Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 10

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

The metaphor of epigenesis: Kant, Blumenbach and Herder


Daniela Helbig a, Dalia Nassar b, *
a
Unit for the History and Philosophy of Science, The University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia
b
Philosophy Department, The University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: Over the last few decades, the meaning of the scientic theory of epigenesis and its signicance for
Available online 6 July 2016 Kants critical philosophy have become increasingly central questions. Most recently, scholars have
argued that epigenesis is a key factor in the development of Kants understanding of reason as self-
Keywords: grounding and self-generating. Building on this work, our claim is that Kant appealed to not just any
Kant; epigenetic theory, but specically Johann Friedrich Blumenbachs account of generation, and that this
Epigenesis;
appeal must be understood not only in terms of self-organization, but also in terms of the demarcation of
Metaphor;
a specic domain of inquiry: for Blumenbach, the study of life; for Kant, the study of reason. We argue
Analogy;
Biology;
that Kant adopted this specic epigenetic model as a result of his dispute with Herder regarding the
Blumenbach; independence of reason from nature. Blumenbachs conception of epigenesis and his separation of a
Herder; domain of the living from the non-living lent Kant the tools to demarcate metaphysics, and to guard
Transcendental deduction reason against Herders attempts to naturalize it.
2016 Published by Elsevier Ltd.

Over the last few decades, Kants interest in the life sciences and concepts of the understanding.4 In the second edition of the
the role of the life sciences in the development of his critical phi- Critique of Pure Reason, however, Kant adds that the legitimacy of
losophy have attracted greater scholarly attention. One strand of the categories can only be established by thinking of them in terms
investigation, opened up by Timothy Lenoir in 1982, examines the of a system of the epigenesis of pure reason.5 Accordingly, other
crucial role of the life sciences in the Critique of Judgment and the commentators have claimed that by 1787 Kant rejected the meta-
inuence of Kants views on the life sciences themselves.1 A second phor of preformation, and instead introduced that of epigenesis to
strand has argued that key ideas from the life sciences played explicate the non-empirical and non-arbitrary character of the
pivotal roles in the development of Kants earlier writings, espe- categories.6
cially the Critique of Pure Reason.2 Kants interest in the competing While the disagreement over Kants favored biological model is
theories of generationdpreformation and epigenesisdis regarded explicit, his metaphorical use of these models in the context of the
as an especially signicant interpretative tool for understanding the generation of the pure concepts of the understanding has gone
origin, meaning, and role of the pure concepts of the understand- largely unproblematized. According to Phillip Sloan, biological
ing. Thus, Kants statements about the birth place of the pure models of explanation ground7 Kants cognitive theory; they
concepts, and his correlative use of terms such as Keime (seeds) and constitute its scientic foundation.8 Taking the primacy of sci-
Anlagen (predispositions)3 to describe their development, have led entic investigation as a given, Sloan sees Kant as altering his
some interpreters to suggest that Kant used the preformationist theory of reason when this foundation shifts. Gnter Zller, by
model of generation in order to explicate the generation of the pure contrast, regards the purpose of the use of the terms preformation
and epigenesis as more decorative than functional: doctrines of

* Corresponding author.
5
E-mail addresses: daniela.helbig@sydney.edu.au (D. Helbig), dalia.nassar@sydney. Kant (1781/1787), B167.
6
edu.au (D. Nassar). This is the key claim made by Zller (1988). Although Mensch (2013) agrees
1
Lenoir (1982). with Zllers understanding of the signicance of the metaphor of epigenesis, she
2
See Sloan (2002), Zller (1988), and especially Mensch (2013), whose book- demonstrates that Kants turn to epigenesis came much earlier than 1787. She does
length study of the topic of epigenesis in the pre-critical writings and the rst not, however, explicitly address the question of whether there was a transition in
Critique has generated new interest in Kants use of the term. Kants thinking between 1781 and 1787.
3 7
Kant (1781/1787), A66/B90-91. Sloan (2002), 22.
4 8
Sloan (2002). Sloan (2002), 24.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2016.05.003
0039-3681/ 2016 Published by Elsevier Ltd.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107 99

reason are illustrate[d] by means of an analogy, or guratively experience, on natural development) that the metaphor can be
represented by them.9 Neither approach, however, captures the regarded as playing a crucial role in the Transcendental
signicance of the appearance of language borrowed from the life Deduction.12
sciences in crucial parts of the Critique of Pure Reason, whether in Our aims are thus twofold. In the rst instance, we seek to offer a
the Transcendental Analytic or the Transcendental Deduction. new perspective on Kants interest in Blumenbach, via Herder, and
The rst aim of this paper is to clarify the role of the metaphors to show how Kants use of biological metaphors should be under-
of generation in the critical philosophy. We argue that Kants 1787 stood neither as naturalistically nor as illustratively, but as both a
reference is to a specic epigenetic theory, that of Johann Friedrich reection and instrumentalization of emerging disciplinary dis-
Blumenbach rather than Caspar Friedrich Wolff, and that its tinctions in the natural sciences. In the second, we suggest a new
metaphorical use in the context of Kants theory of cognition carries way by which the metaphor of epigenesis can help us to better
wider programmatic connotations, which cannot be grasped by understand the Transcendental Deduction. Our reinterpretation is
taking the analogy with biological generation to be either a natu- based on a clear distinction between Wolffs and Blumenbachs
ralistic blueprint, or a mere illustration. Blumenbachs vitalistic versions of epigenesis. On that basis, Kants use of epigenesis to
theory of epigenesis, and its central notion of Bildungstrieb, func- describe his conception of the mind speaks not only to the
tioned as one of the emerging demarcations of the subject area of deduction of the categories, but also to long-standing questions
the life sciences, thereby clearly distinguishing it from the physical regarding Kants understanding of the unity of reason.
sciences. In various contexts, Kant warned against the confusion of
the problems of metaphysics with those of the special sciences, and 1. Kant on scientic theories of generation prior to the
he had a keen interest in mapping the boundaries of those special Critique of Pure Reason
disciplines.10 His use of Blumenbachs theory as a metaphor in the
context of his conception of reason must therefore be understood Long before his much-cited endorsement of Blumenbachs
not simply in terms of the self-organization or spontaneity of formulation of an epigenetic theory, Kant occasionally discussed
reason,11 but also in terms of the demarcation of a specic domain the competing theories of generation, epigenesis and preformation.
of inquiry: for Blumenbach, that of the study of life; for Kant, that of However, these discussions occur in a number of different contexts.
the study of reason. They weigh the various problems Kant sees with both of the the-
More specically, we argue that Kant introduced the metaphor ories, but their primary goal is neither to espouse one theory over
of epigenesis into his theory of reason in 1787 as a result of his the other as a scientic explanation of the generation of living
dispute with Herder about the independence of reason from nature, beings, nor to use them metaphorically to explicate problems
followed by his explicit adoption of epigenesis as a scientic theory outside the life sciences.13 Against this background, the shift in the
of generation in the Critique of Judgment in 1790. Blumenbachs Critique of Judgment in 1790 is signicant. In this latter work, Kant
separation of a domain of the living from the non-living in terms of explicitly distinguishes two different contexts in which theories of
his notion of Bildungstrieb lent Kant the conceptual tools by which generation are relevant to him, and endorses epigenesis in both.
to demarcate metaphysics as the study of reason, and thus to guard Firstly, he declares Blumenbachs epigenetic theory to provide an
the domain of reason against Herders attempts to naturalize it. We appropriate scientic explanation for generation, having a great
show that it was following his review of Herders Ideen zur Philos- advantage . on experiential grounds over preformation.14 Sec-
ophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (1784e5) that Kant felt the ondly, Kant emphasizes the theorys cognitive appeal in stating that
need to emphasize both the independence of reason from nature reason is favorably disposed to this [epigenetic] explanation. This
and the distinctiveness of the study of reason from the study of second aspect is independent of the rst. It would hold even if one
nature, i.e., to distinguish reason as an object that cannot be studied did not recognize the alleged experiential superiority.15
by means of the natural sciences or anthropology. It was on account The endorsement of a specic explanatory model in the life
of this, we contend, that the specic articulation of epigenesis put sciences thus coincides with a claim about reasons dispositions. A
forward by Blumenbach became central in the second edition of the brief review of Kants discussion of epigenetic and preformationist
rst Critique. theories in the years leading up to the use of metaphors of gener-
Our re-contextualization of Kants employment of the metaphor ation in the Transcendental Analytic at A66/B90-1 may serve to
of epigenesis does not, however, imply that he did not make critical demonstrate the absence of his commitment to either theory as a
use of the term in the Transcendental Deduction. Rather, and in scientic explanation of generation. Such a commitment only
concert with research that draws on the idea of epigenesis to un- comes, as we will argue, when it coincides with a specic rear-
derstand the activity of reason, we argue that by comparing Kants ticulation of the role of reason in Kants systematic philosophy.
rst published use of the termdin his review of Herders Ideend- Kant discusses the generation of plants and animals as early as
with the parenthetical remark he makes in the Deduction, it be- 1763 in The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of
comes clear that the epigenesis of pure reason involves the the Existence of God. Here he distinguishes broadly between a view
limitation of what is and what is not possible in experience, anal-
ogous to the limitation that Kant regards as necessary in natural
generation, and which he formulates in response to Herder. It is 12
We thus aim to elaborate and expand upon the work of Zller (1988) and
through the notion of epigenesis as a form of limitation (on possible Mensch (2013) on the signicance of the notion of epigenesis for the Transcen-
dental Deduction.
13
Our conclusion is in line with Reinhard Lws, who argues that Kant did not
take a consistent position on these questions (Lw, 1980, 168). In particular, we
9
Zller (1988), 88. agree with his problematisation of Kants endorsement of epigenesis. However, our
10
As Kant puts it in his essay on the use of teleological judgment: I have become intention here is different from Lws: we do not seek to determine Kants position
totally convinced that through the mere separation of what is heterogeneous and regarding epigenesis and preformation, but to emphasize that he saw no need to
what previously had been left in a mixed state, often a new light is cast upon the take such a position on the problem of generation as a scientic problem prior to
science . which opens up many authentic sources of cognition where one would 1790.
14
not at all have expected them . (Kant (1788), AA 8, 162). The aim of the scientist, Kant (1790), AA 5, 424.
he continues, must be to challenge the carelessness of letting the boundaries of the 15
Kant (1790), AA 5, 424. See McLaughlins (1982) critical contextualization of this
sciences run into each other. claim, placing it in the context of bourgeois theories of society in the 17th and 18th
11
Zller (1988); Mensch (2013). centuries (371).
100 D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107

of ontogeny as the quantitative evolution (Auswickelung) of a su- only that, as Kant stressesdto rethink the possible action of forces
pernaturally given form, and a view which grants individuals the in living things23:
capacity of qualitatively generating rather than merely unfolding
My intention here is only to show the necessity to grant the
their structural form.16 Although Kant does not name them as such,
things of nature more of a possibility than is commonly done to
the former view corresponds to the theory of preformation, pre-
produce their consequences according to general laws.24
vailing through the rst half of the 18th century and prominently
represented by Albrecht von Haller and Charles Bonnet.17 The latter
view can, in turn, be described as epigenetic, and its rst 18th- It is worth noting that Wolffs explicitly epigenetic theory (dis-
century representative was Caspar Friedrich Wolff (whom Kant cussed below) in its reliance on a force, as opposed to Buffons and
does not mention). It was, however, preceded by anti- Maupertuiss anti-preformationist accounts, could bedalthough
preformationist views as articulated by Pierre Louis de Mau- Kant does not do sodinterpreted as an attempt to fulll just such a
pertuis, and the Comte de Buffon (whom Kant does mention).18 methodological demand in seeking to show how general laws
Both preformationist and anti-preformationist views, Kant might account for the generation of high structural complexity.
contends, are deeply problematic in that they each contain an In his rst mention of the actual term epigenesis in notes dated
arbitrary (willkrlich) element.19 He nds sarcastic words for both. 1772e1776, Kant identies it with the organic as opposed to the
The arbitrariness of preformation consists in positing a supernat- mechanical or chemical, and as such with the idea of an an
ural origin of generation instead of admitting that this origin might animating spirit in plants and animals:
be scientically explicable. Kant mocks this move by invoking the
The question is whether there is an organic formative nature
reproduction of yeast: while as equally ill-understood as the
(epigenesis) or only one which produces form (bildet) me-
problem of explaining higher organisms, this problem does not
chanically and chemically. It seems: to that belongs a spirit
seem to prompt any explanatory recourse to alleged supernatural
because of the unity of the relation of all parts, according to their
causes. Buffons and Maupertuiss non-preformationist theories, in
generation, to every single such part. But isnt there a spiritually
contrast, do not posit any such supernatural origins, but they too
animating essence in animals and plants too. In such a way one
contain arbitrary elements. Kant locates these in the attempts to
would even have to assume an animating spirit in the primor-
counter the difculties in accounting for the origin of qualitatively
dial chaos in order to explain the various animals which can
new structure according to mechanical laws. Maupertuis addresses
now only reproduce.25
the problem of generating structure by the introduction of attrac-
tive forces and particles in the seminal uid of the parents, whereas
Buffon posits the existence of a so-called moule intrieure, or in- This usage of the term epigenesis is sufciently broad and yet
ternal mould, responsible for the formation of the newly generating idiosyncratic to rule out the possibility that Kant is discussing the
body. Kant criticizes both in one and the same breath, suggesting contemporaneous epigenetic theory that had actually been put
that the inner forms of Herr Buffon, which self-assemble according forward by the time he was writing. Wolff s epigenetic Theoria
to the opinion of Herr von Maupertuis, are either as incompre- generationis from 1759 is decidedly anti-animistic in postulating a
hensible as the thing itself, or [.] arbitrary inventions.20 vis essentialis that accounts for the structure of plants and animals
Thus facing a choice between preformation as a theory of su- by the secretion of nutritive uids; the functional unity of their
pernaturally given, and anti-preformationism as a theory of arbi- different parts is a by-product rather than the result of the action of
trarily invented form, Kant concludes that it is perhaps impossible a soul or spirit.
to make out which difculty is the greatest.21 He is perfectly If Kants usage of the term is not aligned with Wolff s, what
explicit in stating the point of his discussion of the two theories of might his sources be? Maupertuiss Systme de la nature. Essai sur la
generation: not to endorse one of them over the other as a scientic formation des corps organiss (1751) claims the impossibility of ac-
(naturphilosophische) theory, but to sort out the weightier meta- counting for an organisms functional unity as a result of a uniform
physical reasons at stake in deciding between them.22 The and blind force, and posits a principle of intelligence to resolve
weightier reason for him, unsurprisingly, is to avoid any recourse to this problem, similar to what we call desire, aversion, memory.
the supernatural in the philosophy of nature. However, and even if he may have left Kant unconvinced, Mau-
However, this does not amount to an endorsement of the spe- pertuis insisted that there was a difference between his principle of
cic anti-preformationist theories of Maupertuis and Buffon, which intelligence and an animating spirit in the sense of a sensitive
he has just ridiculed. Instead, it is a methodological demanddand soul.26 Another potential source for Kants allusion to an animating
principle is Georg Ernst Stahl (from whom Wolff had distinguished
his views explicitly).27 In the Dreams of a spirit-seer, Kant had
defended Stahls organic explanation as being often closer to the
16
Kant (1763), AA 2, 114. truth than
17
See Roe (1981), ch. 2, on Hallers conversion from epigenesis to preformation in
the 1750s.
18
Kants omission of Wolff s name not just here but in any other of his writings
has been discussed at length; see Lw (1980), 176. Wolff and Blumenbach both
explicitly use the term epigenesis to describe their respective, and different, the-
23
ories (see below). Maupertuis and Buffon do not use this term, and it remains a Thus we disagree with Claude Pichs reading of this passage as an obvious
matter of debate whether or not it is appropriate to label their views as epigenetic. adoption of the biological theory of epigenesis (Pich [2001], 186). Firstly, we do
Wolff and Blumenbach each postulate a force responsible for the generation of a not see Kant endorsing the specic theories he sarcastically discusses as arbitrary;
qualitatively new structure, whereas Buffons explanation of this new structure we only see him arguing that bad non-preformationist theories are on safer
relies on spatial arrangements of matter that preexist the newly generated or- metaphysical grounds than preformationist ones. Secondly, applying the broad la-
ganism. For Sloan (2002), this makes Maupertuis and Buffon mechanistic epi- bel epigenetic to the specic non-preformationist theories Kant exposes here
geneticists (6); for Mensch (2013), Buffons internal mould smells too strongly of erases the decisive difference with his later endorsement of Blumenbachs epige-
preformationism to count him among the epigeneticists (chapter 2). netic theory as based on not just a force, but a drive.
19 24
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115. Kant (1763), AA 2, 115 (our translation).
20 25
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115. Kant (1772e1776), AA 17, 591 (our translation).
21 26
Kant (1763), AA 2, 114. Maupertuis (1984 [1751]), 146e147.
22 27
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115. See Roe (1981), 109.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107 101

. Hofmann, Boerhaave and others, who do not consider On the different human races, Kants account of natural genera-
immaterial forces, who stick to mechanical causes and in that, tion is a version of preformationism.31 The assumption of pre-
follow a more philosophical method.28 formed germs (Keime) as well as predispositions (Anlagen) is the
only means, he argues, by which to explain both differences be-
tween species and heritable differences within species, i.e., adap-
Kant thus broadly aligns the term epigenesis with an organic
tation. For insofar as chance or general mechanical laws cannot
process of formation that bears animistic connotations, and uses
bring forth such adaptations, e.g. to climate, it follows that
the term to acknowledge the problem of the relation between the
different species must have within them germs and natural pre-
organically formative on the one hand, and the mechanical on the
dispositions which allow them both to maintain their species line
other. This is, however, neither a discussion of an actually existing
as well as adapt to new conditions.32 The original species is
theory of epigenesis (Stahl did not offer such a theory), nor an
equipped with the potential to adapt to any external condition, but
endorsement of the idiosyncratically animistic articulation of
it is contingent upon these conditions which predisposition is
epigenesis as a viable explanatory option in natural philosophy.
expressed (ausgewickelt). Sloan has characterized this view as a
When he takes up the problem of epigenetic ontogeny again in
combination of preformation with environmentalism.33
notes dated 1776e78, Kant still presents epigenesis as requiring the
Against the background of these varied earlier discussions,
assumption of a soul; however, this soul must understood as a
Kants usage of biological terms of generation in the 1781 edition of
non-localized part of the intelligible world in order to avoid
the rst Critique stands out as markedly different: in contrast to the
animistic implications:
earlier methodological debates or attempts at developing a theory
For epigenesis we have to assume that the soul belongs to the of heredity, this usage is clearly metaphorical in character. Keime,
intelligible world; that it does not have a location in space, that, seeds, is the word Kant uses to describe both the generation of the
once an organized body has come into being through concep- pure concepts of the understanding in the Transcendental Analytic,
tion, it has in itself the condition to be ensouled (beseelt) by the and the development of the special sciences in the Architectonic of
intelligible, vitalizing (belebend) principle; and that in this body Pure Reason.34 In the 1787 edition, Kant retains both passages, and
the soul is present not locally, but virtually.29 thus maintains the metaphorical vocabulary of categories as pre-
formed seeds and dispositions, which develop on the occasion of
experience. However, in the Transcendental Deduction he adds a
In his private remarks on Eberhards Preparations for natural
competing metaphor from the life sciences: the now well-known
theology, and thus in a theological context, Kant discusses phy-
claim of the epigenesis of pure reason.35
logeny rather than ontogeny with regard to the necessity of
Given this ambiguity within the B edition, it is perhaps not
assuming supernatural effects.30 Here, he now uses the term
surprising that commentators have reached contradictory answers
epigenesis in a more conventional way:
to the question which biological mode of explanation informs
The preservation of species can either be regarded as natural, Kants cognitive theory. After all, his many different earlier dis-
or it requires a supernatural inuence. In the rst case the cussions of both epigenesis and preformation offer numerous
origin of species is to be regarded as natural too: for every passages to support either argumentdtypically by emphasizing the
generation is to be regarded as a new origin insofar as there methodological support for epigenesis, or the usage of pre-
are so many foreign causes which can modify or change the formationism in the race essay, respectively.36 But it seems to us
formative force that, were it not for a counteracting principle that these arguments skate too lightly over the difference in context
following general laws, the regularity of reproduction could and usage. Even if Kant had endorsed either theory as scientically
not be explained from a disposition once created. Particularly superior prior to 1790, it would still remain unclear how an
if one assumes epigenesis. endorsement of the scientic theory affects its metaphorical usage
in the theory of cognition. However, we have no such endorsement.
Furthermore, such a discussion does not do justice to Kants use of
A hypothetical endorsement of epigenesis thus renders a
biological language outside of its original context. To understand
natural origin of species more plausible insofar as the theory
what makes Kants employment of the metaphor of epigenesis
purports to explain the generation of every single member of the
poignant, we turn to its usage in the contemporaneous life sciences
species as a renewed origin (Ursprung) without recourse to
and to Kants rst published discussion of the term in his review of
supernatural causes, and thus provides a model for how the rst
Herder.
such origin could be conceived. Kants earlier metaphysical
argument in favor of non-preformationist theories is reiterated
here with explicit reference to epigenesis as a mode of expla-
nation. And yet, this move only posits an epigenetic theory for
the sake of the theological argument, and does not amount to an
31
explicit espousal of epigenesis over other theories in the life McLaughlin (2007).
32
sciences. Kant (1775), AA 2, 435.
33
By the late 1770s, then, Kant has publicly engaged with Sloan (2002), 240.
34
Thus, the aim of the Transcendental Analytic is to pursue the pure concepts
epigenesis and preformation on a methodological meta-level, and
into their rst seeds (Keime) and predispositions (Anlagen) in the human under-
privately considers both the difculties of epigenesis as an standing, where they lie ready (vorbereitet), until with the opportunity of experi-
explanatory strategy in ontogeny, and its phylogenetic implications. ence, they are developed (entwickelt) and exhibited in their clarity by the very same
However, when not working on a meta-level but engaging directly understanding liberated from empirical conditions attaching to them (Kant (1781/
1787), A66/B91). And in the Architectonic: No one attempts to bring about a sci-
and publicly with questions of phylogeny and heredity in his 1775
ence without a grounding idea for that science. However, in elaborating that idea
the schema, even the denition given to that science initially, rarely ever corre-
sponds to that idea; because it lies like a seed (Keim) in reason, a seed in which all
parts are still very much wrapped up (eingewickelt) and lie hidden barely accessible
28
Kant (1766), AA 2, 331 (our translation). to microscopic observation (Kant (1781/1787), B861; our translation).
29 35
Kant (1776e78), AA 18, 189/190. Kant (1781/1787), B167.
30 36
Kant (1776e78), AA 18, 574. Sloan (2002) and Zller (1988), respectively.
102 D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107

2. Blumenbach: Bildungstrieb and generic preformation nature has implemented between the animated, and the inanimate
creation, between the organized, and unorganized creatures, he
Both in his oft-cited letter from August 1790 to Blumenbach, and takes the vitalist point as a premise rather than a problem: there is a
in x81 of the Critique of Judgment, Kant singles out a specic difference in kind between animate and inanimate matter.41 The
formulation among the broad eld of theories associated with the formative drive only acts in animate matter and cannot account for
label epigenesis. In doing so, he draws explicit attention to the the transition from inanimate to animate matter. But once active, it
difference between Blumenbachs concept of Bildungstrieb and a will generate structure that had not been present before its action.
mere formative force, Bildungskraft. What is the nature of this Such spontaneous generation is a characteristic of animate matter,
distinction, which was drawn in the 1789 revised edition of ber present to various degrees throughout its life but ceasing with it:
den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschft, but can be traced back
there is no such thing in nature as preformed germs: rather, a
to Blumenbachs earliest writings on the same topic in 1781?
special drive becomes active in the previously raw and un-
From the very rst treatises on the Bildungstrieb in 1780 and
formed matter of generation, once it has matured and reached
1781, Blumenbach had emphasized the difference between his new
its place of destination, and then remains active life-long.42
concept of a formative drive and all other forces of nature,
stating as his result
In the 1789 edition, Blumenbach also adds the clarication that
that there lies within all living creatures from human beings
the spontaneous generation of structure does occur in inanimate
down to the maggot, from the cedar to mold, a special, innate
matter, such as crystals, as the result of a formative forceeebut a
drive that remains active through their lifetime, initially to make
force lacks the teleological connotation of the drive that sets
them take their shape, then to retain it, and, if possible, to
animate matter apart. The substantive distinction translates into a
restore this shape when destroyed. A drive (or tendency or
normative and programmatic one for Blumenbach. As suggested by
striving, whichever one wishes to call it) that is entirely different
the fruitful comparison between the generation of structure in
both from the general properties of [material] bodies, and from
inanimate and animate matter, one can indeed legitimately
the other forces specically peculiar to organized bodies37; and
employ the phenomena of either of these two major parts of
that seems to be one of the primary causes of all generation,
creation for explaining phenomena of the other.43 As an explan-
nutrition, and reproduction; and which, in order to prevent any
atory strategy, however, this move relies on a prior distinction
misinterpretation, and in order to distinguish it from all other
between the subject matter of biology and physics, as we would say
natural forces, I shall here call the formative drive (nisus
retrospectively, and anticipates a process of institutionalized
formativus).38
disciplinary division that had just begun when Blumenbach was
writing.44 The coincidental, multiple coinings of the term biology
In particular, he warned, the Bildungstrieb should not be around the turn of the century are taken to be suggestive of such a
confused with Wolffs essential force. Wolff s epigenetic account trend of disciplinary division.45 It is in this broader institutional
of generation (Theoria generationis, 1759) relies on the notion of a context in which Blumenbach suggests, as a result of his own
vis essentialis, a non-teleological force which primarily serves research as a professor at the Faculty of Medicine in Gttingen, an
nutritive purposes. Its organizing effect is construed as a by- epistemically productive division of labor in the sciences. Seen from
product of its chemical and mechanical interactions with the this perspective, Blumenbachs notion of the Bildungstrieb de-
environment.39 This intentional alignment of the process of organic marcates a limited domain of inquiry for the life sciences.
with inorganic organization is precisely the opposite of Blu- A second limiting move, this time not on domains of inquiry but
menbachs move, which locates the source of the generation of on the action of the formative drive itself, is Blumenbachs argu-
organic structure in organic matter alone. Thus, his epigenetic ment for the constancy of species in his Beitrge zur Naturgeschichte
theory is built upon the notion of a formative drive, rather than (1780 and later editions). It takes species to be representations of
force, that is unique to and inherent in all living creaturesdand possible forms of the organization of matter. In every single newly
those alone. Blumenbach realizes that the formative drive might generated individual, the Bildungstrieb acts on the specic physio-
easily be confused with Wolffs vis essentialis, given that they both logical composition of matter passed down from the parent gen-
are responsible for the effects because of which we ascribe life to eration. Crucially, this composition limits the possible results of
[plants and animals] [weswegen wir [Panzen und Tieren] ein Leben formative action. As Peter McLaughlin argues, For Blumenbach,
zuschreiben].40 However, in contrast to Wolffs, Blumenbachs epigenesis of the individual implies generic preformation.46 Just
vitalistic epigenetic theory locates the difference between the like the distinction between Bildungskraft and Bildungstrieb, this
living and the non-living in the formative drive. implication did not escape Kants attention; indeed, Kant proved
If this point remains implicit in the earlier edition, Blumenbach himself to be a perceptive commentator in characterizing epigen-
emphasizes it all the more strongly in the 1782 edition of his Hand- esis as a system of generic preformation in the Critique of Judg-
buch der Naturgeschichte, and in the revised 1789 edition of the trea- ment.47 The specic form to be reached in epigenetically described
tise on the Bildungstrieb. Both the distinction between drive and
mere force, and between the domain of the living and the non-living
become more pronounced. When Blumenbach states that no one can
be more profoundly persuaded than I am of the massive gap which 41
Blumenbach (1789), 71.
42
Blumenbach (1789), 24.
43
Blumenbach (1789), 72.
44
This disciplinary diversication is one of the characteristics of 18th-century
37
In the 1789 edition, Blumenbach species those as contractibility, irritability, science. Approaching the question from the study of experimental practice rather
sensibility etc., i.e. as the mechanical forces described by Haller and others as being than from an institutional perspective, Klein and Lefvre date the introduction of
at work in the physiological functioning of the animal bodies. Blumenbach (1789), organic substances as those created by the processes of life as occurring around
25. 1790. Klein and Lefvre (2007), ch. 13.
38 45
Blumenbach (1781), 12 (our translation). McLaughlin (2002).
39 46
See Witt (2008) for a recent discussion. McLaughlin (1982), 17e18.
40 47
Blumenbach (1781), 17 (our translation). Kant (1790), AA 5, 423.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107 103

ontogenesis is always prescribed, and in that sense limited, by between Herders portrayal of epigenesis, as endorsed by Kant, and
virtue of the individuals being part of a species. Blumenbachs formulation, is striking. Herder emphasizes Blu-
menbachs point that the formative force is a principle of life, not
a force that might act in organic or inorganic matter. But the sim-
3. 1787
ilarities of vocabulary go further.
In the rst volume of the Ideen (1784), Herder contends that no
There is a noticeable difference between Kants views of
eye has seen preformed germs, and goes on to state that if a being
epigenesis qua scientic theory in the late 1780s and 1790, on the
possesses organic forces [wirkende organische Krfte], then it can
one hand, and his notes from the 1770s and early 1780s, on the
generate itself [so erzeugt es selbst].53 Blumenbach, in the 1781
other. In 1787 Kant made use of the phrase the epigenesis of pure
version of his treatise, had pointed to the fact that the perfection
reason, and in 1789 he published the essay On the use of teleo-
[Vollkommenheit] of our magnication lenses is no good news for
logical principles in philosophy in which he rst mentions Blu-
the yet unseen preformed germs, and continues to describe the
menbachs Handbuch. The idea of Bildungstrieb, Kant writes in the
action of epigenesis instead: in the raw matter of the future
essay, brought so much light into the doctrine of generations, not
creature, after its due period of preparation, the formative drive
to inorganic matter but only to the members of organized be-
is stirred and can begin the formation of the hitherto unformed
ings,48 thus emphasizing Blumenbachs distinction between
matter.54 In his review of Herder, Kant reiterates the language of
organic and inorganic matter. In the Critique of Judgment, Kant
matter as prepared: what accounts for generation is an action
identies Blumenbach with epigenesis, and epigenesis with
inherent to, and limited to, this kind of matter, i.e. organic matter.
immanent natural development. Epigenesis considers nature . as
Kant does, however, have one reservation regarding Herders
itself producing [als selbst hervorbringend] rather than merely as
take on epigenesis:
developing [als entwickelnd] those things that can initially be rep-
resented as possible only in accordance with the causality of ends, if the cause organizing itself from within were limited by its
and thus with the least possible appeal to the supernatural, leaves nature only perhaps to a certain number and degree of differ-
everything that follows from the rst beginning to nature.49 Thus ences in the formation of a creature (so that after the institution
Kant singles out two different reasons for his endorsement of of which it were not further free to form yet another type under
Blumenbachs theory of epigenesis as a scientic theorydand in so altered circumstances), then one could call this natural vocation
doing, incisively highlights Blumenbachs main programmatic of the forming nature also germs or original predispositions,
points. Firstly, and in line with his long-standing methodological without thereby regarding the former as primordially implanted
demands, Blumenbachs version of epigenesis did not require any machines and buds that unfold themselves only when occa-
appeal to divine or supernatural forces. As a scientic theory, his sioned (as in the system of evolution), but merely as limitations,
account specically emphasizes the immanent development, or in not further explicable, of a self-forming faculty, which latter we
Kants words, regards nature as self-producing (selbst hervor- can just as little explain or make comprehensible.55
bringend). Secondly, in its limitation to organic matter, it had a
clearer demarcation of explanatory scope than Wolffs theory.
In this comment, Kant anticipates his later formulation of generic
While we do not know for certain when Kant rst read Blu-
preformation by suggesting that the main explanatory advantage of
menbach, his rst published mention of the term epigenesis
preformation, which Kant had used in his 1775 race essay, can be
appeared in his 1785 review of Herders Ideen, which owed a great
accommodated by an epigenetic theory, with one caveat: the limi-
deal to Blumenbach.50 It was also in this review that Kant rst
tation of form. Thus he stresses a point that (pace Kant) Herder had
formulates a viable conception of epigenesis, which remained at
failed to emphasize in his account of epigenesis, but which Blu-
the core of his later account of epigenesis in the Critique of Judg-
menbach had clearly made in the Handbuch der Naturgeschichte: the
ment. In the review, Kant provides numerous quotations from the
form to be reached in ontogenic development is limited phyloge-
Ideen, some commentary on these quotations, and nally a brief,
netically. It is also clear that Kant does not consider the language of
albeit highly critical, response to Herders methodology and his
germs to be inherently in contradiction with that of epigenesis: in
conception of reason. This highly critical attitude toward Herders
the terminology he uses here, germs correspond to Blumenbachs
methodology strongly contrasts with Kants more tempered reac-
prepared matter rather than primordially implanted machines.
tion to Herders views of epigenesis.
This looseness of terminology explains why Kant does not see a need
Kant begins the review by noting Herders disagreement with
to remove the language of Keime and Anlagen in the 1787 edition of
the word epigenesis. The prex epi, Herder explains, mislead-
the Transcendental Analytic.56
ingly implies action from outside of newly generated material. For
It is important that Kants rst published use of the term
this reason, Herder offers the alternative term Bildung to imply
epigenesiseein a quotation from Herdereecoincides with the one
formation that is internal to nature. Kant quotes Herder: It is Bil-
moment in his review of the Ideen where Kants tone is not entirely
dung (genesis), an effect of inner forces for which nature had pre-
critical, but surprisingly agreeable. Kants reworking of Herders
pared a mass to which they give their form, in which they are to
conception of epigenesis is, in turn, strikingly similar to Blu-
make themselves visible.51 Kant is not averse to this point. Rather,
menbachs formative drive. It thus seems that Kants interest in
he writes that the reviewer fully concurs [ihm der Recensent vllig
epigenesis in the late 1780s was prompted by Herder, and
beitritt] with Herders notion of Bildung, which Kant describes as a
principle of life, which appropriately modies itself internally in
accordance with differences of the external circumstances [inner-
lich nach Verschiedenheit der ueren Umstnde].52 The parallel 53
Herder (1784/1785 [1989]), 6, 171 (our translation).
54
Blumenbach (1781), 42.
55
Kant (1785), AA 8, 62e63 (emphasis added on limited and limitation).
48
Kant (1788), AA 8, 180. 56
For this reason, and in contrast to the majority of the scholarship, we do not
49
Kant (1790), AA 5, 424. think that Kant was actually offering two competing or paradoxical formulations in
50
Richards (2002), 225. the 1787 edition of the rst Critique. Given that he came to conceive of epigenesis
51
Kant (1785), AA, 8, 50. along Blumenbachian lines, he did not regard the language of Keim and Anlage as
52
Kant (1785), AA, 8, 62. inherently opposed to epigenesis. See n. 1 above.
104 D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107

specically coincides with Blumenbachs version of epigenesis.57 spine is less curved; the breast is widened; the shoulders have
What appeals to Kant in this conception of epigenesis is its two clavicles; the hands have ngers endowed with the sense of
inbuilt limitations. Blumenbachs formative drive is restricted to feeling; to crown the structure, the receding head is exalted on
the domain of the living, and he construes it as a genuinely the muscles of the neck . 60
formative, yet inherently limited faculty acting within that domain.
In x81 of the Critique of Judgment, Kant explicitly calls this impli-
It is on account of the whole organismeeits structure, the re-
cation of Blumenbachs epigenetic theory generic preformation. It
lations between its parts, and its relation with its environmentee
is this conception of epigenesis as Bildung with limits that Kant
that, Herder goes on to explain, uprightness becomes possible.
invokes metaphorically in the second edition of the rst Critique.
Importantly, he notes that uprightness is not essential to being
human, as is evident in children or humans who live among ani-
4. Reason and Herders Ideen mals. Nonetheless, the very structure of the human body makes
uprightness possible. This means that uprightness is something
Herders Ideen played a key role in Kants formation on at least acquired in the right conditions. The same, Herder contends, holds
two counts. As we have shown, it was in the review that Kant rst for reason. Thus, as one of the chapter titles so clearly puts it, the
formulated a viable conception of epigenesis as a scientic theory. human being is organized for reason [Der Mensch ist zur Vernunft-
It was also in the context of the review that he recognized the fhigkeit organisiert].61 In other words, reason is possible given the
epistemic signicance of epigenesis as a metaphor for his theory of structure and environment of the human being. As such, it is not
reasoneeleading him to employ the metaphor in 1787. something with which we are simply born. Rather, reason must be
A key claim of Herders Ideen is that reason is nothing but developed in the right circumstances. Thus, even if rationality in
something received, a learned proportion and direction of ideas the human being is not entirely contingent (the structure of the
and forces to which the human being is formed through its orga- human body makes rational thought possible, in contrast to other
nization and way of life . This means, he continues, that reason animals who lack this structure), it is also not entirely independent
is not innate. . . 58 Rather, it develops over time and is thus of these circumstances. It is, in other words, not self-grounding;
necessarily historical. It is, furthermore, effected by its natural (and rather, it is inextricably linked both to the total structure of the
historical) environment, such that a proper understanding of human being and the environment.
reason involves understanding its natural history. In his review of Herder, Kant sees this move as a kind of natu-
The study of reason that Herder enumerates in the Ideen radi- ralization of reason. The review begins with an enumeration of
cally differs from the picture Kant had offered in the rst Critique. Herders key claims, including the claims that alteration of the
According to Herders account, to grasp reason, one must trace its animals and of the human being [is] in accordance with the cli-
development and emergence in history, andeein deep contrast to mates and that organization pervades all of nature, including dead
Kants transcendental conditions of possibilityeedistinguish the or inanimate nature, such as the ice crystal or snowake.62 Kant
natural conditions of its possibility. One such condition, Herder emphasizes Herders use of the terms organic and organic force,
argues, is uprightness. Importantly Herders explication of the noting that Herder does not reckon with germs . but rather with
development of reason does not amount to an explanation of the an organic force [Kraft], in plants as much as animals.63 This force,
generation of reason through the coming together of isolated parts Kant goes on, underlies all of creation manifesting itself differently
whose emergence (and individual existence) is entirely contingent in different beings. It is the transformation of this one force, Kant
(i.e., dependent on a variety of environmental circumstances). maintains, that determines differences between beings. In the hu-
Rather, his view is that the development of reason goes hand in man being, Kant continues, this force is manifest at the erect gait.
hand with the development of the whole organism, such that it is While Kants characterization of Herders account emphasizes
impossible to speak of reason as independent of the other parts of uprightness in a way that overlooks Herders holistic understand-
the human organism. ing of development, the point that Kant wants to draw out and
Thus Herder writes that every creature is suitably organized to which he nds most problematic holds: for Herder, reason is not
live and move in its element . every creature . has its own, a new innate but acquired, and its acquisition depends on the natural
world.59 He offers several examples to clarify what he means, development of the human being in general. As such, it can be
illustrating how in each case, the animal or plant is structured ac- studied in the same way that other aspects of the human organ-
cording to its needs, and its complexity is commensurate with its ismeeand of nature in generaleecan be studied. It can be studied,
particular situation and environment. In the case of the human in other words, through the comparative method that Herder
being, Herder begins by noting that uprightness is specically hu- employed in the Ideen and which he designated as anthropology.
man, adding that this is not an accident but accords with the It is Herders naturalization of reason and his corresponding
structure and shape of the human body: elimination of the task of metaphysics (and its replacement by
anthropology) that Kant found deeply problematic. In turn, it is in
the foot of man is more rm and broad: he has a great long toe, light of these problematic views that Kant went on to develop and
while the ape has only a thumb; his heel too is on a level with put to use the notion of the epigenesis of pure reason as a met-
the sole of his foot. All the muscles acting in this position are aphor in explicating the character of the categories. Kants pro-
adapted to it. The calf of the leg is enlarged; the pelvis is drawn grammatic aim in the adoption of that metaphor mirrors
backwards; the hips are spread outwards from each other; the Blumenbachs in insisting on a separate domain of inquiry for the
life sciences: just as Blumenbach had argued that the generation of
structure in animate matter is the result of a capacity inherent to
57
This is in contrast to both Sloan and Zller, who do not specically identify
Herder (and Kants reworking of Herder in the review) with Blumenbach. Rather,
Sloan (2002) sees Herder as promoting a Wolfan version of epigenesis, while
Zller (1989) sees Kants comments in the review as evidence of Kants familiarity
60
with Wolffs and Blumenbachs concept of epigenesis (81). On Herders familiarity Herder (1989), 112.
61
with Blumenbachs work, see Richards (2002), 225e6 and Nisbet (1970), 196. Herder (1989), 116.
58 62
Herder (1989), p. 144; see also p. 93. Kant (1785), AA 8, 47.
59 63
Herder (1989), p. 89. Kant (1785), AA 8, 48.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107 105

animate matter and animate matter alone, and thereby created a Kant rejects this third option because in such a case the cate-
distinctive domain of knowledge, so Kant sought to show that the gories would lack the necessity that is essential to their concept. He
development of the categories employed by reason can only be elaborates via example: the concept of cause, which asserts the
explained within an independent theory of reason, and not as the necessity of a consequent under a presupposed condition, would be
product of natural-historical processes. Their development cannot false if it rested only on subjective necessity, arbitrarily implanted in
be explained through the action of natural forces, nor can it be us, of combining certain empirical representations according to
derived from nature, just as the generation of organization in such a rule of relation.67 Precisely because they are arbitrarily
animate matter cannot be explained as the action of mere formative implanted in us, Kant contends, innate ideas do not bear any ne-
forces (as in inorganic matter such as crystals) but only as that of a cessity with regard to their concept. That is to say, the necessity is
formative drive. Where Blumenbach establishes a domain of the not inherent to the concept, but external to it: they lack the ne-
study of life, Kant sought to reafrm metaphysics as the singular cessity that essentially belongs to their concept.68 Thus, they
domain for the study of reason. cannot produce objectively valid knowledge.
This might seem like an odd claim. Why, one might ask, would
innate ideas not deliver objective knowledge? Gnter Zller has
5. B166-168 responded to this question by focusing on the distinction between
innate ideas and the a priori categories born out of the self-
The signicant passages in the second edition of the Critique of generating character of reason. The claim is that insofar as reason
Pure Reason, in which Kant mentions the epigenesis of pure is self-grounding and self-generating, the categories must be un-
reason, and uses the notion to describe the only possible way by derstood not as original or innate, but as acquired in and through
which to understand the relation between the categories and the activity of thinking.69 This contrasts with the innatist view,
experience, comes toward the end of the Transcendental Deduction which rests on mere coincidence, due to some divine prear-
at B167. Kant introduces the notion of epigenesis here in a paren- rangement.70 The categories are not arbitrary, then, because they
thetical remark, following a dismissal of an alternative way by are the self-thought products of the activity of thinking itself.
which to understand the relation between experience and con- Although Zller is right to emphasize the self-generating char-
cepts. He writes: acter of reason, and on that basis distinguish the categories from
innate ideas, the notions of self-generation and self-thought
Now there are only two ways in which a necessary agreement of alone do not fully explicate the character of the categories, account
experience with the concepts of its objects can be thought: for their objective validity, or distinguish the specicity (and
either the experience makes these concepts possible or these thereby the real signicance) of Kants use of the metaphor of
concepts make the experience possible. The rst is not the case epigenesis.71 For Zller, Kants conception of epigenesis amounts to
with the categories (nor with pure sensible intuition); for they the self-generation of reason, and can thus be modeled on either
are a priori concepts, hence independent of experience (the Wolffs or Blumenbachs theories.72 As we have argued, however,
assertion of an empirical origin would be a sort of generatio already in 1785, Kant had formulated a conception of epigenesis
aequivoca). Consequently only the second way remains (as it that mirrors Blumenbachseea conception that distinctively em-
were a system of the epigenesis of pure reason): namely that the phasizes limitation on two counts: the delimitation of living from
categories contain the grounds of the possibility of all experi- non-living beings, and phylogenetic limitation. The real import of
ence in general from the side of the understanding.64 Kants metaphor, then, cannot simply be the notion of self-
generation, but rather generation with limitation.
It is important to begin by emphasizing the exact way in which This becomes clear when we examine the context of the met-
Kant is invoking epigenesis here; he is not stating that the mind is a aphor. It appears in the Deduction, where Kant aims to justify the
biological organism, which develops according to the laws of bio- categories. As numerous commentators have argued, this means
logical epigenesis. Rather, his claim is that epigenesis offers a model that he must show not only that the application of the categories is
by which to understand the workings of the mind, more specif-
ically, the relationship between the categories and experience.
After he invokes this model, Kant goes on to reject a third model, 67
Kant (1781/1787), B168; emphasis added.
which he identies with a kind of preformation-system of pure 68
Kant (1781/1787), B168.
reason.65 Such a picture of the mind, he explains, implies that the 69
And not, as is the case in Herder, through the overall development of the
categories were neither self-thought [selbsgedachte] a priori rst natural organism in its environment. Zller quotes Kant: The Critique admits
principles of our cognition nor drawn from experience, but were absolutely no divinely implanted (anerschaffene) or innate (angeborene) represen-
rather subjective predispositions for thinking.66 From this, it is tations. It regards them all, whether they belong to intuition or to concepts of the
understanding, as acquired. Zller (1989), 227.
evident that the epigenetic model means that the categories are 70
Zller (1989), 231. Zller explains that the innatist problem would not arise for a
self-thought. This contrasts with the very rst option he had theory of knowledge that is entirely based on innate ideas, without any input from
offered, in which the categories are merely empirical, drawn from mind-external entities. It is only a theory of knowledge that regards knowledge as
experience. In turn, the nal (third) option that Kant offers (and the outcome of both something non-empirical and something empirical that re-
identies with preformation) contrasts with the rst two in that quires a distinction between necessary (a priori) and non-necessary (empirical)
ideas.
the categories are neither self-thought, nor drawn from experience, 71
We agree with Mensch (2013) who has shown that the signicance of
but rather implanted [eingepanzt] in the mindeeas one would epigenesis in the Transcendental Deduction goes beyond the claim that reason is
imagine the germs are implanted in the natural organism. In other self-generating and the categories are self-thought; in addition, she argues,
words, the preformation-system of pure reason implies some- epigenesis implies a transcendental afnity within cognition itself, an afnity
thing like innate ideas. which grants unity to the experience of natures coherence (134). Our claim is
that this unity is achieved through limitation.
72
See n. 57. Precisely because Zller does not recognize the way in which Kant
reinterprets epigenesis as a form of generic preformation in the Herder review, he
64
Kant (1781/1787), B166-7. misses the fact that by 1787 Kant is specically identifying epigenesis with generic
65
Kant (1781/1787), B167. preformation (i.e., Blumenbach), such that its real import rests not simply in the
66
Ibid. notion of self-generation, but also in the notion of limitation.
106 D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107

possible, but also that the categories constrain or limit experience, two key factors: the rst, which many have emphasized, concerns
such that it is this limiting capacity that ensure[s] that the logical the self-generating character of living beings and reason. The sec-
function of subject-predicate judgment is used in a certain way ond, much less noted aspect, involves limitation. It is precisely this
.73 In other words, to demonstrate the objective validity of the second aspect that attracted Kant to Blumenbachs specic
categories, Kant needs to show that, as products of the activity of conception of epigenesis and that Kant formulated in his Herder
thought, the categories are also limiting forces of and on this review.
activity.74 As we have shown, for Blumenbach the term epigenesis in-
Precisely because the categories are the self-thought prod- volves limitation on two levels. First, it involves the limitation of the
ucts of the operation of the understanding, they are not originally formative drive by the composition of the reproductive matter of a
present in the mind but formed through the activity of thinking. given species. On the cognitive level for Kant, this implied the
This formation, in other words, takes place according to the rule- limitations of the categories, insofar as they are the outcomes of
bound activity of the understanding. The categories are thus the rules of thought and the application of these rules.
products of the mind applying itself according to its own rules. Limitation for Blumenbach also meant the delimitation of
The categories are therefore both the outcome of a rule of biological entities as opposed to physical oneseewith the cor-
thoughteesuch that they can be described as self-thoughtee responding differentiation between biology and physics. For
and the application of this rule onto experience. As the application Kant, too, epigenesis involved limitation on this level, specif-
of this rule onto experience, the categories play a limiting func- ically, the delimitation and independence of the domain of
tioneethe carve out experience into entities that must always be reason from the domain of nature. Metaphysics, as the study of
subjects or entities that are predicated of these subjects. And it is reason, is thus separated from natural history and anthropology.
this limiting function of the categories that warrants their objec- As self-forming or self-born, reason is not born out of
tive validity: they non-arbitrarily impose cognitive parameters on something other than itself (i.e., natural forces) and thus cannot
experience. be studied in the same way that other beings are studied. Contra
The manner in which the categories actually determine and Herder, metaphysics for Kant is preserved as an independent
constrain our experience in certain ways is beyond the scope of this domain of study.
paper. Our purpose is not to explain how this application occurs,
but rather to show that it is this rule-bounded and limiting char-
acter of the categories, mirroring the account of limited natural References
generation that Kant had formulated in his review of Herder, which
Blumenbach, J. F. (1780). Professor Blumenbach ber den Bildungstrieb (nisus for-
led Kant to adopt the metaphor of epigenesis to explicate his mativus) und seinen Einu auf Generation und Reproduction (pp. 247-266).
conception of the mind.75 The categories, then, to quote Kants Gttingisches Magazin der Wissenschaften und Litteratur, 1. Jg., 5. Stck.
statement from the review, are limitations, not further explicable, Blumenbach, J. F. (1781). D. Johann Friedrich Blumenbach ber den Bildungstrieb und
das Zeugungsgeschfte. Gttingen: Johann Christian Dieterich.
of a self-forming faculty [weiter nicht erklrliche Einschrnkungen Blumenbach, J. F. (1782). Handbuch der Naturgeschichte. Zweyte durchgehends
eines sich selbst bildenden Vermgens].76 verbesserte Ausgabe. Gttingen: Johann Christian Dieterich.
The parallel between this conception of the pure concepts of the Blumenbach, J. F. (1789). ber den Bildungstrieb. Gttingen: Johann Christian Dieterich.
Guyer, P. (1992). The transcendental deduction of the categories. In P. Guyer (Ed.),
understandingeeas the outcome of the rule-governed activity of The cambridge companion to Kant (pp. 123-160). Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
the understanding and the limiting application of this ruleeeand versity Press.
Kants conception of epigenesis qua scientic theory is clear. As we Herder, J. G. (1989). Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit. In
J. Brummack, & M. Bollacher (Eds.), Johann Gottfried Herder: Werke in zehn
have argued, Kants understanding of epigenesis after 1785 involves Bnden (Vol. 6) Frankfurt am Main: Deutsche Klassiker Verlag. First published
1784 and 1785.
Kant, I. (1763). Der einzig mgliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins
Gottes. In AA vol. II, pp. 63e164.
73
Kant, I. (1766). Trume eines Geistersehers, erlutert durch Trume der Metaphysik. In
Guyer (1992), 131. AA II, pp. 315e374.
74
Zammito (2003) makes a similar point with regard to Zllers interpretation. As Kant, I. (1772e1776). Reexionen zur Metaphysik. In AA XVII, pp. 227e754 and
he puts it, Spontaneity of the categories was not sufcient for Kants transcen- AA XVIII, pp. 3e725.
dental deduction, he also needed their constitutive sovereignty over experience Kant, I. (1775). Von den verschiedenen Racen der Menschen. In AA II, pp. 427e444.
(92). Zammito takes this to be the ability of the mind to produce new knowledge, Kant, I. (1781/1787). Kritik der reinen Vernunft (A1781; B 1787) In AA vol. 3, and
which is to say that the mind had to be a real cause (of knowledge) . leading him AA vol. IV, pp. 1e252.
to conclude that Kants epigenesis analogy . built intellectual causation (deter- Kant, I. (1785). Recensionen von J. G. Herders Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der
mination; constitution) into the fundamental structure of the transcendental Menschheit. Theil 1. 2. In AA vol. VIII, pp. 43e66.
deduction of the possibility of experience. As Zammito notes, such a conception Kant, I. (1788). ber den Gebrauch der teleogischen Principien in der Philosophie. In AA
vol. VIII, pp. 157e184.
waseeon Kants transcendental principleseeunacceptable; but Kant had, accord-
Kant, I. (1790). Kritik der Urteilskraft. In AA vol. V, pp. 165e486.
ing to Zammito, not fully understood the meaning of the analogy he was drawing,
Klein, U., & Lefvre, W. (2007). Materials in eighteenth-century science: A historical
because he was especially ignorant of the revolution in thinking about this phe- ontology. Cambridge: MIT Press.
nomenon inaugurated by Blumenbach in 1781 (93). We have tried to show that Lw, R. (1980). Philosophie des Lebendigen. Der Begriff des Organischen bei Kant, sein
this was indeed not the case, rather, that Kant did have a grasp of the revolution in Grund und seine Aktualitt. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
thinking brought about by Blumenbach, and that it was precisely on account of this Maupertuis, P. L. (1984). Essai de Cosmologie. Systeme de la nature. Response aux
revolution that he came to adopt this metaphor. Thus, in contrast to Zammitos objections de M. Diderot. Presentation de Franois Azouvi [1751]. Paris: Libraire
interpretation of where the sovereignty of the categories comes from on an Philosophique J. Vrin
epigenetic model, we argue that it has nothing to do with the production of new McLaughlin, P. (1982). Blumenbach und der Bildungstrieb. Zum Verhltnis von
knowledge (i.e., content), but rather with the (formal) application of the rules epigenetischer Embryologie und typologischem Artbegriff. Medizinhistorisches
inherent to thought. Journal, 17, 357-372.
75
Sloan (2002) thinks that Kants preference for preformation and his insistence McLaughlin, P. (2002). Naming biology. Journal of the History of Biology, 35, 1-4.
McLaughlin, P. (2007). Kant on heredity and adaptation. In S. Mller-Wille, & H.-
on the use of the language of preformation to speak about the activity of cognition
J. Rheinberger (Eds.), Heredity produced: At the crossroads of biology, politics and
has to do with the limitations that the preformative theory places on the self-
culture (pp. 277-291). Cambridge: MIT Press.
structuring capacity of living beings (244e245). As we have shown, however,
Mensch, J. (2013). Kants Organicism: Epigenesis and the development of critical phi-
Kants conception of epigenesis following his Herder review involves limitation, losophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
such that in the 1787 edition of the rst Critique, he can invoke the metaphor of Pich, C. (2001). The precritical use of the metaphor of epigenesis. In T. Rockmore
epigenesis and imply limitation. Preformation, by contrast, is regarded as a deeply (Ed.), New essays on the precritical Kant (pp.182-200). New York: Humanity Books.
problematic metaphor for the mechanism of cognition. Roe, S. (1981). Matter, life, and generation: 18th-century embryology and the Haller-
76
Kant (1785), AA 8, 63. Wolff-debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107 107

Sloan, P. (2002). Preforming the categories: eighteenth century generation theory Further reading
and the biological roots of Kants a priori. Journal of the History of Philosophy,
40(2), 229-253.
Kant, I. (2000). In P. Guyer (Ed.), Critique of the power of judgment. Cambridge:
Witt, E. (2008). Form e a matter of generation. Science in Context, 21(4), 649-664.
Cambridge University Press.
Zammito, J. (2003). This inscrutable principle of an original organization: epigen-
Kant, I. (2002). In H. Allison, P. Heath, G. Hateld, & M. Friedman (Eds.), Theoretical
esis and looseness of t in Kants philosophy of science. Studies in the History
philosophy after 1781. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
and Philosophy of Science Part A, 34(1), 73-109.
Kant, I. (2007). In G. Zller, & R. B. Louden (Eds.), Anthropology, history, and edu-
Zller, G. (1988). Kant on the generation of metaphysical knowledge. In H. Oberer, &
cation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
G. Seel (Eds.), Kant: Analysen-Probleme-Kritik (pp. 71-90). Wrzburg: Knig-
shausen & Neumann.
Zller, G. (1989). From innate to a priori. The Monist, 72(2), 222-235.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi