters hand advances onto a void; yet, unlike, the story of divine creation, the human act is not an embodiment of a being that precedes creation.As we have seen in Nancys ontology, there is no brute givenness of Being, no pure unshared presence presence to nothing.Nancy insists on a language that begins with the manifestation or the givenness the gift of Being: Being itself, the phenomenon of Being, is meaning that is, in turn, its own circulation and we are this circulation (p. 2). In Painting in the Grotto, the cave is the site of meanings originary circulation.Yet, as is underscored in the description of the first painter, meaning is not something that can ever be traced back to an ultimate or first signification. In French, the word fond means both ground and depth and, in this context, the intertwining of these senses in Nancys title Au fond des images makes the point clear: the ground of the image is the images depth.The image unfolds as meaningful, but there is no self or identity that grounds meanings appearance, no unified, self-contained form that supports this unfolding. For the painter, the image he creates is a surprise; it is born at the very instant that separates him from himself through a separation [that] is the act of his being. In other words, since we are meanings circulation, i.e. since meaning is made possible by who we are as humans, meaning begins where presence is not pure presence but where presence comes apart in order to be itself as such (p. 2, emphasis in original). For Nancy, there is no meaning if there is no self, of some form of another (p. 94). In Painting in the Grotto (1996), he thinks of the origins of painting in a manner that calls into question the cohesiveness of the self and, in turn, thinks of the alterity and difference that are at play in the constitution of selfhood in order to illuminate the manner in which an image becomes meaningful: Man began with the strangeness of his own humanity. Or with the humanity of his own strangeness The similar came before the self, and this is what it, the self was. Such was his rst knowledge, his skill, the quickness of the hand whose secret he wrested from the very strangeness of his nature the schema of man is the monstration of this marvel: self outside of self, the outside standing for self, and the being surprised in face of self. Painting paints this surprise.This surprise is painting. (p. 69) In the spirit of Lacans Mirror Stage, Nancy offers a dialectical reading of the relationship between the rst painter and his newly made image. The painters act leads to the appearance of an image which is, itself, operative in the constitution of the painters self a human self whose identity, in turn, can become manifest (as meaningful) only on the condition that it can never be possessed by that self.

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

70

journal of visual culture 9(1)

The hand-image is the creators hand; but only in the sense that it is the imprint or the negative of that hand. It is through the image that the prehistoric painter can see his hand as the hand which is his; it is through the image that he can recognize himself as the man of the hand, and yet what he sees shows itself only from within a distance that has opened up, an outside in relation to which the self can become meaningful as a self. Nancys reflections on the origin of the painted image are inseparable from his understanding of the origin of selfhood. The ability to create and see images is, according to him, a fundamental sign of our strangeness as humans, a mark of the constant crossing over, the mutual intrication and distancing, in the fundamental structure of the self (Nancy, 2000: 204). However, while focusing on the differencing that is constantly at work in the structure of selfhood, Nancys treatment of the image seems to disregard what is, for him, an essential dimension of the singular plural: our being-with-one-another. Nancy develops his understanding of the images being in analogy to the irresolvable tensions that are constitutive of the human being-there. Yet, in the last resort, he only follows halfway the analogy to Heideggers Dasein and, thus, never opens his account of the images singular plurality to the question of the images being-with.

Painting and Being-With: Questions to Jean-Luc Nancy


In Being Singular Plural (2000), Nancys thinking develops on at least two separate levels of abstraction. While elaborating his understanding of the singular plural as an abstract metaphysical concept or as an ontological principle, Nancy also discusses the singular plural in a manner that seems to be motivated by the ordinary experience of relating to the alterity of the other person whose singularity is, always already, part of a we, a crowd, a city, a people. The relationship between the ontological and the phenomenological dimensions of the singular plural is not always made clear. But, at the same time, it is not difficult to see that Nancys ontological formulations are often grounded in or at least intimately tied to structures of transindividuality, alterity and difference, spacing and division of presence that are fundamental to the experience of our being-there as a being-with. This very humble layer of our everyday experience contains another rudimentary attestation: what we receive (rather than what we perceive) with singularities is the discrete passage of other origins of the world. What occurs there, what bends, leans, twists, addresses, denies from the newborn to the corpse is neither primarily someone close nor an other nor a stranger nor someone similar; it is an origin; it is an afrmation of the world, and we know that the world has no other origin than this singular multiplicity of origins (pp. 89). When it comes to the singular multiplicity of paintings origins, however, the concrete presence of others seems to recede and disappear into the darkness of the cave in which Nancy locates the primordial appearance of the image. Nancy

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Hagi Kenaan What Makes an Image Singular Plural?

71

has created for the image a murky, imaginary, dreamlike space of appearance that he then illuminates with one spotlight so as to allow the presentation of a surprising event a single gesture of a single human being. Reading Nancys description of the first painter, we may easily forget that the animalman in the cave is not alone in the world and that he is, most likely, not even alone in the cave itself. According to anthropological research on this early type of prehistoric images, hand-prints are typically understood in the context of communal rituals in which the first image-creators presumably had a distinctive role. As such, the hands used to create the hand-prints we see today in the caves are often understood as belonging to the painters fellow humans rather than to the painters themselves.3 Is the first painting born, then, as Nancy argues, out of the complex encounter with ones self(hood) or, rather, with the living, often disturbing, presence, the hand, of the other? What exactly is the first painter facing and what does he see? Does he see the coming of the stranger that he himself is or is it the you [who is] absolutely strange because the world begins its turn with you? Is the first painting the trace of the strangeness that comes like an open intimacy, more internal than any intimacy, deep-set like the grotto (Nancy, 1996: 70, emphases in original), or is it a trace of a different, albeit a closely connected, kind of strangeness [that] refers, as in Being Singular Plural, to the fact that each singularity is another access to the world ... [that] there is nothing but the manner, the turn of the other access which conceals itself in the very gesture wherein it offers itself to us (Nancy 2000: 14)? These two options are, of course, not mutually exclusive. And yet, in his work on the origin of painting as well as in much of his work on the visual arts Nancy seems indifferent to the relevance of the you, the other whose alterity is its being-origin. This is not to say that Nancys work on the origin of art overlooks the possible presence of others, but that the unique character of this presence and its relationship to the image is never taken up and addressed in its actuality. In this respect, Nancys thinking of the images being seems to miss the potential of his ontological thinking. Thus, in spite of his critique of Heidegger, Nancy ultimately seems to reproduce the Heideggerian elision of the possibilities opened by the existentiale of being-with.4 To be specific, he approaches the images being-there without allowing its being-with to open up as a genuine question, without grappling, to use Nancys own words against Heidegger, with the possibility of an explicit and endless exposition of co-originarity and the possibility of taking account of what is at stake at the togetherness of the ontological enterprise (Nancy, 2000: 26).

The Singular-Plural Origins of Painting


The call for an endless exposition of co-originarity is primarily that is, prior to its ontological implications an ethical imperative.It reects philosophys commitment to the ethical in the sense that ethics begins with an acknowledgement of the unending enigma that the other person presents to us in his or her very being. This is one of the central themes in the writing of Emmanuel Lvinas for whom the fundamental form of our acknowledgement of the others alterity is that of responsibility. For Lvinas (1998), the presence of the other person
Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

72

journal of visual culture 9(1)

signies an irrecusable order, a command which puts a stop to the availability of consciousness What is at stake here is the calling of a consciousness into question and not a consciousness of calling into question. The I loses its sovereign self-coincidence, its identication, in which consciousness returns triumphantly to itself to rest on itself. Before the exigency of the other, the I is expelled from this rest [the others] presence is a summons to answer. The I does not only become aware of this necessity to answer it is in its very position a responsibility To be an I then means not to be able to escape responsibility. (p. 97) The questioning that concerns Lvinas is not one that can be solved conceptually or, better, it does not belong to the order of the conceptual. It does not offer itself to a knowing or an understanding, but summons to moral responsibility. Morality is the enigmas way (p. 72). Consequently, Lvinas offers a vision of a philosophy whose task is an endless response to the unsettling presence of the other endless in that it brings to the fore but never exhausts the enigma of a persons alterity.5 Nancy has a complicated relationship with Levinass thinking which deserves a separate discussion.6 However, for the purposes of this article, I think that the kind of Lvinasian sensitivity towards the irresolvable enigmatic presence of the other person is necessary if we wish to make the singular plural the fundamental ground of our understanding of the image. To begin taking the first step towards such an explicit and endless exposition of co-originarity, I suggest we turn to a figure, an image that would allow us to illuminate the origin of painting in a manner that embraces the condition of being-with as fundamental. What I have in mind is a mythical, age-old, image that appears again and again in the history of reflection on painting, from Quintilian to Alberti to Leonardo and Vasari to Rousseau and Romanticism and, in 20th-century French philosophy, from Merleau-Ponty to Derrida.7 This image tale or myth of the origins of painting (or of drawing) is first found in Plinys Natural History which provides two versions of the myth. While both versions describe the first act of painting as a tracing of a mans shadow on a wall, the more detailed account locates the first painting in a story of love and abandonment. This more elaborate account is given by Pliny precisely at the moment he moves away from painting to a discussion of a different art form, the modelling of clay. Enough and more than enough has been said about painting. It may be suitable to append to these remarks something about the plastic art. It was through the service of that same earth that modelling portraits from clay was rst invented by Butades, a potter from Sycion, at Corinth. He did this owing to his daughter, who was in love with a young man; and she, when this young man was going abroad, drew in outline on the wall the shadow of his face thrown by the lamp. Her father pressed clay on this and made a relief, which he hardened by exposure to re with the rest of his pottery; and it is said that this likeness was preserved in the shrine of the nymphs (Pliny, 1952[779]: 43). Nancy is acquainted with this tale of origins and, although he does not seem to be interested in its details, he touches briefly on it in Visitation: Of Christian Painting (2005), and offers the following reading:
Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Hagi Kenaan What Makes an Image Singular Plural?

73

The legend of its own origin that painting made for itself the Greek story of the girl who traces the outline of her ancs shadow on the wall as he leaves for war should not be understood as a parable of representation. This girl is not seeking to reproduce an image of the one who will no longer be there, in order to recollect it later: rather, she xes the shadow, the obscure presence that is there whenever light is there, the double of the thing of everything and its invisible ground. (p. 121) For Nancy, the gist of Plinys story is found in its afrmation of one of Nancys key positions: the being of an image calls for a non-representational understanding that releases the image from its traditional servitude to the order of the actual. The painted image is not a form of representation. It has nothing to do with a reproduction or a recollection of the world but, on the contrary, with an opening towards what he terms the immemorial: painting opens onto the immemorial: presence always-already there and always there again, inexhaustibly withdrawn into itself, relentlessly exposed before us ourselves before being born, after dying the immemory of a dawn or a twilight of the world (p. 121). For Nancy, the first painter is not seeking to reproduce an image of the one who will no longer be there, in order to recollect it. This is because what she faces and responds to is the there of a beyond (p. 125, emphases in original), an invisibility in which painting, itself, is grounded. The painter responds, in painting, to the invisible grounds, the transcendental conditions of visibility. But does this really capture the drama of the first painting or the significance of the first gesture of drawing? Even if we agree with Nancy that what is at stake here is not at all a representation, can we begin to understand the girls image without coming to terms with the fact that the inner form of her painting is a response to the complicated presence of another person? Plinys account provides a rich and concrete setting for the legendary birth of painting, one that integrates the allegedly technical act of the tracing of a shadow into the particularity of a painful and dramatic moment. Butades who, in the tradition takes on the name of her father becomes the first painter through a gesture directed towards her lovers imminent departure. Painting, as such, originates at an intersection: it takes place at the crossroad of desire and the experience of loss, of wanting to hold on to what one loves in a familiar way and of letting go. Once we recognize desire and loss as the twofold root of the act of painting, we shall also see why the predominant way of speaking about the first painting as a form of replacement or substitution cannot suffice. Butades is not creating a substitute because she has no need for a substitute. Her love is real and she cannot sell it short. The young woman is in love. She wants to love and she wants one specific love, but she also knows she has been abandoned. Desiring, she faces the object of her love. Yet, she also faces, just the same, the impossibility of fulfilling that love. Butades faces her limits and limitations, her finitude herself. In other words, the first painter is a woman who experiences the world without collapsing the experience of desire and loss into one another, without replacing one for another. In this sense, her act of painting is not a means for construing a stand-in for her lover, a surrogate or a substitution. To use the common rhetoric of presence and absence, we
Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

74

journal of visual culture 9(1)

should notice that the issue here is not the alternation between these two poles. Butades is not concerned with filling up and eliminating the absence which has pervaded her life. Her act is not an attempt to replace absence with a new form of presence but, on the contrary, it reflects an attempt to create a new place for herself in between the opposite poles of absence and presence. Indeed, the notion of the in between is helpful. It is precisely a domain of in between-ness that the act of the Corinthian maid opens up. As she faces her situation, Butades could have responded in a variety of ways. The field of options is there for her, characteristically arranged in pairs of oppositions.Yet, in her response, she resists the appeal of the either-or. She neither tries to prevent her lover from leaving nor does she insist on joining him. She neither holds on to her object of love nor does she renounce or turn her back on it. She is neither active practical, goaloriented nor passive. She opts for an option that has no significant objective consequence, no real effect in the world, but she clearly does not retreat into the privacy of the purely subjective. The act of the Corinthian maid is neither a something nor a nothing. It is, to use Vladimir Jankelvitchs expression, a presque And it is in this location of infinitesimality that painting originates. This is rien. where the image opens up. Furthermore, we need to notice that, in the act of painting, Butades not only reorients herself in the world, but she is, more specifically, taking a new stance in relation to the person she loves.8 The primordial act of drawing is thus inseparable from her response to the other person whose presence has become elusive and which can no longer be taken for granted. To put this more generally, we may understand the making of the first image as an expression of an unresolved tension which is characteristic of our relationship with others. This is a tension between the others existence as opening for us a meaningful world of things that affect us that we want and love and care about and, at the same time, as marking a world that remains forever elusive, unexpected and impenetrable: a world whose strangeness refers to the fact that each singularity is another access to the world (Nancy, 2000: 14). In this context, Butades act of tracing should also call for our attention.9 Butades traces the shadow of another person who, having being close and intimate, now loses its grounding in the common domain of the familiar and the known. Butades no longer relates to the ordinary figure of the person she loves, but only to a trace found at the limits of his shadow. What can this teach us about the origin and the essence of painting? Should we understand Butades gesture in Lvinasian eyes as a tracing of the trace of the other, a trace [that] obliges with regard to the infinite, to the absolutely other, and that establishes a relationship with illeity, a relationship which is personal and ethical? (Lvinas, 1998: 105). Plinys tale of origins deserves a more comprehensive reading than the one I can offer here. But, what we are already in a position to see is that his image of the first image is, in fact, an invitation: the tale of Butades and the origin of painting invites us to come to terms with the senses in which the singularity of the image is always already pluralized by the human condition of being-with. In responding to this invitation, we shall be taking the first step towards a thinking of the ethical dimension of the image.

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Hagi Kenaan What Makes an Image Singular Plural?

75

Notes
1. In Being Singular Plural (2000), the question of the image is not central; and yet, when touched upon, the imagesymbol appears to be a clear case in point: objecting to the critique of the image which has become a sort of ideological trope in theories of the spectacle and in theories of communication, Nancy argues that the sole criterion of symbolization is not the exclusion or debasement of the image, but instead the capacity of allowing a certain play, in and by the imagesymbol with the opened interval that articulates it as sym-bol. For Nancy, the term symbol (with its prex sun = with) already suggests that the dimension, space and nature of the with are in play here the symbolic is not simply an aspect of being-social it is this Being itself (p. 58). 2. In Painting in the Grotto (Nancy, 1996), Platos allegory of the cave is a recurring, albeit a criticized, point of reference. For Nancy, the Platonic cave with its topography of high and low, beyond and under, open and enclosed is an image of that Platonic space of thinking which he attempts to subvert. Nancy inverts the platonic order of meaning and, refusing to privilege the transcendent realm of bright daylight, locates the roots of the meaningful in the depth of the dark cave. 3. See, for example, David Lewis-Williams (2002) on the hand print in the cave of Gargas: This co-operative mode of making at least some of the prints seems to be conrmed in the case of Gargas where the hand and the forearm of a child were held against the rock by an adult, whose grip on the childs arm can be seen: it was not the child who was blowing the paint. (p. 220)

4. An interesting question in this context has to do with how Heideggers avoidance of the being-with bears on his understanding of the visual? Is there a signicant connection, for example, between his blindness towards the experience of alterity which is always part of Daseins world and his blindness towards the personal dimension of Van Goghs famous painting of shoes? On Heideggers failure to respond to Van Goghs painting of shoes, see Kenaan (2005). In this context, we should ask further: is there a connection between Heideggers elision of the singularity of Van Goghs shoes and the neglect of the concrete presence of the others alterity in Nancys ontology of the image? 5. On the relationship between the enigma of the other person and the grounds of the meaningful, see Kenaan (2006b). 6. It can be shown that Nancy is not only well acquainted with Lvinas central positions but that he is also very inuenced by Lvinasian formulations. At the same time, his mentioning of Lvinas is almost always critical. In Being Singular Plural (2000), Nancy hardly mentions Lvinas, but he explicitly criticizes positions that assume surreptitiously that Man is entirely a question of the Other.This is, according to him what is most often at work in the call to ethics: a transcendental unrepresentability of the most concrete presence (pp. 489). Nancy explains that something unrepresentable or ungurable runs the risk of revealing itself as completely oppressive and terrifying, if not terrorists, open to anguish of an originary Lack. In contrast, the gure proves itself to be capable of opening onto the with as its border, the very limit of its outline (p. 48). Is Nancy criticizing Lvinas or Lacan or perhaps both? In any case, Nancys turn to the gure as that which ties the with to the question of an outline will be particularly relevant to our discussion of the origins of painting. 7. In this context, the work of Robert Rosenblum has a unique status in the way it sets the eld for an investigation of the origin of painting as an iconographical problem. Rosenblum (1957) is primarily concerned with the manner in which Plinys tale is turned into a prevalent pictorial theme by romantic classicism. He is interested in explaining the surprising abundance of pictorial images of the Corinthian maid the

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

76

journal of visual culture 9(1) rst painter in the last third of the 18th century.Yet, as he proceeds with an anatomy of this image of origin and of the signicance it carries for late 18th-century painting, Rosenblum also provides a condensed history of Plinys tale from late antiquity to the 18th century that enables us to appreciate the complex matrix of versions and interpretations which presented itself to the imagination of romantic classicism. A more recent interpretation and analysis of Plinys tale, to which I am indebted, is Stoichita (1997), which underscores the signicance and role of the shadow in this tale of origins. 8. I notice that Plinys story of the Corinthian maid, positions the rst painter in relation to two male gures: her lover and her father. 9. For a more comprehensive discussion of the phenomenological implications of Plinys tale and, particularly, of the signicance of the act of tracing, the line and the shadow, see Kenaan (2006a).

References
Heidegger, M. (1996[1927]) Being and Time, trans. J. Stambaugh. New York: SUNY Press. Kenaan, H. (2005) The Present Personal: Philosophy and the Hidden Face of Language. New York: Columbia University Press. Kenaan, H. (2006a) Tracing Shadows: Reections on the Origins of Painting, in C. Versar and G. Fishof (eds) Pictorial Languages and Their Meanings. Tel Aviv: Tel Aviv University, Faculty of the Arts. Kenaan, H. (2006b) The Plot of the Saying, Etudes Phenomenologiques: Lvinas et la phnomnologie XXII(434). Louvain: Ousia. Lvinas, E. (1985) Ethics and Innity: Conversations with Philippe Nemo, trans. R. Cohen. Pittsburgh, PA: Dusquesne: Duquesne University Press. Lvinas, E. (1998) Collected Philosophical Papers, trans. R. Cohen. Pittsburgh, PA: Dusquesne: Duquesne University Press. Lewis-Williams, D. (2002) The Mind in the Cave: Consciousness and the Origins of Art. London:Thames & Hudson. Nancy, J-L. (1996) The Muses, trans. P. Kamuff. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Nancy, J-L. (2000) Being Singular Plural, trans. R. Richardson and A. OByrne. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Nancy, J-L. (2005) The Ground of the Image, trans. J. Fort. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Nancy, J-L. (2006) Multiple Arts: The Muses II, trans. S. Sparks. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Pliny, (1952[779]) Natural History, XXXV, 43, trans. H. Rackman. Cambridge: Loeb Classical Library. Rosenblum, R. (1957) The Origin of Painting: A Problem in the Iconography of Romantic Classicism, The Art Bulletin 39(4): 27990. Stoichita, V. (1997) A Short History of the Shadow. London: Reaktion Books.

Hagi Kenaan is Senior Lecturer in the Department of Philosophy, T el-Aviv University. He has published essays on phenomenology, aesthetics and the philosophy of art, on Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Heidegger, Derrida and Lvinas. He is the author of The Present Personal: Philosophy and the Hidden Face of Language (Columbia University Press, 2005) and of Otherwise than Seeing: The Ethical Optics of Emmanuel Lvinas (forthcoming). Address:Tel Aviv University [email: kenaan@post.tau.ac.il]

Downloaded from vcu.sagepub.com at University of Sydney on February 19, 2014

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi