Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 4

Legitimacy of international espionage activity

Felix Staicu
Mihai Claudiu Barloiu

Espionage among nations is an exceptionally old and extensive humand endevours.


Our account of international espionage begins from the observation that espionage between
states is an undercover, state-sponsored intrusion into the restricted space of another state for
the sake of collecting information1.
Espionage and international law start from different points. Espionage dates from the
beginning of history while interantional law as embodied, in customs, conventions or treaties,
is a more recent phenomenon. They are also based on contradictory principles, the core of
espionage being treasury and deceit while the core of international law is decency and
common humanity.
Surprisingly, this costly and harmful activity lacks a clear justification. Legal and
philosophical scholarship is extremely interested in, for example, the legitimacy of war
among nations, and the proper legal framework for regulating war. The legitimacy of the
domestic use of governmental force, too, is debated rigorously. Yet when it comes to
espionage, moral theorists are as soundless as spies. Throughout our argument, we follow a
basic distinction between espionage during states of emergency (such as war or conflict) and
espionage during peacetime (or ordinary circumstances). I define an emergency as a time
that calls for remedial action in order to address a clear, imminent, and serious threat posed
by one state against a basic interest of another. It is peacetime espionage that poses the real
justificatory challenge.
Espionage that is undertaken in response to emergencies can be justified sufficiently, seems to
us, by reference to Just War Theory (JWT) and the rules of necessity and self-defense.
Similarly, just as it assesses the legality of military acts (jus in bello), JWT should decide
which means are legitimate for intelligence-gathering and which are not. I suggest that this
seemingly attractive and powerful argument is fallacious. At best, it justifies the collection of
intelligence during wartime or other emergencies. But peacetime espionage and wartime
espionage are fundamentally different.2

On various approaches to defining espionage, see M MARK LOWENTHAL, INTELLIGENCE: FROM


SECRETS TO POLICY
2
Angela Gendron, Just War, Just Intelligence: An Ethical Framework for Foreign Espionage,
18 INTL J. INTELLIGENCE & COUNTERINTELLIGENCE 398 (2005)

Espionage functionally permits states not only to verify that their neighbors are complying
with international obligations, but also to confirm the legitimacy of those assurances that their
neighbors provide.
States are more willing to cooperate across various functional lines because espionage is
available as a tool by which to monitor foreign behavior.3
Most of the literature concerning espionage and international law addreses situations in which
the laws of war apply.
The rules of espionage in times of war, wheter based on The Hague Regulation of 1907, the
Geneva Conventions, The Protocol Additional to the Geneva Convention or other sources are
straight forward.
According to Article 29 Convention (IV) respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land
Hague- A person can only be considered a spy when, acting clandestinely or on false
pretences, he obtains or endeavours to obtain information in the zone of operations of a
belligerent, with the intention of communicating it to the hostile party.
Significantly, the Hague Regulations do not make belligerent espionage a violation of the
laws of war. International law neither endorses nor prohibits espionage, but rather preserves
the practice as a tool by which to facilitate international cooperation.
National representatives are faced, in the international original position, with the choice
between endorsing and rejecting a duty of basic transparency enforced exclusively through
espionage. If they reject this rule, states will not be required to be transparent, and their
neighbors will have no right to spy on them.
The representatives are expected to adopt a maximin strategy: i.e., to choose the option that
offers the best minimum result. Let us suppose that the international community adopts a ban
on espionage. From each states point of view, giving up intelligence-gathering means
practically accepting a kind of national blindness. In fact, this particular form of blindness
would extend to information about other states non-compliance with the rule against
espionage, since other states would presumably conduct their espionage clandestinely. This is
a crucial point, because the stability of any international norm hinges on each nations
expectation that the other nations will observe it.4
The literature concerning the espionage in international law outside of the laws of war is
much less developed as Richard Fold noted: Traditional International Law is remarkably
oblivious to the peacetime practice of espioange. The literature that does exist on peacetime
espionage can be split into three groups, one group suggests peacetime espionage is legal (not
illegal) under international law , another group suggests peacetime espionage is legal under
international law, a third group placed between the other two, maintains that peacetime

http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1176&context=auilr
JANNA THOMSON, JUSTICE AND WORLD ORDER: A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY 31 (1992); Forde,
supra note 8, at 76
4

espionage is neither legal nor illegal. In any event the uncertainty in the literature supports the
thesis that espionage is beyond international consensus .

1. Espionage is not illegal


Geogrey Demarest aggrees that there is an interesting lacuna betwen
espionage and international law also he distinguish betwen wartime espionage and
peacetime espionage .Demarests conclusion , althogh espionage unfriendly act it does
not violate interantional law.To prove his statements Denmarest argues that there is a
trend where by international organizations such as the United Nations have incesed
thier inteliggence gatbhering capabillities . To give espionage some legall support we
tide it up to the right of anticipatory or paremptory self defense under the UN Charter
and international law.5
2. Espionage is illegal
Professor Manuel Garcia Mora belives that peacetime espionage is regarde as
an international delinquency and a violation of international law.6Professo Quincy
Wright belives that peacetime espionage violates a duty that states have under
International Law to respect to teritorial integrity and political independence of other
states.7According to Delupis espionage appears to be illegal under international law in
time of peace if it involves the presence of agents sent clandestinely by a foreign
power into the teritoy of another state.In to Delupis knowledge international tribunals
have not convicted anyone for the simple wrong of espionage.8

3. Espionage is neither legal or legal.


Two former Cia officials Daniel Silver, and Frederick Hitz state that there is
something almost oxymoronic about addressing the legality of espionage under
international law,9Speaking of the ambiguos of espionage under international law they
conclude that espionage is neither clealy condoned nor condemnd under international
law . The rules and the ethics are situational . Countries are much less tolerant when
espionage is commited against them, then when they are commiting it against friends
and foes. Wheter espionage is legall or ilegall under international law they are realista
about the fact that countries for reason of self defense and for their own interest are
going to commit espionage in other countries. According to them that may explain
why no treaties specifically prohibit espionage. As Cristopher Baker argues :
5

Lt.Col. Geoffrey B.Denmarest, Espionage in Interantional Law

Manuel Garcia Mora, Treason, Sedition and Espionage as Poltical Offenses unde the law of extradition,
Quincy Wright, Espionage and the doctrine of non-intervention in internal affaires.
8
Ingrid Delupis-foreing worships and immunity from espionage,
7

Daniel Silver, Intelligence and Counter Intelligence

International Law neither endorses nor prohibits espionage but rather preserves the
practice as a tool by which to facilitate international cooperation . Looking back to
another era when the Americans and Soviets negotiated over the size of their nuclear
stockpiles , Baker demonstrates that shared inteliggence can be vey useful in
monitoring and enforcing agreements in arms control. Whitout espionage countries
could be required simply to accept the information provided by other treaty partners as
accurate.10
Proffessor Simon Chesterman states that espionage creates functional benefits for the
internatonal community and he further suggests that the benefits of sharing
intelligence with multilateral organizations could lead the international community to
develop new international norms.11
Conclusion
Based on the things that we presented we agree with the last theory that
international espionage is neither legal nor illegal, and that states accept this situation
as a common practice.
Intelligence gathering will always be a key part in states self-defence policy,
because trust cannot be a guidance in a state security policy. So if states do not seek
complete disarmament, there is no reason to ban espionage practices, because even if
they were banned, states will find a way to continue the information-gathering
practices, for well-known purposes.

10
11

Cristopher D.Baker, Tollerance of International Espionage. A functional approach.


Simonn Chesterman, The spy who came in from the Cold War: Intelligence and International Law.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi