Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 6

bcbl conferences

Priming implicit communication


Rees, A. & Bott, L.
Cardiff University

Speakers must choose whether to communicate explicitly, and say exactly what
they mean, or implicitly, and let the listener do the work. We investigate whether
this choice can be primed (e.g., Bock, 1987).
Participants engaged in a communication game in which they took turns with a
confederate describing and identifying a card. Speakers could be implicit,
requiring the addressee to use a conversational implicature (Grice, 1975), or
explicit. The DV was whether the participant produced an implicit or an explicit
construction. Experiment 1 used a between-subject manipulation, in which a
confederate described target cards using either explicit or implicit expressions.
Participants in the explicit condition used more explicit expressions than those
in the implicit condition. Experiment 2 manipulated the priming within-subject
and found similar results.
Our findings demonstrate that the decision to communicate implicitly depends
on the style embraced by the conversational partner. The only previous
suggestion about why people communicate implicitly is that they do so for
reasons of politeness (Brown & Levinson, 1978) and our results cannot be
explained in this way. We suggest our effects arose because we primed
abstract, meaning-based structures associated with conversational implicatures,
similar to syntactic frames (Branigan & Pickering, 1998).
Posters
A pragmatic account of implicit causality
van den Hoven, E. & Ferstl, E.
University of Freiburg

In sentences like the following, the preferred interpretation of the pronoun 'she'
depends on the matrix verb: 'Mary frightened/criticized Sue because she was
unpredictable.' This phenomenon is known as implicit causality (IC). Whereas
recent studies on IC attribute causality biases to lexical semantics, we introduce
a pragmatic account of IC. On our account, causality biases are due to
inferences to the stereotype. That is, verbs do not entail anything about likely
explanations. Rather, likely explanations are inferred. In a stereotypical
situation, A may criticize B because she thinks B did something wrong, but this
is a defeasible inference, unlike the requirement that A communicates
something. Hence there is no inconsistency in the sentence 'Mary criticized
John, although she knew he didn't do anything wrong.', like there is in the
sentence '??Mary criticized John, although she didn't communicate anything.'
The pragmatic account predicts a strong influence of discourse context. Data
from a story completion study support this account, showing that IC biases can
be altered with a discourse context that runs counter to the stereotype (e.g. A
has reason to be jealous prior to criticizing B). Data for a follow-up visual world
study investigating the online comprehension process are pending.
[PS-1.6] All the time you need to calculate implicatures
Dotlacil, J.
University of Groningen

It is well-known that when interpreting, we consider what has been said, as well
as what has not been said. Thus, if someone mentions that some boys are

tired, it is common to assume that the fact that the speaker did not use "all"
instead of "some" suggests that the universal statement is not true (implicated
meaning; implicature). Recently, several frameworks have been developed that
model the way humans arrive at implicatures (e.g., Bayesian models, RSA
theory). However, such statistical models are atemporal -- they only predict
whether an implicature is drawn, not what amount of time it would take.
I present an ACT-R model that aims to capture the data from Bott and Noveck
(2004) (B&N), who studied implicatures in sentences like "Some elephants are
mammals". The model starts by learning implicatures related to "some" (by
learning what quantifiers are relevant alternatives). This process arguably
happens as part of acquisition. The resulting model applied to B&N and
supplemented with simple reasoning module for category relations (elephants
are mammals) correctly predicts mean RTs for target sentences with and
without implicatures, as well as several mean RTs for baseline conditions which
use "all" instead of "some".
[PS-1.12] Contextual effects on online pragmatic inferences
King, J. , Loy, J. & Corley, M.
University of Edinburgh

Where the veracity of a statement is in question, listeners show a bias towards


interpreting speaker disfluency as signalling dishonesty. This bias is not limited
to post-hoc judgements, but can also be found during online speech processing.
The present study investigated whether listeners were influenced by contextual
information about the potential causes of speaker disfluency. Participants
listened to a speaker describe the location of some treasure, while viewing a
scene comprised of the referent and a distractor. They were told that not all
utterances were honest, and their task was to click on where they believed the
treasure to be. In line with previous work, participants were more likely to click
on the distractor when the description was disfluent. Furthermore, this effect
corresponded to an early fixation bias to the distractor, demonstrating the online
nature of the pragmatic judgement. When there was a plausible external cause
of the speaker disfluency (background noise), however, participants initially
fixated on the referent, only later fixating on and selecting the distractor. One
account of these findings would suggest that whilst participants did make early
inferences about the contextual causes of disfluencies, these were overridden
by an explicit dishonesty bias for disfluent utterances.
[PS-1.11] Cognitive Load Impairs But Does Not Suspend Contrastive
Inferences
Stranahan, E. , Hardenbergh, D. & Snedeker, J.
Harvard University

Working memory load impairs scalar implicature computation [Marty et al.


2013], suggesting quantifier upper-bounds are not encoded lexically. Do scalar
adjectives ('tall') encode contrast lexically, or are pragmatic processes required?
If contrast is lexical, we expect minimal interference with contrastive inference
(CI, [Grodner & Sedivy, 2011]) computation by cognitive load. We manipulated
how many letters participants memorized alongside a picture-selection task
designed to elicit CIs [G&S]. In both low- and high-load conditions, participants
looked equally at a tall pitcher and a tall glass before hearing the final noun

when instructed to 'Click on the tall glass' when no short glass was present. But
when a short glass was introduced, low-load participants showed a strong
preference to look at the tall glass after hearing 'tall', and high-load participants'
displayed a similar preference but one significantly weaker 200-300ms after the
adjective. Listeners are thus able to use context to derive contrastive meaning
even while under cognitive load--suggesting contrast is lexically encoded--but
this ability can be impaired under high load---suggesting some aspect of CI
computation is pragmatic.
PS-2.6] Allocation and use of processing capacity in language production are
reflected in P300 amplitude and theta power
Shitova, N. 1, 2 , Roelofs, A. 1 , Coughler, C. 1 & Schriefers , H. 1
1 Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University Nijmegen
2 International Max Planck Research School for Language Sciences, Max Planck Institute for
Psycholinguistics Nijmegen

There is some evidence that the allocation and use of processing capacity in
spoken language production are reflected in the amplitude of the P300
component. However, little is known about their relation to reaction time (RT)
and theta power, which reflects capacity demand outside the language domain.
To examine this, we had participants switch every second trial between
describing pictures using noun phrases with one adjective (size only; simple
condition) or two adjectives (size and colour; complex condition) in the format
determiner + adjective(s) + noun. RTs were longer for complex than for simple
trials. Moreover, complexity and sequence interacted: RTs were longer on
switch than on repeat trials for simple phrases (switch cost) but shorter on
switch than on repeat trials for complex phrases (switch benefit), while there
was no main effect of sequence. P300 amplitude and theta power increased
with complexity. There was no main effect of sequence in electrophysiological
measures, but both P300 amplitude and theta power decreased on switch trials
as compared to repeat trials for simple phrases. These results provide evidence
that the allocation and use of processing capacity in language production are
reflected in P300 amplitude and theta power.

[PS-2.42] Interference effects in sentence comprehension: A


synthesis
Jger, L. 1 , Engelmann, F. 2 & Vasishth, S. 1, 3
1 University of Potsdam
2 University of Manchester
3 Universit Paris Dauphine

Engelmann et al (2015) (http://bit.ly/1Vu1Kk1) recently reviewed 68 published


papers (SPR and eyetracking) on interference effects in sentence
comprehension, focusing on so-called Target Match and Mismatch

configurations; in Match, the correct target for retrieval fully matches the
retrieval cues, in Mismatch there is only a partial match. The studies also vary in
whether interference is proactive (PI) or retroactive (RI), and in type of
dependency: antecedent-reflexive/reciprocal, subject-verb, and agreement
attraction configurations. We present the first-ever quantitative synthesis of
these studies using a Bayesian random-effects meta-analysis. The metaanalysis shows that in Match, overall a slowdown is observed (posterior mean
2.5 ms, 95% credible intervals (CrI) -2.75,8.49). In Mismatch, too, a slowdown is
seen (mean 8.43, CrI -0.8,17.74). A meta-regression further showed that (a)
number-cue based agreement attraction is different from other dependencies as
it leads to a speedup compared to other retrieval cues (Match: mean -5.28, CrI
-10.27,-0.35; Mismatch: -8.35, CrI -16.64,-0.35), (b) in Match, PI leads to a
slowdown compared to RI (mean 5.19, CrI 0.2,10.38), (c) in Mismatch, PI leads
to a speedup (mean -5.48, CrI -14.05,4.09), (d) in Mismatch, if the distractor is
more prominent, a greater slowdown is observed (mean 13.8, CrI -5.74,33.57).

[PS-3.7] Believing what you're told:Politeness and scalar


inferences
Mazzarella, D. 1 , Trouche, E. 1 , Mercier, H. . 1, 2 & Noveck, I. 1
1 Institut des Sciences Cognitive 'Marc Jeannerod', Universit de Lyon / CNRS
2 University of Neuchtel

Recent behavioural studies in experimental pragmatics investigate the effect of


politeness on the derivation of scalar inferences, e.g. 'Not all X-ed' from 'Some
X-ed'. Bonnefon and colleagues (2009, 2011) claim that when the scalar
utterance is face-threatening ('Some people hated your speech') (i) the scalar
inference is blocked, (ii) the semantic interpretation of 'some' (at least some) is
arrived at slowly and effortfully. This contradicts much evidence showing that
the derivation of the scalar inference comes with extra cost (since Bott &
Noveck, 2004). Drawing on the distinction between comprehension and
acceptance of communicated information, we hypothesized that in facethreatening contexts scalar inferences are derived but less likely to be accepted
as true, and that the extra processing effort is associated with rejecting the
communicated content. We tested our hypothesis through a series of MTurk
studies inspired by Bonnefon et al.'s task. Our main innovation is that we
separated the presentation of the scalar utterance (comprehension stage) from
participants' evaluation of it (epistemic assessment stage) so that Reaction
Times to each part could be measured separately. In line with our predictions,
we found that the latencies in the face-threatening condition were due to longer
RT at the epistemic assessment stage.

[PS-3.13] Consequences of scalar inference derivation revealed


through eye movement measures
Politzer-Ahles, S. 1, 2 & Husband, E. M. 1
1 University of Oxford
2 New York University Abu Dhabi

[Scalar] pragmatic inferences are sensitive to context. For instance, in a


sentence where 'some' is likely to trigger a 'some'+>'not all' inference (e.g.,
upward-entailing 'Yousef ate some of the cookies, and the rest are on the
table'), 'the rest' is read more quickly than in a sentence where 'some' is unlikely
to trigger the inference (e.g., downward-entailing 'If Yousef ate some of the
cookies, then the rest are on the table'), because the inference makes salient
the complement set, e.g., the cookies that were not eaten. Little is known,
however, about the correlates of these effects in eye-tracking, which offers a
more fine-grained window into reading processes. We measured eye
movements in 33 English speakers as they read such stimuli (based on
Hartshorne et al., 2015, LCN). Like most self-paced reading studies, we did not
find a significant slowdown on the scalar expression, but did find significant
facilitation at 'the rest' in total reading times (p=.031). Furthermore, first-pass
reading times changed over the course of the experiment: a facilitation effect
only emerged as the experiment progressed, suggesting that the manner in
which implicatures were processed underwent adaptation as a result of
exposure to the stimuli.

[PS-3.43] Investigating the time course of pragmatic expectations


- ERP evidence on German implicature processing
Augurzky, P. & Franke, M.
University of Tuebingen

ERP studies on scalar implicatures show heterogeneous results with respect to


time course of inference generation, potential processing cost, and observed
ERP correlates of implicature processing. Hypothesizing that results may differ
because of a previous focus on specific sentential positions (i.e. the quantifier or
its argument), we investigated the time-course of implicature processing by
comparing ERPs at different positions (quantifier, adjective, and clause-final
NP). German sentences like 'All/Some dots are red/blue that are in the
circle/square' were preceded by pictures showing a square and a circle,
containing variable proportions of red/blue circles. Our hypothesis is largely
confirmed by standard ERP analyses involving ANOVAS at each position of
interest.
Moreover, we suggest a post-hoc modeling approach based on subjects'
incrementally updated pragmatic expectations about sentence continuations.

We derive pragmatic expectations from a variant of the Rational Speech Act


model (Frank & Goodman, 2012) as a quantitative measure of what a speaker
seeing the picture would likely utter. This measure is a highly successful
predictor in a regression model of the observed ERPs, suggesting that EEG
data might be influenced by violations of listener expectations more generally:
not only syntactic or semantic (e.g. Levy 2008), but also pragmatic expectations
may matter.

[PS-3.57] Question structure and non-actuality implicatures


Kim, C.
University of Kent

Non-actuality implicatures (NAIs; Grant, Clifton & Frazier 2012) highlight the
contrast between a described state of affairs and the actual world, introducing
implicit Questions under Discussion (QUD; Roberts 1996) as to whether the
described state holds. NAIs are triggered by predicates like want or modals like
should; e.g. ''Alice should've eaten breakfast'' implicates Alice did not eat
breakfast. This study asks whether the question structure of the discourse
containing a NAI trigger influences how likely the inference is to survive, or
alternatively, be cancelled. Experiment1 varied whether NAI sentences
appeared as an answer to a QUD followed by another QUD (creating the
impression of a complete answer to the first question), or as one of multiple
continuations all partially answering the same QUD. Even though NAIs were
never explicitly cancelled, discourses where NAI sentences were construed as
partial answers gave rise to more ''cancellation'' interpretations (''Alice should've
eaten breakfast'' meaning that she did eat breakfast). Experiment2 asks
whether, even in structurally congruent discourses, the type of questions
following a NAI can shift interpretations toward implicature or cancellation
readings. NAIs followed by ''Why not?'' questions reinforced the implicature,
whereas ''Why?'' (''Why is it important to eat breakfast?'') questions increased
cancellation interpretations.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi