Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 7

Philosophical

Presuppositions of
Hermeneutic Phenomenology
By Alan S. Cajes
Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) introduced phenomenology as a method of philosophical inquiry in
his Logical Investigations (1900-01), although he developed this approach further in Ideas I (1913).
Phenomenology, as a method, begins by experiencing phenomenon as is. It is like letting reality be without
ascribing anything into it. This means experiencing phenomenon without any interpretation. In order to
make this possible, Husserl proposed techniques, such as the phenomenological epoch, or suspension of
the natural attitude, as well as eidetic and transcendental reductions. In his later work Experience and
Judgment (1938), he used the phrase prepredicative experience (die vorprdikative Erfahrung) to come in
contact with the life-world (Lebenswelt), the world in which we are always already living and which
furnishes the ground for all cognitive performance and all scientific determination (Husserl, 1938, p. 38).
Phenomenology, therefore, begins by suspending knowledge and the approach is through a strategy of
absolutely denying any knowledge. Husserl (1938) explains the need to go back to the phenomenon that
appears as such; hence, not as I see it (p. 34). By doing this phenomenological reduction, the
phenomenologist grasps the essence or the universal through a particular phenomenon. Husserl (1938)
calls this eidetic intuition. Thus, phenomenology is similar to the eidetic sciences, such as the mathematical
sciences.
Martin Heidegger (18891976) took off from Husserl, his teacher, but proposed a phenomenology that
does not suspend judgment or knowledge when dealing with phenomena. He altered the direction that
Husserl set and argued for a phenomenology that adopts the historicity, facticity, temporarity or
concreteneness of human experience. This means a phenomenology that involves interpretation or
hermeneutical phenomenology.[1]
Heideggers line of thought can be traced back to his 1913 doctoral thesis entitled Die Lehrevom Urteil in
Psychologismus (The Doctrine of Judgment in Psychologism), which posed the question: What is the
meaning of meaning? For him, the very act of asking the question presupposes a pre-understanding of
meaning. He propounded this idea in his Being and Time (1927; trans. 1962) arguing that phainomenon is
that which shows itself in itself, the manifest (p. 28), logos is discourse or to let something be seen (p.
32) and that truth or aletheia is to reveal or disclose that which is hidden (p. 33). Thus, the hermeneutic
phenomenologist interprets phenomena based on his/her beingness in time. Clearly, Moran (2002) says,
he deviated from Husserl and linked his ideas to Dilthey, who was influenced by Schleiermacher.
Freidrich Schleiermacher (1768-1834) started his hermeneutic exposition with an analysis of the
methodology of Georg Anton Friedrich Ast (1778-1841) and Friedrich August Wolf (1759-1824). The reason
is that he wanted to provide a proper methodology to hermeneutics itself. The search for a hermeneutic
method is important because we often find instances where difficult passages are carelessly overlooked or
foolishly distorted because of the interpreters pedantic lack of sensitivity (Schleiermacher, 1829, p. 62).

Schleiermacher developed his methodology that he called the divinatory and the comparative or the
psychological and the grammatical. The formulation of his method is based on the notion that hermeneutics
or the art of interpretation aims to understand a thought or series of thoughts expressed in words
(Schleiermacher, 1829, p. 66). The grammatical interpretation follows canons stating that a more precise
determination of any point in a given text must be decided on the basis of language common to the author
and his original public, and the meaning of each word of a passage must be determined by the context in
which it occurs (Schleiermacher, 1990, pp. 72-97.
Grammatical interpretation, however, is not enough. The art of understanding should be sensitive to the
particular way an author combines the thoughts, for had those thoughts been formulated differently, even in
the same historical situation and the same kind of presentation, the result would have been different
(Schleiermacher, 1829, p. 68). Thus, the divinatory method is necessary to understand the creative act of
the author, which is to reconstruct the creative act that begins with the generation of thoughts which
captivate the author and to understand how the requirement of the moment could draw upon the living
treasure of words in the authors mind in order to produce just this way of putting it and no other
Schleiermacher, 1829, p. 11).
The two methods are the only methods of interpretation, says Schleiermacher. They are necessary to
obtain complete understanding and must complement each other (Schleiermacher, 1829, p. 72). This is
the reason why the success of the interpretation depends on the interpreters linguistic competence and
ability for knowing people.
While Schleiermacher starts with a critique of past hermeneuticists, Wilhelm Dilthey (1833-1911) begins
with the question: Is it possible to study individual human beings and particular forms of human existence
scientifically? Diltheys answer to this question led hermeneutics into the heart of the human sciences,
particularly in the science of history.
For Dilthey (1986), the human sciences have the advantage over the physical sciences because their
subject isinner reality directly experienced in all its complexity (P. 33). Consequently, the human
sciences deliver a form of knowledge unlike from that of the natural sciences. The difference lies primarily
in the difference of the subject of the two disciplines. They physical sciences deals with physical entities
while the human sciences deal with human persons who are capable of self-reflection. Humans are
endowed with rationality that could turn around and examine itself. This enables them to shape their lives in
response to their historical conditions. In the process of living, humans create a culture that curves a niche
or historicity.
Every action is a function of what is the mind. In other words, there are no human actions that do not spring
from human cognition. Thoughts, therefore, beget actions. Humans are what they think. Indeed, as Dilthey
claimed, the physical expressions are manifestations of mental events or states. They appear in the world
of the senses as manifestations and expressions of the mind. These manifestations of the mind are called
life expressions.
There are three types of life-expressions. The first type includes conceptions, judgments, and larger ideas.
The second type consists of actions. The third type covers expressions of experience. The first type of lifeexpressions refers to plain statements that can easily be understood when expressed. Those under the
second type are not products of an intention to communicate. They are more difficult to interpret and are

generally the expression of the cultural patterns of peoples own communities. Thus, it is important to
distinguish which actions are the life-expressions against the total life-structure in which the actions are
grounded. The third type are the most difficult to interpret because of the special relation that exists among
expressions of experience, the life from which they emerge, and the mind that interprets them.
The mind, however, can penetrate the inside of these life-expressions through an activity called
understanding. This is what Dilthey (1986) calls the process by which we recognize some inner content
from signs received by the senses. Indeed, understanding is the process of recognizing a mental state
from a sense-given sign by which it is expressed (p. 94). This systematic understanding of recorded
expression is called exegesis or interpretation (p. 94).
Understanding takes the form of what he calls elementary and higher understanding. Elementary
understanding refers to the immediate understanding of life-expressions in ones familiar community. The
meaning of these expressions can be immediately understood without a need for further investigation. The
higher forms of understanding are more complex due to the possible contractions between the expression
and the mental state or event. Thus, interpretation of these forms of understanding demands further
verification.
What makes understanding or interpretation systematic? According to Dilthey (1986), the analysis of
understandingis the basis of making interpretation systematicThe possibility of valid interpretation can
be deduced from the nature of understanding (p. 103). This point is important because it constitutes the
anvil by which Dilthey forged his hermeneutical theory. In fact, the analysis of understanding is his
hermeneutic methodology. The problem now is not what people can know, but how people know. In other
words, the hermeneutic problem is concerned with the nature of historical knowledge because lifeexpressions are the responses of human beings to their own historical condition.
Dilthey made his point clear. Humans react to their own historical condition. This reaction takes the form of
life-expressions. Life-expressions are the manifestations of the mental states or events that ground them.
Understanding is the process by which one recognizes the mental states or events.
But what makes understanding possible? The possibility of understanding life-expressions hinges on the
common nature shared by human beings and the fact they express their thoughts in language. What
Dilthey is saying is that human beings can understand the feelings or thoughts of other human beings
through the life-expressions because they too express feelings and thoughts through life-expressions. This
commonality of nature, of the way to express the mental events, makes one capable of understanding the
meaning behind the sense-given signs.
In addition, human beings express their thoughts in language. Language is a product of culture, which is a
system of behavior, attitudes and beliefs that all human beings have. This is the reason why it is possible to
reproduce a life that is foreign to an interpreter into ones own thoughts. By so doing, understanding could
lead to the reconstruction of the authors intentional acts in its proper cultural and linguistic context, and
more so, it could mean understanding the author better than he understood himself/herself (Dilthey, 1986,
pp. 103-104).
Through the critique of historical reason, Dilthey (1986) answers his hermeneutic problem: What is the
nature of historical knowledge? Given the nature of the inquiring consciousness, then human beings should

be studied in the light of it. It is on this basis that hermeneutics, as the theory of interpretation of lifeexpressions, can be the epistemology of the human sciences (p. 152).
For Hans Georg Gadamer (1900-2002), the question plays a central role in hermeneutics. It is the
questions that beget assertions. Every assertion is an answer to a question. Gadamer (1986) says, which
answers to which question fits the facts. This phrase is in fact the hermeneutical Urphanomen: No assertion
is possible that cannot be understood as an answer to a question, an assertion can only be understood in
this way (p. 185). Indeed, he says, the real power of hermeneutical consciousness is our ability to see
what is questionable (p. 186).
Productive questions are products of the imagination, which in turn is a function of reason. The imagination
does not only create questions, it anticipates them. This was the case of Galileo who worked out the laws
of the free fall at a time when no one could have observed a free fall empirically, since it was only in postGalilean times that a vacuum was experimentally produced (Gadamer, 1986, p. 63). Gadamer (1986)
explains:
It is imagination (phantasie) that is the decisive function of the scholar. Imagination naturally has a
hermeneutic function and serves the sense for what is questionable. It serves the ability to expose real,
productive questions, something in which, generally speaking, only he who masters all the methods of his
science succeeds (p. 186).
Gadamer stresses the value of imagination against method, especially the methodology of the natural
sciences. The use of the imagination in hermeneutics can only be equaled by one who masters all the
methods of his science. In other words, the art of hermeneutics should not be limited to one or several
methodologies. It should encompass all of the methodologies ever known to man. Whether it is possible to
know and master all the existing methodologies, that is another question.
The reason why Gadamer has a critical attitude towards method is that it does not guarantee the
acquisition of valid and certain knowledge. Gadamer (1986) explains,
Whoever wants to learn a science has to learn to master its methodology. But we also know that
methodology as such does not guarantee in any way the productivity of its application. Any experience of
life can confirm the fact that there is such thing as methodological sterility, that is, the application of a
method to something not really worth knowing, to something that has not been made an object of
investigation on the basis of a genuine question (p. 54).
Thus, science is not anymore the crowning glory of rationality as its devotees have claimed. It is no longer
the quintessence of knowledge and of what is worth knowing, but a way. It is a way of addressing and
penetrating into unexplored and unmasked realms (Gadamer, 1986, p. 242).
Gadamer has declared an all-out intellectual war against the method of science, most especially the
modern sciences, which, through method, impose on natural consciousness a deep-rooted alienation. The
notion of alienation corresponds to what he calls the I-It relation, that is, when the interpreter treats the text
as a mere object of interpretation and not as an Other, whose otherness is an invitation for a dialogue.

Science, with its inherent alienation, is directly opposed to Gadamers idea of hermeneutics as an I-Thou
activity, a communication, and a dialectical process. Bernstein (1986) explains,
As Gadamer frequently reiterates, the hermeneutic phenomenon is basically not a problem of method at
all. It is not concerned with a method of understanding, by means of which texts are subjected to scientific
investigation like all other objects of experience. It is not concerned primarily with amassing ratified
knowledge that satisfies the methodological ideal of science yet, it is concerned, here too, with knowledge
and with truth.For Gadamers perspective, it has been the obsession with Method, and with thinking that
the primary task of hermeneutics is to specify a distinctive method of the Geisteswissenschaften, which
plagued and distorted nineteenth-century hermeneutics (p. 88).
He further emphasized that Gadamer constantly plays on the idea that it is philosophical hermeneutics, not
epistemology, method or science, which can achieve what philosophy has always promised humankind
some profound access to truth that is not available to us by the limited and normal methods of science (p.
362).
The hermeneutic problem, for Paul Ricoeur (1913-2005), was first raised within the limits of exegesis, that
is, within a framework of a discipline which proposes to understand a text to understand its beginning with
its intention on the basis of what it attempts to say (Ricoeur, 1980, p. 236). This means that the goal of
interpretation is not merely to decipher the literal meaning of a text but, more importantly, the genesis of the
text so that the interpreter would be able to ground what it attempts to say. That is why Ricoeur (1980)
considers interpretation as the work of thought which consists in deciphering the hidden meaning implied
in the literal meaning (p. 245).
Since Gadamer has discounted the capacity of methodical science to interpret, how would Ricoeur answer
the hermeneutic problem? First, Ricoeur (1986) says, that the methodology of the sciences implies an
assumption of distance, which presupposes the destruction of the primordial relation of belonging: without
which there would be no relation to the historical as such (302). Now, this idea of distanciation hinders a
person from understanding the text beyond its literal meaning, that is, the cultural epoch that conditions the
embodiment of thought in the text. To correct this distanciation brought about by the methodology of the
sciences is a precondition for understanding. This is so because the purpose of all interpretation is to
conquer the past cultural epoch to which the text belongs and the interpreter himself. By overcoming the
distance, by making himself contemporary with the text, he makes its familiar, that is, he makes it as his
own (Ricoeur, 1980, p. 249. Overcoming the problem of distance is, therefore, the starting point of
Ricoeurs hermeneutics. This implies that the methodological attitude of the sciences has to be abandoned
because placing at a distance is a methodological attitude (Ricoeur, 1986, p. 311).
By rejecting the scientific methodology, Ricoeur attempts to bring back hermeneutics to ontology. Ricoeur
(1986) declares that the struggle against methodological distanciation transforms hermeneutics into a
critique of critique; it must always push the rock of Sisyphus up again, restore the ontological ground that
methodology has eroded away (p. 315). Method has robbed humans of their historical existence and to
correct this necessitates a radical repositioning of epistemology. Ricoeur (1986) explains,
To restore the historical dimension of man requires much more than a simple methodological reform
Only a fundamental upheaval that subordinates the theory of knowledge to ontology can bring out the real

sense of the Vorstruktur des Verstehens the forestructure (or structure of anticipation) of understanding
that is the condition for any rehabilitation of prejudice (p. 306).
Thus Ricoeur (1980) grounds hermeneutics in ontology via what he calls the short route, just like what
Heidegger did. He says,
"I call such an ontology of understanding the short route because, breaking with any discussion of method,
it carries itself directly to the level of an ontology of finite being in order to recover understanding, no longer
as a mode of knowledge, but rather as a mode of being Instead of asking: on what condition can a
knowing subject understand a text or history? one asks: What kind of being is it whose being consists of
understanding? The hermeneutic problem thus becomes a problem of the Analytic of this being, Dasein,
which exists through understanding (p. 239).
With the radical overhaul of the epistemic framework, understanding ceases to be a mode of knowledge.
As a result, the question of truth is no longer a question of method; it is the question of the manifestation of
being for a being whose existence consists in understanding being (Ricouer, 1980, p. 242).
By giving hermeneutics an ontological dimension, interpretation is brought to a new context. The subject
who interprets signs or symbols is no longer the cogito rather, he being who discovers, by the exegesis of
his own life, that he is placed in being before he places and possesses himself (Ricouer, 1980, p. 243).
This paves the way for what he calls the overcoming of distance, in which hermeneutical phenomenologists
can make themselves a contemporary of the text, and can thereby make it as their own.
In summary, hermeneutic phenomenology recognizes the importance of a phenomenon as the object of
knowing. However, it does not suspend any interpretation of the phenomenon unlike the Hussserlian
approach. What hermeneutic phenomenology seeks is to understand the phenomenon by interpreting it as
if the interpreter enters into a dialogue with the phenomenon.
[1]

This approach is associated with Heidegger, Gadamer and Ricouer and is distinguished from
Transcendental phenomenology (Eugen Fink, et. al.), Existential phenomenology (Merleau-Ponty, et. al.),
Linguistic phenomenology (Derrida, et. al.), and Ethical phenomenology (Scheler, et. al.) Retrieved August
3, 2014 from http://www.phenomenologyonline.com/inquiry/orientations-in-phenomenology/
References
Betti, Emilio. (1980). Hermeneutics as the General Methodology of the Geisteswissenschaften. In: Josef
Bleicher. (1980). Contemporary Hermeneutics: Hermeneutics as Method, Philosophy and Critique.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980.
Bleicher, J. (1980). Contemporary Hermeneutics: hermeneutics as method, philosophy, and
critique. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Bohman, James. (1991) New Philosophy of Social Science: Problems of Indeterminacy. United Kingdom:
Polity Press.

Caputo, J. D. (1987). Radical hermeneutics: Repetition, deconstruction, and the hermeneutic project.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Dilthey, W. (196466). Collected Works, Vol. 7, [originally Stutgart, Teubner 1927]
_______([1900] 1990) Die Entstehung der Hermeneutik. In: Gessamelte Schriften, vol 5, 8th edn. Misch, G.
(ed)
Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time. Oxford: Blackwell. [1927, Sein and Zeit]
Kant, Immanuel. (1987). Critique of Judgment: Including the First Introduction, trans. and intro.
Klemm, David E. (1986). Hermeneutical Inquiry Volume 1 The Interpretation of Texts. Atlanta: Scholars
Press.
Madison, G. B. (1988). The hermeneutics of postmodernity: Figures and themes. Indianapolis: Indiana
University Press
Moran, Demot. (2002). Introduction to Phenomenology. Taylor & Francis e-Library.
Mueller-Vollmer, Kurt. (Ed.). (2006). The Hermeneutics Reader. New York: The Continuum International
Publishing Group, Inc.
Ricoeur, Paul. (1970). Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation (Dennis Savage, Trans.). New
Haven: Yale University Press.
_______. (1981). Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action and Interpretation,
Translated and edited by Thompson, J.B., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ricoeur, Paul & Mudge, Lewis S. (1980) Essays in Biblical Interpretation. Philadelphia: Fortress Press.
Wachterhauser, Brice R. (Ed.). (1986). Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy. New York: State University
of New York Press.
_______. (Ed.). (1994). Hermeneutics and Truth. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
_______. (1999). Beyond Being. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi