Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 2

INFECTIOUS DISEASE/EDITORIAL

The Limits of Techne and Episteme emergency care systems response to the severe acute
respiratory syndrome (SARS) outbreak in Singapore
Robert L. Wears, MD, MS illustrates the shortcomings of both.
Crossover trials, where each subject participates in
From the Center for Safety in Emergency Care and the Department each arm of a study, thus serving as his or her own con-
of Emergency Medicine, University of Florida Health Science
trol subject, have a strong intuitive appeal. Indeed,
Center, Jacksonville, FL.
Reed2 found 84 crossover trials in a 7-year search of 3
See related articles, p. 6 and p. 54. prominent emergency medicine journals (including
Annals)about 1 per month across all 3 journals. Reed
[Ann Emerg Med. 2004;43:15-16.] notes that, in a sample of these studies, none explicitly
examined the possibility of carryover effects, the most
The ancient Greeks identified 4 different kinds of knowl- important bias peculiar to crossover designs. We then
edge. Two of them, episteme and techne, are dominant in expect a technical explanation of how to do a statistical
medical research. Episteme involves abstract reasoning test for carryover, accompanied by exhortations to be
about idealized, disembodied, universal concepts. Its more careful next time, but instead a review of the main
methods are deduction and generalization; it is the basis methods for such testing reveals that none of them work.
for modern science and appears in medicine as the Even worse, the current opinion of experts in the field
quest for methodological rigor. Its most muscular man- is that no successful method will be devised.4 The care-
ifestation is the evidence-based medicine movement. ful application of techne to this issue leads to the con-
Techne involves a mix of the abstract and the practical. clusion that techne will not be able to help us.
Its goals are the development and testing of recipes; it Thams3 narrative about Singapores response to the
is the basis for modern engineering and appears in SARS outbreak exemplifies a situation where both
medicine largely in the form of numeric reasoning, such techne and episteme are inadequate. If Thams article
as applied statistical inference. had been a scientific study of the development of a clin-
Techne and episteme have dominated Western ical decision rule to identify patients at high risk for
thought since the Renaissance, and no one would deny SARS, reviewers would have found it seriously flawed.
the benefits that modern science and engineering have Their screening tool was put into use 4 days after the
produced in health care. In fact, they have become so first nurses became ill; at that time, there had been only
dominant it is sometimes hard for us to conceive, much about 10 cases of confirmed SARS at their hospital, not
less admit, that they may be limited. To some, no other nearly enough to support development of a screening
forms of legitimate knowledge even exist. Taken to- test. It was repeatedly modified during the course of its
gether, techne and episteme are judgments about how use. And, even if they had been lucky enough to come
knowledge is to be verified, codified, and expressed, up with a decision rule that was highly sensitive, the
once it has been discovered.1 confidence limits on sensitivity would have been ludi-
In this issue of Annals, 2 seemingly disparate articles crously wide.
combine to illustrate the limits of techne and episteme. Similarly, if the article were an evaluation of their
Reeds2 article on crossover trials presents a paradox, interventions, it would also have been flawed. There is
where the methods of techne demonstrate the limita- no comparison group, the outcome measures are
tions of techne, and Thams3 article describing the unclear, and the opportunities for bias in assessing the
outcome are great. In the world of techne and episteme,
there seems to be little that can be learned here.
But, we dont live in the world of techne and episteme.
0196-0644/$30.00 We live in the real world of changeable and unpre-
Copyright 2004 by the American College of Emergency Physicians. dictable situations, in a fluid and chancy reality, with
doi:10.1016/j.annemergmed.2003.08.007 limited time, too much information but not enough of

JANUARY 2004 43:1 ANNALS OF EMERGENCY MEDICINE 1 5


L I M I T S O F T E C H N E A N D E P I S T E M E Wears

the right kind, and one where waiting for a better deci- - in uncertain situa-
break illustrates the value of metis
sion can be riskier than acting on hunches and inade- tions. It also raises important, hard-to-answer ques-
quate information. tions. In the face of a new, unknown threat, relaxing the
What is needed in these situations is a third type of evidentiary standards for taking action seems easy, but
knowledge, which the Greeks called metis - . Metis
- is fre- what about situations that are less clear, times that are
quently translated as cunning, but that does not do it less than a crisis, but are still ambiguous and discon-
justice. What it refers to is a kind of oblique, conjectural, certing?
often tacit, unaware, and intuitive knowledge drawn Both articles illustrate the value of knowledge that is
from long practical experience.1,5 Metis - is a difficult-to- not captured in the objectified worlds of episteme and
express knowledge of short cuts, of sagacious envi- techne. We have subordinated this knowledge for so
sioning, of perspicuous intervention, even more muta- long that we risk its disappearance. Revaluing it and
ble than the situation it has to cope with.5 It is more finding the proper balance among these types should be
involved with producing new conjectures and new one of the central intellectual questions medicine faces.
knowledge than establishing the truth of a given con- How can we cultivate and value metis - while simultane-
jecture. We are familiar with this type of knowledge in ously avoiding the slide into romanticism, anecdote,
the clinical world, although we have come progres- and superstition? We may not see answers even far off,
sively to distrust it for a variety of reasons.6 but agreeing on the importance of the question would
Tham3 and colleagues were able to use this sort of be a good first step.
-
knowledge ( metis) about how diseases act, how people
react to them, what resources were at hand, and how The Center for Safety in Emergency Care is funded in part by a grant
social systems work to quickly devise an adaptive re- from the Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality.
sponse to a dynamic, uncertain, and changing situation. Reprints not available from the author.
We can never know for sure whether their responses Address for correspondence: Robert L. Wears, MD, MS, Depart-
were correct, but it seems likely that waiting for a sci- ment of Emergency Medicine, University of Florida Health Science
entifically sound evidentiary base would have been a Center Jacksonville, 655 West 8th Street, Jacksonville, FL 32209;
worse strategy. 904-244-4124, fax 904-244-4508; E-mail wears@ufl.edu.
Returning to crossover trials, what should we do
about them? The easy and obvious answer is simply to REFERENCES
1. Scott JC. Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human
ban them. Reed2 points out that the US Food and Drug Condition Have Failed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press; 1998.
Administration has, in effect, done that, although some 2. Reed JF III. Analysis of two-treatment, two-period crossover trials in emergency
disagree with their stance.4 A more enlightened ap- medicine. Ann Emerg Med. 2004;43:54-58.
3. Tham K-Y. An emergency department response to severe acute respiratory syn-
proach would be to require that authors (and editors drome: a prototype response to bioterrorism. Ann Emerg Med. 2004;43:6-14.
and reviewers) explicitly examine the question of car- 4. Senn S. Cross-over Trials in Clinical Research. 2nd ed. London, United Kingdom:
John Wiley & Sons Ltd; 2002.
ryover effects. If, on the basis of their knowledge of the 5. Baumard P. Oblique knowledge: the clandestine work of organizations [Institut
domain they believe carryover can be neglected, then dAdministration des Entreprises dAix-en-Provence Web site]. Available at: http://
www.iae.univ-aix.fr/cv/baumard/oblique_knowledge.htm. Accessed March 20, 2003.
they should clearly indicate that the results are contin- 6. Berg M. Rationalizing Medical Work. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 1997.
gent on the validity of that assumption; if not, then the
crossover design must be abandoned. This will require
a degree of subjective insight and judgment (that is,
-
metis) that some may find uncomfortable. This discom-
fort is unwarranted, however. All studies, whether
crossover trials or not, contain innumerable unverified
and unverifiable assumptions. They may seem less
bothersome because many are less obvious, and many
we have simply gotten used to, but they are there none-
theless. Reeds article on crossover trials illustrates what
an important role this sort of knowledge plays in the
research world, even though it is seldom spoken of there.
Similarly, Thams3 story of how workers in Singapore
reacted adaptively to the unknown in the SARS out-

1 6 ANNALS OF EMERGENCY MEDICINE 43:1 JANUARY 2004

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi