Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 3

Introduction to Part II

How can we gain moral knowledge? In some cases, to refute the skeptical position that refuses to credit
philosophers treat this question as a specific instance of anyone with knowledge.
the more general question: how we can gain knowl- Discussions in moral epistemology rarely start by
edge of anything? This more general question is usually considering these most radical forms of skepticism.
framed by reference to a variety of skeptical challenges. Instead, such discussions usually begin with the ass-
The deepest of these, and the ones hardest to answer, umption that we can know at least some things that
are those that cast doubt on our ability to know two and two are four, that there are rivers and moun-
anything at all. tains and volcanoes on earth, that other people are
Consider, for instance, the relevant alternatives argu- alive, can think, and can feel roughly as we do.
ment: in order to know that some claim is true, one Importantly, the knowledge that gets taken for granted
must first be able to decisively exclude all views that are in such discussions is straightforward, nonmoral knowl-
incompatible with the original claim. But one can edge. The challenge in ethics typically originates by
never do that. So one can never know anything. noting important differences between the nonmoral
Or consider the vicious circle argument: in order to claims that are usually accepted as knowledge, and
know that some claim is true, one must first know that moral claims, which often are not.
ones methods for sorting true from false beliefs are One perennial source of skepticism about moral
reliable. But in order to know that ones methods are knowledge is the comparatively greater degree of disa-
reliable, one must first know some particular facts, greement about moral claims than about mathematical
whose existence is vindicated by those methods. Since or empirical claims. As we saw in Part I, some philoso-
knowing the facts requires knowing the methods, and phers use this fact about the scope of moral disagree-
knowing the methods requires knowing the facts, we ment to argue that ethics is not objective. But other
cant escape from this vicious circle, and consequently, philosophers cite this fact as the basis for a more modest
we know nothing. claim. Even if widespread moral disagreement is com-
There are plenty of other general skeptical argu- patible with ethical objectivity, such extensive
ments, i.e., arguments designed to impugn our knowl- disagreement undermines the chance of ever knowing
edge of anything at all. If knowledge requires a decisive right from wrong. For (it is claimed) if a belief remains
refutation of such skepticism, then knowledge may controversial among intelligent and rational people,
well be an impossibility, since it is notoriously difficult then we should suspend judgment on its merits.

Ethical Theory: An Anthology, Second Edition. Edited by Russ Shafer-Landau.


2013 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2013 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

0001513940.INDD 71 4/25/2012 3:20:49 AM


72 int roduction

Allmoral beliefs are controversial in this way. And so specific intuitions to serve as a basis, and a criterion, for
we should suspend belief about all moral matters. establishing our network of justified moral beliefs. We
Renford Bambrough, in his selection here, tries to have very strong convictions about cases, and though
rebut this traditional criticism. (I also try my hand at we neednt regard them as self-certifying, we do regard
rebutting this argument in my article in Part I.) them as warranted starting points for ethical investiga-
Bambrough argues that we must ensure that compari- tion. He is no doubt correct about the way in which we
sons between moral and nonmoral knowledge are fair, actually proceed in our moral justifications. Indeed, he
and that when we do, we will see that moral knowl- doesnt see any other plausible way to proceed in trying
edge fares no worse than nonmoral knowledge. It to decide what is right and wrong. As Kagan argues,
wouldnt do to impugn the possibility of scientific however, our reliance on such convictions may well fail
knowledge just because there are a number of unsolved to yield justified moral beliefs.
scientific questions that engender controversy. After all, Kagans doubts are rooted in a set of disanalogies
there are a great many scientific claims that garner drawn between the way in which we acquire justified
near-universal consensus. But things are no different empirical belief and the manner in which we come to
when it comes to morality. Discussions of moral hold the moral beliefs we do. The problem isnt that
knowledge often highlight the disputed cases, but there there is more disagreement in ethics than in science.
is also a great deal of near-unanimity on many moral Rather, the problem is that while we have some
matters for instance, that it is wrong to deliberately account of the reliability of empirical belief, we lack
withhold available anesthesia from a patient when such an account in ethics. Certain of our empirical
performing a very painful surgery. beliefs strike us immediately as being correct, and,
In his very interesting selection here, George Sher further, we have a roughly coherent picture of the way
argues that it isnt the presence of widespread disagree- the natural world works that explains how our senses
ment alone that generates problems for moral knowl- are reliable indicators of its contents. Granted, certain
edge. Rather, it is this disagreement combined with of our moral beliefs, too, strike us immediately as being
what he calls contingency namely, the claim that we hold clearly correct. But here, claims Kagan, we lack a
most of the moral beliefs we do largely as a result of coherent overall theory of morality that underwrites
accidents of birth and upbringing.Were we born in very our moral intuitions. Until we have a better-developed
different circumstances, or exposed to very different account of the moral world, and of the moral sense that
influences, wed have very different moral beliefs from would intuit its contours, it is doubtful that we are
the ones we presently hold. This fact, combined with justified in relying on intuitions in the crucial ways we
the existence of such broad ethical disagreement, casts do when thinking about ethics.
doubt on the reliability of our moral beliefs. Robert Audis contribution to this section offers a
Bambroughs article considers this objection, too, as detailed account and defense of ethical intuitionism,
well as a number of other traditional arguments for which seeks precisely to justify our reliance on our
moral skepticism. His reply is, as before, to try to estab- moral intuitions our strongly held, non-inferentially
lish the parity between moral and nonmoral beliefs. It formed moral beliefs. Intuitionism has a long history,
is true, says Bambrough, that we would have very and Audi traces some of it, while updating its for-
different nonmoral beliefs from the ones we presently mulation in several important ways. Intuitionism has
hold, were we to have been born or raised in very dif- frequently been relied on to solve the regress problem,
ferent circumstances from our actual ones. But just as an especially difficult skeptical worry about moral
that fact does not undermine our claims to ordinary belief. The regress problem states that every justified
nonmoral knowledge, neither should it undermine our moral belief requires supporting reasons that confer its
otherwise warranted claims to moral knowledge. justification. These reasons have to come from other
Still, we might ask why most of us are so confident of beliefs. But these other beliefs will be either nonmoral
having at least some moral knowledge that surgeons or moral. They cant be nonmoral, since, following
ought to use easily available anesthetics, that genocide Hume, no moral belief is entailed by a nonmoral one.
and slavery are immoral, that offering nourishment and But the supporting beliefs cannot be moral, either,
love to a starving child is a morally good thing. Shelly since any such supporting belief must itself be supported
Kagan has an answer namely, that we rely on our case- by yet other moral beliefs, and so on, and so on (this is

0001513940.INDD 72 4/25/2012 3:20:49 AM


int roduction 73

the regress that gives the argument its name). Since In a nutshell: we are justified in holding a belief only
moral beliefs require support, and no support can be if wehave reasons that support it; these reasons must
offered, no moral beliefs are justified. Hence we cannot come from other beliefs, and not the belief itself;
have any moral knowledge. therefore all epistemic justification must be inferential;
The ethical intuitionist solves this problem by denying therefore there are no self-evident beliefs. If a line of
that all justified moral beliefs must receive support from moral questioning cannot stop, though, with a self-
other beliefs. Rather, we are justified in believing some evident belief, then how can we avoid an infinite
moral claims just because we understand them. Such regress? The coherentist argues that we need to
beliefs are known as self-evident moral beliefs. Suppose abandon the idea of a wholly linear chain of
you believe as you very likely do that it is immoral justification, and instead consider that a belief can
to torture children for the sole purpose of generating receive support, and in turn lend support to, a variety
sadistic pleasure. Do you really need to introduce of other beliefs. So long as there is this mutual
evidence in support of such a claim? All argument must support, a belief is justified.
stop somewhere. Intuitionists claim that some highly This of course looks like an endorsement of circular
credible moral beliefs are satisfactory stopping points. reasoning, since a belief s supporting evidence will
That these beliefs may not garner universal consensus is consist of other beliefs whose justification is ultimately
neither here nor there. There are many truths, and some a matter of having received support from the initial
justified beliefs, that will not attract the endorsement of belief under scrutiny. Coherentists reply that fans of
everyone. If some moral outliers fail to see the truth of self-evidence are no better off. Indeed, say coherentists,
certain moral claims, that reveals a defect in their they are worse off, since self-evidence is the epitome of
understanding. It does not show that the self-evident circular reasoning. To claim that a belief can provide
beliefs require outside support. Nor does it undermine evidence for itself is to use the very belief in question
the status of such beliefs as self-evident. as its own support a very small circle indeed.
The moral coherentist will have none of this. The debate between fans of self-evidence and fans of
Coherentists, here represented by Geoffrey Sayre- coherentism represents a series of ongoing controver-
McCord, claim that beliefs are justified if, and to sies in moral epistemology. Readers are well-advised to
theextent that, they cohere with ones other beliefs. consider these arguments, and whether those of either
No beliefs are self-evident. Sayre-McCord here side can adequately address the worries raised by Kagan
provides a powerful argument against self-evidence. and Sher.

0001513940.INDD 73 4/25/2012 3:20:49 AM

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi