Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 15

TWELFTH EOITION

GREAT TRADITIONS
IN ETHICS

THEODORE C. DENISE
Late of Syracuse University

NICHOLAS P. WHITE
University of California, Irvine
University of Utah

SHELDON P. PETERFREUND
Late of Syracuse University

THOMSON

VVADSVVORTH

AUSTRALIA BRAZIL CANADA MEXICO SINGAPORE


SPAIN UNITED KINGDOM UNITED STATES
Philosophy Editor: Worth Hawes Permissions Editor: Bob Kauser
Assistant Editor: Barbara Hillaker Production Service: Matrix Productions Inc.
Editorial Assistant: Patrick Stockstill Text Designer: Lisa Henry
Technology Project Manager: Julie Aguilar Photo Researcher: Susan Edelen
Marketing Manager: Christina Shea Copy Editor: Cheryl Smith
Marketing Assistant: Mary Anne Payumo Cover Designer: Yvo Riezebos
Marketing Communications Manager: Cover Image: Statue ofAthena) George Blonsky/Ala my
Stacey Purviance Compositor: International Typesetting and
Creative Director: Rob Hugel Composition
Executive Art Director: Maria Epes Text and Cover Printer: West Group
Print Buyer: Linda Hsu

COPYRIGHT 2008, 2005 Thomson Wadsworth, a Thomson Higher Education


part of The Thomson Corporation. Thomson, the Star 10 Davis Drive
logo, and Wadsworth are trademarks used herein Belmont, CA 94002-3098
under license. USA
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. No part of this work
covered by the copyright hereon may be reproduced or
For more information about our products,
used in any form or by any means-graphic, electronic,
contact us at:
or mechanical, including photocopying, recording,
Thomson Learning Academic Resource Center
taping, Web distribution, information storage and
1800423-0563
retrieval systems, or in any other manner-without the
For permission to use material from this text or
written permission of the publisher.
product, submit a request online at
Printed in the United States of America http://www.thomsonrights.com
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 11 10 09 08 07 Any additional questions about permissions
can be submitted by e-mail to
Library of Congress Control Number: thomsonrights@thomson.com
2006933906
ISBN 13: 978-0-495-094982
ISBN-10: 0-495-094986
CHAPTER THREE

Moral Character

ARISTOTLE (384-322 B.C.E.), the philosopher


'Nith whom only Plato compares in influence on
the history of Western thought, was born in the
Greek colony ofStagir.l in Macedonia. His father,
Nicomachus, a student of natural history and an
eminent physician, held the post of physician to
Amnytas II, King of Macedonia, father of Philip
the Great, until his death in Aristotle's eighteenth
year. At his father's death, Aristotle, who had
been brought up in an atmosphere of science
and scholarship, went to Athens to study phiioso
~ phy under Plato, and he remained at the Academy
~ until Plato's death in 347 B.C.E.
l Though Aristotle was unquestionably Pla
J to's most talented student, he \Vas by no
means his most devoted disciple: "Dear is
ARISTOTLE Plato, but dearer still is truth." It has been sug
gested that his refusal to defer to the master cost
him the nomination to succeed Plato as the head of the Academy. In any event, Aris
totle was passed over in favor of Speusippus, a man who did not approach him in
intellectual stature. In 343 B.C.E. Aristotle was selected as tutor to Alexander, the
thirteen-year-old son of King Philip of Macedonia. It was Philip who planned and
began the world conquest that Alexander the Great so nearly fulfilled. There is no
evidence that Aristotle, in his three years as tutor, modified the influence of father
on son or in any way affected the subsequent thoughts and deeds of Alexander; nei-
ther is there evidence that Aiistotle ever recognized the significance of Alexander's
goal of political unity. A bond of friendship was formed between teacher and
pupil, however, and it is reported that Alexander later subsidized some of Aristotle's
researches in the natural sciences.
At the age of forty-nine, Aristotle returned to Athens and founded the Lyceum,
the second of the four great schools of antiquity. An immediate success as a lecturer,

- 'll -
-~ ---~- --------

22 CHAPTER 3 Moral Character

he entered into the enormously productive period of his life: combining the roles of
encyclopedist, scientist, and philosopher, he is reputed to have written over four hun-
dred works, to have conducted and directed prodigious researches in botany and
zoology, and to have amassed one of the great libraries of the Greek world. As the
result of an anti-Macedonian uprising after the death of Alexander in 323 B.c.E., Aris-
totle left Athens. It is said by some authorities that he was accused of dangerous
teachings and indicted by the Athenian citizens, just as Socrates had been seventy-
six years earlier, but that he, in contrast to Socrates, accepted the option of exile.
Aristotle died at Chalcis on the island of Euboea in the next year.
According to Aristotle's own classification, his works deal with the theoretical
sciences, as in Metaphysics, Physics, De Caelo (astronomy), De Generatione et Corrup-
tione (biology), De Anima (psychology); the practical sciences, as in Nicomachean
Ethics, Eudemian Ethics, Politics; the productive or poetical sciences (Rhetoric,
Poetics); and logic (Organon). On such impressive evidence, it is said of Aristotle
that for his time he knew all that was to be known.
Historically, Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics is the first systematic treatment of
ethics in Western civilization. It belongs in the tradition begun by Socrates and
advanced by Plato, a tradition that stresses both the supremacy of our rational nature
and the purposive nature of the universe. Nevertheless, within this broad framework,
the ethical theories of Aristotle and those of his teacher, Plato, stand in sharp con-
trast. This difference stems from conflicting conceptions of the nature of the ultimate
moral principle and is a consequence of different metaphysical positions. Aristotle
takes issue with Plato's thesis that individual objects are intelligible only in terms
of immutable forms or ideas that exist in and of themselves. According to Aristotle's
doctrine, the forms that make objects understandable cannot exist apart from partic-
ular objects. That is, individual objects, for Aristotle, are a unity of a universal,
repeatable form and a unique content or matter: ''no form \Vithout matter, no matter
with form." Consequently, Aristotle rejects the Platonic view that the moral evalua-
tions of daily life presuppose a "good" that is independent of experience, personality,
and circumstances. Rather, he insists that the basic moral principle is immanent in the
activities of our daily lives and can be discovered ouly through a study of them.
In keeping with his general position, Aristotle begins his ethical inquiry with an
empirical investigation of what it is that people fundamentally desire. In his search, he
finds such goals as wealth and honors inadequate. He points out that an ultimate end
for people must be one that is, first, self-sufficient-"that which [even J when isolated
malces life desirable and lacking in nothing"-second, final-"that which is always
desirable in itself and never for the salce of something else"-and third, attainable.
People are agreed, Aristotle maintains, that happiness alone is the goal that meets
these requirements. However, he recognizes that this is no more than a preliminary
agreement about what it is that we should investigate in ethics. More specifically, we
want to know the nature of happiness and the conditions of its attainment.
Following Plato, Aristotle tells us that happiness must be explained in terms of
reason, a human being's distinctive function or activity. In his philosophical system,
however, this view is significantly modified by the doctrine of potentiality and actu-
ality. Just as the acorn actualizes its unique potentiality by becoming an oak, people
cirrn::ilize. their distinctive or defining potentiality by living the life of reason. To Aris-
ARISTOTLE 23

Consideration of the conditions requisite to the attainment of happiness leads


Aristotle into a discussion of virtue. For him, as for other Greek philosophers, virtue
refers to the excellence of a thing and hence to the disposition to perform effectively
its proper function. For example, a "virtuous" knife cuts well, and a "virtuous" phy-
sician successfully restores patients to health. By the same token, Aristotle argues, a
virtuous person lives according to reason, thus realizing his or her distinctive poten-
tiality. However, he subdivides human virtue into two types, the moral and the
intellectual. The moral virtues concern the habitual choice of actions in accordance
with rational principles. The contemplation of theoretical truths and the discovery
of the rational principles that ought to control everyday actions give rise to the
intellectual virtues. But whereas contemplation, that activity by which people may
attain the highest human happiness, is limited to the divinely gifted few, the prac-
tical virtues, with their lesser degrees of happiness, are vvithin reach of the ordinary
person.
Aristotle, then, in harmony -with the Greek tradition, stresses the value of con-
templation but, withal, is much impressed with the fact that people live for the
most part at the level of practical decision and routine behavior. The good habits
necessary to moral virtue are not strictly personal matters but can best be formed
in a sound social and legal structure:
It is difficult to get from youth up a right training for virtue if one has not been
brought up under right laws; for to live temperately and hardily is not pleasant to
most people, especially \.vhen they are young. For this reason their nurture and occu-
pations should be fixer. by law; for they 'Will not be painful \.Vhen they have become
customaiy. But it is surely not enough that \.Vhen they are young they should get the
right nurture and attention; since they must, even when they are grown up, practice
and be habituated to them, we shall need laws for this as Vi'ell, and generally speaking
to cover the whole life; for most people obey necessity rather than argument, and
punishments rather than the sense of what is noble.a

there are ends apart from the actions, it is the


1. Aristotle assumes that any investigation, nature of the products to be better than the activ-
pr'actical or theoretical,. has a teleological ities. Now, as there are many actions, arts, and
basis-that is, it ai.ms at some end or good. By sciences, their ends also are many; the end of
using _examples from ordinary experience, he the medical art is health, that of shipbuilding a
attempts to show that ends or goods form a vessel, that of strategy victory, that of economics
hierarchy.
wealth. But where such arts fall under a single
capacity-as bridle making and the other arts
Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every concerned vvith the equipment of horses fall
action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some under the art of riding, and this and every military
good; and for this reason the good has rightly action under strategy, in the same way other arts
been declared to be that at which all things aim. fall under yet others-in all of these the ends of
But a certain difference is found among ends; the master arts are to be preferred to all the sub-
some are activities, others are products apart ordinate ends; for it is for the sake of the former
from the activities that produce them. VVhere that the latter are pursued. It malces no difference
24 CHAPTER 3 Moral Character

whether the activities themselves are the ends of


the actions, or something else apart from the 3. Aristotle warns us againsLeXpeCting--a_ high
activities, as in the case of the sciences just degree of precision fn_:oLJr _study :of political
mentioned.b science, because it deal_s- with the, human vari-
able. As such, it is a subject best .handled by
those of experience.
2. AnaJogou_sly, each theoretical_ pursuit has its
apr)ropria_te end, but the science of politics-
ethics and social philosophy-includes all the
Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much
others in the sense that ft determines their-roles
clearness as the subject matter admits of, for pre-
and 'direCts-'their developme'nt. For this reason,
the_--science of politics can_ have as its proper cision is not to be sought for alike in all discus-
, end nothing_-!ess thcln "the good for man." sions, any more than in all the products of the
crafts. Now fine and just actions, which political
science investigates, admit of much variety and
If, then, there is some end of the things vve do, fluctuation of opinion, so that they may be
which we desire for its own sake (everything thought to exist only by convention, and not by
else being desired for the sake of this), and if nature. And goods also give rise to a similar fluc-
we do not choose everything for the sake of tuation because they bring harm to many people;
something else (for at that rate the process for before now men have been undone by reason
'\vould go on to infinity, so that our desire of their vvealth, and others by reason of their
would be empty and vain), clearly this must be courage. We must be content, then, in speaking
the good and the chief good. Will not the knowl- of such subjects and with such premises to indi-
edge of it, then, have a great influence on life? cate the truth roughly and in outline, and in
Shall we not, like archers who have a mark to speaking about things which are only for the
aim at, be more likely to hit upon what is right? most part true and with premises of the same
If so, '\Ve must try, in outline at least to determine kind to reach conclusions that are no better. In
what it is, and of vvhich of the sciences or capaci- the same spirit, therefore, should each type of
ties it is the object. It would seem to belong to statement be received; for it is the mark of an edu-
the most authoritative art and that which is cated man to look for precision in each class of
most truly the master art. And politics appears things just so far as the nature of the subject
to be of this nature; for it is this that ordains admits; it is evidently equally foolish to accept
which of the sciences should be studied in a probable reasoning from a mathematician and
state, and which each class of citizens should to demand from a rhetorician scientific proofs.
learn and up to what point they should learn Now each man judges well the things he
them; and we can see even the most highly knows, and of these he is a good judge. And so
esteemed of capacities to fall under this, for exam- the man who has been educated in a subject is a
ple, strategy, economics, rhetoric; now, since pol- good judge of that subject, and the man who
itics uses the rest of the sciences, and since, again, has received an all-round education is a good
it legislates as to what we are to do and what vve judge in general. Hence a young man is not a
are to abstain from, the end of this science inust proper hearer of lectures on political science; for
include those of the others, so that this end he is inexperienced in the actions that occur in
must be the good for man. For even if the end life, but its discussions start from these and are
is the same for a single man and for a state, that about these; and, further, since he tends to follow
of the state seems at all events something greater his passions, his study '\\rill be in vain and unprof-
and more complete whether to attain or to pre- itable, because the end aimed at is not knowledge
serve; though it is worthwhile to attain the end but action. And it makes no difference whether
merely for one man, it is finer and more godlike he is young in years or youthful in character;
to attain it for a nation or for city-states.c the defect does not depend on time, but on his
ARISTOTLE 25

living, and pursuing each successive object, as strategy, and in the other arts likewise. 'What then
passion directs. For to such persons, as to the is the good of each? Surely that for whose salce
incontinent, knowledge brings no profit; but to everything else is done. In medicine this is health,
those who desire and act in accordance 'Nith a in strategy victory, in architecture a house, in any
rational principle knowledge about such matters other sphere something else, and in every action
will be of great benefit. d and pursuit the end; for it is for the sake of this
that all men do whatever else they do. Therefore,
if there is an end for all that we do, this will be the
4. Among those who are sufficiently mature to
good achievable by action, and if there are more
discuss ethics, there_ i_s verbal agreement-that
than one, these will be the goods achievable by
the ultiinate human good is happiness, but opin-
ions about its precise nature vary. action.
So the argument has by a different course
reached the same point; but vve must try to
Let us resume our inquiry and state, in view of state this even more clearly. Since there are evi-
the fact that all knowledge and every pursuit dently more than one end, and we choose
aims at some good, what it is that we say political some of these (for example, wealth, flutes, and
science aims at and what is the highest of all in general instruments) for the sake of so1nething
goods achievable by action. Verbally there is else, clearly not all ends are final ends; but the
very general agreement; for both the general chief good is evidently something final. There-
run of men and people of superior refinement fore, if there is only one final end, this will be
say that it is happiness, and identify living well what we are seeking, and if there are more than
and doing well with being happy; but with regard one, the most final of these will be what we are
to what happiness is they differ, and the many do seeking. Now we call that which is in itself wor-
not give the same account as the \Vise. For the thy of pursuit more final than that which is wor-
former think it is some plain and obvious thing, thy of pursuit for the sake of something else, and
like pleasure, wealth, or honor; they differ, how- that which is never desirable for the sake of
ever, from one another-and often even the same something else more final than the things that
man identifies it with different things, with health are desirable both in themselves and for the
when he is ill, with wealth when he is poor; but, sake of that other thing, and therefore we call
conscious of their ignorance, they admire those final without qualification that which is always
who proclaim some great ideal that is above desirable in itself and never for the sake of some-
their comprehension. Now some thought [for thing else.
example, Plato J that apart from these many Now such a thing happiness 1 above all else, is
goods there is another which is self-subsistent held to be; for this we choose always for itself and
and causes the goodness of all these as well. To never for the sake of something else, but honor,
examine all the opinions that have been held pleasure, reason, and every virtue we choose
were perhaps somevvhat fruitless; enough to indeed for themselves (for if nothing resulted
examine those that are most prevalent or that from them we should still choose each of
seem to be arguable.' them), but we choose them also for the sake of
happiness, judging that by means of them we
shall be happy. Happiness, on the other hand,
F~_::_-s_:_--'-Affs~o1:!e then proceeds to -discuss the general
'>'_--9riteria that make possible the identification of a no one chooses for the sal<:e of these, nor, in gen-
":: b_u--rnan -being's Chief good. eral, for anything other than itself.
From the point of view of self-sufficiency the
sa1ne result seems to follo\v; for the final good is
Let us again return to the good we are seeking, thought to be self-sufficient. Now by self-sufficient
and ask what it can be. It seems different in differ- \Ve do not mean that which is sufficient for a man
ent actions and arts; it is different in medicine, in by himself, for one who lives a solitary life,
but also for parents, children, wife, and in general '\Vhat is peculiar to man. Let us exclude, therefore,
for his friends and fellow citizens, since man is the life of nutrition and growth. Next there
born for citizenship. But some limit must be set would be a life of perception, but it also seems
to this; for if we extend our requirement to ances- to be common even to the horse, the ox, and
tors and descendants and friends' friends \Ve are eve1y animal. There remains, then, an active life
in for an indefinite series. Let us examine this of the element that has a rational principle; of
question, however, on another occasion; the this, one part has such a principle in the sense
self-sufficient we now define as that which when of being obedient to one, the other in the sense
isolated makes life desirable and lacking in noth- of possessing one and exercising thought. And,
ing; and such we think happiness to be; and fur- as "life of the rational element" also has two
ther we think it most desirable of all things, meanings, we must state that life in the sense of
without being counted as one good thing activity is what we mean; for this seems to be
a1nong others-if it were so counted it would the more proper sense of the term. Now if the
clearly be made more desirable by the addition function of man is an activity of soul which fol-
of even the least of goods; for that wbich is lows or implies a rational principle, and if we
added becomes an excess of goods, and of say "a so-and-so" and "a good so-and-so" have
goods the greater is always more desirable. Hap- a function which is the same in kind, for example,
piness, then, is something final and self-sufficient, a lyre player and a good lyre player, and so \vith-
and is the end of action. f out qualification in all cases, eminence in respect
of goodness being added to the name of the func-
tion (for the function of a lyre player is to play the
6. Although it is agreed that happiness meets lyre, and that of a good lyre player is to do so
these criteria, Aristotle recognizes that the pre- well): if this is the case, [and we state the function
cise nature of happiness still remains to be
of man to be a certain kind of life, and this to be
explained. His definition of happiness contains
two' vitaL concepts: "Activity of souf," which
an activity or actions of the soul implying a ratio-
means the exercise of reason, and "in accor- nal principle, and the fi.mction of a good man to
dance' with virtue/' which describes the quality be the good and noble performance of these, and
of the performance. if any action is well performed when it is per-
formed in accordance '\vith the appropriate excel-
lence: if this is the case,] hu1nan good turns out
Presumably, however, to say that happiness is to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue,
the chief good seems a platitude, and a clearer ai1d if there are more than one virtue, in accor-
account of what it is is still desired. This might dance with the best and most complete.
perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain the But we must add "in a complete life." For
function of man. For just as for a flute player, a one svvallow does not make a summer, nor does
sculptor, or any artist, and, in general, for all one day; and so too one day, or a short time,
things that have a function of activity, the good does not make a man blessed and happy ....
and the "well" is thought to reside in the func- [Also, a happy man J needs the external goods as
tion, so vvould it seem to be for man, if he has vvell; for it is impossible, or not easy, to do
a fw1ction. Have the carpenter, then, and the tan- noble acts without the proper equipment. In
ner certain functions or activities, and has man many actions we use friends and riches and polit-
none? Is he born vvithout a filnction? Or as eye, ical povver as instruments; and there are some
hand, foot, and in general each of the parts evi- things the lack of which takes the luster from hap-
dently has function, may one lay it down that piness, as good birth, goodly children, beauty; for
inan similarly has a function apart from all the man who is ve1y ugly in appearance or ill born
these? What then can this be? Life seems to be or solitary and childless is not very likely to be
common even to plants, but we are seeking happy, and perhaps a man would be still less likely
if he had thoroughly bad children or friends or element in the soul is irrational and one has a ratio-
had lost good children or friends by death. g nal principle. Whether these are separated as the
parts of the body or of anything divisible are, or
are distinct by definition but by nanue inseparable,
7~ Aristotle's definition of_happiness cannot be like convex and concave in the circumference of a
fully understood until the nature_ of virtue has
circle, does not affect the present question.
been thoroughly examined. But the nah.1r_e _of vir-
Of the irrational element one division seems
tue, in turn, depends on the structure of the sou!,
which contains both rational and irrational com- to be widely distributed, and vegetative in its
ponents._Two functions fall to the rational 'part: nature, I mean that \Vhich causes nutrition and
the control of a human being's irrationa/'propen- growth; for it is this kind of power of the soul
sities and the exercise of reason fbr its own sake. that one must assign to all nurslings and to
embryos, and this same power to foll-grown crea-
tures; this is more reasonable than to assign some
Since happiness is an activity of soul in accor- different power to them. Now the excellence of
dance with perfect virtue, we must consider the this seems to be common to all species and not
nature of virtue; for perhaps we shall thus see bet- specifically human ... let us leave the nutritive fac-
ter the nature of happiness. The true student of ulty alone, since it has by its nature no share in
politics, too, is thought to have studied virtue human excellence.
above all things; for he wishes to make his fellow There seems to be also another irrational ele-
citizens good and obedient to the lavvs. As an ment in the soul-one which in a sense, however,
example of this we have the lawgivers of the Cre- shares in a rational principle. For we praise the
tans, the Spartans, and any others of the kind that rational principle of the continent man and of
there may have been. And if this inquiry belongs the incontinent, and the part of their soul that
to political science, clearly the pursuit of it will be has such a principle, since it urges them aright
in accordance with our original plan. But clearly and towards the best objects; but there is found
the virtue we must study is human virtue; in them also another element naturally opposed
for the good vve vvere seeking vvas human good to the rational principle, \Vhich fights against
and the happiness human happiness. By human and resists that principle. For exactly as paralyzed
virtue we mean not that of the body but that of limbs when we intend to move them to the right
the soul; and happiness also we call an activity turn on the contrary to the left, so is it \Vi.th the
of soul. But if this is so, clearly the student of pol- soul; the impulses of incontinent people move
itics must know somehow the facts about soul, as in contrary directions. But while in the body
the man who is to heal the eyes or the body as a \Ve see that which moves astray, in the soul \Ve do
whole must know about the eyes or the body; not. No doubt, however, we must none the less
and all the more since politics is more prized suppose that in the soul too there is something
and better than medicine; but even among doc- contrary to the rational principle, resisting and
tors the best educated spend much labor on opposing it. In what sense it is distinct from the
acquiring knowledge of the body. The student other elements does not concern us. Now even
of politics, then, must study the soul, and must this seems to have a share in a rational principle,
study it with these objects in view, and do so as we said, at any rate in the continent man it
just to the extent which is sufficient for the ques- obeys the rational principle-and presumably in
tions we are discussing; for further precision is the temperate and brave man it is still more obe-
perhaps something more laborious than our pur- dient; for in him it speal<s, on all matters, with the
poses require. same voice as the rational principle.
Some things are said about it, adequately Therefore the irrational element also appears
enough, even in the discussions outside our to be twofold. For the vegetative element in
school, and we must use these; e.g., that one no \vay shares in a rational principle, but the
28 CHAPTER 3 Moral Character

appetitive, and in general the desiring element in to its nature. For instance the stone \Vhich
a sense shares in it, insofar as it listens to and nature moves downwards cannot be naou:uatea
obeys it; this is the sense in which we speak of to move upwards, not even if one tries to
"taking account" of one's father or one's friends, it by throwing it up ten thousand times;
not that in \Vhich we speak of "accounting" for a can fire be habituated to move down-v.rards,
mathematical property. That the irrational ele- can anything else that by nature behaves in
ment is in some sense persuaded by a rational prin- \Vay be trained to behave in another. Neither
ciple is indicated also by the giving of advice and nature, then, nor contrary to nature do the
by all reproof and exhortation. And if this element tues arise in us; rather we are adapted by ua.cwco.
also must be said to have a rational principle, that to receive them, and are made perfect by
which has a rational principle (as well as that which Again, of all the things that come to us
has not) will be twofold, one subdivision having it nature we first acquire the potentiality and
in the strict sense and in itself, and the other hav- exhibit the activity (this is plain in the case
ing a tendency to obey as one does one's father. h the senses; for it was not by often seeing
often hearing that we got these senses, but
the contrary we had them before Vl'e used
8. The virtues corresponding to the two func- and did not come to have them by using
tions of reason are the intellectual and the but the virtues we get by first exercising
moraL The wise individual personifies the intel- as also happens in the case of the arts as
lectual virtues, whereas the continent person For the things \Ve have to learn before \Ve can
typifies th moral virtues. The former's excel-
do them, we learn by doing them, e.g., men
lence is attained through instruction and evi-
denced by knowledge. The excellence of the become builders by building and lyre players by
latter is produced by habits of choice and playing the lyre; so too we become just by
expressed in practical actions tempered by doing just acts, temperate by doing temperate
both the circumstance and the individual. acts, brave by doing brave actsJ

Virtue too is distinguished into kinds in accor- 9. Aristotle turns his attention to the task of
explaining moral virtue. He analyzes human
dance \Vith this difference; for we say that some
personality into three elements: "passions, fac-
of the virtues are intellectual and others moral, ulties, and states of character." Because pas-
philosophic wisdom and understanding and sions (for example, anger and fear) and
practical wisdom being intellectual, liberality faculties (for example, the ability to feel anger
and temperance moral. For in speaking about a and fear) are not in and of themselves blame-
man's character V1'e do not say that he is \vise or worthy or praiseworthy, virtue must be a state
has understanding but that he is good tempered of character. Experience shows that the states
or temperate; yet \Ve praise the wise man also of character that enable a person to fulfill his
\Vith respect to his state of mind; and of states or her proper function aim at an intermediary
of mind we call those \vhich merit praise virtues. point between the opposing extremes of excess
Virtue, then 1 being of two kinds, intellectual and deficiency. The morally virtuous person,
then, always chooses to act according to the
and moral, intellectual virtue in the main owes
"golden mean," but, Aristotle points out, the
both its birth and its gro\vth to teaching (for mean is not the same for all individuals.
\Vhich reason it requires experience and ti1ne ),
\vhile moral virtue co1nes about as a result of
habit, whence also its name ethike is one that is VVe must ... not only describe [moral] virtue as a
formed by a slight variation from the vvord ethos state of character, but also say \Vhat sort of
(habit). From this it is also plain that none of state it is. We n1ay re1nark, then, that every virtue
the moral virtues arises in us by nature; for noth- or excellence both brings into good condition
ing that exists by nature can form a habit contrary the thing of which it is the excellence and malces
ARlSTOTLE 29

the work of that thing be done well; e.g., the relative to us, this being determined by a rational
excellence of the eye makes both the eye and its principle, and by that principle by which the man
work good; for it is by the excellence of the eye of practical wisdom would determine it. Now it is
that we see well. Similarly the excellence of the a mean between two vices, that which depends on
horse makes a horse both good in itself and excess and that which depends on defect; and
good at running and at carrying its rider and at again it is a mean because the vices respectively
awaiting the attack of the enemy. Therefore, if fall short of or exceed what is right in both pas-
this is true in every case, the virtue of man also sions and actions, 'vhile virtue both finds and
will be the state of character which makes a man chooses that which is intermediate. Hence in
good and which makes him do his own work well. respect of its substance and the definition which
How this is to happen we have stated already, states its essence virtue is a mean, with regard
but it will be made plain also by the following to what is best and right an extreme.
consideration of the specific nature of virtue. In But not every action nor every passion admits
everything that is continuous and divisible it is of a mean; for some have names that already
possible to take more, less, or an equal amount, imply badness, e.g., spite, shamelessness, envy,
and that either in terms of the thing itself or rel- and in the case of actions adultery, theft, murder;
atively to us; and the equal is an intermediate for all of these and suchlike things imply by their
between excess and defect. By the intermediate names that they are themselves bad, and not the
in the object I mean that which is equidistant excesses or deficiencies of them. It is not possible,
from each of the extremes, which is one and the then, ever to be right vvith regard to them; one
same for all men; by the intermediate relatively to must always be wrong. Nor does goodness or
us that which is neither too much nor too little- badness with regard to such things depend on
and this is not one, nor the same for all. For committing adultery with the right woman, at
instance, if ten is many and two is fev{, six is the the right time, and in the right \Vay, but simply
intermediate, taken in terms of the object; for it to do any of them is to go wrong. It would be
exceeds and is exceeded by an equal amount; equally absurd, then, to expect that in unjust,
this is intermediate according to arithmetical pro~ cowardly, and voluptuous action there should
portion. But the intermediate relatively to us is be a mean, an excess, and a deficiency; for at
not to be taken so; if ten pounds are too much that rate there would be a mean of excess and
for a particular person to eat and two too little, of deficiency, an excess of excess, and a deficiency
it does not follow that the trainer will order six of deficiency. But as there is no excess and defi-
pounds; for this also is perhaps too much for ciency of temperance and courage because vvhat
the person who is to take it, or too little-too lit- is intermediate is in a sense an extreme, so too
tle for Milo [a famous Greek athlete], too much of the actions \Ve have mentioned there is no
for the beginner in athletic exercises. The same mean nor any excess and deficiency, but however
is true of running and \Vrestling. Thus a master they are done they are wrong; for in general there
of any art avoids excess and defect, but seeks is neither a mean of excess and deficiency, nor
the intermediate and chooses this-the interme- excess and deficiency of a mean.k
cliate not in the object but relatively to us.i

11_. His general formulation of moral virtue


10-. Aristotle -is now ready to assemble the completed, Aristotle proceeds to a direct exam-
results of his investigation into a- definition of ination of specific moral virtues.
moral virtue.

We must, however, not only make this general


Virtue, then, is a state of character concerned statement, but also apply it to the individual
with choice, lying in a mean, i.e., the mean facts. For among statements about conduct
30 CHAPTER 3 Moral Character

those which are general apply more widely, but intermediate person ambitious and sometimes
those which are particular are more genuine, unambitious, and sometimes praise the ambitious
since conduct has to do with individual cases, man and sometimes the unambitious. The reason
and our statements must harmonize with the of our doing this will be stated in what follows;
facts in these cases. We may take these cases but nov.r let us speak of the remaining states
from our table. With regard to feelings of fear according to the method which has been
and confidence courage is the mean; of the peo- indicated.
ple who exceed, he who exceeds in fearlessness VVith regard to anger also there is an excess, a
has no name (many of the states have no deficiency, and a mean. Although they can
name), while the man who exceeds in confidence scarcely be said to have names, yet since we call
is rash, and he who exceeds in fear and falls short the intermediate person good tempered let us
in confidence is a coward. With regard to pleas- call the mean good temper; of the persons at
ures and pains-not all of them, and not so the extremes let the one who exceeds be called
much "With regard to the pains-the mean is tem- irascible, and his vice irascibility, and the man
perance, the excess self-indulgence. Persons defi- who falls short an inirascible sort of person, and
cient with regard to the pleasures are not often the deficiency inirascibility. 1
found; hence such persons also have received no
name. But let us call them "insensible."
With regard to giving and taking of money 12. Next, Aristotle investigates the intellectual
virtues-that is, the virtues that accompany the
the mean is liberality, the excess and the defect
proper exercise of reason in its various func-
prodigality and meanness. In these actions people tions. The primary tasks of intellect are first, to
exceed and fall short in contrary vvays; the prodi- give us knowledge of invariable and fixed prin-
gal exceeds in spending and falls short in talting, ciples and second, to provide a rational guide
while the mean man exceeds in taking and falls for action in daily life. The pursuit and discovery
short in spending .... With regard to money of truth is the aim of philosophical wisdom,
there are also other dispositions-a mean, mag- whereas the purpose of practical wisdom is
nificence (for the magnificent man differs from intelligent conduct. The basis for intelligent con-
the liberal man; the former deals with large duct is the union of true knowledge of what we_
sums, the latter v.rith small ones), an excess, ought to do and the desire to do it. Aristotle con-
tastelessness and vulgarity, and a deficiency, trasts his view with that of Socrates on this point.
He holds that Socrates was correct in associating
niggardliness ....
virtue with princip!es discovered by reason but
With regard to honor and dishonor the mean was wrong in assuming that knowledge of the
is proper pride, the excess is known as a sort of good is necessarily accompanied by a desire to
"empty vanity," and the deficiency is undue act on this knowledge.
humility; and as we said liberality was related to
magnificence, differing from it by dealing with
small sums, so there is a state similarly related We divided the virtues of the soul and said that
to proper pride, being concerned with small hon- some are virtues of character and others of intel-
ors '\Vhile that is concerned with great. For it is lect. N ov.r \Ve have discussed in detail the moral
possible to desire honor as one ought, and virtues; with regard to the others let us express
more than one ought, and less, and the man our view as follows, beginning with some remarks
who exceeds in his desires is called ambitious, about the soul. We said before that there are two
the man who falls short unambitious, while the parts of the soul~that vvhich grasps a rule or
intermediate person has no name. The disposi- rational principle, and the irrational; let us no'\v
tions also are nameless, except that that of the dravv a si1nilar distinction v.rithin the part vvhich
ambitious man is called ambition. Hence the peo- grasps a rational principle. And let it be assumed
ple who are at the extremes lay claim to the mid- that there are tvvo parts '\vhich grasp a rational
dle place; and we ourselves sometimes call the principle-one by which we contemplate the
ARISTOTLE 31

kind of things whose originative causes are invari- and intellect or without a moral state; for good
able, and one by which we contemplate variable action and its opposite cannot exist without a
things; for where objects differ in kind the part combination of intellect and character. Intellect
of the soul answering to each of the two is differ- itself, however, moves nothing, but only the
ent in kind, since it is in virtue of a certain likeness intellect which aims at an end and is practical;
and kinship with their objects that they have the for this rules the productive intellect as vvell,
knowledge they have. since everyone who makes makes for an end,
... The virtue of a thing is relative to its and that which is made is not an end in the
proper work. Now there are three things in the unqualified sense (but only an end in a particular
soul which control action and truth-sensation, relation, and the end of a particular operation)-
reason, desire. only that which is done is that; for good action is
Of these sensation originates no [moral J an end, and desire aims at this. Hence choice is
action; this is plain from the fact that the lower either desiderative reason or ratiocinative desire,
animals have sensation but no share in [such] and such an origin of action is a man.
action. 1 ... This is why some say that all the virtues
What affirmation and negation are in think- are forms of practical vvisdom .... Socrates in .I
ing, pursuit and avoidance are in desire; so that one respect was on the right track while in
since moral virtue is a state of character con-
cerned with choice, and choice is deliberate
desire, therefore both the reasoning must
another he went astray; in thinking that all the
virtues were forms of practical wisdom he \Vas
wrong, but in saying they implied practical wis-
lI
be true and the desire right, if the choice is to
be good, and the latter must pursue just what
the former asserts. Now this kind of intellect
dom he was right. This is confirmed by the fact
that even now all men, \vhen they define virtue,
after naming the state of character and its objects
II
and of truth is practical; of the intellect which add "that (state) which is in accordance with the
I
;l
is contemplative, not practical nor productive, right rule"; now the right rule is that which is in
the good and the bad state are truth and falsity accordance vvith practical wisdom. All men, then,
respectively (for this is the work of everything seem somehovv to divine that this kind of state is
intellectual); while of the part which is practical virtue, viz., that which is in accordance with prac-
and intellectual the good state is truth in agree- tical wisdom. But we must go a little further. For
ment with right desire. it is not merely the state in accordance with the
The origin of [moral] action-its efficient, right rule, but the state that implies the presence
not its final cause 2 -is choice, and that of choice of the right rule, that is virtue; and practical \Vis-
is desire and reasoning with a view to an end. This dom is a right rule about such matters. Socrates,
is why choice cannot exist either without reason then, thought the virtues were rules or rational
principles (for he thought they were, all of
them, forms of scientific knowledge), while we
1
Aristotle's analysis in this passage is directed toward those thinlc they involve a rational principle.m
actions of people of which it may be said, in some sense,
that their "moving principle is in the agent himself, he
being a\vare of the particular circumstances of the action"-
that is, voluntary actions. He ascribes no moral significance 13. Aristotle maintains that we should not
to involuntary action.r-that is, actions for \vhich people are choose activities by how pleasant they are.
not responsible (for example, actions resulting from external Rather, although good activities are pleasant,
forces, those arising "by reason of ignorance" of the particular and are choiceworthy because they are pleas-
circumstances, and those done because of excessive pain or the ant, their pleasantness is a function of their
fear of excessive pain).
goodness, not vice versa.
2
Aristotle distinguishes the efficient cause, the agent or force
that produces an effect, from the final cause, the end or pur-
pose "for the sake of \Vhich a thing is done." For example, the
efficient cause of the mural on the wall of an auditorium is the Now the activities of thought differ from those
painter, \vhereas its final cause is the decoration of the room. of the senses, and both differ among themselves,
32 CHAPTER 3 Moral Character

in kind; so, therefore, do the pleasures that com- have been stated to do much the same as pain;
plete them. they destroy the activity, only not to the same
This may be seen, too, from the fact that each degree.
of the pleasures is bound up with the activity it No\v since activities differ in respect of good-
completes. For an activity is intensified by its ness and badness, and some are vvorthy to be cho-
proper pleasure, since each class of things is better sen, others to be avoided, and other neutral, so,
judged of and brought to precision by those who too, are the pleasures; for to each activity there
engage in the activity with pleasure; e.g., it is a proper pleasure. The pleasure proper to a
is those who enjoy geometrical thinking that worthy activity is good and that proper to an
become geometers and grasp the various proposi- unworthy activity bad; just as the appetites for
tions better, and, similarly, those who are fond of noble objects are laudable, those for base objects
music or of building, and so on, mak:e progress in culpable. But the pleasures involved in activities
their proper function by enjoying it; so the pleas- are more proper to them than the desires; for
ures intensify the activities, and what intensifies a the latter are separated both in time and in
thing is proper to it, but things different in kind nature, while the former are close to the activities,
have properties different in kind. and so hard to distinguish from them that it
This Vlrill be even more apparent from the admits of dispute whether the activity is not the
fact that activities are hindered by pleasures aris- same as the pleasure .... As activities are different,
ing from other sources. For people who are fond then, so are the corresponding pleasures. Now
of playing the flute are incapable of attending to sight is superior to touch in purity, and hearing
arguments if they overhear some one playing the and smell to taste; the pleasures, therefore, are
flute, since they enjoy flute-playing more than similarly superior, and those of thought superior
the activity in hand; so the pleasure connected to these, and within each of the t\vo ldnds some
with flute-playing destroys the activity con- are superior to other. n
cerned \vith argument. This happens, similarly,
in all other cases, when one is active about nvo
things at once; the more pleasant activity drives 14. Although Aristotle acknowledges the impor-
out the other, and if it is much more pleasant tance of reason as a guide to moral action, he
does so all the more, so that one even ceases maintains that philosophic wisdom is superior
from the other. This is why when we enjoy any- even to practical wisdom. He defends his
thing very much we do not throv.r ourselves into esteem for contemplation by showing that the
anything else, and do one thing only when we life of contemplation comes closest to meeting
are not much pleased by another; e.g., in the the conditions for happiness.
theatre the people who eat sweets do so most
when the actors are poor. No\V since activities
are made precise and more enduring and better If happiness is activity in accordance vvith virtue,
by their proper pleasure, and injured by alien it is reasonable that it should be in accordance
pleasures, evidently the tv.ro kinds of pleasure with the highest virtue; and this will be that of
are far apart. For alien pleasures do pretty the best thing in us. Whether it be reason or
much \Vhat proper pains do, since activities are something else that is this element which is
destroyed by their proper pains; e.g., if a man thought to be our natural ruler and guide and
finds writing or doing sums unpleasant and pain- to take thought of things noble and divine,
ful, he does not \vrite, or does not do sums 1
whether it be itself also divine or only the most
because the activity is painful. So an activity suf- divine element in us, the activity of this in accor-
fers contrary effects from its proper pleasures dance with its proper virtue will be perfect happi-
and pains, i.e., from those that supervene on it ness. That this activity is contemplative \Ve have
in virtue of its own nature. And alien pleasures already said.
ARISTOTLE 33

Now this would seem to be in agreement honors, or at all events happiness, for him and
both with what we said before and with the his fellow citizens-a happiness different from
truth. For, firstly, this activity is the best political action, and evidently sought as being
(since not only is reason the best thing in us, different. So if among virtuous actions political
but the objects of reason are the best of know and military actions are distinguished by nobil-
able objects); and, secondly, it is the most con- ity and greatness, and these are unleisurely and
tinuous, since we can contemplate truth more aim at an end and are not desirable for their
continuously than we can do anything. And we sake, but the activity of reason, vvhich is con-
think happiness has pleasure mingled with it, templative, seems both to be superior in serious
but the activity of philosophic wisdom is admit worth and to aim at no end beyond itself, and to
tedly the pleasantest of virtuous activities; at all have its pleasure proper to itself (and this aug
events the pursuit of it is thought to offer pleas ments the activity), and the self-sufficiency, lei
ures marvelous for their purity and their endur- sureliness, unweariedness (so far as this is
ingness, and it is to be expected that those who possible for man), and all the other attributes
know will pass their time more pleasantly than ascribed to the supremely happy man are evi
those who inquire. And the self-sufficiency dently those connected with this activity, it fol-
that is spoken of must belong most to the con lows that this will be the complete happiness of
templative activity. For while a philosopher, as man, if it be allowed a complete term of life (for
well as a just man or one possessing any other none of the attributes of happiness is
virtue, needs the necessaries of life, when they incomplete).
are sufficiently equipped with things of that But such a life would be too high for man;
sort the just man needs people towards whom for it is not insofar as he is man that he will
and with whom he shall act justly, and the tern live so, but insofar as something divine is pres-
perate man, the brave man, and each of the ent in him; and by so much as this is superior
others is in the same case, but the philosopher, to our composite nature is its activity superior
even when by himself, can contemplate truth, to that which is the exercise of the other kind
and the better the vviser he is; he can perhaps of virtue. If reason is divine, then, in compari-
do so better if he has fellow workers, but still son vvith man, the life according to it is divine
he is the most self-sufficient. And this activity in comparison with human life. But we must
alone would seem to be loved for its own salce; not follow those who advise us, being men, to
for nothing arises from it apart from the con- think of human things, and, being mortal, of
templating, while from practical activities vve mortal things, but must, so far as vve can,
gain more or less apart from the action. And make ourselves immortal, and strain every
happiness is thought to depend on leisure; for nerve to live in accordance vvith the best thing
we are busy that vve may have leisure, and in us; for even if it be small in bulk, much
make war that we may live in peace. Now the more does it in power and vvorth surpass every-
activity of the practical virtues is exhibited in thing. This would seem, too, to be each inan
political or military affairs, but the actions con- himself, since it is the authoritative and better
cerned with these seem to be unleisurely. War- part of him. It would be strange, then, if he
like actions are completely so (for no one were to choose not the life of his self but that
chooses to be at war, or provokes war, for the of something else. And what we said before
salce of being at war; anyone would seem abso- will apply now; that which is proper to each
lutely murderous if he were to make enemies thing is by nature best and most pleasant for
of his friends in order to bring about battle each thing; for man, therefore, the life accord-
and slaughter); but the action of the statesman ing to reason is best and pleasantest, since rea-
is also unleisurely, and-apart from the political son more than anything else is man. This life
action itself-aims at despotic power and therefore is also the happiest. 0

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi