Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 35

JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL CHILD PSYCHOLOGY 46, 289-323 (1988)

Contextualism: The World View of Behavior Analysis


EDWARD K. MORRIS

Department of Humon De\~elopment. University (If Kurrstrs

The thesis of this paper is that contemporary behavior analysis-and the behavior
analysis of child development in particular-is contextualistic in world view, in
contrast to its traditional characterization as being mechanistic. The contextualistic
character of behavior analysis is introduced by presenting some material on the
fields historical background. This material, though, is not presented in the manner
of the standard account, but rather in a revised account with respect to such
movements as empiricism, associationism. positivism. operationism. and prag-
matism. The thesis is then developed more fully by comparing and contrasting
the contextualism of behavior analysis with mechanism. both of which are analyzed
with respect to five core developmental issues: (a) elementarism versus holism.
(b) development as response-based change versus structural change. (c) causal
versus functional analysis, (d) continuity versus discontinuity, and (e) the passive
versus active nature of development. Finally. the importance of context in
contextualism is examined and organized according to current behavior-analytic
practices. Concluding commentary focuses on the salutory effects of having both
behavior analysis and mainstream developmental psychology be commensurable
in world view. especially with regard to such issues as cognition. ~tl IYXX Acadcmlc
PlC\\. Inc.

In 1942, Stephen C. Pepper published a book entitled World Hypothesis:


A Study in Evidence. In that philosophically enlightened but sometimes
opaque work, Pepper presented what he took to be several relatively
adequate and autonomous world views-among them, mechanism, con-
textualism, and organicism-formulated somewhat commonsensically ac-

This paper is dedicated to Sidney W. Bijou-mentor. colleague. and friend-in celebration


of the 25th anniversary of his having founded the Jorrr-rrtrl c!fEupc,~i,,?c,/tttr/ Child P.s.w/~h~~.
Appreciation is extended to Philip N. Hineline. who invited an initial version of this paper
for a 1987 symposium conducted at the meeting of the American Psychological Association
(Morris, 1987). and to Donald M. Baer, Lisa M. Johnson, Bryan D. Midgley. Hayne W.
Reese, Susan M. Schneider. James T. Todd, and Grover Whitehurst. who provided helpful
comments on other versions of the present manuscript. The author. however. is responsible
for any remaining alchemy of argument or maladroitness of mind. Appreciation is extended
also to the Harvard University Department of Psychology and to the May institute (Chatham,
MA) for their respective Spring and Summer 1988 Visiting Scholar appointments. Reprint
requests should be sent to the author at the Department of Human Development. University
of Kansas, Lawrence. KS 66045.

289
0022-0965/8X $3.00
290 EDWARD K. MORRIS

cording to their respective underlying root metaphors. those being the


machine, the historic event, and the living organism.
For many years. Peppers analysis of how these world views interacted
with the conduct of normal science was of little explicit consequence in
developmental psychology for perhaps two related reasons. First. Pepper
argued against the possibility of a strictly empiricist and logical epistemology
devoid of world views (see also Lakatos. 1978; Laudan. 1977), thereby
taking a position that ran counter to the logical positivism that had
dominated psychology since the 1930s. And second, Hull-Spence S-R
learning theory-a derivative of this logical positivism-gave rise first
to dynamic social learning theory (Bandura & Walters. 1963: Berlyne.
1965; Dollard & Miller, 1950; Miller & Dollard, 1941: Mowrer, 1960:
Sears, Maccoby. & Levin. 1957) and then to cognitive social learning
theory (Bandura, 1977), which became the orthodox views within de-
velopmental psychology between about 1940 and 1970 (see White. 1970).
stultifying other considerations-in this case. countervailing ontological
and epistemological views.
Not until the early 197Os, when a major shift in orientation occurred
within developmental psychology, did Peppers analysis seem relevant.
It was then that Reese and Overton (1970; Overton & Reese, 1973),
among others (see, e.g., Lerner. 1976), adopted Peppers distinctions
between the mechanistic and organismic world views as a basis for
understanding the tensions produced by the shift from a learning-theory-
based child psychology to a cognitive-developmental one. These tensions
concerned the criteria for evaluating meaningful research questions, ap-
propriate research strategies, acceptable explanations for empirical findings.
and adequate theories of development in general.
The exemplars of the mechanistic and organismic world views offered
by Reese and Overton at that time were, respectively, Bijou and Baers
behavior analysis ofchild development (see Baer. 1970. 1973. 1976: Bijou.
1976; Bijou & Baer. 1961, 1965, 1978) and Piagets cognitive-developmental
psychology (see Piaget, 1952, 197 1, 1983: see also Lerner & Kauffman.
1985). Although Reese and Overton presented mechanism and organicism
with impartiality, the profession of developmental psychology since then
has generally championed organicism and dismissed mechanism. Indeed,
mechanism has acquired such pejorative connotations that to be cast as
a mechanist can be among the gravest of aspersions.

What it means to be mechanistic ib, of course. subject to many interpretations (see


Zuriff, 1985. pp. 186-192). Indeed. on the positive side. to be mechanistic is. in one sense.
only to be scientific-that is. to assume that the sub.ject matter of psychology i$ lawful:
Man is not made into a machine by analyzing his behavior in mechanical term\.
Man is a machine in the sense that he is a complex \yhtem hehaving in lawful way\
(Skinner. 1971. p. 102). That sort of mcchani\m ha\ heen and bill continue to be highly
productive. In biology. for instance. the triumph of mechanism over vitalism \*a\ clcxly
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 291

But mechanism and organicism were only two of Peppers world views.
In the past decade, contextualism has emerged within the developmental
and life-span literatures as a third alternative (Morris, 1986), promoted
initially as a form of dialectics (Riegel, 1975, 1976a, 1976b) and more
recently (a) as an integration of contextualism with either dialectics (Lemer,
Skinner, & Sorell, 1980) or organicism (Lerner & Kauffman, 1985), (b)
as an integration of mechanism and organicism (Lerner, Hultsch, &
Dixon, 1983), or (c) simply as contextualism per se (Blank, 1986; Dixon,
1986); it has an affinity, as well, to developmental systems theory (e.g.,
Sameroff, 1983). Psychology, more generally, has also begun resonating
to these and similar views, as evinced by Rosnow and Georgoudis (1986)
recent Contextualism and Understanding in Behavioral Science (Morris,
1988b; Taylor, 1988), where the approach has been related, as well, to
transactionalism, constructionism/constructivism, and perspectivism. In
none of these cases, however, should contextualism be taken as a dominant
view or as not having raised criticism (see, e.g., Kendler, 1986), for the
other world views still largely characterize contemporary psychology.
Contextualism, though, is an exciting new alternative as psychology in
all its pluralism continues to evolve as a science.
Throughout all of this, behaviorism in general, and S-R learning theory
in particular, has been cast (and castigated) by organicists and contextualists
as being mechanistic and, as such, for adhering to a world view inherently
incapable of representing human development in any adequate fashion
(e.g., Lerner, 1976; Sameroff & Cavanagh, 1979). Such criticisms are
both right and wrong. They are wrong in the sense that Pepper presented
each world view as relatively adequate and autonomous within its own
metatheoretical framework, meaning also that cross-view criticisms are
misplaced in that they contribute nothing to the intellectual validity of
the alternative programs (Pepper, 1942, pp. 98-99). Those criticisms,
though, do contribute political and emotive validity to their own programs
through rhetorical style (cf. Czubaroff, 1988), which serves to remind

a major positive advance in the scientific (i.e.. mechanistic) development of that domain
of inquiry. Interestingly, though, as the self-actional. vitalist views (the first stage of
scientific evolution) once gave way to the mechanistic views (the second stage of scientific
evolution), so too has mechanism now given way to contextualistic, field-theoretic views
in biology (the third stage of scientific evolution) (see Weiss, 1969; cf. Dewey & Bentley,
1949; Kantor, 1946; Pronko & Herman, 1982). In a like manner, physics had earlier moved
from classical mechanics to the relativity of a contextualistic, integrated-field perspective
(Einstein & Infeld, 1961). So too might we hope that psychology will evolve from its
versions of vitalistic (i.e.. self-actional, sometimes organismic) and mechanistic world views
toward a contextualistic, integrated-field perspective (cf. Dewey & Bentley, 1949; Kantor,
1946; Pronko & Herman, 1982). If so, then perhaps Peppers world views are not as
individually adequate and autonomous as originally construed. Perhaps they are stages in
the evolution of science toward an increasingly successful working with the subject matter-
clearly a topic for another paper.
292 EDWARD K. MORRIS

us that science is as fallible as the behavior of scientists and as fallible


as the culture in which the science is embedded-an important pragmatic
concern (e.g., with respect to funding, see Kaufman. 1970) and a not
uncontextualistic perspective. In another sense, however, the criticisms
are right by their respective internal standards. and they are devastating
in their characterization of the inadequacies of the S-R tradition on that
basis, albeit sometimes mean-spirited in tone.
But a problem exists in all of this: The behavior theory being criticized
bears little resemblance to the actual behavior-analytic view of child
development (Bijou, 1979, in press). Some distinctions between the two
behavioral traditions have been made of course, but they have largely
focused on relatively nonmetatheoretical issues pertaining to matters of
terminology and definition, research design, theory construction (e.g..
inductive vs deductive), and clinical and educational applications (see.
e.g., Cairns, 1983; Stevenson, 1983; White, 1970). Fundamental meta-
theoretical differences have been largely overlooked or misunderstood
(but see Reese, 1982, 1986).
Reciting litanies of how behavior analysis differs from the S-R learning
theory tradition (or from its typical caricaturizations) typically evokes
in-unison concurrence within the behavior-analytic community and serves,
as well, internally important clarifying and motivational functions (see,
e.g., Bijou, 1979; Horowitz, 1975; Todd & Morris, 1983). Such recitations,
though, too infrequently make a substantive enough contribution toward
explicating and expanding the behavior-analytic program, especially as
that program contrasts with alternative views. The present paper thus
seeks a more ecumenical and constructive spirit: Its thesis is that behavior
analysis is contextualistic in world view, a thesis that is developed in
three ways.
First, a discussion of the contextualism within behavior analysis seems
appropriately begun with some historical background, because contex-
tualisms root metaphor is the historic event. Broadly speaking, this
metaphor directs us to the continually evolving character of behavior,
as well as of the field of behavior analysis: Each interaction is the unique
product of past activity in current context, as well as being. the historical
context for the next interaction. For present purposes, what it means
for behavior analysis to be contextualistic can, in part, be understood
in terms of its historical development, which is presented in the first
section of this paper-however, not in the manner of the received view,
but in a revised account. In the next section, the thesis is developed
further and more specifically by comparing and contrasting contextualism
with mechanism, and analyzing both with respect to their consequences
for five core developmental issues: (a) elementarism versus holism, (b)
development as response-based change versus structural change, (cl causal
versus functional analysis, (d) continuity versus discontinuity, and (e)
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 293

the passive versus active nature of development and related issues in


agent-action locutions and in the trait-situationism controversy. Finally,
an overview is offered on what is meant by context and the role it
serves in behavior analysis-for context is what gives behavior its meaning.
Establishing this thesis in full unfortunately requires more time, space,
and intellectual acumen than are presently mine, but the following analysis
may offer at least the patina of the rich quality and deep texture of this
material. Moreover, I will not assert the contextual nature of behavior
analysis dogmatically because, although 1 am strongly inclined to that
position, who could judge the truth of it? The truth will eventually be
rendered pragmatically as a matter of successful working among sci-
entists interacting with the psychological subject matter-at least that is
the contextual construal of this dilemma. Such an assertion would also
raise difficulties because neither contextualism nor behavior analysis is
any one thing. As described earlier, contextualism has been instantiated
in a variety of forms and combinations, not all of them compatible on
all categorical fronts-for instance, as to whether or not contextualisms
organism possesses agency and intentionality. or whether or not con-
textualism embraces teleological causation (see Rosnow & Georgoudi.
1986, for inconsistencies in these regards). Also, by certain definitions
and under certain circumstances, behavior analysis evinces a mechanistic
character (Bijou, in press: Crabb, 1988: Hayes. Hayes, & Reese, 1988),
albeit a mechanism that is largely derivative, and not categorical. In any
event, I probably go beyond the established philosophical and conceptual
facts about contextualism and behavior analysis, and 1 admit that,
but so too have the advocates of contrary views, and they have been
doing so for many scores of years.

SOME HISTORICAL ROOTS


The Received View
In the standard account of the history of psychology, behaviorism and
mechanism are taken to be aligned together through the legacy of De-
mocrituss atomism, the material and reflex side of Cartesian dualism,
Lockes espousal of an epistemological tabuln YNSCI,and on down through
the empiricist and associationist movements in philosophy, from Hume
and Berkeley, through the Mills, both father and son. Then, with the
founding of the first systems of psychology, Wundts and Titcheners
structuralism became the thesis for the antithesis of Jamess and Angells
functionalism, from which Watsons (1913, 19301 classical behaviorism
emerged, in part, as synthesis. This synthesis, accompanied by its phil-
osophical legacies of elementarism, reductionism, environmentalism, and
associationism, sought scientific credibility, first, through an admixture
of Comtes positivism and Loebs operationism, and then later and more
294 EDWARD K. MORRIS

formally through logical positivism. B. F. Skinners descriptive behaviorism


of the 1930s-the neobehaviorism out of which the behavior analysis of
child development evolved (e.g., Bijou. 1955)-is said to have inherited
these central traits, with mechanism being cardinal.
This rendering of the history of psychology and of behavioristics
more specifically, is largely in the tradition of E. G. Borings (1950) T/ICJ
History of Exprrimentd Psycho1og.v (see also Boring, 1964). However,
although this account remains widely accepted, recent scholarship has
questioned the narrowness and accuracy with which the lines of psy-
chologys descent have been drawn, including the relative emphases
placed on, and the inclusions of. particular individuals. schools. and
systems (see e.g., Buxton, 1985; ODonnell, 1985: Smith, 1986). Emerging
from this material is a revised account of the history of behavior analysis,
within which its contextualistic roots may be gleaned.

Nat~rralism crnd mutc~rirrlistn. A more accurate history of behavior


analysis would trace its origins back to the naturalism of Hellenic Greek
philosophy, particularly as espoused by Aristotle, the importance of
which was lost in later theologically based reinterpretations of that material
(Kantor, 1963). The subsequent rekindling of naturalistic attitudes toward
human behavior during the Renaissance and the soon-to-come Scientific
Revolution were strongly influenced by these and later theological views,
especially those of Rene Descartes. who established separate paths for
the psychology that followed-one path interested in the immaterial soul-
cum-mind and the other interested in the material body. Neither path,
though, characterizes contemporary behavior analysis, for it is neither
mentalistic nor materially reductionistic, especially as the latter has been
construed mechanistically within S-R psychology (Reese, 1986: Ringen,
1976). In contrast. behavior analysis is focally concerned with the field
of purpose and intention (Day. 1976a), conceptualized in its own fashion-
also a major concern within contextualism.
Empiricism and assoLirrtiollisn1. The role of British empiricism and
associationism in the history of behavior analysis requires revision as
well. With respect to empiricism, John Lockes epistemological tuhrrlrr
rum never negated organismic structure and function as sources of in-
dividual differences, within or across children. nor did it negate the
private or inaccessible aspects of what we speak of as feeling, thinking,
or consciousness. Likewise, neither does behavior analysis. Biology, for
instance, is taken to participate in all psychological activity-it serves
as an ever-evolving context that is necessary though not sufficient for
behavioral development (see Delprato. 1979; Kantor, 1947: cf. Lehrman,
1953; Lewontin, 1976; Schneirla. 1966). Behavior analysis also self-
consciously acknowledges psychological privacy (Schnaitter. 197X). as
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 295

well as psychological activity within the skin, accepting the latter as a


proper though difficult domain for analysis (Skinner, 1945, 1974). Moreover,
biology, privacy, and all behavioral relations are taken as the historical
context for subsequent behavior, which brings some sense of an evolving
rationalism to the behavior-analytic account of child development in what
is otherwise viewed as a strictly empiricist endeavor.
Behavior analysis is also not philosophically or psychologically as-
sociationistic (Branch, 1977). Associationism represents a reductionistic
and, in one sense, a molecular view in which fundamental and universal
atomic elements of the mind-now. formally instantiated as stimuli and
responses-are taken as things that exist in nature. Multiplied out
through contiguity in time and succession, the S-S and S-R associations
are then said to produce and explain complex behavior. In contrast,
behavior analysis adheres to a molar perspective in which elementary
stimulus and response units do not exist on an a priori basis, the biological
reflexes notwithstanding. Rather, behavior is characterized in terms of
evolving, codefining classes of stimulus and response functions in context-
said interrelationships being the structure of behavior (see Bernstein,
1982; Thompson & Zeiler. 1986). In this latter view, the extension of
behavioral structure in space or in time is irrelevant to its molarity. That
is, the physical size of the members of the functionally interrelated stimulus
and response classes is not a defining characteristic of behavioral structure-
behavior ranges from salivation to grdnd insaturation. Also, behavior
analysis does not restrict the functional relationships between classes of
stimuli and responses to temporal contiguity, but rather enriches them
by accepting relationships that exist at a temporal distance. but without
the physiological or mental aether needed in mechanism to link them
in contiguity (Marr, 1983). In sum, only at the molar level does behavior
take on meaning (see Day, 1980; Krechevesky, 1939: Verplanck, 1954,
on the gestalt-like nature of behavior analysis).
Structuralisrn und f~tnctionulisrn. With respect to the first schools and
systems of psychology, behavior analysis is properly aligned with func-
tionalism (cf. Dewey, 1896; James, 1890; Mead. 1934), especially in its
emphasis on the utility and adaptiveness of mind and consciousness-
now, behavior. This does not mean, though, that behavior analysis views
structural concerns with antipathy (see, e.g., Catania, 1972). for at issue
is not the correctness of structural versus functional analyses, but rather
the nature of the questions asked and the use to which the answers are
put. That the province of structural analysis is generally within the purview
of cognitive psychology, and that of functional analysis within the purview
of behavioral psychology, has unfortunately resulted in the respective
correlation of structural and functional concerns with the disputatious
dualism of cognition and behavior, thereby pitting structural and functional
analyses against one another in a dogma eat dogma world. As in biology,
296 FDWAKD I(. MORRIS

structural and functional analyses should not stand in opposition or conflict:


They are a false dichotomy whose concerns are orthogonal to the cognitive-
behavioral dichotomy, a false dichotomy itself within contextualism.
The issues involved here are, of course, vastly more complex than
just characterized. For instance, within contextualism, differences between
structural and functional concerns are actually matters of the observers
temporal perspective and the duration of events. for behavior is never
static, but always active. Nonetheless, disentangling the two analytic
dimensions from cognitive psychology and behavior analysis illustrates
that even when cognitive and behavioral developmentalists may be dif-
ferentiated by their respective concerns over structure and function,
those concerns are nondefining of the two orientations and are amenable
to analysis from either perspective (Catania, 1973, 1978).
Behavioral biology. As the material to this point suggests, little of what
has been taken to be the history of behavior analysis is exactly so. Indeed,
contemporary behavior analysis actually owes less to the history of psy-
chological science than to developments in biology, especially as they
evolved from the work of Charles Darwin (1859, 1871, 1872) (Boakes,
1984; Herrnstein, 1969). This heritage yields today a behavior analysis
that adheres (a) to continuity across species in biology and behavior,
without denying the possibility of principles unique to humans (Skinner,
1938, p. 424; see Hayes, 1987): (b) to parsimony in seeking an account
of behavior at the level of behavioral systems in context. avoiding the
tendency to explain by naming (Ryle, 1949); (c) to research practices
derived from Claude Bernards (1949) work in experimental medicine,
not from the social sciences (see Thompson, 1984); (d) to a view of
behavioral adaptation in terms of selection by consequences in a
manner analogous to natural selection (Skinner, 1981); and (e) to phil-
osophical pragmatism, which is elaborated below.
Positivism, operationism, and pragmatism. Under the influence of the
Vienna Circle (Carnap, 1935; Popper, 19591, positivism and operationism
of the sorts promoted earlier by August Comte and Jacques Loeb became
an institutional characteristic of psychology during the 1930s (see, e.g.,
Stevens, 1939). The message seemed clear at the time: If psychology
were to be a real science, it would have to develop objective definitions
for its subjective terms, and exclude that which was not logically or
linguistically definable from its subject matter. The methodological be-
haviorism that grew out of these views, though, had several deleterious
effects on psychology (Moore, 1980, 1981, 1985). First, although ostensively
objective, the movement did not satisfactorily resolve the mind-body
problem because the mind was still presumed to exist, albeit outside the
realm of scientific psychology, thereby restricting the domain of the
psychology to be explained (Moore, 1981; Skinner, 1974). Second, op-
erational definitions and positivistic philosophy became so narrow that
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 297

terms lost their ordinary-language meaning, thereby restricting the character


of the behavior that could be understood to an arid truth-by-agreement
(Deitz & Arrington, 1984; Skinner, 1945). And third, too much of the
movement ignored the involvement of the scientist in science, thereby
restricting the proper account of science as the behavior of scientists
and the products thereof (Skinner, 1956, 1957, pp. 418-431; Smith, 1986).
These are matters of epistemology that cannot be glossed over with the
veneer of objectivism (Day, 1983).
Much of psychology has continued in the mold of this operationism
and positivism, but not without protest, most commonly from pheno-
menologists, Gestalt psychologists, psychoanalysts, humanists, and now
hermeneuticists. Contrary to the received view, however, contemporary
behavior analysis is also critical of such scientism. Specifically, behavior
analysis adheres to a psychological, not a logical epistemology (Smith,
1986, pp. 259-297), with a line of descent from the inductive positivism
of Francis Bacon (1889; see Smith, 1986, pp. 259-297) and Ernst Mach
(1960; see Day, 1980; Mart-, 1985; Skinner, 1945; Smith, 1986) and from
analytic philosophies reflected in Ludwig Wittgensteins (1953, 1958) later
work (Arrington & Deitz, 1986; Day, 1969a; Deitz & Arrington. 1984;
Morris, 1985a). In these views, the problem is not how to make subjective
terms objective by a priori logical definitions and operational, linguistic
conventions, for the subjective-objective distinction is a false one. Rather,
the problem is how to discover and describe the historical and current
context in which subjective terms are spoken, because context is what
gives those terms their meaning (see Day. 1976b: Malcolm,, 1977; Skinner,
1945, 1957). Behavior analysis never ruled out the subjective and private
as a subject matter; rather. it accepts such activity as behavior in context.
This epistemology, then, has a phenomenological, even hermeneutical,
quality to it that belies the mechanistic distinction between the knower
and the known (Day. 1969a. 1969b. 1977, 1988; see Giorgi, 1975; Kvale
& Grenness, 1967).
What this analysis begs, of course, is a truth criterion. That, though,
is found in pragmatism. Not only did William James establish functional
psychology, but he was also central, along with Charles S. Peirce, in
developing pragmatism both as a philosophy and as a method for defining
truth and value (James, 1907; Peirce, 1923, 1940). In the hands of James
and Peirce, as well as of John Dewey (1896) and G. H. Mead (1934),
and as influenced by the biological concept of adaptiveness, pragmatism
takes knowledge to be relative, with absolute truth a categorical impos-
sibility. Simply put, knowing refers to behavioral relations, and be-
havioral relations are a function of their historical and current context.

As Ira Gershwin might have lyricized. had he known more about the philosophy of
science, You say Popper and I say Pepper.
29x EDWARD K. MORRIS

Knowing the truth can never step outside of itself (i.e., outside the
stream of behavior) for some absolute evaluation because that evaluation,
too, is a behavioral relation in context. and so forth. Under this pragmatic
philosophy, the criterion for knowledge and truth is successful working.
which again reflects a psychological. not a logical or linguistic. epis-
temology. Within behavioranalysis, this criterion is spoken ofas effective
action, whether in basic or applied research or in conceptual analysis
(see Day. 1980, pp. 134-237, 1983: Hayes & Brownstein, 1986; Lamal.
1983: Skinner. 1974, p. ?I: Zuriff. 1980. 1985. pp. 257-%I).

Although this revised account of the history of behavior analysis is


insufficiently developed, the lines of descent show a decided contextual
lineage, much different from the mechanistic heritage that is commonly
presumed-if the account has not been overly presentist. As for
contextualism itself. it was literally born of the pragmatism of Peirce,
James, Dewey, and Mead. Indeed, contextualism may be said to be the
modern instantiation of philosophical pragmatism. These lines of descent,
though, are more hints and suggestions than direct argument that behavior
analysis is contextualistic in world view. For the latter. let me turn to
the next section of the paper in which the typical rendering of Peppers
view of mechanism is contrasted with the contextualism of behavior
analysis, especially with respect to the consequences these two views
have for several core developmental issues.
MECHANISM AND CONTEXTUALISM
According to the mechanistic world view, as presented in the devel-
opmental literature (see, e.g., Overton & Reese, 1973; Reese & Overton,
1970). behavior and environment are reduced, respectively, to responses
and stimuli, both existing as primary, universal, unchanging, discrete
elements out of which the whole of development in all its complexities
and qualities is built. As for causation, the elements are said to act on

Although successful working is contextualisms pragmatic theory of truth. to adopt


the behavior-analytic effective action version of this truth criterion-as in, for instance,
effective prediction and control-is not necessarily to adopt contextualism as a world
view. Successful working and effective action are not precisely interchangeable (Reese,
1984). though both are still beyond the arid truth-by-agreement.
For more thorough treatments. see Kantors (1963. 1969) two-volume. The Scirntific
Er~lution ofPsvcho/o,q~, which presents a historical treatment of the development of a
natural science of psychology; Days (1980) chapter. The Historical Antecedents of Con-
temporary Behaviorism. which covers the philosophical lineage of radical behaviorism
more specifically: and Smiths (1986) Behaviorism md Logicd Positi~ismt A RCLISS~.SS~IC~I~
c?fthe ANiuncr. which clarifies the psychological. as opposed to logical. epistemology of
the neobehaviorists-Tolman. Hull. and Skinner. For other treatments of the history of
behaviorism, see Boakes t IY84) and ODonnell (1985).
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 299

one another as do physical forces, the results of which are chain-like


connections between, or sequences of, stimuli and responses. Causation
flows from stimulus to response in a manner that is immediate, contiguous,
and efficient. The truth criterion of these causal mechanisms is corre-
spondence: Given that knowledge in mechanism is knowledge about the
nature of a realist ontology, the truth of that knowledge is found in the
correspondences across domains of the activity of the machine or in
predictions between what is said about the machine (e.g., hypotheses)
and how the machine operates (e.g., confirmations). Finally, according
to the mechanistic view, the developing organism and its responses are
characterized as being passive and inherently at rest. They are being-
not at all becoming. Mechanisms locutions are nominal and thing-
based.
As for the world view of contextualism, it will be introduced more
inductively and elaborated on more fully in the material to follow. For
present purposes, however, a brief description will suffice. In contextualism,
behavior occurs in context and must be studied as such, for context
gives behavior its meaning (i.e., its function)-the whole is primary, the
elements are derived as abstractions or constructs. The meaning of behavior
emerges from the ever-evolving historic context (i.e., through historical
causation) and is instantiated in the current context, as the present becomes
past for subsequent behavior-hence the root metaphor of the historic
event for the ongoing act-in-context. In the historic event, change is
categorically given, thereby making the ontology of the psychological
present both active and evolving, and obliging epistemology to be forever
relative. Because knowledge about the world is never final, but rather
inductive, inferential, and conceptual, the criterion for truth is the ever-
pragmatic successful working. Finally, behavior is characterized as
active and inherently developmental (evolutional) in nature. It is never
being, but always becoming. Contextualisms locutions are verb-
based and active.
With mechanism and contextualism now sketched, some of their con-
sequences for core issues in developmental psychology are compared
and contrasted, thereby illustrating further the contextual nature of con-
temporary behavior analysis. Before beginning, however, let me offer
one caveat: The main thesis of this paper-that behavior analysis is
contextual in world view-does not yet find broad, explicit acknowledgment
within the field of behavior analysis, even in the most informed of pres-
entations (e.g., Branch, 1987; Michael, 1985; E. P. Reese, 1986), but
neither is the thesis novel (see, e.g., Hayes, 1986, 1988; Hayes, Hayes,
& Reese, 1988: Morris, 1982; H. W. Reese. 1982. 1986). In general,
though, the perspectives and arguments used in making the present case
may be implicitly found in, and are supported by. the mainstream behavior-
analytic literature. To be specific, not only does this material characterize
300 EDWARD K. MORRIS

radical behaviorism as a philosophy of the science of behavior (Skinner,


1945, 1953, 1957, 1969, 1971, 1974), but it is also clearly pronounced in
the integrated-field nature of interbehavioral psychology (Kantor, 1950.
1959, 1971, 1981, 1984; Smith, Mountjoy, & Ruben, 1983) (see Morris.
1982, 1984; Morris, Higgins, & Bickel. 1982, 1983; contra Parrott, 1983).
Indeed, a blend of the radical behavioral and interbehavioral perspectives
seems exactly what Bijou and Baer sought to achieve in their behavior
analysis of child development, especially in its later forms (Bijou, in
press; Bijou & Baer, 1978).
Enough background and academic fastidiousness. Let me turn to the
consequences of mechanism and contextualism for five core issues in
developmental psychology (see also Morris, 1988a). the first of which is
elementarism versus holism.

Elementarism versus Holism


Mechanistic theories of development are said to adhere to elementarism,
as opposed to holism, and to represent children and their environments
as but collections of materially fundamental, atomic response and stimulus
elements. Complex action is then but an associative compounding of the
basic elements and their interrelations, in which identical response elements
and identical stimulus elements are taken, respectively, to have identical
meanings or functions-such is the character of a machine. In both cases,
the whole can always be reconstituted in terms of its parts because the
parts are unchanging.
But this is not the behavior-analytic view-for at least two reasons.
First, behavior is the unit of analysis, not the spatiotemporally defined
response or muscle twitch (Skinner, 1931, 1935; see Thompson &
Zeiler, 1986). A response per se is a physiological and anatomical entity.
such that the analysis of behavior in terms of responses alone would be
elementaristic at best and reductionistic at worst-superficial in either
case. In contrast, behavior is a dynamic, synergistic, and active inter-
relation, not a thing, in which a response is but one component. The
unit of behavior includes not only responses, but more importantly the
functions of those responses, along with their interrelated stimulus functions
in current and historical context (see Bijou, in press; Skinner, 1935, 1938:
Kantor, 1959). The behavior-analytic view, then, is holistic in that neither
responses nor stimuli have psychological meaning, function, or significance
in themselves, but only in their interdependent relationships with one
another and their context, through which they are codefining features of
behavior. Behavior analysis knows no fundamental, atomic stimulus or
response elements definable a priori or out of context. The stream of
behavior and its lines of fracture are fluid and ever-changing.

In Skinners words, As it stands. Im not sure that response is a very useful concept.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 301

The second reason why the mechanistic depiction of development is


not the behavior-analytic view pertains to the form-function distinction
and their interrelationships. Given that responses and stimuli have no
psychologically inherent meaning or function, then physically identical
responses and stimuli need not have the same meaning or function across
or within individuals (Baer, 1982). Indeed, they can never have precisely
the same meaning given that the contexts of each individuals history,
and hence the function of the present circumstances, are unique and
ever-changing. Relatedly, physically dissimilar responses and physically
dissimilar stimuli can have respectively similar meanings or functions
(i.e., be members of the same stimulus and response class). Thus, individual
differences in form-function relationships are ubiquitous across a lifetime,
and the process-achievement, means-end relation between them is a
highly dynamic one (cf. Kantor, 1933).
In sum, inherent in this contextual characterization of behavior analysis
is a holistic quality in which neither responses nor stimuli have meaning
unto themselves. Rather, meaning is an emergent property of their in-
terrelationship within their historical and current contexts. all of which
constitutes a dynamic unit of analysis.

Development us Response-Based Change versus Structural Change


A second consequence of the mechanistic and contextualistic world
views pertains directly to what it is that develops. From the mechanistic
perspective, development comprises changes in responding across chron-
ological age. It represents a continuous, linear succession of cause and
effect, wherein changes in responding are reducible to, and exactly pre-
dictable from, their prior immutable forms. In contrast, the contextual
character of behavior analysis focuses on development as the ongoing
evolution of interrelationships among stimulus and response functions in
context-the interactions being mutual and reciprocal, and constitutive
of behaviors structure. In this sense, development refers to broad gen-
eralized changes in the organization or structure of the behavioral relations
(i.e., changes in acts, not in mere responses, see Lee, 1987).
This approach to structure has been characterized as a behavioral
system (Delprato, 1986; Ray & Delprato, in press) or integrated field of
factors (Kantor, 1959)-a view that is receiving increased conceptual and
empirical attention (see, e.g., Bernstein & Brady. 1986; Lubinski &
Thompson, 1986; Sidman, 1986a, 1986b; Wahler & Fox, 1982). From
this perspective, the analysis of behavior is an analysis of its sequential
patterning across time (sequential analyses) and/or among its concurrently

Behavior is very fluid; it isnt made up of lots of little responses packed together. I hope
I will live to see a formulation which takes this fluidity into account (Evans. 1968. pp.
20-21).
302 EDWARD K. MORRIS

interrelated stimulus and response functions in context (concurrent anal-


yses). Such analyses thereby largely require multiple-response research
methodologies not only for relations among Ss and Rs, but also for
relations among Ss and Ss, and Rs and Rs-no matter what the level,
from dispositional analyses of personality (Lubinski & Thompson, 1986),
to psychopathological symptomology (Kazdin, 1982). to sequential de-
pendences in clinically significant behavior (Reid. Patterson, & Loeber.
1982), to response substitutions, both normal (Bernstein & Ebbesen.
1978) and deviant (Wahler & Fox, 1982), and to the distribution and
organization of operant behavior in laboratory contexts (see, e.g.. Collier,
1982; Henton & Iversen, 1978; Rachlin, 1982).
As an important aside, the mutualism among the relations within
the behavioral structure not only stresses that development refers to
changes in response functions, but also to changes in stimulus functions.
It is a psychological fallacy to conceive of the environment as if it were
an extant physical thing to which children must somehow accommodate
their responses throughout their lifetimes. In contrast, in the behavior-
analytic view, the behavioral (psychological) environment develops in
mutual, reciprocal interaction with the behavioral (psychological) organ-
ism-there is no parsing of development into child and environment as
separable causes, or into the mental and the environmental. Not only
does contextualism go beyond dualistic accounts of development in which
the environment is represented in the mind, but it also goes beyond
environmentalistic accounts in which a realist physical environment is
taken to be external to behavior (see also. Gibson, 1979). Instead, the
stimulus function of the environment is part of, or internal to, the unit
of behavior. In contextualism, child and environment. and stimulus function
and response function, evolve, develop. and stand in a largely systematic.
that is, a structural, interrelationship with one another (Dewey. 1976;
Waddington, 1975; see Pronko & Herman, 1982).
Unfortunately, the term structure suggests that behavior has a static,
thing-ness quality to it, whereas the contextual implications of behavior
analysis are quite the opposite, so let me comment further. The behavioral
system is a fluid, ongoing, living system. As such. the structure of be-
havior-that is, the interrelated stimulus and response functions in con-
text-has not only evolved to the point of the psychological present, but
it continues to evolve as present becomes past for more present. Through
this, the historical context is altered for the next interaction. and so
forth. Put differently, the behavioral structure adapts by assimilating and
accommodating changes in stimulus and response functions, the dynamics
of which are organized according to the basic behavioral processes or
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 303

principles which keep the system from becoming dispersive. This is an


active, organized system, one in which development is not derived, but
in which development is categorically given (see Delprato, 1980). Indeed,
both contextualism and behavior analysis are inherently developmental
in this sense.

Causal versus F~rnctioncrl Antriysis


In mechanism, the scientific task is an analytic account of behavior
in terms of antecedent-consequent, if-then relations, that is, in terms
of contingent and contiguous cause-and-effect between independent and
dependent variables (see Russell, 1953). As a conceptual and experimental
tactic, such parsing is central to the methods of contemporary psychological
science, just as the parsing of behavior into the three-term contingency
(i.e., discriminative stimuli, operant responses, and reinforcing stimuli,
that is, SD+R+SR) has become central to behavior-analytic practices
(e.g., control of the developmental process, cf. Baer, 1973).
Contextualistically, however, the analysis of behavior proceeds dif-
ferently. As suggested in the previous section, it focuses first on the
general function of behavior as adaptation, and second on the general
structure of behavior as the systematic interrelation of stimulus and
response functions in context. Within this perspective, the typical notion
of efficient cause-and-effect relationships between dependent and inde-
pendent variables, or between antecedents and consequents, gives way
to an integrated-field perspective of functional interdependencies. In the
latter, cause loses any essential meaning when causation becomes the
entire field of currently interdependent factors necessary for understanding
behavior (cf. Einstein & Infeld, 1961).
This contextual view comports well with the approach Skinner (1931,
193.5) took in his early analysis of the generic nature of stimuli and
responses, in which he emphasized the organization of codefining and
interrelated stimulus and response classes, not their temporally antecedent
and consequent relations. When viewed in terms of classes of events,
stimulus and response functions stand in direct interrelationship with one
another, a view that contrasts with conceptualizations of the unit of
behavior as a temporal ordering of independent and dependent variables,
which is how they appear from the standpoint of observers, but not from
the standpoint of the events themselves (i.e., their codefining functional
relationships and the mutual evolution of those functions over time).
Indeed, characterizing behavior in terms of independent and dependent
variables and making the former into causes has more to do with the
behavior of scientists than with the functional interelations under study.

6 In contrast, others have sometimes sought to solve the problem of dispersion by


merging contextualism with organicism (see. e.g.. Lerner & Kaufman. 1985).
304 EDWARD K. MORRIS

Similar issues arose in behavior analysis when respondent and operant


units of analysis were abstracted out of the generic stimulus and response
classes, and with the concommitant organization of the stimulus function-
response function interrelationships along a temporal dimension (i.e., the
S-R reflex and the SD+R+SR three-term contingency) (Skinner, 1938).
In making these abstractions. behavior analysts represented the two units
in terms of antecedent-consequent, independent-dependent causal re-
lationships, foregoing the earlier view of behavior as a systematic correlation
of stimulus and response classes (or functions). The relative success of
such parsing has unfortunately led some behavior analysts to overlook
their own context theory of meaning and to be conditioned into a
more mechanistic view than their actual metatheoretical allegiances should
allow. Thus, although such causal analyses are not necessarily categorical
in behavior analysis, some tension clearly exists with respect to the
mechanistic view these units imply (Baltes & Reese, 1977; Midgley &
Morris, in press).
The preceding notwithstanding, current trends in the analysis of behavior
have a more contextualistic flavor, especially with respect to the structure
of behavior (e.g.. Bernstein, 19821, the concommitant necessity of more
systems-like research strategies (e.g.. Delprato, 1986; Henton & Iversen,
1978; Ray & Delprato, in press), and an emphasis on integration and
synthesis, as well as analysis (e.g., Thompson & Zeiler, 1986).
Continuity versus Discontinuity
With respect to the character and course of development, the mechanistic
model views development as a process of continuous, quantitative change
in responses over time, as opposed to qualitative discontinuous change
in behavior. Development, then. occurs in linear succession of cause
and effect in which changes in responding are, in principle, exactly
predictable and reproducible from prior responding and its causes. All
of this follows straightforwardly from the foregoing descriptions of the
mechanistic world view.
In contextualism, however, change is categorical-behavior is never
static. And, given that change occurs in the context of an ever-unique
historical context, then behavioral development is discontinuous in the
sense that the behavioral structure of functional relationships undergoes
qualitative reorganization with each interaction. As mentioned previously,
neither responses nor stimuli have meaning unto themselves, but only
through their interrelationships with one another and their context; the
whole is more than the sum of its material constituents. Thus, when one
the systems of functional stimulus-response interrelations changes-a
ubiquitous character of becoming-then the general character of the
entire behavioral structure changes. Such change may facilitate or inhibit
subsequent development, hence grounds again for denying the pernicious
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 305

aspects of philosophical empiricism attributed to behavior analysis. In


any event, in the sense that these changes in functional interrelations
represent a reorganization of the behavioral structure, then developmental
change is of a qualitative, novel, and discontinuous sort.
Two seemingly paradoxical consequences fall from this view. First,
the categorical position with respect to discontinuity does not deny con-
tinuity in the sense that behavior, constituted of stimulus and response
functions in context, is continuously active. That is, behavior is emergent
and its development proceeds as a continuous process. Second, adhering
to discontinuity might seemingly require that development be characterized
in terms of qualitatively discrete stages, but this is not necessarily so.
Behavior, as a historic event, evolves on a moment-to-moment basis,
reflecting a dialectical process of change and interchange within its structure
(Krapfl, 1977). These changes are indeed qualitative and novel, but typically
inappreciably revolutionary for the usual concept of developmental stages
to have significant meaning. Still, behavior may display organization on
different levels (see Thompson & Zeiler, 1986), where at some point the
concept of stages may have sufficient heuristic descriptive and predictive
value to warrant formalization. In any event, the typical stage concept
is derived from contextualisms discontinuity-it is not categorical to it.

The Passive versus the Active Organism


A fifth and final issue on which the mechanistic and contextualistic
world views converge is on the passive versus the active nature of
development. Within the mechanistic account, causation is characterized
in terms of the effects of efficient independent causes on dependent
material-material that is otherwise at rest. Stimuli and responses are
taken to be linearly sequenced as cause and effect, a view sometimes
represented in the behavior-analytic literature in terms of the responsive
organism (e.g., Baer, 1976; see Reese, 1976). This is not to say that
mechanists do not talk about bidirectional causality, but such talk is
usually about back-and-forth linear causality-from the effects of the
environment on responses to the effects of responses on the environment,
and so forth. Research on child effects on adult behavior (see, e.g., Bell
& Harper, 1977), for instance, is not inherently contextualistic; it can
be construed in mechanistic sequences of weak reciprocal interactions
as well, and usually is.
As described earlier, even though the unit of behavior in behavior
analysis is parsed into stimuli and responses, the focus is on their functional
interrelations in context. More importantly, those functional relations
stand in a strong reciprocal interaction or better-in Dewey and Bentleys
(1949, p. 108) terminology-in a transactional relation with one another;
306 EDWARD K. MORRIS

they are mutually defining and implicative. From this perspective. both
stimulus and response functions contribute to behavior, and behavior
may thus be said to be active, not passive. This view is pertinent to two
interrelated problems within psychology: The locutional problem of
speaking about behavior in agent-action terms and the problem of traits
and situations. the latter of which is a pseudo-problem within contextualism.
Both of these are discussed below.
7hr locrrtioncrl problem. To put the contextual construal of the active-
passive problem in an organism-based locution, children are said to be
the active agents of development through the unique. individual meaning
they give to their behavior, that is, to the stimulus functions they give
their environments and to the response functions they give their activities-
all through the action of the child on the environment. Development,
though, may also be put in an environment-based locution, where the
environment is said to be the active agent through the unique, individual
meaning it gives to behavior. that is, to the stimulus functions it gives
to stimuli and to the response functions it gives to child activity-all
through the action of the environment on the child. The first locution,
though, makes the environment appear passive, which it is not, while
the second locution makes children appear passive, which they are not.
Unfortunately, neither organism-based nor environment-based locutions
capture the essence of contextualism, in which stimulus and response
functions are mutually defined by their transactional relationship, for the
two locutions align too closely with the organismic and mechanistic world
views, respectively. Not only are these two locutions misleading, but,
to compound the problem, their grammatical forms seem easily acquired
and spoken in ordinary English or in Standard Average European
(Whorf, 19.56). The latter may be a consequence of the disposition of
our grammatical structure to agent-action syntax, to agent nouns (i.e.,
organisms, traits. structures, representations-and the environment) reified
from verbs, adverbs, and adjectives (actions and their qualities), and to
the priority of things and agents over action and change. In contrast,
our language offers few fluid, nonawkward, or easily understood gram-
matical structures for speaking contextuahstically; hence such talk is
difficult for speakers and writers, and often obscure to listeners and
readers (sic). English grammar and syntax simply seem mismatched with
the subject matter of psychology (Hackenberg, 1988; Hineline, 1980;
Lee, 1988; see Whorf, 1956).
The deep structure of organism-based locutions no doubt has had its
benefits for the organization of social order and moral responsibility that

For further commentary on the transactional nature of contemporary behavior analysis,


see Pronko and Hermans (1982) From Deweys Reflex Arc Concept to Transactionalism
and Beyond (see also Keehn. 1980).
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 307

emerged in the Renaissance; likewise, the deep structure of environment-


based locutions had its benefits for the subsequent conduct of naturalistic
inquiry that emerged from the Scientific Revolution. Interestingly, the
organismic and mechanistic world views largely inherent in the two lo-
cutions overlap considerably with the respective character of the first
two stages of scientific evolution- the self-actional and the mechanical
(see Dewey & Bentley, 1949; Einstein & lnfeld, 1961; Kantor. 1946;
Pronko & Herman, 1982). At this point in the history of psychology,
however, our languages lack of a deep structure for speaking contex-
tualistically may be hindering the emergence of the third stage of scientific
evolution-the intergrated-field stage-with its underlying contextualistic
world view. At the very least, the linguistic inadequacy is hindering
fruitful interchange between behavior analysts and developmental psy-
chologists, who, with their respective environment- and organism-based
locutions, seem to identify very different subject matters and causal
schemes, thereby obscuring their common interest in development.*
In any event, in arguing for the active character of behavior, the
behavior-analytic position is not that children are self-actional, autonomous
agents. Likewise, though, neither do (or should) behavior analysts assert
that the environment is an autonomous cause, the practical utility of the
latter notwithstanding (Hayes & Brownstein. 1986). The tension here
between these views of causality is at the heart of the trait-situationism
debate, in which are embedded the locutional problems described above,
as well as some of the logical characteristics and flaws with the nature-
nurture issue so closely aligned with the presumed contrast between
developmental psychology and behavior analysis.
The @air-situation& prohlenz. From a contextual perspective, stimulus
functions and response functions develop historically and exist simul-
taneously with respect to one another. and are defined in terms of each
other in context. As such, stimulus functions have no more control
over behavior than do response functions-the two are interdependently

* Verplanck (1954) has commented astutely on how differences in locution and vocabulary
have produced unfortunate misunderstandings about Skinners experimental and conceptual
analyses:

Because of the existence in Sherrington and Pavlov of sets of data of the kind
[Skinner] believes are needed [for his system], he has adopted many of their terms
and applied some of their laws in defining behavior. As a consequence, he has
been misinterpreted. In his choice of terminology, Skinner has assured that his
work and those of his followers will be read easily by the followers of Hull and
Guthrie and only with emotion, if not with difficulty. by those who have selected
the organismic-field-Gestalt-force family of words to work with. Skinners conditioned
responses seem to many readers just as ,nere as those of Pavlov or Hull, with
the extraordinary result that he has been classed with Hull rather than with
Tolman. with Guthrie rather than with Lewin. in his general position. (p. 307).
308 EDWAKD K. MORRIS

and mutually defining. A situation does not compel a response to occur


except through a childs historically derived response functions for that
situation, but neither does a child compel a response to occur except
through the situations historically derived stimulus functions for the
response. Thus, situations do not possess independent or inherent power
to control behavior any more than children possess independent or inherent
power for such control. Both are products of unique. ever-changing
interactional histories, a point commonly misunderstood in appraisals of
behavior analysis (see, e.g., Bowers, 1973).
Interactions may display qualities attributable to personal or situational
control, depending on how the interactions are viewed or investigated,
but those attributions are merely shorthand conventions derived from
an overemphasis on organismic and mechanistic thinking, as opposed to
a contextual world view. What is most objectionable here, though, is
the reification and causal status given to the child as a relatively auton-
omous, active agent, as per organicism. or to the situation as a relatively
autonomous physically stimulating force, as per mechanism. Behavior,
of course, can be predicted on the basis of information about children
or about the situations in which they find themselves, but the ability to
do so does not thereby bestow causal power on either. Attributions of
such causal powers have more to do with the behavior of scientists than
with child development. To assert that such power exists at all moves
the analysis of behavior away from the contextual account it requires in
contextualism.

Summary
To this point in the paper, a case has been developed that behavior
analysis is contextual in world view, as opposed to being mechanistic,
by examining, first, its historical development and, second, some con-
sequences of its contextualism for five key developmental issues. The
presentation of this material has been highly conceptual in nature, perhaps
even ethereal for the empirically minded child psychologist; thus. let me
focus the third and final section of this paper on a more concrete. operational
sense of context -wherein context is what gives meaning to behavior.

THE CONTEXT IN CONTEXTUALISM


Within the past decade or so, psychology has shown an increased
interest in context. This is evinced not only in psychology as a whole,
where much of this focus has been on an ecological orientation (Gibbs.
1979; Wicker, 1983). but also in its various subdisciplines, for instance.
in studies of social psychology, personality, language, and development
(see Rosnow & Georgoudi, 1986), and in specific empirical research
areas, such as memory (Jenkins. 1974: see Marr. 1983). perception (Gibson.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 309

1979; see Costall, 1983), and the psychology of learning (Balsam & Tomie,
1984; see Mandell, 1986).
In most of these domains, context usually refers to the contextual and
multiple determinants of behavior, that is, to broad, complex, and numerous
antecedent causes, and to the interplay of the various concurrent levels
at which behavior occurs (e.g., personal, social, and cultural; see Bron-
fenbrenner, 1977. 1979). Although context often provides more facade
than facts in these cases because of its lack of specificity and precision,
these moves to broaden the scope of psychology seem obviously quite
right and quite necessary.
To give contextual determinants their due, however, is not necessarily
to embrace contextualism as a world view (see Valsiner & Benigni, 1986,
for parallel problems with the ecological perspective). Such determinants
can be handled mechanistically, as well, in the sense that all causes have
contexts. Within this latter world view, any sophisticated and thoughtful
analysis of behavior would of course incorporate multiple, complex, and
interlocking mechanisms, as well as inhibitory and facilitory servome-
chanisms, as illustrated, for instance, in the S-R model of learning (Hull,
1952) and in the currently fashionable computational models of cognitive
science (see, e.g., Block, 1980, 1981; Haugland, 1981). In contrast, within
contextualism, context of a different and more specific sort is categorical:
Context imbues behavior with meaning-the meaning of behavior emerges
from its context. Behavior is not the mere interplay of materially defined
stimuli and responses, but rather is represented by strong reciprocal
interactions among stimulus and response functions in conrext-where
those functions emerge from their context and from nowhere else.
Within behavior analysis, context can be organized into the historical
and the current, each of which serves distinctive functions. The function
of the historical context-both phylogenic and ontogenic-is to establish
what stimulus and response functions may occur in behavior, whereas
the current context-its structure and its function-establishes what par-
ticular behaviors can and will occur, respectively. And, of course, all
three contexts interact to affect and change one another over a lifetime.

The Historical Context


With respect to phylogenic history, it is not only the source of (a)
species-typic boundaries and preparedness in biological structure, but is
also the source of species-typic boundaries and preparedness in behavioral
function through the inheritance of (b) the basic behavioral processes
(e.g., reinforcement and operant behavior) and (c) the initial relationships

9 As a matter of historical note, these concerns over context are hardly new, for they
were an integral part of much important psychology of an earlier era (e.g., Barker, 1968:
Brunswik, 1952; Koffka, 1935; Kohler. 1929: Titchener. 1910; Tolman, 1932).
310 EDWARD K. MORRIS

among stimulus and response functions (e.g.. unconditioned respondents


and unconditioned reinforcers)-as well as a source of variability in all
three domains. Given a phylogenic history. ontogenic history then begets
the subsequent individual-typic boundaries and preparedness in biological
and behavioral form and function, and variability in both.
With respect to behavioral form and function, in particular, the ontogenic
history has been a fundamental and explicit characteristic of behavior-
analytic research on such topics as adult-child social interaction history
(e.g., Redd, Morris, & Martin, 1975), reinforcement schedule history
(e.g., Weiner, 1981, 1983). and the integration of independently acquired
response repertoires (Epstein, Kirschnit. Lanza. & Rubin, 1984: Epstein,
Lanza, & Skinner, 1981)-all of which elucidates sources of intra- and
interindividual differences.
Overall, then, historical causation is central to behavior analysis, for
the historical context establishes the form and function of behavior as
the context for subsequent behavior (see Skinner, 1981).
The Current Context
Given that the historical context functions to establish what behavior
may occur, the particular behavior that roil/ occur and that can occur
depends, respectively, on the actualizing and enabling character of the
current context. What will occur (or be actualized) depends on the be-
havioral function of the current context; what can occur (or be enabled)
depends on the physical structure of the current context. As for the
latter, the structure of the current context exists materially as the biological
organism (i.e., the childs anatomy and physiology), the environment
(i.e., the environments physical ecology), and as changes and variability
in both, thereby enabling what behavior can (or cannot) physically occur.
In turn, the function of the current context actualizes behavior by imbuing
stimuli and responses with their dynamic and ever-evolving functions
(i.e., their meaning).
Albeit sometimes conflated with multiple causation and the structure
of the current context, the function of the current context has been an
implicit consideration within behavior analysis for many years. For instance,
concerns about the function of the current context were extant in Skinners
(1931) third variables (e.g., deprivation, fatigue, drug effects), Kantors
(1946, 1959. p. 95) setting factors, Bijou and Baers (1961. p. 17)
setting events, Goldiamonds (1962, p. 295; Goldiamond & Dryud,
1967, pp. 74-75) state and potentiating variables, and Gewirtzs
(1972) contextual determinants. The importance of such functions,
however, has recently become a more explicit concern, as evidenced
both in conceptual analyses and in basic and applied empirical research
on, for instance, setting events (Bijou & Baer, 1978, pp. 26-28; Wahler
& Dumas, in press; Wahler & Fox. 1981. 1982). establishing operations
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 311

and establishing stimuli (e.g., McPherson & Osborne, 1988; Michael,


1982), the conditional stimulus control character of the relationships
involved in stimulus equivalence (Sidman, 1986a. 1986b), and function-
altering, contingency-specifying stimuli (e.g., rules, Blakely &
Schlinger, 1987; Schlinger & Blakely, 1987). The relationships to which
these terms refer are not all identical: for instance, some terms refer to
the effects of context on the eliciting function of stimuli (both conditioned
and unconditioned), others to effects on the discriminative function, and
still others to effects on the reinforcing function (both unconditioned and
conditioned). These relationships are organized more generally here,
though, as the function of the current context, in that they all function
in one manner or another to imbue, potentiate, or actualize the functions
of stimuli and responses for behavior.

Summary
In light of the foregoing discussion, behavior analysis can be said to
adhere to a context theory of meaning-the context being both historical
and current. Context, though, has typically been controlled for within
behavior analysis, both as a source of variation due to the historical
context (e.g., species and individual history) and of variation due to the
structure (e.g., current biological and physical parameters of the organism
and experimental setting, respectively) and function of the current context
(e.g., deprivation and instructions). As a consequence, context has not
until recently been an explicit character of the behavioral unit of analysis
or a subject matter for experimental analysis in its own right. Rather, it
has been taken as a source of variation to be held constant.
This relative inattention given to context, as opposed to the contin-
gencies of reinforcement, has contributed to the appearance that behavior
analysis represents the child as but a black box, and usually an empty
one at that-both biologically and psychologically (Todd & Morris, 1983).
The current concern over context, however, begins to clarify a source
of such misunderstandings from outside the field, and to encourage from
within the field an increased scope of analysis for phenomena that behavior
analysis is said to have dismissed or overlooked-phenomena that here-
tofore have largely been the province of the rest of developmental psy-
chology and that have been explained in other conceptual systems. Among
the latter are phenomena described and explained in terms of the structure
and function of the personality (e.g., traits) or in terms of cognitive
structures (e.g., schemas and rules) and processes (e.g., expectations
and perception) (see Baron & Perone, 1982; Harzem, 1984). Contextualism
offers a fresh new perspective on these issues, a point touched on in
closing.
312 EDWARD K. MORRIS

CONCLUSION
The present characterizations of behavior analysis, of contextualism,
and of behavior analysis as contextualistic remain, of course, unfinished
and underdeveloped. Indeed, for mechanists and organicists alike, the
argument may seem merely to have translated mechanism into a con-
textualistic language without having actually presented contextualism as
an alternative view. Moreover. contextualism itself rests on a slippery
slope-it seems forever about to slide into organicism or into mechanism
(Pepper, 1942). Nonetheless, 1 trust that the foregoing analysis has elu-
cidated the contemporary behavior-analytic metatheory as being clearly
nonmechanistic in world view, at least to the point that some version
of contextualism is the only viable alternative among Peppers world
hypotheses.
The implications and import of this argument, of course. extend in
more directions than a conclusion can contend with. One specific point,
however, seems worth making-it has to do with the consequences of
the current moves of both behavior analysis and developmental psychology
toward contextualism, and of how these moves will affect the analysis
of cognition as process and as product. I raise this issue because cognition
is generally taken to be pivotal to distinctions between behavior analysis
and developmental psychology-it is said to be something behavior analysis
overlooks.
For the past 20 years, behavior analysis and developmental psychology
have largely been speaking across world views, or across cognition as
process as opposed to content, or hardly speaking at all (Morris et al.,
1982). Developmental psychologists, for instance, have often dismissed
behavior analysis for being mechanistic in world view, for being envi-
ronmentalistic, and, if you will, for being cogniphobic, that is, for being
blind to cognition as a developmental process, or at least as a behavioral
product (i.e.. behavioral content). Behavior analysts, in turn, have often
dismissed developmental psychology for being organismic in world view,
for being maturationist and mentalistic, and for being cogniphilic, that
is, for being self-absorbed in considering cognition to be the central
process and content of development.
From a contextual perspective, the fundamental conflict is largely a
matter of differences in world views-mechanism and organicism-and
only superficially a matter of cogniphobia and cogniphilia. That is, although
behavior analysis and developmental psychology have been taken to be
incommensurable because of their respective positions on environmen-
talism, on mentalism. and on cognition as process and content, the
incommensurability has actually been more a function of fundamental
paradigmatic differences between mechanism and organicism. With a
convergence of both behavior analysis and developmental psychology
toward contextualism, however. they become commensurable in world
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 313

view. And, with that, environmentalism, mentalism, and the conceptual


and empirical place of cognition in child development become cast as
concerns orthogonal to the defining characteristics of the two world
views.
In addition, cognition becomes a content domain or quality of devel-
opment to be explained, as opposed to being an underlying process that
does the explaining (Ryle, 1949; Schnaitter, 1985), because a contextual
or ordinary-language analysis of the term cognition shows it to be
behavior-in-context or behavioral content (Arrington & Deitz, 1986; Day,
1969b; Deitz & Arrington, 1984; Morris, 1985a, 1985b; Skinner, 1945;
cf. Wittgenstein, 1953, 1958; see also Costa11 & Still, 1987). That is,
cognition refers to a broad domain of development-a domain whose
existence is commonly enough contacted that a socially shared and con-
ventional language has developed for describing it. In other words, and
to use the vulgar behaviorese of an environment-based locution: To speak
(tact) the word cognition is to emit a verbal operant under the
discriminative control of the occurrence of certain behavioral relations
in their historical and current contexts-relations that, in turn, may come
under finer discriminative control so as to be tacted as further and finer
subclasses of ordinary language terms such as perceiving, remembering,
and problem-solving. In any event, and contextualistically speaking,
cognitive is an adjective, cognitively an adverb, and cognizing
a verb-all describing particular characteristics of child development.
There is no such agent, process, or thing as cognition:

Cognizing does not begin and end in ones head or at ones skin; it is not superordinate
to our relationships, for our thoughts are our relationships. Attributions, motivation,
perception, and personality-what it is to be a person-are re/trrio,lship.s. not
things going on in any one locus, whether that be a stable package of schema
or biological processes or a subjective phenomenological reality. (Blank. 1986,
pp. 121-122)

Or, as befitting the ubiquitous nature of cognition in our ordinary


language, Descartess well-known dictum-Cogito, ergo sum-is perhaps
better rendered as Sum, ergo cogito.
In closing, I am not arguing that behavior analysis and developmental
psychology will soon, or even necessarily, become one--that would be
overly optimistic. Rather, my point is that as they evolve toward the
common world view of contextualism, then neither can dismiss the other
on the basis of paradigmatic incommensurability, and hence each must
confront important issues, such as cognition, from a common and com-
mensurable perspective. Moreover, by adhering to contextualism, both
behavior analysis and developmental psychology may also become more
effective in their respective conceptual and empirical practices. And
finally, they may be able to work together successfully. along with a
314 EDWARD K. MORRIS

contextually construed anthopology/sociology (e.g., Harris, 1980), ev-


olutionary biology (e.g., Dawkins, 1986), and physiology (e.g., Gollin,
1981; Schneirla, 1966; Weiss, 1969), toward the common goal of under-
standing child development in all of its contexts. That would be a historic
event.

REFERENCES
Arrington, R. L., & Deitz, S. M. (1986). A second call. Behaviorism, 14, 103-106.
Bacon, F. (1889). Novum organum. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. (Original work published
1621)
Baer, D. M. (1970). The age-irrelevant concept of development. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly,
16, 238-245.
Baer, D. M. (1973). The control of the developmental process: Why wait? In J. R. Nesselroade
& H. W. Reese (Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology: Methodological issues
(pp. 187-193). New York: Academic Press.
Baer, D. M. (1976). The organism as host. Human Development, 19, 87-98.
Baer, D. M. (1982). The imposition of structure on behavior and the demolition of behavioral
structures. In D. Bernstein (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivafion, 1981 (Vol.
29, pp. 217-254). Lincoln: Univ. of Nebraska Press.
Balsam, P. D., & Tomie, A. (1984). Context and learning. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Baltes, M. M., & Reese, H. W. (1977). Operant research in violation of the operant
paradigm? In B. C. Etzel, J. M. LeBlanc, & D. M. Baer (Eds.), New developments
in behavioral research: Theory, method, and application. In honor of Sidney W. Bijou
(pp. 11-30). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bandura, A. (1977). Social learning theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bandura, A., JL Walters, R. H. (1963). Social learning and personality development. New
York: Holt, Rinehart, & Winston.
Barker, R. G. (1968). Ecological psychology. Stanford: Stanford Univ. Press.
Baron, A., & Perone, M. (1982). The place of the human subject in the operant laboratory.
The Behavior Analyst, 5, 143-158.
Bell, R. Q., & Harper, L. V. (Eds.). (1977). Child effects on adults. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Berlyne, D. E. (1965). Structure and direction in thinking. New York: Wiley.
Bernard, C. (1949). An introduction to the study of experimental medicine. New York:
Dover Press. (Original work published 1865)
Bernstein, D. J. (Ed.). (1982). Response structure and organization. Nebraska Symposium
on Motivation, 1981 (Vol. 29). Lincoln: Univ. of Nebraska Press.
Bernstein, D. J., & Brady, J. V. (1986). The utility of continuous programmed environments
in the experimental analysis of human behavior. In H. W. Reese & L. J. Parrott
(Eds.), Behavior science: Philosophical, methodological, and empirical advances (pp.
229-245). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bernstein, D., & Ebbesen, E. (1978). Reinforcement and substitution in humans: A multiple
response analysis. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 30, 243-253.
Bijou, S. W. (1955). A systematic approach to an experimental analysis of young children.
Child Development, 26, 161-168.
Bijou, S. W. (1976). Child development: The basic stage of early childhood. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bijou, S. W. (1979). Some clarifications of the meaning of a behavior analysis of child
development. The Psychological Record, 29, 3-13.
Bijou, S. W. (in press). Behavior analysis of human development. In H. W. Reese (Ed.).
Advances in child behavior and development. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 315

Bijou, S. W., & Baer, D. M. (l%l). Child development I: A systematic and empirical
theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bijou, S. W., & Baer, D. M. (1965). Child development II: Universal stage of infancy.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bijou, S. W., & Baer, D. M. (1978). Behavior analysis of child development. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Blakely, E., & S&linger, H. (1987). Rules: Function-altering contingency specifying stimuli.
The Behavior Analyst, 10, 183-187.
Blank, T. 0. (1986). Contextual and relational perspectives on adult psychology. In R. L.
Rosnow 8~ M. Georgoudi (Eds.), Contextualism and understanding in behavioral
science: Implications for research and theory (pp. 105-124). New York: Prager.
Block, N. (Ed.). (1980). Readings in the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 1). Cambridge:
Harvard Univ. Press.
Block, N. (Ed.). (1981). Readings in the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 2). Cambridge:
Harvard Univ. Press.
Boakes, R. (1984). From Darwin to behaviourism. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.
Boring, E. G. (1950). The history of experimental psychology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Boring, E. G. (1964). The trend toward mechanism. Proceedings of the American Philosophical
Society, 108, 451-454.
Bowers, K. S. (1973). Situationism in psychology. Psychological Review, 80, 307-336.
Branch, M. N. (1977). On the role of memory in the analysis of behavior. Journal of
the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 28, 171-179.
Branch, M. N. (1987). Behavior analysis: A conceptual and empirical base for behavior
therapy. The Behavior Therapist, 10, 79-84.
Bronfenbrenner, U. (1977). Toward an experimental ecology of human development. American
Psychologist, 32, 513-531,
Bronfenbrenner, U. (1979). The ecology of human development: Experiments by nature
and design. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.
Brunswik, E. (1952). The conceptual framework of psychology. International Encyclopedia
of UniJied Science, 1, l-102.
Buxton, C. E. (Ed.). (1985). Points of view in the modern history of psychology. Orlando,
FL: Academic Press.
Cairns, R. B. (1983). The emergence of developmental psychology. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.),
Handbook of child psychology, Vol. 4. History, theory, and methods (W. Kessen,
vol. Ed.) (pp. 41-102). New York: Wiley.
Camap, R. (1935). Philosophy and logical syntax. London: Kegan Paul.
Catania, A. C. (1972). Chomskys formal analysis of natural languages: A behavioral
translation. Behaviorism, 1, 1-15.
Catania, A. C. (1973). The psychologies of structure, function, and development. American
Psychologist, 28, 434-443.
Catania, A. C. (1978). The psychology of learning: Some lessons from the Darwinian
revolution. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 309, 18-28.
Collier, G. H. (1982). Determinants of choice. In D. Bernstein (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium
on Motivation, 1981 (Vol. 29, pp. 69-127). Lincoln: Univ. of Nebraska Press.
Costall, A. P. (1983). Are theories of perception necessary? A review of Gibsons The
ecological approach to visual perception. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of
Behavior, 41, 109-115.
Costall, A., & Still, A. (Eds.). (1987). Cognitive psychology in question. New York: St.
Martins Press.
Crabb, P. B. (1988). A contextual psychology? The curious case of behavior-analytic theory.
Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 8(2), 28-34.
316 EDWAKD K. MORRIS

Czuberoff. J. (1988). Criticism and response in the Skinner controversies. Jorrr,ltr/ (!/ ti~ca
Experimenfal At~alysis ofBe/rrr~~ior. 49, 32 I-339.
Darwin, C. (1859). On fl7e origins of specic~s hy 177~~11~7s c?f ,trr~rrr~~/ scJ/ec.fio,t.London:
Murray.
Darwin, C. ( 1871). T/jr drscer7t t!/ ~70~. London: Murray.
Darwin, C. ( 1872). The r.rprc~.ssio/~of rrnotio,l.s i,l ,?t(,,~rrt7d tr/rbncr/.v. London: Murray.
Dawkins. R. (1986). Tile blind uwtc.hmrrker. New York: Norton.
Day, W. F. (1969a). On certain similarities between the Phi/osophica/ In~~e.sti~crtions of
Ludwig Wittgenstein and the operationism of B. F. Skinner. Jorrrncll oflllr E.xperi/nc~rztcrl
Analysis of Behavior, 12, 489-506.
Day, W. F. (1969b). Radical behaviorism in reconciliation with phenomenology. Jorcn~trl
of the E?cperimental Analysis of Behavior. 12, 3 15-328.
Day, W. F. (1976a). Contemporary behaviorism and the concept of intention. In W. J.
Arnold (Ed.). Nebraska Swnposillr?z 011 Morivc7tion. (Vol. 25, pp. 65-131). Lincoln:
Univ. of Nebraska Press.
Day, W. F. (1976b). Analyzing verbal behavior under the control of private events. Be-
haviorism, 4, 195-200.
Day. W. F. (1977). On the behavior analysis of self-deception and self-development. In
T. Mischel (Ed.). The se/J Psychological and philosophical issues (pp. 224-249).
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Day, W. F. (1980). The historical antecedents of contempory behaviorism. In R. W. Rieber
& K. Salzinger (Eds.). Psycholog,v: Tl7eoreti~crl-histori~fll perspecti\,es (pp. 203-262).
New York: Academic Press.
Day, W. F. (1983). On the difference between radical and methodological behaviorism.
Behaviorism. 11, 89-102.
Day, W. F. (1988). Hermeneutics and behaviorism. American Psychologist. 43, 129.
Deitz. S. M.. & Arrington. R. L. (1984). Wittgensteins language games and the call to
cognition. Behaviorism. 12, 7- 14.
Delprato. D. J. (1979). The interbehavioral alternative to brain dogma. The Psycholo~ic~al
Record, 21, 409-418.
Delprato, D. J. (1980). The reactional biography concept: Early contribution to a perspective
for the psychology of aging. Human Development, 23, 314-322.
Delprato, D. J. (1986). Response patterns. In H. W. Reese & L. J. Parrott (Eds.), Behavior
science: Philosophical. methodological, and empirical advances (pp. 61-l 13). Hillsdale,
NJ: Erlbaum.
Dewey. J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3, 357-
370.
Dewey, J. (1976). Lectures on psychological and physical ethics. New York: Hafner.
(Original work published 1898)
Dewey, J., & Bentley, A. F. (1949). Knowing and the known. Boston: Beacon Press.
Dixon, R. A. (1986). Contextualism and life-span developmental psychology. In R. L.
Rosnow & M. Georgoudi (Eds.). Contextualism and anderstanding in behavioral
science: Implications for research and theory (pp. 125-144). New York: Praeger.
Dollard, J., & Miller, N. E. (1950). Personality and psychotherapy. New York: McGraw-
Hill.
Einstein, A., & Infeld, L. (1961). The evolation ofphysics: The growth of ideas from ear/y
concepts to re/ativity and quanta. New York: Simon and Schuster. (Original work
published 1938)
Epstein, R.. Kirschnit. C. E., Lanza, R. P.. & Rubin. L. C. (1984). Insight in the
pigeon: Antecedents and determinants of an intelligent performance. Natare (London).
308, 61-62.
Epstein, R., Lanza, R. P., & Skinner, B. F. (1981). Self-awareness in the pigeon.
Science, 212, 695-696.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 317

Evans, R. 1. (1968). B. F. Skinner: The mun and Isis ideas. New York: Dutton.
Gewirtz. J. L. (1972). Some contextual determinants of stimulus potency. In R. D. Parke
(Ed.), Recent trends in social /earning theory (pp. 7-33). New York: Academic Press.
Gibbs, J. C. (1979). The meaning of ecologically oriented inquiry in contemporary psychology.
American Psychologist. 34, 127-140.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton-
Mifflin.
Giorgi, A. (1975). Convergences and divergences between phenomenological psychology
and behaviorism: A beginning dialogue. Behariorism, 3, 200-212.
Goldiamond. 1. (1962). Perception. In A. J. Bachrach (Ed.), Experimental faandations af
clinical practice (pp. 286-340). New York: Basic Books.
Goldiamond, I.. & Dryud. J. (1967). Behavioral analysis for psychotherapy. In J. Schlien
(Ed.), Research in psychotherapy (Vol. 3. pp. 58-89). Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association.
Gollin, E. S. (Ed.). (1981). Behavioral plasticity. New York: Academic Press.
Hackenberg, T. (1988). Operationism, mechanism, and psychological reality: The second-
coming of linguistic relativity. The Psychological Record, 38, 187-201.
Harris, M. (1980). Ctrltaral materialism: The straggle jbr a science ofcaltrrre. New York:
Random House.
Harzem, P. (1984). The experimental analysis of individual differences and personality.
Journal of the Experimental Anal.vsis of Behavior, 42, 385-395.
Haugland. J. (Ed.). (1981). Mind design. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Hayes, S. C. (1986). Behavioral philosophy in the late 1980s. Theoretical and Philosophical
Psychology, 6(l), 39-43.
Hayes, S. C. (1987). Upward and downward continuity: Its time to change our strategic
assumptions. Behavior Analysis, 22,(l), 3-6.
Hayes, S. C. (1988). Contextualism and the next wave of behavioral psychology. Behuvior
Analysis, 23, 7-22.
Hayes, S. C., & Brownstein, A. J. (1986). Mentalism. behavior-behavior relations, and
a behavior-analytic view of the purposes of science. The Behavior Ana/yst. 9, 175-
190.
Hayes, S. C., Hayes, L. J., & Reese, H. W. (1988). Finding the philosophic core: A
review of Stephen C. Peppers World hypotheses. Journal of the Experimental Analysis
of Behavior, 50, 97-l I 1.
Henton. W. W, & Iversen. I. H. (1978). Classical conditioning urld operant condirioning:
A response puttern ana/ysis New York: Springer-Verlag.
Herrnstein. R. J. (1969). Behaviorism. In D. L. Krantz (Ed.). Schools of psychology: A
symposiam (pp. 5 l-67). Englewood Cliffs. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Hineline, P. N. (1980). The language of behavior analysis: Its community, its function,
and its limitations. Behaviorism. 8, 67-86.
Horowitz, F. D. (1975). Living among the ABAs: Retrospect and prospect. In E. Ramp
& G. Semb (Eds.), Behavior analysis: Areas of research und upplication (pp. 3-15).
Englewood Cliffs. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Hull, C. L. (1952). A behavior system. New York: Wiley.
James, W. (1890). Principles of psychology. New York: Holt.
James, W. (1907). Pragmatism. New York: New American Library.
Jenkins, J. J. (1974). Remember that old theory of memory? Well. forget it. American
Psychologist, 29, 785-795.
Kantor, J. R. (1933). In defense of stimulus-response psychology. Psychologicul Revierc,,
40, 324-336.
318 EDWARD K. MORRIS

Kantor. J. R. (1946). The aim and progress of psychology. Anrrric~n Scientist. 34, 25 I -
263.
Kantor, J. R. (1947). P,oh/e,?ls of ph~siologic~trl p.spc~/~o/op~.Chicago: Principia Press.
Kantor, J. R. (1950). P.s~%o/o~qy trr~d logic. (Vol. 2). Chicago: Principia Press.
Kantor. J. R. ( 1959). Interbehal~ioruI p.s&o/op~. Chicago: Principia Press.
Kantor. J. R. (1963). The sc+nt$c, ero/&~/~ c$p.~,vc~ho/o~:v(Vol. I ). Chicago: Principia
Press.
Kantor, J. R. ( 1969). The s&nr$fic, c~~~o/r&~l c!f p.s.vc&~/o~:v(Vol. 2). Chicago: Principia
Press.
Kantor. J. R. (197 I ). The trim end progress of ps~c~ho/o~~ (I& other .sc.iencc~s.Chicago:
Principia Press.
Kantor, J. R. (1981). InterbehalkruI p/~i/osophv. Chicago: Principia Press.
Kantor. J. R. ( 1984). Selecrrd t~~riti~~~.siti phi/osophy. p.s.vc~ho/og~. and other sciences.
Chicago: Principia Press.
Kaufman, A. S. (1970). The aim of scientific activity. In J. H. Gill (Ed.). Philosoplly rod(r)
(No. 3, pp. 93-l I I). New York: Macmillan Co.
Kazdin. A. E. (1982). Symptom substitution, generalization, and response co-variation:
Implications for psychotherapy outcome. Psycho/o~icu/ Bulletin. 91, 349-365.
Keehn, J. D. (1980). Beyond an interactional model of personality: Transactionalism and
the theory of reinforcement schedules. Behaviorism. 8, 55-56.
Kendler. T. S. (1986). World view and the concept of development: A reply to Lerner
and Kaufmann. Developmental Re)k~~, 6, 80-95.
Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Restrrlt psychology. New York: Harcourt. Brace.
Kohler. W. (1929). Gesrrrlr p.sycholog.v. London: Liveright.
Krapfl. J. E. (1977). Dialectics and operant conditioning. In N. Datan & H. W. Reese
(Eds.). Life-span developmental psychology: Diulectical perspectitses on experimental
research (pp. 295-310). Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
Krechevsky, I. (1939). [Review of The behu\Gr of orgunisms.] Journal of Abnormul und
Social Psychology, 34, 404-407.
Kvale. S.. & Grenness, C. (1967). Skinner and Sartre. Re\+e\ls of Existential Psycholog)
und Psychiatq, 7, 128-149.
Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientijc reseurch progrummes. In I. Lakatos
(Ed.), Philosophical papers (J. Worrall & G. Currie, vol. Eds.) (Vol. I). Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press.
Lamal, P. A. (1983). A cogent critique of epistemology leaves radical behaviorism unscathed.
Behaviorism, 11, 103-109.
Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Tobt,ard a theory of scientific gromlth.
Berkeley: Univ. of California Press.
Lee, V. L. (1987). The structure of conduct. BeharGrism. 15, 141-148.
Lee, V. L. (1988). The language of action: A review of Schafers A news (anguage .for
psychoanalysis. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 49, 429-436.
Lehrman, D. S. (1953). A critique of Konrad Lorenzs theory of instinctive behavior.
Quarterly Review, of Biology, 28, 337-363.
Lemer, R. M. (1976). Concepts and theories of human development. Reading. MA: Addison-
Wesley,
Lerner, R. M., Hultsch, D. F., & Dixon, R. A. (1983). Contextualism and the character
of developmental psychology in the 1970s. In J. W. Dauben & V. S. Sexton (Eds.).
History and philosophy of science: Selected papers. Annals of the New York Academy
of Sciences, 412, 101-128.
Lerner. R. M., & Kauffman, R. M. (1985). The concept of development in contextualism.
Developmental Revien?. 5, 309-333.
Lerner. R. M.. Skinner, E. A.. & Sorell. G. T. (1980). Methodological implications of
contextual/dialectic theories of development. Human Development. 23. 225-235.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 319

Lewontin, R. C. (1976, March/April). The fallacy of biological determinism. The Sciences,


6-10.
Lubinski, D., & Thompson, T. (1986). Functional units of human behavior and their
integration: A dispositional analysis. In T. Thompson 8~ M. D. Zeiler (Eds.), Analysis
and integration of behavioral units (pp. 275-314). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Mach, E. (1960). The science ofmechanics (T. .I. McCormack, Trans.). LaSalle, IL: Open
Court. (Original work published 1883)
Malcolm, N. (1977). Memory and mind. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ. Press.
Mandell, C. (1986). Putting learning back in context [review of Context and learning]. The
Behavior Analyst, 9, 205-210.
Marr, M. J. (1983). Memory: Models and metaphors. The Psychological Record, 33, 12-
19.
Marr, M. J. (1985). Tis the gift to be simple: A retrospective appreciation of Machs The
science of mechanics. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 41, 129-138.
McPherson, A., & Osborne, J. G. (1988). Control of behavior by an establishing stimulus.
Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 49, 213-227.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.
Michael, J. L. (1982). Distinguishing between discriminative and motivational functions of
stimuli. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 31, 149-155.
Michael, J. L. (1985). Behavior analysis: A radical perspective. In B. L. Hammonds (Eds.),
Psychology and learning (pp. 99-121). Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association.
Midgley, B. D., & Morris, E. K. (in press). The integrated field: An alternative to the
behavior-analytic conceptualization of behavioral units. The Psychological Record.
Miller, N. E., & Dollard, J. (1941). Social learning and imitation. New Haven: Yale Univ.
Press.
Moore, J. (1980). On behaviorism and private events. The Psychological Record, 30,439-
475.
Moore, J. (1981). On mentalism, methodological behaviorism, and radical behaviorism.
Behaviorism, 9, 55-77.
Moore, J. (1985). Some historical and conceptual relations among logical positivism, op-
erationism, and behaviorism. The Behavior Analyst, 8, 53-63.
Morris, E. K. (1982). Some relationships between interbehavioral psychology and radical
behaviorism. Behaviorism, 10, 187-216.
Morris, E. K. (1984). Interbehavioral psychology and radical behaviorism: Some similarities
and differences. The Behavior Analyst, 7, 197-204.
Morris, E. K. (1985a). Wittgensteins language games and the call to cognition. Behaviorism,
13, 137-146.
Morris, E. K. (1985b). The Molloy-Bimbrauer exchange: How many factors do a psychology
make? Behaviour Change, 3, l-14.
Morris, E. K. (1986). Doin what comes naturlly [review of Theories and concepts of
development]. Contemporary Psychology, 31, 662-663.
Morris, E. K. (1987, August). Not so worlds apart: Contextualism, radical behaviorism,
and developmental psychology. Paper presented at behavior Analysis: A Loyal Apposition
to Mainstream Psychology, A symposium conducted at the meeting of the American
Psychological Association, New York.
Morris, E. K. (1988). Not so worlds apart: Contextualism, radical behaviorism, and de-
velopmental psychology. The Znterbehaviorist, 16(I), 8-15.
Morris, E. K. (1988). [Review of Contextualism and understanding in behavioral science.]
The Psychological Record, 38, 363-367.
Morris, E. K., Higgins, S. T., & Bickel, W. K. (1982). The influence of Kantors inter-
behavioral psychology on behavior analysis. The Behavior Analyst, 5, 158-173.
320 EDWARD K. MORRIS

Morris, E. K., Higgins, S. T., & Bickel. W. K. (1983). Contributions of .I. K. Kantor to
contemporary behaviorism. In N. W. Smith. P. T. Mountjoy. 8r D. H. Ruben (Eds.).
Reassessment in psychology: The interbehar~ioral alternati~~e (pp. 5 I-89). Washington.
DC: University Press of America.
Morris, E. K., Hursh, D. E.. Winston. A. W.. Gelfand, D. M., Hartmann. D. P.. Reese.
H. W., & Baer. D. M. (1982). Behavior analysis and developmental psychology.
Human Development, 25, 340-364.
Mowrer, 0. H. (1960). Learning theory and the symbolic processes. New York: Wiley.
ODonnell, J. M. (1985). The origins of behaviorism: American psychology. 1870-1920.
New York: New York Univ. Press.
Overton, W. F., & Reese, H. W. (1973). Models of development: Methodological implications.
In J. R. Nesselroade & H. W. Reese (Eds.). Life-span dn~elopmental p.syc~ho/o~y:
Methodological issacs (pp. 65-86). Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
Parrott. L. J. (1983). On the differences between Skinners radical behaviorism and Kantors
interbehaviorism. Mexican Journal of Behavior Ana/ysis. 9, 95-I 15.
Peirce, C. S. (1923). How to make our ideas clear. In C. S. Peirce, Love, chance, turd
/ogic: Philosophical essays (M. R. Cohen, Ed.) (pp. 32-60). New York: Harcourt.
Brace. (Original work published 1878).
Peirce, C. S. (1940). Philosophical tltritings of Peirce (.I. Buchler, Ed.). New York: Dover.
Pepper, S. C. (1942). World hypotheses: A study in evidence. Berkeley: Univ. of California
Press.
Piaget. J. (1952). The origins ofinte//igence in children. New York: International Universities
Press.
Piaget, J. (1971). Biology and kno+v/edge. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.
Piaget, J. (1983). Piagets theory. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.). Handbook of child p.s~cho/op~.
Vol. 1. History, theory, and methods (W. Kessen. vol. Ed.) (pp. 103-128). New York:
Wiley.
Popper, K. R. (1959). The logic of scientifc disc,olvery. New York: Harper and Row.
Pronko. N. H.. & Herman, D. T. (1982). From Deweys reflex arc concept to transactionalism
and beyond. Behaviorism, 10, 229-254.
Rachhn, H. (1982). Absolute and relative consumption space. In D. Bernstein (Ed.). Nebraska
Symposium on Motivation, 1981 (Vol. 29. pp. 129-167). Lincoln: Univ. of Nebraska
Press.
Ray, R. D., & Delprato, D. J. (in press). Systems methodology: Investigating continuity
and organization in developmental interactions. In S. H. Cohen & H. W. Reese (Eds.).
Life-span developmental psychology Methodological innovations. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Redd, W. H., Morris, E. K.. & Martin, J. A. (1975). Effects of positive and negative
adult-child interactions on childrens social preferences. Jorrmal ofExperimental Child
Psychology, 19, 153-164.
Reese, E. P. (1986). Learning about teaching from teaching about learning: Presenting
behavior analysis in an introductory survey course. In W. P. Makosky (Ed.). The
Master Lecture Series (Vol. 6, pp. 69-127). Washington. DC: American Psychological
Association.
Reese, H. W. (1976). Conceptions of the active organism: Discussion. Haman Der~elopmem.
19, 108-119.
Reese, H. W. (1982). Behavior analysis and life-span developmental psychology. De,le/-
opmental Review*, 2, 150-161.
Reese, H. W. (1984, May). Historical and philosophical utrtr/~sis of curtscrlity. Paper presented
at the meeting of the Association for Behavior Analysis. Columbus. OH.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 321

Reese, H. W. (1986). Behavioral and dialectical psychologies. In L. P. Lipsitt & .I. H.


Cantor (Eds.), Experimental child psychologist: Essays in honor of Charles C. Spiker
(pp. 157-195). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Reese, H. W., & Overton, W. F. (1970). Models of development and theories of development.
In L. R. Goulet & P. B. Baltes (Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology: Research
and theory (pp. 115-145). Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
Reid, J. B., Patterson, G. R., & Loeber. R. (1982). The abused child: Victim, instigator,
or innocent bystander? In D. Bernstein (Ed.), Nebraska Symposiam on Motivation,
1981 (Vol. 29, pp. 47-68). Lincoln: Univ. of Nebraska Press.
Riegel, K. F. (1975). Toward a dialectical theory of development. Haman Development,
18, 50-64.
Riegel, K. F. (1976a). The dialectics of human development. American Psychologist, 31,
689-700.
Riegel, K. F. (1976b). Psychology in development and history. New York: Plenum.
Ringen, J. (1976). Explanation, teleology, and operant behaviorism. Philosophy ofScience,
43, 223-253.
Rosnow, R. L., & Georgoudi, M. (Eds.). (1986). Contextualism and anderstanding in
behavioral science: Implications for research New York: Praeger.
and theory.
Russell, B. (1953). On the notion of cause, with applications to the free-will problem. In
H. Feigel & M. Brodbeck (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 387-
407). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Ryle, G. (1949). The concept ofrhe mind. London: Hutchinson.
Sameroff, A. J. (1983). Developmental systems: Contexts and evolution. In P. H. Mussen
(Ed.), Handbook of child psychology, Vol. I. Histop, theory. and methods (W. Kessen,
vol. Ed.) (pp. 237-294). New York: Wiley.
Sameroff, A. J., & Cavanagh. P. J. (1979). Learning in infancy: A developmental perspective.
In J. D. Osofsky (Ed.), Handbook of infant development (pp. 344-392). New York:
Wiley.
Schlinger, H., & Blakely. E. (1987). Function-altering effects of contingency-specifying
stimuli. The Behavior Analyst, 10, 41-45.
Schnaitter, R. (1978). Private causes. Behariorism 6, I-12.
Schnaitter, R. (1985). The haunted clockwork: Reflections of Gilbert Ryles The concepr
of mind. Journal of rhe Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 43, 145-153.
Schneirla, T. C. (1966). Behavioral development and comparative psychology. Quarter/y
Review of Biology, 41, 238-302.
Sears, R. R., Maccoby, E. E., & Levin. H. (1957). Parrerns of child rearing. Stanford,
CA: Stanford Univ. Press.
Sidman, M. (1986a). Functional analysis of emergent verbal classes. In T. Thompson &
M. D. Zeiler (Eds.), Ana/ysis and integration of behavioral units (pp. 213-245). Hillsdale.
NJ: Erlbaum.
Sidman, M. (1986b). The measurement of behavioral development. In N. A. Krasnegor.
D. B. Gray, & T. Thompson (Eds.), Developmental behavioral pharmacology (pp.
43-52). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Skinner, B. F. (1931). The concept of the reflex in the description of behavior. Journal
of General Psychology, 5, 427-458.
Skinner, B. F. (1935). The generic nature of the concepts of stimulus and response. Journal
of General Psychology, 12, 40-65.
Skinner, B. F. (1938). The behavior of orgunisms. Englewood Cliffs. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational analysis of psychological terms. Psycholog&/
Review, 52, 270-277, 291-294.
Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science und human behavior. New York: Macmillan Co.
322 EDWARD K. MORRIS

Skinner. B. F. (1956). A case history in scientific method. Amrric~trn Psyc~ho/ogist. I I.


221-233.
Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal be/zu~~ior. Englewood Cliffs. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Skinner. B. F. (1969). Contingencies oj. reinfbrcemerrt. Englewood Cliffs. NJ: Prentice-
Hail.
Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom arzd dignity. New York: Knopf.
Skinner, B. F. (1974). Abour behrrGorism. New York: Knopf.
Skinner. B. F. (1977). Why I am not a cognitive psychologist. Beha~Grism, 5, I-10.
Skinner, B. F. (1981). Selection by consequences. Science. 213. 501-504.
Smith, L. D. (1986). Behaviorism und logical positivism: A reussessment of the olli(mce.
Stanford, CA: Stanford Univ. Press.
Smith, N. W., Mountjoy, P. T., & Ruben. D. H. (Eds.). (1983). Reossessmenf iu ps.vcho/ogy.
The interbehavioral alternative. Washington. DC: University Press of America.
Stevens, S. S. (1939). Psychology and the science of science. Psychological Bn//e/in, 36,
221-263.
Stevenson, H. (19831. How children learn. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Hu~~dhook of child
psychology, Vol. 1. History, theory, and methods (W. Kessen, vol. Ed.) (pp. 213-
236). New York: Wiley.
Taylor, D. A. (1988). Through a time tunnel: The metamorphosis of psychological thinking
[review of Contextucdism und understcrnding in behcrviorcrl scienc~e]. Contemportrr>
Psychology, 33, 363-364.
Thompson. T. (1984). The examining magistrate for nature: A retrospective review of
Claude Bernards An introduction to the study of experimentcrl medicine. Joromd qf
the Experimental Anulysis of Behrrrior. 41. 21 I-216.
Thompson. T., & Zeiler, M. D. (Eds.). ( 1986) Antr/ysis and integrution ofbehcr~%~r-tr/ rmits.
Hillsdale. NJ: Erlbaum.
Titchener. E. B. (1910). Text-book ofpsycholo~y. New York: Macmillan Co.
Todd, J. T., & Morris, E. K. (1983). Misconception and miseducation: Presentations of
radical behaviorism in psychology textbooks. T/?P Behcrlior Ancr/y.st. 6, 153-160.
Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposilse behrrl,ior in crnimrrls trnd mtrn. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
Valsiner. J.. & Benigni, L. (1986). Naturalistic research and ecological thinking in the
study of child development. Developmenfal Revielc~. 6, 203-223.
Verplanck, W. S. (1954). Burrhus F. Skinner. In W. K. Estes. S. Koch, K. MacCorquodale,
P. E. Meehl. C. G. Mueller. W. N. Schoenfeld. & W. S. Verplanck (Eds.). Modern
learning theory (pp. 267-3 16). Englewood Cliffs. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Waddington, C. H. (1975). The er.o/rrtion of cm e\*o/r/tionist. Edinburgh: Edinburgh Univ.
Press.
Wahler, R. G., & Dumas, J. E. (in press). Attentional problems in dysfunctional mother-
child interactions: An interbehavioral model. Psycholo~iccrl Bullerit~.
Wahler. R. G., & Fox, J. J. (1981). Setting events in applied behavior analysis: Toward
a conceptual and methodological expansion. Jortrncd of Applied Behcruior Antr/ysis.
14. 327-338.
Wahler, R. G.. & Fox, J. J. (1982) Response structure and deviant child-parent relationships:
Implications for family therapy. In D. Bernstein (Ed.). Nehrosku S.vmposirtm on Mo-
tirration, 198/ (Vol. 29, pp. l-46). Lincoln: Univ. of Nebraska Press.
Watson, J. B. (1913). Behu\siorism. New York: Norton.
Weiner. H. (1981). Contributions of reinforcement schedule histories to our understanding
of drug effects in human subjects. In T. Thompson & C. E. Johanson (Eds.). Behtrliorrd
pharmacology crnd hrtmrm drrrp dependence. Rockville. MD: National Institute of
Drug Abuse.
Weiner. H. (1983). Some thoughts on discrepant human-animal pelformanceh under schedule5
of reinforcement. Tllr Ps~clrolo~ic~trl Rrc,ord. 33, 52 I-523.
CONTEXTUALISM AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 323

Weiss, P. A. (1969). The living system: Determinism stratified. In A. Koestler & J. R.


Smythies (Eds.), Beyond redrrctionism: Nets perspectilaes in the life sciences (pp. 3-
42). New York: Macmillan Co.
Wharf. 9. L. (1956). Language. thought, and retr/it.v. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Original
work published 1940)
Wicker, A. W. (1983). AII introduction to ecologiccrl ps~c.ho/o~~. New York: Cambridge
Univ. Press.
White, S. H. (1970). The learning theory tradition and child psychology. In P. H. Mussen
(Ed.), Carmichaels manual of child p.syho/ogy. (pp. 657-701). New York: Wiley.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). New
York: Macmillan Co.
Wittgenstein. L. (1958). The blue crnd the hrostn ho&s. New York: Harper and Row.
Zuriff. G. E. (1980). Radical behaviorist epistemology. Psyhologictrl RevieLcl, 87, 337-
350.
Zuriff, G. E. (1985). Behaviorism: A conceptuul reconstruction. New York: Columbia
Univ. Press.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi