Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 6

9/21/2014

Bentham/Mill

Philosophy Pages

Dictionary
History

Study Guide
Timeline

Logic
Philosophers

FAQs
Locke

Utilitarianism
At the outset of the nineteenth century, an influential group of British thinkers developed a set of
basic principles for addressing social problems. Extrapolating from Hume's emphasis on the
natural human interest in utility, reformer Jeremy Bentham proposed a straightforward
quantification of morality by reference to utilitarian outcomes. His An Introduction to the
Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789) offers a simple statement of the application of this
ethical doctrine.
Bentham's moral theory was founded on the assumption that it is the consequences of human
actions that count in evaluating their merit and that the kind of consequence that matters for human
happiness is just the achievement of pleasure and avoidance of pain. He argued that the hedonistic
value of any human action is easily calculated by considering how intensely its pleasure is felt, how
long that pleasure lasts, how certainly and how quickly it follows upon the performance of the
action, and how likely it is to produce collateral benefits and avoid collateral harms. Taking such
matters into account, we arrive at a net value of each action for any human being affected by it.
All that remains, Bentham supposed, is to consider the extent of this pleasure, since the
happiness of the community as a whole is nothing other than the sum of individual human interests.
The principle of utility, then, defines the meaning of moral obligation by reference to the greatest
happiness of the greatest number of people who are affected by performance of an action.
Similarly, Bentham supposed that social policies are properly evaluated in light of their effect on
the general well-being of the populations they involve. Punishing criminals is an effective way of
deterring crime precisely because it pointedly alters the likely outcome of their actions, attaching
the likelihood of future pain in order to outweigh the apparent gain of committing the crime. Thus,
punishment must "fit" the crime by changing the likely perception of the value of committing it.

John Stuart Mill


A generation later, utilitarianism found its most effective exponent in
John Stuart Mill. Raised by his father, the philosopher James Mill, on
strictly Benthamite principles, Mill devoted his life to the defence and
promotion of the general welfare. With the help his long-time
companion Harriet Taylor, Mill became a powerful champion of lofty
moral and social ideals.
Mill
Life and Works
. . Utilitarianism
. . Individual Liberty
. . Women's Rights
Bibliography
Internet Sources

Mill's Utilitarianism (1861) is an extended explanation of utilitarian


moral theory. In an effort to respond to criticisms of the doctrine, Mill
not only argued in favor of the basic principles of Jeremy Bentham but
also offered several significant improvements to its structure, meaning,
and application. Although the progress of moral philosophy has been
limited by its endless disputes over the reality and nature of the highest
good, Mill assumed from the outset, everyone can agree that the
consequences of human actions contribute importantly to their moral value. (Utilitarianism 1)

Mill fully accepted Bentham's devotion to greatest happiness principle as the basic statement of
http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5q.htm

1/6

9/21/2014

Bentham/Mill

utilitarian value:
" . . . actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as
they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure,
and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure."
(Utilitarianism 2)
But he did not agree that all differences among pleasures can be quantified. On Mill's view, some
kinds of pleasure experienced by human beings also differ from each other in qualitative ways, and
only those who have experienced pleasure of both sorts are competent judges of their relative
quality. This establishes the moral worth of promoting higher (largely intellectual) pleasures among
sentient beings even when their momentary intensity may be less than that of alternative lower
(largely bodily) pleasures. Even so, Mill granted that the positive achievement of happiness is often
difficult, so that we are often justified morally in seeking primarily to reduce the total amount of
pain experienced by sentient beings affected by our actions. Painor even the sacrifice of pleasure
is warranted on Mill's view only when it results directly in the greater good of all.
Against those who argue that the utilitarian theory unreasonably demands of individual agents
that they devote their primary energies to the cold-hearted and interminable calculation of
anticipated effects of their actions, Mill offered a significant qualification. Precisely because we do
not have the time to calculate accurately in every instance, he supposed, we properly allow our
actions to be guided by moral rules most of the time. Partly anticipating the later distinction
between act and rule utilitarianism, Mill pointed out that secondary moral principles at the very
least perform an important service by providing ample guidance for every-day moral life. Finally,
however, he emphasized that the value of each particular actionespecially in difficult or
controversial casesis to be determined by reference to the principle of utility itself.
What motivates people to do the right thing? Mill claimed universal agreement on the role of
moral sanctions in eliciting proper conduct from human agents. (Utilitarianism 3) But unlike
Bentham, Mill did not restrict himself to the socially-imposed external sanctions of punishment and
blame, which make the consequences of improper action more obviously painful. On Mill's view,
human beings are also motivated by such internal sanctions as self-esteem, guilt, and conscience.
Because we all have social feelings on behalf of others, the unselfish wish for the good of all is
often enough to move us to act morally. Even if others do not blame or punish me for doing wrong,
I am likely to blame myself, and that bad feeling is another of the consequent pains that I
reasonably consider when deciding what to do.
In Chapter Four, Mill offers as "proof" of the principle of utility an argument originally
presented by his father, James Mill. The best evidence of the desirability of happiness is that people
really do desire it; and since each individual human being desires her own happiness, it must follow
that all of us desire the happiness of everyone. Thus, the Mills argued, the greatest pleasure of all is
morally desirable. (Utilitarianism 4) The argument doesn't hold up well at all in logical terms, since
each of its inferences is obviously fallacious, but Mill may have been correct in supposing on
psychological grounds that seeking pleasure and avoiding pain are the touchstones by which most
of us typically live.
Finally, Mill argued that social applications of the principle of utility are fully consistent with
traditional concern for the promotion of justice. Justice involves respect for the property, rights, and
deserts of individual citizens, along with fundamental presumptions in favor of good faith and
impartiality. All of these worthwhile components of justice are adequately preserved by
conscientious application of the principle of utility, Mill supposed, since particular cases of each
clearly result in the greatest happiness of all affected parties. (Utilitarianism 5) Although a
retributive sentiment in favor of punishing wrong-doers may also be supposed to contribute to the
traditional concept of justice, Mill insisted that the appropriately limited use of external sanctions
on utilitarian grounds better accords with a legitimate respect for the general welfare. Mill also
http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5q.htm

2/6

9/21/2014

Bentham/Mill

pointed out that the defence of individual human freedom is especially vital to living justly, but that
had been the subject of another book.
On Liberty
John Stuart Mill's On Liberty (1859) is the classic statement and defence of the view that
governmental encroachment upon the freedom of individuals is almost never warranted. A
genuinely civil society, he maintained, must always guarantee the civil liberty of its citizenstheir
protection against interference by an abusive authority. This is true even when the government
itself relies upon the democratic participation of the people. (On Liberty 1) The tyranny of the
majority is especially dangerous to individual liberty, Mill supposed, because the most commonly
recommended remedy is to demand that the recalcitrant minority either persuade the majority to
change its views or learn to conform to socially accepted norms.
Mill had a different notion. The proper balance between individual liberty and governmental
authority, he proposed, can be stated as a simple principle:
"[T]he only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of
a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others." (On Liberty 1)
Although society has a clear responsibility for protecting its citizens from each other, it has no
business interfering with the rest of what they do. In particular, anything that directly affects only
the individual citizen must remain absolutely free. On Mill's view, this entails in particular that the
government is never justified in trying to control, limit, or restrain: 1) private thoughts and feelings,
along with their public expression, 2) individual tastes and pursuits as efforts to live happily, or 3)
the association of like-minded individuals with each other. (On Liberty 1) No society is truly free
unless its individual citizens are permitted to take care of themselves.
Considering first freedom of thought and discussion, Mill argued that because even a majority
opinion is fallible, society should always permit the expression of minority views. There is a
chance, after all, that the unconventional opinion will turn out, in the long run, to be correct, in
which case the entire society would suffer if it were never allowed to come to light. Sincere
devotion to the truth requires open inquiry, not the purposeful silencing of alternative views that
might prove to be right. (On Liberty 2) Even if the unconventional opinion turns out to be incorrect,
Mill argued, there is still good reason to encourage its free expression. The truth can only be
enlivened and strengthened by exposure to criticism and debate through which the majority view is
shown not to be merely an inadequately grounded superstition. (On Liberty 2) In the most common
instance, Mill supposed, there will actually turn out to be some measure of falsity in the clearest
truth and some element of truth in the most patent falsehood. Thus, on every possible occasion,
encouraging civil discussion of alternative views genuinely benefits society as a whole.
Mill supposed that behavior as well as thought often deserves protection against social
encroachment. Human action should arise freely from the character of individual human beings, not
from the despotic influence of public opinion, custom, or expectation. No matter what patterns of
behavior may constitute the way we ought to be, he argued, each person must choose her or his
own path in life, even if it differs significantly from what other people would recommend. (On
Liberty 3) No less than in the realm of thought, in the realm of behavior unconventionality and
originality are often signs of great personal genius, which should never be curtailed by social
pressures.
In summary, then, Mill emphasized that individual citizens are responsible for themselves, their
thoughts and feelings, and their own tastes and pursuits, while society is properly concerned only
with social interests. In particular, the state is justified in limiting or controlling the conduct of
individuals only when doing so is the only way to prevent them from doing harm to others by
http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5q.htm

3/6

9/21/2014

Bentham/Mill

violating their rights. (On Liberty 4) Where the conduct in question affects only the person who
does iteven if it clearly results in harm to that personthe state has no business in even trying to
suppress the mode of being that person has chosen. Thus, on Mill's view, legislation that attempts
to promote good conduct or to prevent people from harming themselves is always wrong. The line
he drew between private and social concerns is a fairly clear one: society should not endeavor to
limit my drinking, but rightly prosecutes me for harming others while drunk.
In the essay's final chapter, Mill carefully noted several apparent exceptions to the general
principle. (On Liberty 5) Governmental interference is not necessary even in some of the instances
where it might be justifiable. Economic life involves social interest and may therefore be subject to
regulation, even though free trade is often more effective. Speech or action by one individual that
encourages someone else to commit self-harm is appropriately restricted. Indirect action by the
state designed to encourage or discourage (without requiring or restraining) individual conduct is
permissible; in fact, doing so is simply good utilitarian legislation. According to Mill, the state's
legitimate interest in preventing harm to its citizens extends even into the domain of family life, as
in forbidding spousal abuse or providing for the education of children.
Finally, Mill noted that even if the involvement of the government in some specific aspect of the
lives of its citizens does not violate their individual liberty, there may remain other good reasons
for avoiding it. If the conduct to be regulated can be performed better by individuals themselves, if
it is more desirable that it be done by them, or if regulation would add significantly to the alreadydangerous power of the social establishment, then the state ought not to be allowed to interfere. (On
Liberty 5) Mill's conclusion, then, is strictly in favor of liberty: governmental action is legitimate
only when demonstrably necessary for the protection of other citizens from direct harm caused by
the conduct in question. On every other contingency, the liberty of the individual should remain
inviolate.
The Subjection of Women
One of John Stuart Mill's last and finest literary efforts was written in support of a political
cause of which he had long been a leading champion. The Subjection of Women (1869) offered both
detailed argumentation and passionate eloquence in bitter opposition to the social and legal
inequalities commonly imposed upon women by a patriarchal culture. Mill granted the practical
difficulty of arguing successfully against an opinion that is widely-held and deeply-entrenched even
though it relies upon nothing better than a vaguely-expressed presumption of the natural superiority
of males. In fact, Mill pointed out, the domination of men over womenlike conquest or slavery in
any other formoriginated in nothing more than the brute application of physical power. But this
reliance upon physical force as a means of obtaining and maintaining control over other human
beings has been abandoned in every other area of political life.
"The social subordination of women thus stands out an isolated fact in modern social
institutions; a solitary breach of what has become their fundamental law . . . ."
(Subjection of Women 1)
Mill argued that reliance upon physical strength and violence should not be tolerated in this
instance, either.
Although it is often claimed that male domination over women is a purely natural expression of
biological necessity, Mill found little genuine evidence for this. Any conventional social
discrimination, made familiar by long experience and social prevalence, will come to seem natural
to those who have never contemplated any alternative. The appearance of voluntary submission by
women is even more misleading, on Mill's view, since it could as easily reflect enslavement of
mind and feeling as genuine sentiment. Certainly men, whose awareness of women's thinking is
severly limited, are in no position to speak confidently about what women really want:
http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5q.htm

4/6

9/21/2014

Bentham/Mill

"Many a man thinks he perfectly understands women, because he has had amatory
relations with several, perhaps with many of them. If he is a good observer, and his
experience extends to quality as well as quantity, he may have learnt something of
one narrow department of their naturean important department, no doubt. But of
all the rest of it, few persons are generally more ignorant, because there are few
from whom it is so carefully hidden." (Subjection of Women 1)
If society really wanted to discover what is truly natural in gender relations, Mill argued, it should
establish a free market for all of the services women perform, ensuring a fair economic return for
their contributions to the general welfare. Only then would their practical choices be likely to
reflect their genuine interests.
In the patriarchal culture, many women are trapped by social expectations in the traditional
forms of marriage, which had its origins as bondage or involuntary servitude. Although Mill
granted that some men are less despotic toward their wives than the laws would permit, he
supposed this a mixed blessing and noted those who wish to do so find little difficulty in securing a
slave-wife. Mill saw no reason why either partner in a marriage should dominate the other; he
proposed that a family governed by consenual separation of functions could, in principle become a
profoundly serious example of free association.
"What marriage may be in the case of two persons of cultivated faculties, identical
in opinions and purposes, between whom there exists that best kind of equality,
similarity of powers and reciprocal superiority in themso that each can enjoy the
luxury of looking up to the other, and can have alternately the pleasure of leading
and of being led in the path of developmentI will not attempt to describe. To those
who can conceive it, there is no need; to those who cannot, it would appear the
dream of an enthusiast. But I maintain, with the profoundest conviction, that this, and
this only, is the ideal of marriage; and that all opinions, customs, and institutions
which favour any other notion of it, or turn the conceptions and aspirations
connected with it into any other direction, by whatever pretences they may be
coloured, are relics of primitive barbarism." (Subjection of Women 4)
Although few men can presently tolerate the prospect of living in intimate association with a
genuinely equal partner, Mill clearly believed it not only possible but highly desirable to do so.
Thus, the liberation of women from patriarchal restrictions holds great promise for human life
generally. The individual property rights of women ought to be wholly independent of their marital
status, for example, and their right to participate in the political process ought to be granted
completely. (Efforts to secure suffrage for women had been a major issue of Mill's own service in
the British Parliament.) Not only can women think as well as men, Mill argued, but their thought
and experience inclines them to be more flexible and practical in applied reasoning and, perhaps,
therefore morally superior to men. Certainly the provision of social equality for women would
serve the general welfare of society by promoting justice, enhancing moral sensitivity, and securing
liberty for all.

History of Philosophy
Previous
Next

http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5q.htm

Philosophical Ethics
Previous
Next

Political Theory
Previous
Next

5/6

9/21/2014

Bentham/Mill

The Philosophy Pages by Garth Kemerling are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0
Unported License.
Permissions beyond the scope of this license may be available at http://www.philosophypages.com/referral/contact.htm.
1997, 2011 Garth Kemerling.
Last modified 12 November 2011.
Questions, comments, and suggestions may be sent to:
the Contact Page.

http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5q.htm

6/6

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi