Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 12

John Austin

Bix, Brian, "John Austin", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)

John Austin is considered by many to be the creator of the school of analytical jurisprudence,
as well as, more specifically, the approach to law known as legal positivism. Austin's
particular command theory of law has been subject to pervasive criticism, but its simplicity
gives it an evocative power that continues to attract adherents.
1. Life
2. Analytical Jurisprudence and Legal Positivism
3. Austin's Views
4. Criticisms
5. A Revisionist View?
Bibliography

1. Life
John Austin's life (17901859) was filled with disappointment and unfulfilled expectations.
His influential friends (who included Jeremy Bentham, James Mill, John Stuart Mill and
Thomas Carlyle) were impressed by his intellect and his conversation, and predicted he
would go far. However, in public dealings, Austin's nervous disposition, shaky health,
tendency towards melancholy, and perfectionism combined to end quickly careers at the Bar,
in academia, and in government service (Hamburger 1985, 1992).
Austin was born to a Suffolk merchant family, and served briefly in the military before
beginning his legal training. He was called to the Bar in 1818, but he took on few cases, and
quit the practice of law in 1825. Austin shortly thereafter obtained an appointment to the first
Chair of Jurisprudence at the recently established University of London. He prepared for his
lectures by study in Bonn, and evidence of the influence of continental legal and political
ideas can be found scattered throughout Austin's writings. Commentators have found
evidence in Austin's writings of the German Pandectist treatment of Roman Law, in
particular, its approach to law as something that is, or should be, systematic and coherent
(Schwarz 1934; Stein 1988: pp. 223229, 238244; Lobban 1991: pp. 223256)
1

Lectures from the course he gave were eventually published in 1832 as Province of
Jurisprudence Determined (Austin 1832). However, attendance at his courses was small and
getting smaller, and he gave his last lecture in 1833. A short-lived effort to give a similar
course of lectures at the Inner Temple met the same result. Austin resigned his University of
London Chair in 1835. He later briefly served on the Criminal Law Commission, and as a
Royal Commissioner to Malta, but he never found either success or contentment. He did
some occasional writing on political themes, but his plans for longer works never came to
anything during his lifetime, due apparently to some combination of perfectionism,
melancholy, and writer's block. His changing views on moral, political, and legal matters also
apparently hindered both the publication of a revised edition of Province of Jurisprudence
Determined, and the completion of a longer project started when his views had been
different.
(There is some evidence that Austin's views later in his life may have moved away from
analytical jurisprudence (see below) towards something more approximating the historical
jurisprudence school (Hamburger 1985: pp. 17891).)
Much of whatever success Austin found during his life, and after, must be attributed to his
wife Sarah, for her tireless support, both moral and economic (during the later years of their
marriage, they lived primarily off her efforts as a translator and reviewer), and her work to
publicize his writings after his death (including the publication of a more complete set of his
Lectures on Jurisprudence) (Austin 1879). Credit should also be given to Austin's influential
friends, who not only helped him to secure many of the positions he held during his lifetime,
but also gave important support for his writings after his death (Hamburger 1985: pp. 33,
197; Morison 1982: p. 17; Mill 1863).
Austin's work was influential in the decades after his passing away. E. C. Clark wrote in the
late 19th century that Austin's work is undoubtedly forming a school of English jurists,
possibly of English legislators also. It is the staple of jurisprudence in all our systems of legal
education. (Clark 1883: pp. 45) A similar assessment is made by H.L.A. Hart, looking
back nearly a century later: within a few years of his death it was clear that his work had
established the study of jurisprudence in England (Hart 1955: p. xvi). As will be discussed,
Austin's influence can be seen at a number of levels, including the general level of how legal
theory, and law generally, were taught (Stein 1988: pp. 238244), and the use of an analytical
approach in legal theory. At such levels, Austin's impact is felt to this day. Hart could write
that Austin's influence on the development of England of [Jurisprudence] has been greater
than that of any other writer, (Hart 1955: p. xvi) even while Austin's particular command
theory of law became almost friendless, and is today probably best known from Hart's use of
it (1958, 1994) as a foil for the elaboration of Hart's own, more nuanced approach to legal
theory. In recent decades, some theorists have revisited Austin's command theory (and other
works), offering new characterizations and defenses of his ideas (e.g., Morison 1982,
Rumble 1985).
2

2. Analytical Jurisprudence and Legal


Positivism
Early in his career, Austin came under the influence of Jeremy Bentham, and Bentham's
utilitarianism is evident (though with some differences) in the work for which Austin is best
known today. On Austin's reading of utilitarianism, Divine will is equated with Utilitarian
principles: The commands which God has revealed we must gather from the terms wherein
they are promulg[ate]d. The command which he has not revealed, we must construe by the
principle of utility (Austin 1873: Lecture IV, p. 160; see also Austin 1832: Lecture II, p. 41).
This particular reading of utilitarianism, however, has had little long-term influence, though
it seems to have been the part of his work that received the most attention in his own day
(Rumble 1995: p. xx). Some have also seen Austin as being one of the early advocates of
rule utilitarianism.(e.g., Austin 1832: Lecture II, p. 42, where Austin urges that we analyze
not the utility of particular acts, but that of class[es] of action). Additionally, Austin early
on shared many of the ideas of the Benthamite philosophical radicals; he was a strong
proponent of modern political economy, a believer in Hartleian metaphysics, and a most
enthusiastic Malthusian (Rumble 1985: pp. 1617). Austin was to lose most of his radical
inclinations as he grew older.
Austin's importance to legal theory lies elsewherehis theorizing about law was novel at
four different levels of generality. First, he was arguably the first writer to approach the
theory of law analytically (as contrasted with approaches to law more grounded in history or
sociology, or arguments about law that were secondary to more general moral and political
theories). Analytical jurisprudence emphasizes the analysis of key concepts, including law,
(legal) right, (legal) duty, and legal validity. Though analytical jurisprudence has been
challenged by some in recent years (e.g., Leiter 2007a, 2007b), it remains the dominant
approach to discussing the nature of law. Analytical jurisprudence, an approach to theorizing
about law, has sometimes been confused with what the American legal realists (an influential
group of theorists prominent in the early decades of the 20th century) called legal
formalisma narrow approach to how judges should decide cases. The American legal
realists saw Austin in particular, and analytical jurisprudence in general, as their opponents in
their critical and reform-minded efforts (e.g., Sebok 1998: pp. 65-69). In this, the realists
were simply mistaken; unfortunately, it is a mistake that can still be found in some
contemporary legal commentators.
Second, Austin's work should be seen against a background where most English judges and
commentators saw common-law reasoning (the incremental creation or modification of law
through judicial resolution of particular disputes) as supreme, as declaring existing law, as
discovering the requirements of Reason, as the immemorial wisdom of popular custom.
Such (Anglo-American) theories about common law reasoning fit with a larger tradition of
theorizing about law (which had strong roots in continental European thoughte.g., the
3

historical jurisprudence of theorists like Karl Friedrich von Savigny (1975)): the idea that
generally law did or should reflect community mores, spirit, or custom. In general, one
might look at many of the theorists prior to Austin as exemplifying an approach that was
more community-orientedlaw as arising from societal values or needs, or expressive of
societal customs or morality. By contrast, Austin's is one of the first, and one of the most
distinctive, theories that views law as being imperium orientedviewing law as mostly the
rules imposed from above from certain authorized (pedigreed) sources. More top-down
theories of law, like that of Austin, better fit the more centralized governments (and the
modern political theories about government) of modern times (Cotterrell 2003: pp. 2177).
Third, within analytical jurisprudence, Austin was the first systematic exponent of a view of
law known as legal positivism. Most of the important theoretical work on law prior to
Austin had treated jurisprudence as though it were merely a branch of moral theory or
political theory: asking how should the state govern? (and when were governments
legitimate?), and under what circumstances did citizens have an obligation to obey the law?
Austin specifically, and legal positivism generally, offered a quite different approach to law:
as an object of scientific study (Austin 1879: pp. 11071108), dominated neither by
prescription nor by moral evaluation. Subtle jurisprudential questions aside, Austin's efforts
to treat law systematically gained popularity in the late 19th century among English lawyers
who wanted to approach their profession, and their professional training, in a more serious
and rigorous manner. (Hart 1955: pp. xvi-xviii; Cotterrell 2003: pp. 74-77; Stein 1988: pp.
231-244)
Legal positivism asserts (or assumes) that it is both possible and valuable to have a morally
neutral descriptive (or conceptualthough this is not a term Austin used) theory of law.
(The main competitor to legal positivism, in Austin's day as in our own, has been natural law
theory.) Legal positivism does not deny that moral and political criticism of legal systems is
important, but insists that a descriptive or conceptual approach to law is valuable, both on its
own terms and as a necessary prelude to criticism.
(The term legal positivism is sometimes used more broadly to include the position that we
should construct or modify our concept of law to remove moral criteria of legal validity; or
to include a prescription that moral values should not be used in judicial decision-making
(Schauer 2010see the Other Internet Resources). I do not think anything turns on whether
the term is used more broadly or more narrowly, as long as it is clear which sense is being
used. Additionally, while Schauer claims (2010) that Austin could be seen as supporting
some of the views associated with the broader understanding of legal positivism, there is
need for more evidence and argument before the point should be granted.)
There were theorists prior to Austin who arguably offered views similar to legal positivism or
who at least foreshadowed legal positivism in some way. Among these would be Thomas
Hobbes, with his amoral view of laws as the product of Leviathan (Hobbes 1996); David
Hume, with his argument for separating is and ought (which worked as a sharp criticism
4

for some forms of natural law theory, which purported to derive moral truths from statements
about human nature) (Hume 1739); and Jeremy Bentham, with his attacks on judicial
lawmaking and on those, like Sir William Blackstone, who justified such lawmaking with
natural-law-like justifications (Bentham 1789).
Austin's famous formulation of what could be called the dogma of legal positivism is as
follows:
The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether it be or be not is
one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different
enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a law, though we happen to dislike it, or though it
vary from the text, by which we regulate our approbation and disapprobation. (Austin 1832:
Lecture V, p. 157)
(While Austin saw himself as criticizing natural law theory, a view shared by most of the
legal positivists who followed him, the extent to which the two schools disagree, and the
location of their disagreement, remains a matter sharply contested (e.g., Finnis 2000a, 2000b;
Bix 2000).)
Fourth, Austin's version of legal positivism, a command theory of law (which will be
detailed in the next section), was also, for a time, quite influential. Austin's theory had
similarities with views developed by Jeremy Bentham, whose theory could also be
characterized as a command theory. Bentham, in a posthumously published work, would
define law as:
as assemblage of signs declarative of a volition conceived or adopted by the sovereign in a
state, concerning the conduct to be observed in a certain case by a certain person or class of
persons, who in the case in question are or are supposed to be subject to his power: such
volition trusting for its accomplishment to the expectation of certain events which it is
intended such declaration should upon occasion be a means of bringing to pass, and the
prospect of which it is intended should act as a motive upon those whose conduct is in
question. (Bentham 1970: p. 1)
However, Austin's command theory was more influential than Bentham's, because the latter's
jurisprudential writings did not appear in an even-roughly systematic form until well after
Austin's work had already been published, with Bentham's most systematic discussion only
appearing posthumously, late in the 20th century (Bentham 1970, 1996; Cotterrell 2003: p.
50).

3. Austin's Views
Austin's basic approach was to ascertain what can be said generally, but still with interest,
about all laws. Austin's analysis can be seen as either a paradigm of, or a caricature of,
analytical philosophy, in that his discussions are dryly full of distinctions, but are thin in
5

argument. The modern reader is forced to fill in much of the meta-theoretical, justificatory
work, as it cannot be found in the text. Where Austin does articulate his methodology and
objective, it is a fairly traditional one: he endeavored to resolve a law (taken with the largest
signification which can be given to that termproperly) into the necessary and essential
elements of which it is composed (Austin 1832: Lecture V, p. 117).
As to what is the core nature of law, Austin's answer is that laws (properly so called) are
commands of a sovereign. He clarifies the concept of positive law (that is, man-made law) by
analyzing the constituent concepts of his definition, and by distinguishing law from other
concepts that are similar:
Commands involve an expressed wish that something be done, combined with a
willingness and ability to impose an evil if that wish is not complied with.
Rules are general commands (applying generally to a class), as contrasted with
specific or individual commands (drink wine today or John Major must drink
wine).
Positive law consists of those commands laid down by a sovereign (or its agents), to
be contrasted to other law-givers, like God's general commands, and the general
commands of an employer to an employee.
The sovereign is defined as a person (or determinate body of persons) who receives
habitual obedience from the bulk of the population, but who does not habitually obey
any other (earthly) person or institution. Austin thought that all independent political
societies, by their nature, have a sovereign.
Positive law should also be contrasted with laws by a close analogy (which includes
positive morality, laws of honor, international law, customary law, and constitutional
law) and laws by remote analogy (e.g., the laws of physics).
(Austin 1832: Lecture I).
Austin also wanted to include within the province of jurisprudence certain exceptions,
items which did not fit his criteria but which should nonetheless be studied with other laws
properly so called: repealing laws, declarative laws, and imperfect lawslaws
prescribing action but without sanctions (a concept Austin ascribes to Roman [law] jurists)
(Austin 1832: Lecture I, p. 36).
In the criteria set out above, Austin succeeded in delimiting law and legal rules from religion,
morality, convention, and custom. However, also excluded from the province of
jurisprudence were customary law (except to the extent that the sovereign had, directly or
indirectly, adopted such customs as law), public international law, and parts of constitutional
law. (These exclusions alone would make Austin's theory problematic for most modern
readers.)

Within Austin's approach, whether something is or is not law depends on which people
have done what: the question turns on an empirical investigation, and it is a matter mostly of
power, not of morality. Of course, Austin is not arguing that law should not be moral, nor is
he implying that it rarely is. Austin is not playing the nihilist or the skeptic. He is merely
pointing out that there is much that is law that is not moral, and what makes something law
does nothing to guarantee its moral value. The most pernicious laws, and therefore those
which are most opposed to the will of God, have been and are continually enforced as laws
by judicial tribunals (Austin 1832: Lecture V, p. 158).
In contrast to his mentor Bentham, Austin, in his early lectures, accepted judicial lawmaking
as highly beneficial and even absolutely necessary (Austin, 1832: Lecture V, p. 163). Nor
did Austin find any difficulty incorporating judicial lawmaking into his command theory: he
characterized that form of lawmaking, along with the occasional legal/judicial recognition of
customs by judges, as the tacit commands of the sovereign, the sovereign's affirming the
orders by its acquiescence (Austin 1832: Lecture 1, pp. 3536). It should be noted,
however, that one of Austin's later lectures listed the many problems that can come with
judicial legislation, and recommended codification of the law instead (Austin 1879: vol. 2,
Lecture XXXIX, pp. 669704).

4. Criticisms
As many readers come to Austin's theory mostly through its criticism by other writers
(prominently, that of H.L.A. Hart; see also Kelsen 1941: 54-66), the weaknesses of the
theory are almost better known than the theory itself:
First, in many societies, it is hard to identify a sovereign in Austin's sense of the word (a
difficulty Austin himself experienced, when he was forced to describe the British
sovereign awkwardly as the combination of the King, the House of Lords, and all the
electors of the House of Commons). Additionally, a focus on a sovereign makes it difficult
to explain the continuity of legal systems: a new ruler will not come in with the kind of
habit of obedience that Austin sets as a criterion for a system's rule-maker.
A few responses are available to those who would defend Austin. First, some commentators
have argued that Austin is here misunderstood, in that he always meant by the sovereign
the office orinstitution which embodies supreme authority; never the individuals who happen
to hold that office or embody that institution at any given time (Cotterrell 2003: p. 63,
footnote omitted); there are certainly parts of Austin's lectures that support this reading (e.g.,
Austin 1832: Lecture V, pp. 12829; Lecture VI, p. 218).
Secondly, one could argue (see Harris 1977) that the sovereign is best understood as a
constructive metaphor: that law should be viewed as if it reflected the view of a single will (a
similar view, that law should be interpreted as if it derived from a single will, can be found in
Ronald Dworkin's work (1986: pp. 176190)).
7

Thirdly, one could argue that Austin's reference to a sovereign whom others are in the habit
of obeying but who is not in the habit of obeying anyone else, captures what a realist or
cynic would call a basic fact of political life. There is, the claim goes, entities or factions in
society that are not effectively constrained, or could act in an unconstrained way if they so
chose. For one type of example, one could point out that if there was a sufficiently large and
persistent majority among the United States electorate, nothing could contain them: they
could elect Presidents and legislators who would amend the Constitution and, through those
same officials, appoint judges who would interpret the (revised or original) Constitution in a
way amenable to their interests. A different sort of example (and some would say that there
are recent real-life examples of this type) would be a President who ignored the constraints
of statutory law, constitutional law, and international treaty commitments, while the public
and other officials lacked the will or the means to hold that President to the legal norms that
purported to constrain his or her actions.
As regards Austin's command model, it seems to fit some aspects of law poorly (e.g., rules
which grant powers to officials and to private citizensof the latter, the rules for making
wills, trusts, and contracts are examples), while excluding other matters (e.g., international
law) which we are not inclined to exclude from the category law.
More generally, it seems more distorting than enlightening to reduce all legal rules to one
type. For example, rules that empower people to make wills and contracts perhaps can be recharacterized as part of a long chain of reasoning for eventually imposing a sanction (Austin
spoke in this context of the sanction of nullity) on those who fail to comply with the
relevant provisions. However, such a re-characterization misses the basic purpose of those
sorts of lawsthey are arguably about granting power and autonomy, not punishing
wrongdoing.
A different criticism of Austin's command theory is that a theory which portrays law solely in
terms of power fails to distinguish rules of terror from forms of governance sufficiently just
that they are accepted as legitimate (or at least as reasons for action) by their own citizens.
Finally, one might note that the constitutive rules that determine who the legal officials are
and what procedures must be followed in creating new legal rules, are not commands
habitually obeyed, nor can they be expressed as habits of obedience to persons (Hart 1958:
p. 603).
(Austin was aware of some of these lines of attack, and had responses ready; it is another
matter whether his responses were adequate.) It should also be noted that Austin's work
shows a silence on questions of methodology, though this may be forgivable, given the early
stage of jurisprudence. As discussed in an earlier section, in many ways, Austin was blazing
a new path. On matters of methodology, later commentators on Austin's work have had
difficulty determining whether he is best understood as making empirical claims about the

law or conceptual claims; elements of each sort of approach can be found in his writings
(Lobban 1991: pp. 224225; Cotterrell 2003: pp. 8183).
When H.L.A. Hart revived legal positivism in the middle of the 20 th century (Hart 1958,
1994), he did it by criticizing and building on Austin's theory: for example, Hart's theory did
not try to reduce all legal rules to one kind of rule, but emphasized the varying types and
functions of legal rules; and Hart's theory, grounded partly on the distinction between
obligation and being obliged, was built around the fact that some participants within
legal systems accepted the legal rules as reasons for action, above and beyond the fear of
sanctions. Hart's hermeneutic approach, building on the internal point of view of
participants who accepted the legal system, diverged sharply from Austin's approach to law.

5. A Revisionist View?
Some modern commentators appreciate in Austin elements that were probably not foremost
in his mind (or that of his contemporary readers). For example, one occasionally sees Austin
portrayed as the first realist: in contrast both to the theorists that came before Austin and to
some modern writers on law, Austin is seen as having a keener sense of the connection of law
and power, and the importance of keeping that connection at the forefront of analysis (cf.
Cotterrell 2003: pp. 4977). One commentator wrote:
Austin's theory is not a theory of the Rule of Law: of government subject to law. It is a
theory of the rule of men: of government using law as an instrument of power. Such a view
may be considered realistic or merely cynical. But it is, in its broad outlines, essentially
coherent. (Cotterrell 2003: p. 70)
When circumstances seem to warrant a more critical, skeptical or cynical approach to law
and government, Austin's equation of law and force will be attractivehowever distant such
a reading may be from Austin's own liberal-utilitarian views at the time of his writing, or his
more conservative political views later in his life (Hamburger, 1985).

Bibliography
Primary Sources

Austin, John, 1832, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, W. Rumble (ed.),


Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

, 1879, Lectures on Jurisprudence, or The Philosophy of Positive Law, two vols.,


R. Campbell (ed.), 4th edition, rev., London: John Murray; reprint, Bristol: Thoemmes Press,
2002.

Secondary Sources
9

Bentham, Jeremy, 1789, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,


J. H. Burns & H.L.A. Hart (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
, 1970, Of Laws in General, H.L.A. Hart (ed.), London: Athlone Press.

Bix, Brian H., 2000, On the Dividing Line Between Natural Law Theory and Legal
Positivism,Notre Dame Law Review, 75: 16131624.

, 2004, Legal Positivism, in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and
Legal Theory, Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, pp.
2949.

, 2012, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context, 6th ed., London: Sweet & Maxwell.

Clark, E. C., 1883, Practical Jurisprudence: A Comment on Austin, Cambridge:


Cambridge University Press.

Cliffe Leslie, T. E., 1864, Modern Phases of Jurisprudence in England, Westminster


Review, 26: 26176 [U.S. edition, 162: 125132].

Cosgrove, Richard A., 1996, Scholars of the Law: English Jurisprudence from
Blackstone to Hart, Chapter 4, New York: New York University Press.

Cotterrell, Roger, 2003, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to


Legal Philosophy, 2nd edition, London: LexisNexis.

Dewey, James, 1894, Austin's Theory of Sovereignty, Political Science Quarterly,


9: 3152.

Duxbury, Neil, 2005, English Jurisprudence Between Austin and Hart, Virginia
Law Review, 91: 191.

Dworkin, Ronald, 1986, Law's Empire, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Finnis, John, 2000a, On the Incoherence of Legal Positivism, Notre Dame Law
Review, 75: 15971611.

, 2000b, The Truth in Legal Positivism, in The Autonomy of Law, Robert P.


George (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 195214.

Freeman, Michael & Mindus, Patricia (eds.) 2013, The Legacy of John Austin's
Jurisprudence, Dordrecht: Springer.
10

Hamburger, Lotte & Joseph, 1985, Troubled Lives: John and Sarah Austin, Toronto:
University of Toronto Press.

, 1992, Contemplating Adultery: The Secret Life of a Victorian Woman, London:


Macmillan.

Harris, J.W., 1977, The Concept of Sovereign Will, Acta Juridica (Essays in
Honour of Ben Beinart, Volume II), Cape Town: Juta & Co., 1979, pp. 115.

Hart, H.L.A., 1954, Introduction to John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence


Determined, H.L.A. Hart (ed.), London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, pp. vii-xxi.

, 1958, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,Harvard Law Review,
71: 593629.

, 1994, The Concept of Law, 2nd edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Hobbes, Thomas, 1651, Leviathan, Richard Tuck (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge


University Press, 1996.

Hume, David, 1739, A Treatise of Human Nature, David Fate Norton & Mary J.
Norton (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Kelsen, Hans, 1941, The Pute


Jurisprudence, Harvard Law Review, 55: 4470.

Leiter, Brian, 2007a, Naturalism in Legal Philosophy, Stanford Encyclopedia of


Philosophy(Spring
2007
Edition),
URL
=
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/lawphil-naturalism/>

Theory

of

Law

and

Analytical

, 2007b, Naturalizing Jurisprudence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lobban, Michael, 1991, The Common Law and English Jurisprudence 17601850,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Mill, John Stuart, 1863, Austin on Jurisprudence, Edinburgh Review, 118


(October): 43982 [U.S. edition, 118: 222244].

Moles, Robert N., 1987, Definition and Rule in Legal Theory: A Reassessment of
H.L.A. Hart and the Positivist Tradition, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Morison, W. L., 1982, John Austin, Stanford: Stanford University Press.


11

Rumble, W. E., 1985, The Thought of John Austin: Jurisprudence, Colonial Reform,
and the British Constitution, London: Athlone Press.

, 1995, Introduction, in J. Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined,


pp. vii-xxiv.

, 2005, Doing Austin Justice: The Reception of John Austin's Philosophy of Law
in Nineteenth-Century England, London: Continuum.

Savigny, Friedrich Karl von, 1975, On the Vocation of Our Age for Legislation and
Jurisprudence, Abraham Hayward (trans.), New York: Arno Press.

Schauer, Frederick, 2010, Was Austin Right After All?, Ratio Juris, 23: 121.

Schwarz, Andreas B., 1934, John Austin and the German Jurisprudence of His
Time, Politica, 1: 178199.

Sebok, Anthony J., 1998, Legal Positivism in American Jurisprudence, Cambridge:


Cambridge University Press.

Stein, Peter, 1988, The Character and Influence of the Roman Civil Law: Historical
Essays, London: The Hambledon Press.

Tapper, Colin, 1965, Austin on Sanctions, Cambridge Law Journal, 23(2): 271
287.

12

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi