Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 31

Gilles Deleuze (1925–1995)

Deleuze is a key figure in postmodern French philosophy. Considering himself


an empiricist and a vitalist, his body of work, which rests upon concepts such as multiplicity,
constructivism, difference and desire, stands at a substantial remove from the main traditions of
20th century Continental thought. His thought locates him as an influential figure in present-day
considerations of society, creativity and subjectivity. Notably, within his metaphysics he favored
a Spinozian concept of a plane of immanence with everything a mode of one substance, and thus
on the same level of existence. He argued, then, that there is no good and evil, but rather only
relationships which are beneficial or harmful to the particular individuals. This ethics influences
his approach to society and politics, especially as he was so politically active in struggles for
rights and freedoms. Later in his career he wrote some of the more infamous texts of the period,
in particular, Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus. These texts are collaborative works with
the radical psychoanalyst Félix Guattari, and they exhibit Deleuze’s social and political
commitment.
Gilles Deleuze began his career with a number of idiosyncratic yet rigorous historical studies of
figures outside of the Continental tradition in vogue at the time. His first book, Empirisism and
Subjectivity, isa study of Hume, interpreted by Deleuze to be a radical subjectivist. Deleuze
became known for writing about other philosophers with new insights and different readings,
interested as he was in liberating philosophical history from the hegemony of one perspective.
He wrote on Spinoza, Nietzche, Kant, Leibniz and others, including literary authors and works,
cinema, and art. Deleuze claimed that he did not write “about” art, literature, or cinema, but,
rather, undertook philosophical “encounters” that led him to new concepts. As a constructivist,
he was adamant that philosophers are creators, and that each reading of philosophy, or each
philosophical encounter, ought to inspire new concepts. Additionally, according to Deleuze and
his concepts of difference, there is no identity, and in repetition, nothing is ever the same.
Rather, there is only difference: copies are something new, everything is constantly changing,
and reality is a becoming, not a being.
Table of Contents
1. Biography
2. The History Of Philosophy
1. Two Examples: Kant and Leibniz
3. A New Empiricism
1. Hume
2. Spinoza
3. Nietzsche
4. Deleuze’s Central Empiricist Concepts
4. Difference And Repetition
1. Difference-in-itself
2. Contra-Hegel
3. Repetition and Time
4. The Image of Thought
5. Capitalism And Schizophrenia – Deleuze And Guattari
6. Literature, Cinema, Painting
1. Literature
1. Marcel Proust
2. Leopold von Sacher-masoch
3. Franz Kafka
2. Cinema
3. Painting
7. What Is Philosophy?
1. Early Reflections – Naturalism
2. “What is Philosophy?” – Constructivism
8. References and Further Reading
1. Main texts
2. Secondary texts
1. Books and Collections of Essays
2. Additional Uncollected Articles

1. Biography
Gilles Deleuze was born in the 17th arrondisment of Paris, a district that, excepting periods in his
youth, he lived in for the whole of his life. He was the son of an conservative, anti-Semitic
engineer, a veteran of World War I. Deleuze’s brother was arrested by Germans during the Nazi
occupation of France for alleged resistance activities, and died on the way to Auschwitz.
Due to his families’ lack of money, Deleuze was schooled at a public school before the war.
When the Germans invaded France, Deleuze was on vacation in Normandy and spent a year
being schooled there. In Normandy, he was inspired by a teacher, under whose influence he read
Gide, Baudelaire and others, becoming for the first time interested in his studies. In a late
interview, he states that after this experience, he never had any trouble academically. After
returning to Paris and finishing his high school education, Deleuze attended the Lycée Henri IV,
where he did his kâgne, an intensive year of study for students of promise, in 1945, and then
studied philosophy at the Sorbonne with figures such as Jean Hippolyte and Georges
Canguilheim. He passed his agrégation in 1948, necessary for entry into the teaching profession,
and taught in a number of high schools until 1956. In this year, he also married Denise Paul
“Fanny” Grandjouan, a French translator of D.H. Lawrence. His first book, Empiricism and
Subjectivity, on David Hume, was published in 1953, when he was 28.
Over the next ten years, Deleuze held a number of assistant teaching positions in French
universities, publishing his important text on Nietzsche (Nietzsche and Philosophy) in 1962. It
was also around this time that he met Michel Foucault, with whom he had a long and important
friendship. When Foucault died, Deleuze dedicated a book-length study to his work (Foucault
1986). In 1968, Deleuze’s doctoral thesis, comprising of Difference and Repetition and
Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza were published. This was also the period of the first major
incidence of pulmonary illness that would plague Deleuze for the rest of his life.
In 1969, Deleuze took up a teaching post at the ‘experimental’ University of Paris VII, where he
taught until his retirement in 1987. In the same year, he met Félix Guattari, with whom he wrote
a number of influential texts, notably the two volumes of Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Anti-
Oedipus (1972) and A Thousand Plateaus (1980). These texts were considered by many
(including Deleuze) to be an expression in part of the political ferment in France during May
1968. During the seventies, Deleuze was politically active in a number of causes, including
membership in the Groupe d’information sur les prisons (formed, with others, by Michel
Foucault), and had an engaged concern with homosexual rights and the Palestinian liberation
movement.
In the eighties, Deleuze wrote a number of books on cinema (the influential studies The
Movement-Image (1983) and The Time-Image (1985)) and on painting (Francis Bacon (1981)).
Deleuze’s final collaboration with Guattari, What is Philosophy?, was published in 1991
(Guattari died in 1992).
Deleuze’s last book, a collection of essays on literature and related philosophical questions,
Essays Critical and Clinical, was published in 1993. Deleuze’s pulmonary illness, by 1993, had
confined him quite severely, even making it difficult for him to write. He took his own life on
November 4th, 1995.
2. The History Of Philosophy
Deleuze’s whole intellectual trajectory can be traced by his shifting relationship to the history of
philosophy. While in later years, he became quite critical of both the style of thought implied in
narrow reproductions of past thinkers and the institutional pressures to think on this basis,
Deleuze never lost any enthusiasm for writing books about other philosophers, if in a new way.
Most of his publications contain the name of another philosopher as part of the title: Hume, Kant,
Spinoza, Nietzsche, Bergson, Leibniz, Foucault.
Deleuze expresses two main problems with the traditional style and institutional location of the
history of philosophy. The first concerns a politics of the tradition:
The history of philosophy has always been the agent of power in philosophy, and even in
thought. It has played the repressors role: how can you think without having read Plato,
Descartes, Kant and Heidegger, and so-and-so’s book about them? A formidable school of
intimidation which manufactures specialists in thought – but which also makes those who stay
outside conform all the more to this specialism which they despise. An image of thought called
philosophy has been formed historically and it effectively stops people from thinking. (D 13)
This hegemony of thought recurrently comes under attack later in Deleuze’s career, notably in
What is Philosophy? This criticism also sits well with a general theme throughout his writings,
which is the immediate politicisation of all thought. Philosophy and its history is not separated
from the fortunes of the wider world, for Deleuze, but intimately linked to it, and to the forces at
work there.
The second criticism directed at the traditional style of history of philosophy, the construction of
specialists and expertise, leads directly to the foremost positive aspect of Deleuze’s particular
method: “What we should in fact do, is stop allowing philosophers to reflect ‘on’ things. The
philosopher creates, he doesn’t reflect.” (N122) And this creation, with regard to other writers,
takes the form of a portrait:
The history of philosophy isn’t a particularly reflective discipline. It’s rather like portraiture in
painting. Producing mental, conceptual portraits. As in painting, you have to create a likeness,
but in a different material: the likeness is something you have to produce, rather than a way of
reproducing anything (which comes down to just repeating what a philosopher says). (N 136)
Perhaps such a method does not seem extremely creative, or perhaps only in a relatively passive
sense. For Deleuze, however, the history of philosophy also embraces a much more active,
constructive sense. Each reading of a philosopher, an artist, a writer should be undertaken,
Deleuze tells us, in order to provide an impetus for creating new concepts that do not pre-exist
(DR vii).
Thus the works that Deleuze studies are seen by him as inspirational, but also as a resource, from
which the philosopher can gather the concepts that seem the most useful and give them a new
life, along with the force to develop new, non-preexistent concepts.
In an important sense, Deleuze’s whole modus operandi is based in this revaluation of the role of
other thinkers, and the means by which one can use them: each of his books either centers around
one philosopher, or derives much of its texture from references to others. In any case, new
concepts are derived from others’ works, or old ones are recreated or ‘awakened’, and put to a
new service.
a. Two examples: Kant and Leibniz
Deleuze’s book on Kant, his third publication (1963) in general conforms with the standards of
an academic philosophical study. Aside from its surprising breadth, covering as it does all three
of Kant’s Critiques in a slender volume, it focuses on a problem that is clearly of concern to both
Kant himself and the traditional reading of his work, that of the relationship between the
faculties. Deleuze himself, later reflecting on Kant’s Critical Philosophy, distinguishes it from
the other, more constructivist historical studies:
My book on Kant’s different; I like it, I did it as a book about an enemy that tries to show how
his system works, its various cogs – the tribunal of Reason, the legitimate exercises of the
faculties. (N 6)
There are, however, some distinctively creative elements even to this apparently sober study,
which reflect Deleuze’s general interests, two in particular. In this text on Kant, these reveal
themselves by way of emphasis, rather than out-and-out creation.
The first of these is his emphasis on Kant’s rejections of transcendentality at key points in the
Critiques, in favour of a generalised pragmatism of reason. While Deleuze himself locates in
Kant the development of the concept of the transcendental at the root of modern philosophy (DR
135), he is quick to insist that, even as transcendental faculties in Kant, understanding, reason
and imagination act only in an immanent fashion to achieve their own ends:
. . . the so-called transcendental method is always the determination of an immanent employment
of reason, conforming to one of its interests. The Critique of Pure Reason thus condemns the
transcendent employment of a speculative reason which claims to legislate by itself; the Critique
of Practical Reason condemns the transcendent employment of practical reason which, instead
of legislating by itself, lets itself be empirically conditioned. (KCP 36-7; cf. KCP 24-5; NP 91)
Deleuze, then, insists on the critical activity of Kant’s philosophy as not only a critique of reason
used wrongly, but specifies this critique in pragmatic and empiricist terms.
The second Deleuzian feature of Kant’s Critical Philosophy is its insistence on the creative and
affirmative nature of the Critique of Judgement. This runs counter not just to a number of Kant
scholars, who suggest that the third Critique is a defected work as a result of Kant’s age and
decaying mental abilities when he wrote it, but also other prominent French philosophers of
Deleuze’s generation, notably Jean-Francois Lyotard and Jacques Derrida, who both consider
this text primarily in terms of its aporetic nature.
Deleuze, to the contrary, insists on its central importance to Kant’s philosophy. He argues not
only that there are conflicts between the activity of the faculties, and thus between the first two
Critiques, a moot point in reading Kant, but that the Critique of Judgement solves this problem
(already a controversial perspective) by positing a genesis of free accord between the faculties
deeper than their conflicts. Not only are the struggles between the faculties not insoluble: there is
in fact an affirmative creation of a resolution that does not rely upon any transcendental faculty.
When we turn to consider a much later text, The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, we find
Deleuze’s constructivist practice of the history of philosophy developed to its fullest. This text is
not only a “portrait” of Leibniz’s thought, but uses concepts drawn from it, along with new
concepts based in a philosophical ‘take’ on mathematics, art, and music, to characterise the
Baroque period, and indeed vice versa. Leibniz, Deleuze argues, is the philosopher whose point
of view can be best used to understand the Baroque period, and Baroque architecture, music and
art give us a unique and illuminating vantage point for reading Leibniz. In fact, one of the more
astonishing claims that Deleuze makes is that the one cannot be understood properly without the
other:
It is impossible to understand the Leibnizian monad, and its light-mirror-point of view-interior
decoration system, if we do not come to terms with these elements in Baroque architecture. (FLB
39; translation altered)
How is such a statement to be demonstrated? Instead of claiming that in fact there is an a priori
link between Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze creates a new concept, and reads both of them
through it: this is the concept of the fold. In keeping with Leibniz’s theory of the monad, that the
whole universe is contained within each being, like the Baroque church, Deleuze argues that the
process of folding constitutes the basic unit of existence. While there are elements of the fold
already in Leibniz and the architecture and art of the period, as Deleuze points out (N 157), it
gains a new consistency and significance when used as a creative term in this manner.
Throughout the book, and later, in Foucault, Deleuze uses the concept of the fold to describe the
nature of the human subject as the outside folded in: an immanently political, social, embedded
subject.
In addition, in The Fold, we see a remarkable cross-section of Deleuze’s whole work, expressed
in a new way through the material that he analyses. Chapters 4 and 6 give a succinct formulation
of the relationship between the event and the subject (one of Deleuze’s perennial interests),
which leads to a new formulation of the nature of sufficient reason in line with Deleuze’s
concept of the virtual. We also see a return to the question of the body that he examines with
Guattari in Capitalism and Schizophrenia. (FLB sec III: ‘Having a body’), which reinstates the
work of Leibniz on the level of the material, rather than in the realm of idealism.
Deleuze thus provides a reading of Leibniz that strikes the reader as eccentric and certainly at
odds with the traditional approach, and yet which holds to both the text (in all his historical
studies, Deleuze cites quite exhaustively), and to the new direction that he is working in.
3. A New Empiricism
In the English preface to the Dialogues, Deleuze writes the following:
I have always felt that I am an empiricist . . . [My empiricism] is derived from the two
characteristics by which Whitehead defined empiricism: the abstract does not explain, but must
itself be explained; and the aim is not to rediscover the eternal or the universal, but to find the
conditions under which something new is produced (creativeness). (D vii; cf. N 88; WP 7)
One can see that such a definition of empiricism differs sharply, at least apparently, from the
traditional understanding canonised by Anglo-American histories of philosophy. Such a history
would have us believe that empiricism is above all the doctrine that whatever knowledge that we
possess is derived from the senses and the senses alone – the well-known rejection of innate
ideas. Modern views of science embrace such a doctrine, and apply it as a tool to derive facts
about the physical world.
Deleuze’s empiricism is both an extreme radicalisation and rejection of this sense-data model:
“Empiricism is by no means . . . a simple appeal to lived experience.” (DR xx; cf. PI 35). Rather,
it takes a standpoint regarding the transcendental in general. Writing of Hume, he states that, We
can now see the special ground of empiricism: . . . nothing is ever transcendental.” (ES 24) To
claim that knowledge is derived from the senses alone and not from ideas which exist in the
mind prior to experience (as is argued in a long tradition from Plato to Descartes and beyond,
lingering in the discourse of modern science) is indeed a rejection of a certain transcendentality
of the mind, but for Deleuze, this is only the very first moment of a radical displacement of all
transcendentals that is central in all of his work: questioning the supremacy of reason as the a
priori privileged way of relating to the world, questioning the link between freedom and will,
attempting to abolish dualisms from ontology, reinstating politics prior to Being.
To return to the citation from the Dialogues, there are two aspects of Deleuze’s empiricist
philosophy. The first is the rejection of all transcendentals, but the second is an active element:
for Deleuze, empiricism is always about creating. In terms of philosophy, the creation par
excellence is the creation of concepts: “Empiricism is by no means a reaction against concepts . .
. On the contrary, it undertakes the most insane creation of concepts ever.” (DR xx) This idea of
philosophy as an empiricist creation of concepts, or constructivism, is taken up again in What is
Philosophy?, and is present, as noted above, in all of his historical studies of philosophers.
These two facets of empiricism are throughout Deleuze’s work, and it is in this sense that his
claim about being such a philosopher is clearly true. Deleuze primarily developed this point of
view through the texts he wrote prior to 1968, and particularly through three other philosophers,
who he reads as empiricists in the sense mentioned: Hume, Spinoza and Nietzsche.
a. Hume
Deleuze’s first publication, Empiricism and Subjectivity (1953) is a book about David Hume,
who is generally considered the foremost and most rigorous British empiricist, according to the
general ’sense-data’ model described above. Deleuze, however, takes Hume to be far more
radical than he is normally considered to be. While this text very carefully reads Hume’s works,
especially the Treatise of Human Nature, the portrait that emerges is quite strikingly
idiosyncratic.
On Deleuze’s account, Hume is above all a philosopher of subjectivity. His central concern is to
establish the basis upon which the subject is formed. All the well-known arguments about habit,
causation and miracles reveal a more profound question: if there is nothing transcendental, how
are we to understand the self-aware, creative self who seems to govern the nature that he
somehow has sprung up from? Deleuze argues then that the relation between human nature and
nature is Hume’s central concern (ES 109).
Deleuze develops this argument by asserting precisely the opposite of the traditional reading of
Hume:
According to Hume, and also Kant, the principles of knowledge are not derived from experience.
But in the case of Hume, nothing is transcendental, because these principles are simply
principles of our nature . . . (ES 111-2)
Kant proposed transcendental operations of categories in order to make experience possible,
criticising Hume for thinking that we could have unified knowledge of an empirical flux that we
only passively receive. On Deleuze’s reading, however, Hume did not suppose that there were no
unifying processes at work, on the contrary. The difference is that for Hume, these principles are
natural; they do not rely upon the postulation of a priori structures of experience.
The question of the subject is resolved by Hume, according to Deleuze, by the creation of a
number of key concepts: association, belief, and the externality of relations. Association is the
principle of nature which operates by establishing a relation between two things. The
imagination is affected by this principle to create a new unity, which can in turn be used later on
to come to conclusions about other ideas that this unity resembles, is closely related to, or seems
to cause. If we consider the traditional example of the balls on a pool table, the process of
association allows a subject to form a relation of causality between one ball and the next, so that
the next time one ball comes into contact with another, an expectation that the second ball will
move is created.
Thus Hume, for Deleuze, considers the mind to be a system of associations alone, a network of
tendencies (ES 25): “We are habits, nothing but habits – the habit of saying ‘I’. Perhaps there is
no more striking answer to the problem of the Self.” (ES x.) The mind, affected by the natural
principle of association, becomes human nature, from the ground up:
Empirical subjectivity is constituted in the mind under the influence of the principles affecting it;
the mind therefore does not have the characteristics of a preexisting subject. (ES 29)
These associations account not only for experience in the basic sense, but up to the highest level
of social and cultural life: this is the basis for Hume’s rejection of a social contract model of
society (such as Hobbes’), in favour of convention alone. Morals, feelings, bodily comportment,
all of these elements of subjectivity are explained, not by transcendental structures, such as Kant
will propose, but the immanent activity of association.
Once this habitual structure of the self is in place, Deleuze suggests, the Humean concept of
belief comes into play, which is resolutely a central part of human nature. It describes the
particularly human way of going beyond the given. When we expect the sun to come up
tomorrow, we do not do so because we know that it will, but because of a belief based on a habit.
This in turn reverses the hierarchy of knowledge and belief, and results, for Deleuze, in a, “great
conversion of theory to practice.” (PI 36) Every act of belief is a practical application of habit,
without any reference to an a priori ability to judge. Not only is the human being thus habitual,
on Deleuze’s reading, but also creative, even in the most mundane moments of life.
Finally, Deleuze insists that one of Hume’s greatest contributions to modern philosophy is his
insistence that all relations are external to their terms: this is the essence of Hume’s anti-
transcendental stance. Human nature cannot unite itself, there is no ‘I’ which stands before
experience, but only moments of experience themselves, unattached and meaningless without
any necessary relation to each other. A flash of red, a movement, a gust of wind, these elements
must be externally related to each other to create the sensation of a tree in autumn. In the social
world, this externality attests to the always-already interested nature of life: no relation is
necessary, or governed by neutral laws, so every relation has a localised and passional motive.
The ways in which habits are formed attests to the desires at the heart of our social milieu.
Subjectivity, as Deleuze describes it through his reading of Hume, is a practical, passional,
empiricist concept, immediately located at the heart of the conventional, which is to say the
social.
b. Spinoza
While Hume may not be a contentious name to link with a deepened empiricism, Benedict de
Spinoza certainly is. Generally considered the arch-rationalist par excellence, Spinoza is most
well known for the first main thesis proposed in his Ethics: that there is one substance, God or
Nature, and that everything that exists is merely a modulation of this substance. His style of
writing, known as the ‘geometric method’, is composed by propositions, proofs, and axioms.
Such a point of view hardly seems consistent with a radical construction of concepts, and an
essential pragmatism: and yet this is what Deleuze’s interpretation of Spinoza, which has been
very influential (as recent texts such as those by Geneveive Lloyd and Moira Gatens
demonstrate), argues.
Spinoza is without a doubt the philosopher most praised and referred to by Deleuze, often with
words that are rarely a part of philosophical writing. For example:
Spinoza is, for me, the ‘prince’ of philosophers. (EPS 11)
Spinoza is the Christ of philosophers, and the greatest philosophers are hardly more than
apostles who distance themselves from or draw near to this mystery. (WP 60)
Spinoza: the absolute philosopher, whose Ethics is the foremost book on concepts. (N 140)
Spinoza’s greatness for Deleuze comes precisely from his development of a philosophy based on
the two features of empiricism discussed above. Indeed, for Deleuze, Spinoza combines the two
things into one movement: a rejection of the transcendental in the action of creating a plane of
absolute immanence upon which all that exists situate themselves. In more Spinozist language,
we can refer to the thesis of a single substance instead of a plane of immanence; all bodies
(beings) are modal expressions of the one substance (SPP 122).
But not only is The Ethics for Deleuze the creation of a plane of immanence, it is the creation of
a whole regime of new concepts that revolve around the rejection of the transcendental in all
spheres of life. The unity of the ontological and the ethical is crucial, for Deleuze, in
understanding Spinoza, that is:
Spinoza didn’t entitle his book Ontology, he’s too shrewd for that, he entitles it Ethics. Which is
a way of saying that, whatever the importance of my speculative propositions may be, you can
only judge them at the level of the ethics that they envelope or imply [impliquer].
In short, as the title of one of Deleuze’s books, Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, indicates, the
Ethics is only understood when it is seen, at one and the same time, to be theoretical and
practical. Deleuze considers there to be three primary theoretico-practical points in the Ethics:
The great theories of the Ethics . . . cannot be treated apart from the three practical theses
concerning consciousness, values and the sad passions (SPP 28)
First of all, the illusion of consciousness. Spinoza argues that we are not the cause of our
thoughts and actions, but only assume that we are based on their affects upon us. This leads to
dualisms of substance (such as Descartes’ mind/body split). Deleuze insists on this point because
he sees Spinoza bypassing an important illusion of subjectivity: we suppose that we are causes
and not effects.
The illusion of consciousness, for Spinoza a result of inadequate knowledge and sad affects,
allows us to posit a transcendental consciousness supposedly free from the interventions of the
world (as in Descartes). This is in fact a blind-spot which precludes us from knowing ourselves
as caused, the practical meaning of which is that we deny our own ’sociality’, as one mode
amongst others, and the significance of the relations that we enter into, which actually determine
our power to act, and our ability to experience active joy.
The second is the critique of morality. Spinoza’s Ethics, for Deleuze, constitutes a rejection of
the transcendent Good/Evil distinction in favour of a merely functional opposition between good
and bad. Good and Evil, for Spinoza as for Lucretius and Nietzsche, are the illusions of a
moralistic world-view that does nothing but reduce our power to act and encourages the
experience of the sad passions (SPP 25; LS 275-8). The Ethics is for Deleuze rather an
incitement to consider encounters between bodies on the basis of their relative ‘goodness’ for
those modes that are relating. The shark enters into a good relation with salt water, which
increases its power to act, but for fresh water fish, or for a rose bush, salt water only degrades the
characteristic relations between the parts of the bush and threatens to destroy its existence.
So actions have no transcendental scale to be measured upon (the theological illusion), but only
relative and perspectival good and bad assessments, based on specific bodies. Thus the Ethics is,
for Deleuze, an ‘ethology’, that is, a guide to obtaining the best relations possible for bodies.
Finally, Deleuze sees in Spinoza the rejection of the sad passions. This point is linked to the last,
and again closely related to Nietzsche’s critique of ressentiment and slave morality. Sad passions
are for Spinoza all those forces which disparage life. For Deleuze, Spinoza,
denounces all the falsifications of life, all the values in the name of which we disparage life. We
do not live, we only lead a semblance of life; we can only think of how to keep from dying, and
our whole life is a death worship. (SPP 26)
The hinge that this practical reading of Spinoza turns on is Deleuze’s angle of approach to the
Ethics. Rather than emphasising the great theoretical structures found in the first few sections,
Deleuze emphasises the later part of the book (particularly part V), which consists in arguments
from the point of view of individual modes. This approach puts the importance on the reality of
individuals rather than form, and on the practical rather than the theoretical. In the preface to the
English translation of Expressionism in Philosophy, he writes:
What interested me most in Spinoza wasn’t his Substance, but the composition of finite
modes . . . That is: the hope of making substance turn on finite modes, or at least of seeing in
substance a plane of immanence in which finite modes operate . . .” (EPS 11)
Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza has clear and profound relations with all that he wrote after 1968,
especially the two volumes of Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
c. Nietzsche
Aside from Spinoza, Nietzsche is the most important philosopher for Deleuze. His name, and
central concepts that he created appear almost without exception in all of Deleuze’s books. It
would also be accurate to say that he reads both Spinoza and Nietzsche together, one through the
other, and thus highlights the profound continuity of their thought.
The most significant work that Deleuze did with Nietzsche was his highly influential study
Nietzsche and Philosophy, the first book in France to systematically defend and explicate
Nietzsche’s work, still suspected of fascism, after the second World War. This text was and is
extremely well regarded by other philosophers, including Jacques Derrida (Derrida 2001), and
Pierre Klossowski, who wrote the other key French study on Nietzsche in the second half of last
century (Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle, which is dedicated to Deleuze).
While Nietzsche and Philosophy does deal with Nietzsche’s polemical targets, its originality and
strength lies in its systematic exposition of the diagnostic elements of his thought. Indeed, one
critique of this text is that it oversystematises a thinker and writer whose style of writing overtly
resists such a summary approach. For Deleuze, however, it has been one of the hallmarks of bad
readings of Nietzsche that they have relied upon a non-philosophical reading, either seeing him
as a writer who attempts to assert other models of thought over philosopher, or, more commonly,
as an obscurantist or (proto-) madman whose books have no coherence or value.
Nietzsche, for Deleuze, develops a symptomatology based on an analysis of forces that is
elaborate, rigorous and systematic. He argues that Nietzsche’s ontology is monist, a monism of
force: “There is no quantity of reality, all reality is already a quantity of force.” (NP 40) This
force, in turn, is solely a force of affirmation, since it expresses only itself and itself to its fullest;
that is, force says ‘yes’ to itself (NP 186). Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche starts from this point,
and accounts for the whole of Nietzsche’s critical typology of negation, sadness, reactive forces
and ressentiment on this basis. The polemical basis of Nietzsche’s work, for Deleuze, is directed
at all that would separate force from acting on its own basis, that is, from affirming itself.
There is not one force, but many, the play and interaction of which forms the basis of existence.
Deleuze argues that the many antagonistic metaphors in Nietzsche’s writing should be
interpreted in light of his pluralist ontology, and not as indications of some sort of psychological
agressivity.
Nietzsche’s ontology, then, retains the suppleness and reliance on difference while remaining
monist. Thus he, for Deleuze, is characterised as an anti-transcendental thinker.
Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche demonstrates the extent to which he rejected the traditional, or
dogmatic image of thought (see (4)(d) below), which relies upon a natural harmony between
thinker, truth and the activity of thought. Thought does not naturally relate to truth at all, but is
rather a creative act (NP xiv), an act of affect, of force on other forces: “As Nietzsche succeeded
in making us understand, thought is creation, not will to truth.” (WP 54) There is no room for
seeing truth as abstract generality (NP 103) in Deleuze’s account of Nietzsche, but rather to see
truth itself as a part of regimes of force, as a matter of value, to be assessed and judged, rather
than as an innate disposition (NP 108).
Once again, in Nietzsche, we are confronted with the problem of considering a philosopher who
is generally considered to be quite foreign to the tradition of empiricist thought, as an empiricist.
As with Spinoza, however, Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche, as he himself indicates, relies upon
his characterisation of empiricist thought: as the rejection of the transcendental, both in ontology
and thought, and the consequent affirmation of thought as creativity.
d. Deleuze’s Central Empiricist Concepts
While Deleuze often refers to the central concepts of empiricism as classically formulated by
Hume in the Treatise (association, habituation, convention etc.) (ES; LS 305-7; DR 70-3; WP
201-2), he also develops, throughout his work, a number of other key concepts which should be
considered as empiricist. The most prominent of these are immanence, constructivism, and
excess.
The key word throughout Deleuze’s writings, as we have seen, to be found in almost all of his
main texts without fail, is immanence. This term refers to a philosophy based around the
empirical real, the flux of existence which has no transcendental level or inherent seperation. His
last text, published a few months before his death, bore the title, “Immanence: a life . . .” (PI 25-
33). Deleuze repeatedly insists that philosophy can only be done well if it approaches the
immanent conditions of that which it is trying to think; this is to say that all thought, in order to
have any real force, must not work by setting up trancendentals, but by creating movement and
consequences:
If you’re talking about establishing new forms of transcendence, new universals, restoring a
reflective subject as the bearer of rights, or setting up a communicative intersubjectivity, then it’s
not much of a philosophical advance. People want to produce ‘consensus’, but consensus is an
ideal that guides opinion, and has nothing to do with philosophy. (N 152; cf. 145; WP chapter 2)
Deleuze’s insistence on the concept of the immanent also has an ontological sense, as we have
seen in his studies of Spinoza and Nietzsche, and which returns later in works such as Difference
and Repetition and Capitalism and Schizophrenia: there is only one substance, and therefore
everything which exists must be considered on the same plane, the same level, and analysed by
way of their relations, rather than by their essence.
Constructivism is the title that Deleuze uses to characterise the movement of thought in
philosophy. This has two senses. Firstly, empiricism, immanent thought, must create movement,
create concepts if it is to be philosophy and not just opinion or consensus. Deleuze and Guattari
cite Nietzsche on this point: “[Philosophers] must no longer accept concepts as a gift, nor merely
purify or polish them, but first make and create them, present them and make them convincing.”
(WP 5)
Secondly, in relation to other philosophy, Deleuze maintains that we do not just repeat what they
have already said (see (2) above): “Empiricism . . . [analyses] the states of things, in such a way
that non-pre-existent concepts can be extracted from them.” (D vii) This constructivism, for
Deleuze, holds weight in all areas of research, as he demonstrates in his studies of literature,
cinema and art (see (6) below).
Constructivism, moreover, does not proceed along any predetermined lines. There is nothing that
is necessary to create, for Deleuze: thought does not have a pre-given orientation (see (4)(b)
below). Empiricist thought is thus always in some sense strategic (LS 17).
The concept of excess takes the place in Deleuze’s thought of the transcendent. Instead of an
object, a table for example, being determined and given its essence by a transcendental concept
or Idea (Plato) which is directly applicable to it, or the application of a transcendental category or
schema (Kant), everything that exists is exceeded by the forces which constitute it. The table
does not have a for-itself, but has existence within a field or territory, which are beyond its
meaning or control. Thus a table exists in a kitchen, which is part of a three-bedroom family
home, which is part of a capitalist society. In addition, the table is used to eat on, linking itself
with the human body, and another produced, consumable item, a hamburger. For Deleuze, one
can always analyse interminably in any direction these relations of force, which always move
beyond the horizon of the object in question.
For Deleuze, however, nothing is exceeded more than subjectivity. This is not a statement of
ontological priority, but bears on the extreme privilege the conscious-to-self subject has had in
the history of Western thought, it is certainly here that Deleuze makes his most significant use of
the concept of excess. Consider, for example: “Subjectivity is determined as an effect.” (ES 26).
“There are no fewer things in the mind that exceed our consciousness than there are things in the
body that exceed our knowledge.” (SPP 18)
The point is that human forces aren’t on their own enough to establish a dominant form in which
man can install himself. Human forces (having an understanding, a will, an imagination and so
on) have to combine with other forces: an overall form arises from this combination, but
everything depends on the nature of other forces with which the human forces become linked. (N
117; cf. especially DR 254; 257-61)
While Deleuze protests that he never made a big deal out of rejecting traditional postulates like
the subject (N 88), he frequently writes about the notion of the exceeded subject, from his first
book on Hume and throughout his work. This in some sense locates him in the landscape of what
is known as postmodern thought, along with other figures such as Jacques Derrida, Jean-Francois
Lyotard and Michel Foucault.
4. Difference And Repetition
Difference and Repetition (1968) is without doubt Deleuze’s most significant book in a
traditional academic style, and proposes the most central of his disruptions to the canonical
traditions of philosophy. However, precisely for this reason, it is also one of his most difficult
books, dealing as it does with two age-old, overdetermined philosophical topics, identity and
time, and with the nature of thought itself.
a. Difference-in-itself
Deleuze’s main aim in Difference and Repetition is a creative elaboration of these two concepts,
but it essentially precedes by way of a critique of Western philosophy. His central thesis is,
That identity not be first, that it exist as a principle but as a second principle, as a principle
become; that it revolve around the Different: such would be the nature of a Copernican
revolution which opens up the possibility of difference having its own concept, rather than being
maintained under the domination of a concept in general already understood as identical. (DR
41)
From Plato (DR 59-63) to Heidegger (DR 64-6), Deleuze argues, difference has not been
accepted on its own, but only after being understood with reference to self-identical objects,
which makes difference a difference between. He attempts in this book to reverse this situation,
and to understand difference-in-itself.
We can understand Deleuze’s argument by way of reference to his analysis of Plato’s three-
tiered system of idea, copy and simulacrum (cf. LS 253-65). In order to define something such as
courage, we can have reference in the end only to the Idea of Courage, an identical-to-itself, this
idea containing nothing else (DR 127). Courageous acts and people can be thus judged by
analogy with this Idea. There are also, however, those who only imitate courageous acts, people
who use courage as a front for personal gain, for example. These acts are not copies of the
courageous ideal, but rather fakes, distortions of the idea. They are not related to the Idea by way
of analogy, but by changing the idea itself, making it slip. Plato frequently makes arguments
based on this system, Deleuze tells us, from the Statesman (God-shepherd, King-shepherd,
charlatan) to the Sophist (wisdom, philosopher, sophist) (DR 60-1; 126-8).
The philosophical tradition, beginning with Plato (although Deleuze detects some ambiguity here
(eg. DR 59; TP 361)) and Aristotle, has sided with the model and the copy, and resolutely fought
to exclude the simulacra from consideration, either by rejecting it as an external error (Descartes
(DR 148)), or by assimilating it into a higher form, via the operation of a dialectic (Hegel (DR
263)).
While difference is subordinated to the model/copy scheme, it can only be a consideration
between elements, which gives to difference a wholly negative determination, as a not-this.
However, Deleuze suggests, if we turn our attention to the simulacra, the reign of the identical
and of analogy is destabilised. The simulacra exists in and of itself, without grounding in or
reference to a model: its existence is “unmediated” (DR 29), it is itself unmediated difference. It
is for this reason that Deleuze makes his well-known claim that a true philosophy of difference
must be “inverted-” or “anti-Platonism” (DR 127-8): the being of simulacra is the being of
difference itself; each simulacra is its own model.
We might well ask here: what provides the unity of the different? How can we talk about the
being of something that is difference itself? Deleuze’s answer is that precisely there is no
intrinsic ontological unity. He takes up here Nietzsche’s idea that being is becoming: there is an
internal self-differing within the different itself, the different differs from itself in each case.
Everything that exists only becomes and never is.
Unity, Deleuze tells us, must be understood as a secondary operation (DR 41) under which
difference is pressed into forms. The prominent philosophical notion he offers for such unity is
time (see (4)(c) below), but later, in Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze and Guattari offer a political
ontology that shows how this process of becoming is fixed into unitary formulations.
b. Contra-Hegel
Deleuze’s arch-enemy in Difference and Repetition is Hegel. While this critical stance is already
clearly evident in Nietzsche and Philosophy and from there throughout his work, Deleuze’s
revaluation of difference itself takes as its most essential form the rejection of the Hegelian
dialectic, which represents the most extreme development of the logic of the identical.
The dialectic, Deleuze tells us, seems to operate with extreme differences alone, even so far as
acknowledging them as the motor of history. Formed of two opposite terms, such as being and
non-being, the dialectic operates by synthesising them into a new third term that preserves and
overcomes the earlier opposition. Deleuze argues that this is a dead end which makes,
identity the sufficient condition for difference to exist and be thought. It is only in relation to the
identical, as a function of the identical, that contradiction is the greatest difference. The
intoxication and giddiness are feigned, the obscure is already clarified from the outset. Nothing
shows this more than the insipid monocentrality of the circles in the Hegelian dialectic. (DR
263)
While offering a philosophical tool that sees difference at the heart of being, the process of the
dialectic removes this affirmation as its most essential step.
The further consequence of this for Deleuze relates to the place of negation in Hegel’s system.
The dialectic, in its general movement, takes specific differences, differences-in-themselves, and
negates their individual being, on the way to a “superior” unity. Deleuze argues in Difference
and Repetition that this step of Hegel’s mistakes ontology, history and ethics.
“Beneath the platitude of the negative lies the world of ‘disparateness’” (DR 267). There is no
resolution of the differences-in-themselves into a higher unity that does not fundamentally
misunderstand difference. Here Deleuze is clearly recalling his Spinozist and Nietzschean
ontology of a single substance that is expressed in a multiplicity of ways (cf. DR 35-42; 269): In
a famous sentence, he writes: “A single voice raises the clamour of being.” (DR 35)
Hegel is famous for asserting that the negating dialectic is the motor of history, proceeding
towards the often-caricatured end of history and the realisation of absolute spirit. For Deleuze,
history does not have a teleological element, a direction of realisation; this is only an illusion of
consciousness (cf. SPP 17-22):
History progresses not by negation and the negation of negation, but by deciding problems and
affirming differences. It is no less bloody and cruel as a result. Only the shadows of history live
by negation . . . (DR 268)
Finally, regarding ethics, Deleuze argues that an ontology based on the negative makes of ethical
affirmation a secondary, derived possibility: “The false genesis of affirmation . . .: if the truth be
told, none of this would amount to much if it was not for the moral presuppositions and practical
implications of such a distortion.” (DR 268)
c. Repetition and Time
For Deleuze, the central stake in the consideration of repetition is time. As with difference,
repetition has been subjected to the law of the identical, but also to a prior model of time: to
repeat a sentence means, traditionally, to say the same thing twice, at different moments. These
different moments must be themselves equal and unbiased, as if time were a flat, featureless
expanse. So repetition has essentially been considered as the traditional idea of difference over
time understood in a common-sense way, as a succession of moments. Deleuze asks if, given a
renovated understanding of difference as in-itself, we are able to reconsider repetition also. But
there is also an imperative here, since, if we are to consider difference-in-itself over time, based
in the traditional logic of repetition, we once again reach the point of identity. As such,
Deleuze’s critique of identity must revaluate the question of time.
Deleuze’s argument proceeds through three models of time, and relates the concept of repetition
to each of them.
The first is time as a circle. Circular time is mythical and seasonal time, the repetition of the
same after time has passed through its cardinal points. These points may be simple natural
repetitions, like the sun rising daily, the movement of summer to spring, or the elements of
tragedy, which Deleuze suggests operate cyclically. There is a sense of both destiny and theology
in the concept of time as a circle, as a succession of instants which are governed by an external
law.
When time is considered in this fashion, Deleuze argues (DR 70-9), repetition is solely
concerned with habit. The subject experiences the passing of moments cyclically (the sun will
come up every morning), and contracts habits which make sense of time as a continually living
present. Habit is thus the passive synthesis of moments that creates a subject.
The second model of time is linked by Deleuze to Kant (KCP vii-viii), and it constitutes one of
the central ruptures that the Kantian philosophy creates in thought, for Deleuze: this is time as a
straight line. In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant liberates time from the circular model by
proposing it as a form that is imposed upon sensory experience. For Deleuze, this reverses the
earlier situation by placing events into time (as a line), rather than seeing the chain of events
constituting time by the passing of present moments.
Habit can thus no longer have any power, since in this model of time, nothing returns. In order
for sense to be made of what has occurred, there must be an active process of synthesis, which
makes of the past instances a meaning (DR 81). Deleuze calls this second synthesis memory.
Unlike habit, memory does not relate to a present, but to a past which has never been present,
since it synthesises from passing moments a form in-itself of things which never existed before
the operation. The novels of Marcel Proust are for Deleuze the most profound development of
memory as the pure past, or in Proust’s terminology, as time regained. (DR 122; PS passim)
In this second model of time, repetition thus has an active sense in line with the synthesis, since
it repeats something, in the memory, that did not exist before – this does not save it, however,
from being an operation of identity, nonetheless. These two moments, the active constitution of a
pure past, and the disparate experience of a present yet to be synthesised produces a further
consequence for Deleuze: as in Kant, a radical splitting of the subject into two elements, the I of
memory, which is only a process of synthesis, and a self of experience, an ego which undergoes
experience. (DR 85-7; KCP viii-ix)
Deleuze insists that both of these models of time press repetition into the service of the identical,
and make it a secondary process with regards to time. The final model of time that Deleuze
proposes attempts to make repetition itself the form of time.
In order to do this, Deleuze relates the concepts of difference and repetition to each other. If
difference is the essence of that which exists, constituting beings as disparates, then neither of
the first two models of time does justice to them, insisting as they do on the possibility and even
necessity of synthesising differences into identities. It is only when beings are repeated as
something other that their disparateness is revealed. Consequently, repetition cannot be
understood as a repetition of the same, and becomes liberated from subjugation under the
demands of traditional philosophy.
To give body to the conception of repetition as the pure form of time, Deleuze turns to the
Nietzschean concept of the eternal return. This difficult concept is always given a forceful and
careful qualification by Deleuze whenever he writes about it (eg. DR 6;41; 242; PI 88-9; NP 94-
100): that it must not be considered as the movement of a cycle, as the return of the identical. As
a form of time, the eternal return is not the circle of habit, even on the cosmic level. This would
only allow the return of something that already existed, of the same, and would result again in
the suppression of difference through an inadequate concept of repetition.
While habit returned the same in each instance, and memory dealt with the creation of identity in
order to allow experience to be remembered, the eternal return is, for Deleuze, only the repetition
of that which differs-from-itself, or, in Nietzsche’s terminology, only the repetition of those
beings whose being is becoming: “The subject of the eternal return is not the same but the
different, not the similar but the dissimilar, not the one but the many . . .” (DR 126)
As such, Deleuze tells us, repetition as the third meaning of time takes the form of the eternal
return. Everything that exists as a unity will not return, only that which differs-from-itself.
“Difference inhabits repetition.” (DR 76). So, while habit was the time of the present, and
memory the being of the past, repetition as the eternal return is the time of the future.
The superiority of this third understanding of repetition as time has two main impetuses in
Deleuze’s argument. The first is obviously that it keeps difference intact in its movement of
differing-from-itself. The second is as significant, if for different reasons. If only what differs
returns, then the eternal return operates selectively (DR 126; PI 88-9), and this selection is an
affirmation of difference, rather than an activity of representation and unification based on the
negative, as in Hegel.
d. The Image of Thought
Chapter three of Difference and Repetition provides a novel approach to an important question in
philosophy, the problem of presuppositions. Deleuze pursues this topic again later in A
Thousand Plateaus (374-80), and when he writes about conceptual personae in What is
Philosophy? (ch. 3); he had already written on images of thought in Nietzsche and Philosophy
(103-10) and Proust and Signs (94-102).
An example is Descartes’ celebrated phrase at the beginning of the Discourse on the Method:
Good sense is the most evenly shared thing in the world . . the capacity to judge correctly and to
distinguish the true from the false, which is properly what one calls common sense or reason, is
naturally equal in all men . .
For Descartes, thought has a natural orientation towards truth, just as for Plato, the intellect is
naturally drawn towards reason and recollects the true nature of that which exists. This, for
Deleuze, is an image of thought.
Although images of thought take the common form of an ‘Everybody knows . . .’ (DR 130), they
are not essentially conscious. Rather, they operate on the level of the social and the unconscious,
and function, “all the more effectively in silence.” (DR 167)
Deleuze undertakes a thorough analysis of the traditional philosophical image of thought, and
lists eight features which, in all aspects of philosophical pursuit, imply a subordination of
thought to externally imposed directives. He includes the good nature of thought, the priority of
the model or recognition as the means of thought, the sovereignty of representation over
supposed elements in nature and thought, and the subordination of culture to method (or learning
to knowledge). These all imply an a priori nature of thought, a telos, a meaning and a logic of
practice. These features,
crush thought under an image which is that of the Same and the Similar in representation, but
profoundly betrays what it means to think and alienates the two powers of difference and
repetition, of philosophical commencement and recommencement. (DR167)
It is this element, in Difference and Repetition, that founds Deleuze’s most serious criticism of
the traditional image of thought: that it fails to come to terms with the true nature of difference
and repetition. As a result, it is fair to say that this moment of the book is essential for
understanding the way in which Deleuze both wants to base his assessment of traditional
philosophies of identity and time, and how he wishes to exceed them: his reformulation of
difference and repetition is made possible by this critique (cf. N 149).
The other critical angle Deleuze supplies here is related to the first, and derives from Nietzsche’s
critique of Western thought:
When Nietzsche questions the most general presuppositions of philosophy, he says that these are
essentially moral, since Morality alone is capable of convincing us that thought has a good
nature and the thinker a good will, and that only the good can ground the supposed affinity
between thought and the True. (DR132; cf. LS 3)
As we saw above regarding Hegel, the real point of concern is that this image of thought is in the
service of practical, political and moral forces, it is not simply a matter of philosophy, in
segregation from the rest of the world.
To the question ‘why do we have this image of thought?’ Deleuze, along with Nietzsche, that it
is a moral image, and is in the service of power, but there is also a more intrinsic problem with
thinking itself, that is only fully developed in the Conclusion to What is Philosophy?, and this is
that thought itself is dangerous.
In contradistinction to the natural goodness of thought in the traditional image, Deleuze argues
for thought as an encounter: “Something in the world forces us to think.” (DR 139) These
encounters confront us with the impotence of thought itself (DR 147), and evoke the need of
thought to create in order to cope with the violence and force of these encounters. The traditional
image of thought has developed, just as Nietzsche argues about the development of morality in
The Genealogy of Morals, as a reaction to the threat that these encounters offer. We can consider
the traditional image of thought, then, precisely as a symptom of the repression of this violence.
As a result, the relationship of philosophy to thought must have two correlative aspects, Deleuze
argues:
an attack on the traditional moral image of thought, but also a movement towards understanding
thought as self-engendering, an act of creation, not just of what is thought, but of thought itself,
within thought (DR 147).
This is true, dangerous thought, but the sole thought capable of approaching difference-in-itself
and complex repetition: thought without an image. .
The thought which is born in thought, the act of thinking which is neither given by innateness
nor presupposed by reminiscence but engendered in its genitality, is a thought without image.
But what is such a thought, and how does it operate in the world? (DR 167; cf. 132)
This final question directs us towards the central aim of the two texts of Capitalism and
Schizophrenia.
5. Capitalism And Schizophrenia – Deleuze And Guattari
The collaborative texts of Deleuze and Felix Guattari, particularly the two volumes of
Capitalism and Schizophrenia, are outside of the scope of the current article (see the Deleuze and
Guattari entry in this encyclopaedia, forthcoming). However, two brief points are important to
note.
First, that despite the wide notoriety of these works as obscurantist and non-philosophical, they
bear a profound relation to Deleuze’s philosophical enterprise in general, and develop in new
ways many of his concerns: a commitment to an immanent ontology, the importance of the social
and the political to the very heart of being, and the affirmation of difference over the
transcendental hierarchy in every aspect of this work.
Secondly, the manner in which these texts are written by the two writers, between the two and
not seperately, means that many new elements emerge that cannot be drawn from their work
individually. As such, regarding Deleuze, many of the central ideas cited above do undergo an
interesting and novel transformation into a new direction: the very type of relationship
characterised in Capitalism and Schizophrenia as a becoming.
6. Literature, Cinema, Painting
Deleuze’s work on the arts, he never ceases to remind the reader, are not to be understood as
literary criticism, film or art theory. Talking of the 1980’s, during which he wrote almost
exclusively on the arts, he states the following:
let’s suppose that there’s a third period when I worked on painting and cinema: images on the
face of it. But I was writing philosophy. (N 137)
This accords with the aims of Deleuze’s empiricism (see (3) above), to understand philosophy as
an encounter (with a work, philosophical or artistic, an object, a person) out of which “non-pre-
existent concepts,” (DR vii) can be created. Regarding his books on cinema, he is even more
explicit:
Film criticism faces twin dangers: it shouldn’t just describe films but nor should it apply to them
concepts taken from outside film. The job of criticism is to form concepts that aren’t of course
‘given’ in films but nonetheless relate specifically to cinema, and to some specific genre of film,
to some specific film or other. Concepts specific to cinema, but which can only be formed
philosophically. (N 58; C2 280)
All of Deleuze’s work on artists can be assembled under the rubric of the creation of new
philosophical concepts that relate specifically to the work at hand, yet which also link these
works with others more generally. Not a philosophy of the arts per se, but a philosophical
encounter with specific artistic works and forms.
One feature that the artistic works also contain, distinct from many of Deleuze’s other books, is a
concern with a taxonomy of signs. In Proust and Signs, Francis Bacon, and the Cinema books,
Deleuze attempts to develop a systematic approach of classifying different signs. These signs are
not linguistic (C1 ix), since they are not themselves elements of a system, but rather are types of
emissions from a work. Proust, for example, on Deleuze’s account, understands experience itself
as a reception of signs by a proto-subject which must be understood properly, just as the large
variety of images discussed in Cinema 1 and 2 are categorised by Deleuze on the basis of C.S.
Pierce’s semiotics.
Deleuze often comes to consider the questions ‘what is the nature of the artist, and of art?’ Aside
from his specific elaborations of these questions in What is Philosophy?, he is concerned to
emphasise the radically active creative nature of art and artists in his work in general. This
characterisation goes far beyond the general consideration of artists as ‘creative people’, and
highlights the manner in which art is itself a creation of movement, not of representations: that is,
something radically new, an affect, a movement of force or desire (cf. PS xi.,187 n1).
While the dominant Western tradition, from Plato to Heidegger, places art in a relationship to
truth, Deleuze insists in every case on a Nietzschean argument (NP 102-3), that the work of art
only has relations with forces, and that truth is a derivative, secondary formation: art is active.
In another register, Deleuze suggests that artists are themselves created, within thought, and must
be cultured and afflicted by forces which exceed them to develop to the point of creativity (NP
103-9; cf. (4)(d) above). These forces, in turn, account for the frequent frailty of artists and
thinkers. While the work of art sets to work forces of life, the artist themselves has experienced
“too much”, and this wearies and sickens them (D 18; C2 189).
Deleuze’s insistences that the artist is above all someone who creates new ways of being and
perceiving increases in frequency and strength throughout the course of his texts on art and
artists.
a. Literature
Deleuze wrote extensively on literature throughout his career. Aside from dedicating whole
works to Proust (Proust and Signs 1964), Leopold von Sacher-Masoch (”Coldness and
Cruelty”1969), and Kafka (Kafka: Towards a Minor Literature 1975), and a large portion of The
Logic of Sense to Lewis Carroll, he also dealt in some detail with a wide range of figures such as
F. Scott Fizgerald, Herman Melville, Samuel Beckett, Antonin Artaud, Heinrich von Kleist, and
Fyodor Dostoyevsky.
i. Marcel Proust
It is quite easy, if one wishes to attach a philosophical point of view to Marcel Proust’s work, to
see it as a phenomenology of memory and perception, in which his famous text In Search of Lost
Time would be oriented towards an understanding of what underlies and gives substance to
experience and memory.
In essence, Deleuze proposes the opposite of the phenomenological method. He reads Proust’s
work as an anti-logos, that supposes, rather than a transcendental ego which is the necessary
feature of all experience, a passive, receptive subject at the mercy of the signs and symptoms of
the world.
For what does in fact take place in In Search of Lost Time, one and the same story with infinite
variations? It is clear that the narrator sees nothing, hears nothing . . like a spider poised in its
web, observing nothing, but responding to the slightest sign . . . (AO 68)
Rather than memory, the central question of the Search, being based within the subject, and as
the product of certain transcendental operations, it is a creation of something which did not exist
before by way of an original, each-time unique, style of interpretation for experiences (PS 101).
Deleuze uses the term ‘anti-logos’ on the grounds that Proust, as he argues, refuses the
representational model of experience central to Western philosophy:
Everywhere Proust contrasts the world of signs and symptoms with the world of attributes, the
world of hieroglyphs and ideograms with the world of analytic expression, phonetic writing, and
rational thought. What is constantly impugned are the great themes inherited from the Greeks:
philos, sophia, dialogue, logos, phone. (PS 108)
In contrast, Deleuze characterises the Search as a recasting of thought: thought is creative and
not reminiscent (Platonic and phenomenological).
ii. Leopold von Sacher-masoch
Masoch features in a few of Deleuze’s books (K 66-7; D 119-23), but most significantly in his
long study “Coldness and Cruelty”. This early text is a critique of the unity of the clinical and
aesthetic notion “sado-masochism”.
Deleuze argues here that this clinical concept fails to account for the actual writings of the
Maquis de Sade and Sacher-masoch, along with making an unjustified unity from a two quite
distinct groups of symptoms.
Masoch is considered by Deleuze to be an important writer of unusual power, and a master of
suspense, the key literary element of masochism. However, while de Sade has become well-
known, and his writings analysed, Deleuze suggests that our poor understanding of Masoch’s
texts is one of the main culprits in making the confused unity that is sadomasochism. In fact,
according to Deleuze, he offers us a new way of understanding existence by displacing sexuality
into the world of power (M 12). Thus, Deleuze tells us, Masoch was in fact, “a great
anthropologist.” (M 16)
Point by point, Deleuze develops a reading of the two writers, Masoch in particular, that shows
their profound disparity. Alongside this is an analysis of the psychiatric categories of sadism and
masochism that reveals the same lack of common ground.
Sadomasochism is one of these misbegotten names, a semiological howler. We found in every
case that what appeared to be a common ’sign’ linking the two perversions together turned out
on investigation to be in the nature of a mere syndrome which could be further broken down into
irreducibly specific symptoms of the one or the other perversion. (M 134)
In “Coldness and Cruelty”, Deleuze also elaborates a critique of Freud that points in the direction
of Anti-Oedipus, although clearly more limited in scope.
iii. Franz Kafka
Kafka: towards a minor literature can be distinguished from Deleuze’s other texts on literature
in that it was written with Guattari, and it strongly bears the stamp of Anti-Oedipus, published
just three years earlier, and the concepts utilised there. In many ways, it can be read as a
development of the same themes in regard to Kafka’s work.
This text is a marked departure from all of the dominant interpretations of Kafka’s writing,
which is generally considered either psychoanalytically (as a projection of interior guilt onto the
world through writing) or mythically, that is, as a reserve of symbols and closely related to
negative theology and Jewish mysticism. Deleuze and Guattari consider Kafka as a proponent of
a joyful science, of writing as a way of creating a line of flight or freedom from the forms of
domination. They write:
The three worst themes in many interpretations of Kafka are the transcendence of the law, the
interiority of guilt, the subjectivity of enunciation. (K 45)
In contrast, Deleuze and Guattari read Kafka as a proponent of the immanence of desire. The law
is no more than a secondary configuration that traps desire into certain formations: bureaucracy,
of course, is the main example in Kafka’s work, where offices, secretaries, lawyers and bankers
present figures of entrapment.
They also see Kafka as directly targeting the Oedipus complex, the triangle of “daddy-mommy-
me”:
the too-well formed family triangle is really only a conduit for investments of an entirely
different sort that the child endlessly discovers underneath his father, inside his mother, in
himself. The judges, commissioners, bureaucrats, and so on, are not substitutes for the father;
rather, it is the father who is a condensation of all these forces that he submits to and that he
tries to get his son to submit to. (K 11-2)
Thus, for Kafka, according to Deleuze and Guattari, the family are a socially derived unit that
works by trapping the flow of desire. The interiority of guilt is replaced by the exteriority of
subjugation. This is best demonstrated in the analysis of Kafka’s famous short story, The
Metamorphosis (K 14-5).
They also wish to read Kafka, not as a writer of genius, who expresses the superior insight of his
inner sight, but as a writer of minor literature. This is the key concept of Deleuze and Guattari’s
reading of Kafka. Minor literature is a writing that takes a dominant language (German, in
Kafka’s case, French in Beckett’s, and so forth), and pushes it until it becomes a language of
force, and not of signification (K 19). In turn, this connects immediately with the situation of
minorities, minority groups in the first instance, but also the attempts that everyone makes to
create a line of flight outside of majoritarian or molar social formations.
As such, minor literature is an immediately political writing (K 17), which connects the text
immediately to (micro-) political struggle. Thus the third substitution is the collective, that is,
political, nature of enunciation, for the traditional model of the subjective intent behind the
author’s words. Kafka, for Deleuze and Guattari, writes as a node in a field of forces, rather than
a Cartesian cogito, sovereign in the castle of consciousness. “The superiority of Anglo-american
literature”
One clear feature of Deleuze’s relationship to literature is his outspoken appreciation for what he
calls Anglo-American literature, and its superiority over the literature of Europe.
What we find in great English and American novelists is a gift, rare among the French, for
intensities, flows, machine-books, tool-books, schizo-books. (N 23)
The great European tradition in literature is analogous for Deleuze to traditional philosophy: it
always revolves around a relationship to truth, the preservation of some kind of social status quo,
the sovereignty of the author over the text; as Deleuze states, “everybody says “cogito” in the
French novel.”
The strength of Anglo-american literature for Deleuze is rather that it rejects the idea of the book
as a representation of reality, and all of the adjacent problems with the dogmatic image of
literature, and presents the book as a machine, as something which does things, rather than
signifying.
b. Cinema
Part of the reason for the impact of Deleuze’s writings on cinema is simply that he is the first
important philosopher to have devoted such detailed attention to it. Of course, many
philosophers have written about movies, but Deleuze offers an analysis of the cinema itself as an
artistic form, and develops a number of connections between it and other philosophical work.
Deleuze’s first book is entitled Cinema 1: The Movement-Image. It deals with cinema from its
development through to the second World War. For Deleuze, the cinema as an art form is quite
unique, and deals with its subject matter in ways that no other form of art is capable of,
particularly as a way of relating to the experience of space and time.
Deleuze’s analysis begins by coming to new understandings of the concepts of the image and
movement. The image, above all, is not a representation of something, that is, a linguistic sign.
This definition relies upon the age-old Platonic distinction between form and matter, in its
modern Saussurean form of signifier-signified. Rather, Deleuze wants to collapse these two
orders into one, and the image thus becomes expressive and affective: not an image of a body,
but the body as image (C1 58).
This collapse comes about with reference to two philosophers, Henri Bergson and Charles
Sanders Pierce. Deleuze dedicated a book-length study to the former entitled Bergsonism (1968),
and his use of his notions of movement and time in the Cinema texts is already presaged by this
text. Movement for Bergson, Deleuze argues, is not separable from the object which moves: they
are literally the same thing. Thus, no representative relationship can be established without
artificially halting the flow of movement and thus misconstruing the frozen ‘element’ as self-
sufficient. There is only the flow of movement which expresses itself in different ways. Among
other things, this is one of Deleuze’s critiques of phenomenology (C1 56, 60). Thus the early
cinema is characterised for Deleuze by the reign of what he calls the sensory-motor schema. This
schema is the unity of the viewed and the eye that views in dynamic movement.
This model of the movement-image is precisely the nature of cinema, for Deleuze. It does not
falsify movement by extracting segments and stringing them together in a representative fashion,
but creates a wide range of expressive images. It is in order to come to terms with the varieties of
movement-images that Deleuze turns to Pierce, who developed, “the most extraordinary
classifications of images and signs . . .” (C2 30). The main part of Cinema 1 is thus devoted to
using, with some alterations, Pierce’s semiotic classifications to describe the use of movement-
images in cinema, and their centrality before the second World War.
The movement from the first text to Cinema 2: The Time-Image has a significance closely
related to Kant’s so-called Copernican revolution in philosophy. Up until Kant, time was subject
to the events that took place within it, time was a time of seasons and habitual repetition (see (3)
(c) above); it was not able to be considered on its own, but as a measure of movement (C2 34-5;
KCP iv.). One element of Kant’s achievement for Deleuze, as we have seen, is his reversal of the
time-movement relationship: he establishes time itself as an element to which movement must be
subordinated, a pure time.
In the cinema, Deleuze argues, a similar reversal takes place. The historico-cultural reason
behind this reversal is the event of World War two itself. With the great truths of Western culture
put so deeply in question by the before unimaginable methods employed and their forthcoming
results, the sensory-motor apparatus of the movement-image are made to tremble before the
unbearable, the too-much of life’s possibilities, the potential of the present (C2 35). No longer
could the dogmatic truths that had guided society, and cinema to an extent, allow the apparently
‘natural’ movement from one thing to the next in an habitual fashion: ‘natural’ links precisely
lost their efficacy. And with the use of unnatural or false links, which do not follow the sequence
or narrative affect of the movement-image, time itself, the time-image, is manifested in cinema
(Deleuze considers Orson Welles to be the first auteur to make use of the time-image (C2 137)).
Rather than finding time as an, “indirect representation,” (C2 35-6), the viewer experiences the
movement of time itself, which images, scenes, plots and characters presuppose or manifest in
order to gain any sort of movement whatsoever.
Along with this ‘external’ reason, there is also for Deleuze a motivation within cinema itself to
go from the movement-image to the time-image. The movement image has the tendency, thanks
to the habitual experience of movement as normal and centered, to justify itself in relation to
truth: as Deleuze argues with regard to the dogmatic image of thought (see (3)(d) above), there is
the presupposition that thought naturally moves towards truth. Of course, Deleuze suggests,
cinema, when truly creative, never relied upon this presupposition, and yet, “the movement-
image, in its very essence, is answerable to the effect of truth which it invokes while movement
preserves its centres.” (C2 142). In questioning its own presuppositions, Deleuze argues, cinema
moved towards a new, different, way of understanding movement itself, as subordinate to time.
This in turn leads Deleuze to abandon Pierce’s semiotics to a large degree, since it has no room
for the time-image (C2 33-4ff.), and replaces him with Nietzsche. As we have seen in our
consideration of time in Difference and Repetition (see (3)(c) above), Nietzsche is the
philosopher who Deleuze considers to have made the crucial move with regard to time,
surpassing even Kant.
One of the central consequences for cinema that this move from movement-image to time-image
makes again highlights one of Deleuze’s central concerns, to establish an ontology and a
semiology of force: “What remains? There remain bodies, which are forces, nothing but forces.”
(C2 139) Since the cinema of the time-image is concerned to liberate images from carrying or
implying time in order to form narrative (no less than liberating time itself from narrative),
images are themselves free now to express forces, “shocks of force,” (C2 139). Scenes,
movements and language become expressive rather than representative.
c. Painting
Deleuze’s central work in the visual arts is his monograph Francis Bacon: logique de la
sensation (the logic of sensation), but he also engages with a large number of other figures in
various texts (eg. TP 492-500; WP ch.7), such as Turner (AO 132), Van Gogh, Klee, Kandinsky
and Cezanne.
Deleuze’s book on Francis Bacon, as the title suggests, is an attempt to construct a logic of
sensations from the artist’s work (FB 7). This task is largely a taxonomic one. Deleuze develops,
throughout the book, a number of key categorial notions and new concepts that allow him to
move away from the standard representational view of painting, towards a painting of force, that
presents force and creates affects (sensations) rather than representing or describing a scene.
Three central ideas are at work.
The first is an elaboration of the concept of Figure. For Deleuze, while the idea of figuration in
painting has largely been representational, he sees Bacon, and to some extent Cezanne before
him (FB 40, 76), collapsing the Figure into the world of forces, placing it in a new relation to
force. Thus Bacon’s cries, for which he is famous, place the figure in the presence of force: “. . .
painting will place the visible cry, the mouth which cries, into a relation with force.” (FB 41).
For Deleuze the cry expresses an extreme moment of life, rather than suffering or horror. As with
Kafka, Deleuze takes Bacon’s artistic work, is commonly considered very dark and nihilistic,
and considers it as a true sign of life, and of struggle with death.
The second, a refrain familiar from all of his work, relates to a notion of force that makes it
ontologically and artistically fundamental rather than politically oppressive, much as desire is
reconfigured in Capitalism and Schizophrenia. It is in fact this move that allows Deleuze’s
general ‘positivism’ towards Bacon, as we have just seen: “Everything . . . is in relation with
forces, everything is force.” (FB 40) In Francis Bacon, Deleuze thus creates the notion of ‘color-
force’, in order to understand how color can be expressive of force rather than representative (FB
94-7).
Finally, Deleuze draws on the difference between Western, representational models of vision,
and the haptic style of Egyptian art, in which he sees a development of a mode of
writing/drawing which resists being hypostased into the content/form duality common to
philosophical understandings of art.
7. What Is Philosophy?
We have already seen the significance of empiricism for Deleuze’s philosophy ((3) above).
Throughout his work, however, Deleuze gives a number of further formulations concerning the
aim and nature of philosophy. These can be understood in two phases, an early critical
naturalism and a later vitalist constructivism.
a. Early reflections – Naturalism
In his early works in the history of philosophy, culminating with The Logic of Sense, Deleuze
expresses an essentially critical model of philosophy. In his book on Nietzsche, he writes:
When someone asks ‘what’s the use of philosophy?’ the reply must be aggressive, since the
question tries to be ironic and caustic. Philosophy does not serve the State or the Church, who
have other concerns. It serves no established power. The use of philosophy is to sadden. A
philosophy which saddens no one, that annoys no one, is not a philosophy. It is useful for
harming stupidity, for turning stupidity into something shameful. Its only use is the exposure of
all forms of baseness of thought. . . . Philosophy is at its most positive as a critique, as an
enterprise of demystification. (NP 106)
It seems that this is the sole moment in Deleuze’s published work where he uses the term
’sadden’ in a positive manner, as something desirable, and this is an indication of the strength by
which he considers philosophy, in this early sense, as an exercise in naturalism in the sense that
Lucretius uses this term, that is, as an attack on all forms of mystification. Commenting on
Lucretius, Deleuze makes the following, extremely similar, remark:
The speculative object and the practical object of philosophy as Naturalism, science and
pleasure, coincide on this point: it is always a matter of denouncing the illusion, the false infinite,
the infinity of religion and all of the theologico-erotic-oneiric myths in which it is expressed. To
the question ‘what is the use of philosophy?’ the answer must be: what other object would have
an interest in holding forth the image of a free man, and in denouncing all of the forces which
need myth and troubled spirit in order to establish their power? (LS 278)
Deleuze’s philosophical naturalism is thus critical, Spinozist and Nietzschean: it sets as the aim
of philosophy the attack of all that belittles life: the sad passions of Spinoza, the passive and
reactive forces of Nietzsche, and mythology, in Lucretian terms. Naturalism must not here be
understood as opposed to a cosmopolitanism, or constructivism, Deleuze tells us. Rather,
“Naturalism . . . directs its attack against the prestige of the negative; it deprives the negative of
all of its power; it refuses the spirit of the negative the right to speak in the name of philosophy.”
(LS 279)
Mythology, in the sense of these texts, is the eternal danger for the operation of thought. Deleuze
summarises this immanent threat within thought (cf. (4)(d) above) as the threat of stupidity:
Philosophy could have taken up the problem with its own means and with the necessary
modesty, by considering the fact that stupidity is never that of others but the object of a properly
transcendental question: how is stupidity [...] possible? (DR 151)
b. “What is Philosophy?” – constructivism
From Difference and Repetition onwards, Deleuze, while maintaining this critical aspect for
philosophy, develops a thorough-going constructivist view which manifests itself in the final
collaboration between Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy? This text involves arguments
about three central notions: the creation of concepts, the presuppositions of philosophy, and the
relations between philosophy, science and art.
As we have seen, a certain doctrine of empiricist constructivism runs through Deleuze’s work
from the beginning, and on a number of levels. In What is Philosophy? this becomes the central
and explicit theme: “philosophy is the art of forming, inventing, and fabricating concepts”. (WP
2)
The philosopher’s only business is concepts, Deleuze and Guattari tell us, and the concept
belongs only to philosophy (WP 34). This is already clear when we consider Deleuze’s writings
on the arts, which he considers to be philosophical (see (6) above).
The fortunes of the concept, due to lack of attention by philosophers, have fallen, to the point at
which even marketing has taken hold of it, in, “the general movement that replaced Critique with
sales promotion.” (WP 10) However, Deleuze and Guattari insist, philosophy still only has
meaning vis a vis the concept.
A concept is distinctly featured. It is a multiplicity, not in itself a single thing, but an assemblage
of components which must retain coherence with the others for the concept to remain itself (in
this sense, it closely resembles the Spinozist body). These components are singularities: “‘a’
possible world, ‘a’ face, ’some’ words . . .” (WP 20), and yet become indiscernible when a part
of a concept. Each concept also has a relationship to other concepts by way of the similar
problems that they address, and by having similar component elements, and Deleuze and
Guattari describe their relations by the use of the term vibration (WP 23).
Above all, however, the concept must not be confused with the proposition, as in logic (WP 135
ff.), which is to say that it is agrammatical. There is no necessary relation between concepts, nor
is there any given way of relating. The logical functions of either/or, both/and and so forth, do
not do justice to the each-time created nature of conceptual relations. Neither does the concept
have a reference, in the way that a proposition does. Rather, it is intensive and expresses the
virtual existence of an event in thought: consider Descartes’ famous cogito, which expresses the
virtual individual in relation to themselves and the world.
Finally, a concept has no relationship to truth, which is an external determination, or
presupposition, that places thought at the service of the dogmatic image of thought: “The concept
is a form or a force” (WP 144). As such, concepts act, they are affective, rather than
significatory, or expressive of the contents of ideas.
The question of presuppositions, already dealt with via the concept of the image of thought (see
(4)(d) above), is examined in much greater depth by Deleuze and Guattari in What is
Philosophy? Indeed, their answer involves two new concepts, the conceptual personae, and the
plane of immanence.
Conceptual personae (WP ch. 3) are the figures of thought that give concepts their specific force,
their raison d’être. They are to be confused with neither psycho-social types (WP 67), nor with
the philosophers themselves (WP 64), but are like concepts created. Deleuze and Guattari argue
that conceptual personae, while often only implicit in philosophy, are decisive for understanding
the significance of concepts. To take again Descartes’ cogito, the implicit conceptual persona is
the idiot, the regular person, uneducated, untrained in philosophy, potentially betrayed by their
senses at every turn, and yet, able to have perfectly clear and distinct knowledge of themselves,
through the certainty of the ‘I think, therefore I am’. Also mentioned are Nietzsche’s famous
personae, both sympathetic and anti-pathetic: Zarathustra, the last man, Dionysus, the Crucified,
Socrates, and so forth. (WP 64)
Conceptual personae are, for Deleuze and Guattari, internal, non-philosophical preconditions for
the practice of creating concepts. These personae, in turn, are related to the plane of immanence.
This concept has clear and significant resonances with other important elements of Deleuze’s
thought, above all with his monist ontology of forces, and with his practical emphasis on
Nietzsche and Spinoza’s ethics as non-transcendental.
The plane of immanence (WP ch. 2) in thought is opposed to the transcendent in traditional
philosophy. Each time that a transcendent is raised (Descartes’ cogito, Plato’s ideas, Kant’s
categories), thought is arrested, and philosophy is placed at the service of dominant ideas. For
Deleuze and Guattari, all of these instances of the transcendental stem from the same problem:
insisting that immanence be immanent to “something”. (WP 44-5)
For thought to exist, for concepts to be formed and then given body through conceptual
personae, they must operate immanently, without the rule of a “Something” that organises or
stratifies the plane of immanence. Concepts exist on the plane of immanence, and each
philosopher, Deleuze and Guattari tell us, must create such a plane.
The other main concern of What is Philosophy? is to come to an understanding of the relations
between philosophy, art and science respectively. Deleuze and Guattari argue that each discipline
involves the activity of thought, and that in each case it is a matter of creation. What differs is the
sphere of creation and the manner in which it is populated.
Art is concerned with the creation of percepts and affects (WP 164), which are together
sensation. Percepts are not perceptions, in that they do not refer to a perceiver, and neither are
affects the feelings or affections of someone. Just as we saw with concepts, affects and percepts
are independent beings which exist outside of the experience of a thinker, and have no reference
to a state of affairs. Deleuze and Guattari write: “The work of art is a being of sensation and
nothing else: it exists in itself.” (WP 164) The correlate of the conceptual persona in art is the
figure (which is investigated in great depth in Deleuze’s text on Bacon, see (6)(c) above), and for
the plane of immanence, art is created on the plane of composition, which is likewise immanent
only to itself, and populated with the pure forces of percepts and affects (WP 196).
The situation with science is similar. Science is the activity of thought that creates functions.
These functions, in contrast to concepts, are propositional (WP 117), and form the fragments
from which science is able to piece together a kind of makeshift language, one which however,
does not have any prior relation to truth, any more than philosophy does. Functions have
meaning in creating a referential point of view, for Deleuze and Guattari, that is, in creating a
basis from which things can be measured. As such, the first great functions are those such as
absolute zero Kelvin, the speed of light etc., in relation to which a plane of reference is assumed.
The plane of reference, again immanent to the functions that populate it, gains consistency
through the strength and effectiveness of its functions. Also presupposed by science, in What is
Philosophy?, are partial observers, the scientific counterpart of conceptual personae and artistic
figures.
The figure of the partial observer in science, as in philosophy, is frequently implicit, and exists to
give direction to functions: we could consider Gallileo as an example, whose functions regarding
cosmology relate to a plane of reference that gives a greater consistency to the functions that the
previous planes, which often relied upon a religious transcendental structure that damaged and
made scientific thinking difficult by imposing a moral image of thought. The partial observer in
this case would be a figure that makes certain functions in particular take shape and gain force
regarding a certain phenomena, such as the relation of the sun to the moon: the heliocentrist.
8. References and Further Reading
a. Main texts
Below is a list of Deleuze’s main works, in order of their original publication in French. Francis
Bacon: logique de la sensation is currently the only major work without a complete English
translation, although one is currently being completed, and should be expected shortly. Indicated
in parentheses after the original publication date are the initials by which each text is referred to
above. In addition to the following, another resources seem particularly useful to those not
familiar with Deleuze: a long three-part interview conducted with Claire Parnet, L’Abécédaire de
Gilles Deleuze. Parnet suggests a topic for each letter of the alphabet, and Deleuze’s answers, in
most cases, are both substantial and revealing. The video set is available to purchase in French.
• Empiricism and Subjectivity (1953 ES) trans. Constanine Boundas (1991: Columbia
University Press, New York)
• Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962 NP) trans. Hugh Tomlinson (1983: Althone Press,
London)
• Kant’s Critical Philosophy (1963 KCP) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam
(1983: Althone Press, London)
• Proust and Signs (1964 PS) trans. Richard Howard (2000: University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis)
• “Coldness and Cruelty” in Masochism (1967 M) trans. Charles Stivale (1989: Zone
Books, New York)
• Bergsonism (1968 B) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbera Habberjam (1988: Zone
Books, New York)
• Difference and Repetition (1968 DR) trans. Paul Patton (1994: Colombia University
Press, New York)
• Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (1968 EPS) trans. Martin Joughin (1990: Zone
Books, New York)
• The Logic of Sense (1969 LS) trans. Mark Lester and Charles Stivale (1990: Columbia
University Press, New York)
• Spinoza: Practical Philosophy (1970 SPP) trans. Robert Hurley (1988: City Light Books,
San Francisco)
• (with Guattari) Anti-Oedipus – Capitalism and Schizophrenia (1972 AO) trans. Robert
Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen Lane (1977: Viking Press, New York)
• (with Guattari) Kafka: Towards a Minor Literature (1975 K) trans. Dana Polan (1986:
University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota)
• (with Claire Parnet) Dialogues (1977 D) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbera Habberjam
(1987: Althone Press, London)
• (with Guattari) A Thousand Plateaus – Capitalism and Schizophrenia (1980 TP) trans.
Brian Massumi (1987: University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
• Francis Bacon: logique de la sensation (1981 FB: Éditions de la différence, Paris)
• Cinema: The Movement Image (1983 C1) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbera Habberjam
(1989: University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota)
• The Time Image (1985 C2) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta (1989: University
of Minnesota Press, Minnesota)
• Foucault (1986 F) trans. Sean Hand (1988: University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
• The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (1988 FLB) trans. Tom Conley (1993: University of
Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
• Negotiations (1990 N) trans. Martin Joughin (1995: Columbia University Press, New
York)
• (with Guattari) What is Philosophy? (1991 WP) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham
Burchell (1994: Columbia University Press, New York)
• Essays Critical and Clinical (1993) trans. Smith and Greco (1997: University of
Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
• Pure Immanence: Essays on a life ed. John Rajchman trans. Anne Boymen (2001 PI:
Zone Books, New York)
b. Secondary texts
A good text that deals systematically with the whole body of Deleuze’s work, that is also quite
easy to read, is the Rajchman volume. Regarding Capitalism and Schizophrenia, there are a
number of commentaries available; the Massumi text is perhaps the best known and most
consistent, although the general level of all secondary texts in this area is very difficult. The
Clamour of Being, by Alain Baidou is a controversial interpretation of Deleuze’s work,
particularly his ontology, from the perspective of another important French philosopher who
knew Deleuze. Michel Foucault’s 1977 article, “Theatricum Philosophicum,” is also a significant
and well-known interpretation of Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense.
i. Books and Collections of Essays
• Ansell-Pearson ed., Deleuze and Philosophy: the difference engineer (1997: Routledge,
New York) – chapters 2-5, 6, 7 and 13 especially
• Badiou, Alain Deleuze: the Clamour of Being trans. Louise Burchill (2000: University of
Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
• Boundas and Olkowski eds., Gilles Deleuze and the Theatre of Philosophy (1994:
Routledge, New York)
• Buchanan and Colebrook eds., Deleuze and Feminist Theory (2000: Edinburgh
University Press, Edinburgh)
• Hardt, Michael Gilles Deleuze: an apprenticeship in philosophy (1993: University of
Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
• Lecercle, J. Philosophy through the Looking-Glass: Language, Nonsense, Desire (1985:
Hutchinson Press, London)
• Marks, John Gilles Deleuze: Vitalism and Multiplicity (1998: Pluto Press, London)
• Massumi, Brian A User’s Guide to Capitalism and Schizophrenia – deviations from
Deleuze and Guattari (1992: MIT Press, Cambridge)
• Patton, Paul Deleuze and the Political (2000: Routledge, New York)
• Rajchman, John The Deleuze Connections (2000: MIT Press, Cambridge)
ii. Additional Uncollected Articles
• Braidotti, Rosi “Embodiment, Sexual Difference, and the Nomadic Subject” in Hypatia
vol 8, no 1 pp 1-13 (Winter 1993)
• Derrida, Jacques “I’m going to have to wander all alone” in Brault and Nass eds., The
Work of Mourning pp192-5 (2001: University of Chicago Press, Chicago)
• Eribon, Didier “Sickness unto life – the life and works of Gilles Deleuze” Artforum, v34
n7 (March 1996)
• Foucault, Michel “Theatrum Philosophicum” in Language, Counter-memory, Practice
trans. Donald Bouchard and Sherry Simon pp 165-198 (1977: Cornell University Press,
Ithaca)
• Goulimari, Pelagia “A minoritarian feminism? Things to do with Deleuze and Guattari”
Hypatia v14 i2 pp97-9 (Spring 1999)
• Neil, David “The Uses of Anachronism: Deleuze’s History of the Subject” Philosophy
Today 4: 42 Winter pp 418-31 (1998)
Author Information
Jon Roffe
Email: overground@imap.cc
University of Melbourne
Australia
Last updated on July 12, 2005 | Categories: Continental Philosophy, Philosophers
Originally published on: June/2/2002
Search the IEP
Top of Form

submit

Bottom of Form

Browse by Title
• A
• B
• C
• D
• E
• F
• G
• H
• I
• J
• K
• L
• M
• N
• O
• P
• Q
• R
• S
• T
• U
• V
• W
• X
• Y
• Z
Browse by Topic
• ▶History of Philosophy
○ 16th Century European
○ 17th Century European
○ 18th Century European
○ 19th Century European
○ Ancient Philosophy
○ History Misc.
○ History of Analytic Philosophy
○ Medieval Philosophy
○ Philosophers
• ▶Metaphysics & Epistemology
○ Epistemology
○ Metaphysics
○ Mind & Cognitive Science
○ Philosophy of Language
○ Philosophy of Religion
• ▼Philosophical Traditions
○ American Philosophy
○ Chinese Philosophy
○ Continental Philosophy
○ Feminist Philosophy
○ Indian Philosophy
○ Islamic Philosophy
○ Tradition Misc.
• ▶Science, Logic, & Mathematics
○ Logic
○ Philosophy of Mathematics
○ Philosophy of Science
• ▶Value Theory
○ Aesthetics
○ Bioethics
○ Ethics
○ Philosophy of Law
○ Political Philosophy
○ Value Misc.
Recent Articles
• Cheng Yi
• Dai Zhen
• Spinoza’s Epistemology
Print

Printer-friendly Version

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi