Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 5

Ignorance, History of Concept

Barbara Hoenig, Innsbruck University, Innsbruck, Austria


2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Abstract

The term ignorance designates nonknowledge, what is unknown, or absent in empirically valid knowledge. Starting from
a distinction of kindred concepts in different scientic disciplines, particularly the concepts role in theories of social action, in
theories of knowledge, and in organizational studies are considered. Finally, current developments in agnotology and in the
sociology of ignorance are discussed.

Proverbs like ignorance is bliss and what you dont know critically articulating a remarkable amount of ignorance
cant hurt you reect the fact that one should be aware of what implied in ordinary language (Unger, 1975). In political
not to know. In scientic discourse, ignorance designates what theory, the concept veil of ignorance has been used in
is unknown, and absent in empirically valid knowledge, in the a thought experiment for granting fair, unanimous decisions,
sense of nonknowledge. Thus, ignorance is held distinct both assuming that in a ctional situation of decision making,
from the act of ignoring what is known, and from error, risk, rational actors reasoning on social order would be oriented
and false beliefs as forms of imperfect or limited knowledge toward what anyone would wish, do, or agree with, under the
(Moore and Tumin, 1949: p. 788); rather, ignorance can be condition that actors would not know about their own social
regarded as a more or less hidden component of situations position in it (Rawls, 1971). In science and technology studies,
usually discussed in other terms (Moore and Tumin, 1949: p. the assessment of more expectable, calculable risks has given
795). Ignorances dynamic role in social change seems to rise to accounting for ignorance as well, while kindred uncer-
depend on the recognition of its existence and a subsequent tainty has been understood as a subbranch of it (Smithson,
searching for more adequate knowledge. In a similar vein, the 1989: p. 9). According to Michael Smithsons taxonomy,
specication of ignorance has been regarded as prerequisite to ignorance is related both to relevance and error, the latter
the acquisition of knowledge (Merton, 1987). As subsequently indicating distortions or incompleteness in knowledge; in the
will be shown, ignorance is related to kindred concepts in formal sciences, incompleteness is reected in terms of
different scientic disciplines; more specically, the author absence, ambiguity, probability, vagueness, fuzziness, and
takes account of the role of ignorance in theories of social nonspecicity (Smithson, 1989: p. 9). Bearing on ignorance as
action and in theories of knowledge and science studies. After a social scientic concept, distinctions such as structural
outlining how ignorance has been reected as strategic resource (Moore and Tumin, 1949), specied (Merton, 1987), science
in organizational contexts, some recent developments in based (Ravetz, 1987), or strategic ignorance (McGoey, 2012)
agnotology and in the sociology of ignorance are considered. have been suggested. Recently, Andrew Abbott has focused on
the need to specify the quality of ignorance one is subject to in
order to enjoy the positive function of several varieties of
Ignorance and Kindred Concepts ignorance (Abbott, 2010). Investigating ignorance as manifest
in different sources of scientic knowledge, he has drawn
Ignorance and related concepts form an important phenom- a distinction between three types of ignorance connected with
enon in several neighbor disciplines of the social and behav- corresponding actor groups involved in knowledge production:
ioral sciences. Think of Freuds unconscious as path-breaking the amateurs ignorance of central cognitive skills, the
notion in psychology and cognitive science till today: He professionals ignorance of collateral literature, and the
coined the term in trying to understand which type of experts synthetic ignorance of facts, as an inability to perceive
nonconscious knowledge is involved in forgetting a word, them other than in the light of ones own paradigm or theory
producing a linguistic lapse, or understanding a joke (Freud, (Abbott, 2010). While most social scientic approaches toward
1901). Ignorance is close to terms such as oblivion, secrecy, understanding ignorance were independently developed by
censorship, and taboo as well, which were so central in the individual scholars, in the following the author discusses some
works of some social anthropologists (Douglas, 1966). of them either as part of social theories of action or within the
Complex relationships between ignorance and actors rational frame of a sociology of knowledge.
choices are reected in economics, where incomplete knowl-
edge and asymmetric information embodied in situations of
interdependent decision making creates dilemmas and Ignorance in Theories of Social Action
opportunities for strategic action (Schelling, 1960). In political
science, the role of discretion for bureaucratic autonomy has Very often in life, one takes action on the basis of rather little
been a topic in discussing how politicians make use of laws to knowledge, concerning both structural conditions and conse-
shape the policy process (Huber and Shapin, 2002). In quences of ones activities. Ignorance affects ones capacities to
philosophy, skeptical reasoning about knowledge resulted in act in a social structure constraining ones choices; it is also

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 11 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.03088-9 579
580 Ignorance, History of Concept

bound to unknown effects, contingent outcomes, and unan- the occasion for developing a new theory or for extending an
ticipated consequences of action, in contrast to calculable risks, existing theory (Merton, 1957: p. 104).
controllable effects, and desirable aims. Different schools or Symbolic interactionists and phenomenological sociolo-
paradigms of social theory have found divergent answers to gists have produced interesting accounts of ignorance as well
how ignorance is related to social action, and mostly they have (Berger and Luckmann, 1967; Schtz and Luckmann, 1973).
dealt with it as a rather implicit issue of concern (Schneider, Underscoring the idea that social interaction and communi-
1962; Gross, 2007). As Louis Schneider (1962) has shown, cation are made possible by actors sharing a stock of knowl-
the classics of social theory have reected ignorance mainly in edge, meanings of signicant symbols, and negotiated
terms of mystication and in sharp contrast to notions of denitions of situation, they also have mentioned structures of
enlightenment, truth, and knowledge; While Marxism and in ignorance as part of relative or even fundamental opacities in
part Karl Mannheims sociology of knowledge focused on the everyday life and as potential knowledge (Schtz and
cognitive distortion of scientic truth by false consciousness Luckmann, 1973). However, the empirical case of nonshared
and ideology, Max Weber regarded science as a way of experience and asymmetries in knowledge seems to posit an
demystifying the magic ignorance of the world by intellectu- analytical problem for phenomenological approaches
alization and rationalization (Louis Schneider, 1962). In (Smithson, 1989: p. 235). In contrast to that, Erving Goffmans
contrast to the savage who knows incomparably more about (1959) metaphor of the backstage accounts for the fact that
his tools, although for whom magical powers existed as well, some types of social interaction are only possible when social
today one usually does not have much knowledge about, but actors are at least partially ignorant of others intentions.
rather count on, the behavior of technical means such as the Ethnomethodologists (Garnkel, 1967) and social construc-
streetcar, believing that one can, in principle, master all things tivists tried to explicate actors practical competencies of taking
by calculation (Weber, 1917/1919: p. 87). Georg Simmel re- action in everyday life, underscoring its nondiscursive, tacit
ected ignorance as part of an increasing discrepancy of dimension (Polanyi, 1966) as precondition for successfully
objective and subjective culture; as one of few classical sociol- accomplishing it. Thus, they regarded ignorance as basic char-
ogists, he dealt with ignorance as inevitable part of the secrecy acteristic of microsocial interaction and of social reality in
inherent in social relations (Simmel, 1908). general.
Wilbert E. Moore and Melvin Tumin (1949) acknowledged
the inescapable character of ignorance intrinsic to social orga-
nization with the aim of examining its structural functions in Ignorance in Theories of Knowledge
varying institutional contexts. According to them, one function
of ignorance is maintaining privilege in asymmetric power Similar to his distinction of manifest and latent functions of
relations as between lays and experts, specialists and potential social action, Merton (1987) has characterized ignorances
competitors, and in ethnic and class stereotyping as well. As function in science as a social institution, drawing on the
specic kind of institutionalized ignorance they mentioned the importance of its recognition that turns formerly unrecognized
case where ignorance of future chances is institutionally used then to specied ignorance. Contrary to the normative
as a device to create anxieties and spur activity in a competitive expectation that an individual scientist shows humility through
system such that a worker is expected to be motivated by his confessing ignorance by acknowledging ones knowledge
insecurity (Moore and Tumin, 1949: pp. 793f.). However, limitations, Merton claried the cognitive value of specifying
they also acknowledged institutions ignorance of an individ- what exactly is not known: According to him, specication
uals irrelevant personal characteristics as precondition for of ignorance precedes scientic problem nding, a process of
preserving fair competition, for instance, in recruitment by selectively perceiving complex phenomena in a dialectic of
bureaucratic organizations or in peer review procedures of awareness of some and negligence of other aspects (Merton,
science. Apart from that, the attractiveness of any new experi- 1987: p. 8). He illustrated that practice by discussing succes-
ence in life depends on ones ignorance or uncertainty of its sive stages of theory development in the sociology of deviance
outcome (Moore and Tumin, 1949: pp. 793f.). Robert K. from the 1920s onward. Moreover, he was interested in
Merton is one of the most important theorists focusing on the whether scientic disciplines differ in their extent of routinely
role of ignorance in social action: in discussing unanticipated specied ignorance and how this affects the growth of knowl-
consequences of purposeful action (Merton, 1936), in reect- edge in these (Merton, 1987: p. 8). At quite the same time, the
ing the role of serendipity (Merton and Barber, 2004), and term science-based ignorance has been coined by philosopher
specied ignorance in scientic progress (Merton, 1987). John Ravetz (1987) who developed a similar thesis in talking
Unanticipated consequences may arise through the limited about relevant, usable forms of nonknowledge.
knowledge about bases of social action and a correct antici- The classical paradigm of the sociology of knowledge,
pation of its consequences. As barriers to correct anticipation, formulated by Karl Marx and Karl Mannheim and specied by
Merton mentioned not only ignorance, but also error, impe- Merton, focuses on the relationship of cognitive or mental
rious immediacy of interest, basic values, and self-defeating productions to designated existential bases as given by social
prediction (Merton, 1936). Moreover, he dealt with the role structure. In trying to articulate a parallel paradigm for the
of ignorance in the dynamics of scientic discovery and in the sociology of nonknowledge, David Weinstein and Michael
relationship between empirical research and sociological Weinstein asked why and how people exclude certain cogni-
theory, as indicated by the serendipity pattern in science, tions and judgments from their awareness (Weinstein and
designating the fairly common experience of observing an Weinstein, 1978: p. 152). They dened their suggested meta-
unanticipated, anomalous and strategic datum which becomes theory in terms of ground (epistemologies or general theories
Ignorance, History of Concept 581

of knowledge), resultant (types of actors nonknowledge institutional contexts, here the author takes a short digression
involved), and an intervening process between both, in which accounting for the role of ignorance and its strategic uses as
the distorted or inadequate cognition arises (Weinstein and a resource in organizations.
Weinstein, 1978: p. 154). Concerning the epistemological
ground dimension for nonknowledge, they made a distinction
between need-grounded and possibility-grounded concep- Strategic Ignorance as an Organizational Source
tions of nonknowledge, the rst term indicating universal
motivators of social action, the second term bearing upon not When Schneider (1962) has particularly drawn attention on
necessarily universalistic options, purposes, and goals of structural functionalisms usefulness for analyzing the func-
human action. Resultant types of nonknowledge they inter- tions of ignorance in institutional contexts, he did so by
preted in analogy to these types of grounds, as need-grounded developing what Abbott (2010: p. 186) later has called
misinterpretations, on a continuum ranging from falsication a liberating view on ignorance: aiming at specifying those
to distortion presupposing some knowable true description of conditions where ignorance might lead to positive, more
social life, versus possibility-grounded inattentions, neglect, democratic results. Apart from taking ignorances protective
and inadvertence, assuming a standard eld of possibilities function exercised in the context of immediate interaction, or
rather than only one true description of a situation. The its consequences for specic persons in a situational interaction
dynamic component of the suggested paradigm referred to a context into account, like in parentchild interaction or
process through which mistaken cognition or inattention takes a physicianpatient relationship, Schneider thought of more
place (Weinstein and Weinstein, 1978: p. 156); as examples of institutionalized examples of ignorances consequences for
explaining mistaken cognition or the narrowing of possible a wider social structure. Thus, he mentioned Burton Clarks
alternatives, Freudian ego-defense mechanisms or social sanc- (1960) discovery of the cooling out function of higher
tions in structural-functionalism were given. Although in education institutions, as informal practices of discouraging
Weinstein and Weinsteins variegation of the Mertonian para- and adjusting students expectations toward aspiring less
digm for the sociology of knowledge particularly the concep- ambitious goals, and Peter Blaus (1955) study on social
tualization of knowledge bases is confusing, it becomes dynamics in bureaucratic institutions, in which gain through
apparent that the sociology of nonknowledge proposed shall indirection, as one form of ignorance, is often an implicit
not restrict itself to institutional analyses of social structure but practice of concern. In his study, Blau outlined how institu-
to directly make judgments on the meaningfulness of non- tional requirements can be reached by bureaucratic mecha-
knowledges cognitive content (Weinstein and Weinstein, nisms neutralizing possible bias of actors that, unwittingly or
1978: p. 159). not, might inuence decision-making practices by prejudices
The authors explicit cognitive interest and their strong focus against minorities. In functional terms, a social pattern with
on describing ubiquitous processes of not-knowing character- the latent function of impartiality, statistical records, was more
izes more recent constructivist sociology of scientic ignorance effective than a different pattern with the same manifest func-
as well. For instance, Karin Knorr-Cetina (1981) emphasized tion, antidiscrimination rules. Since latent function is dened
that knowledge and ignorance, and the criteria by which they as an unintended consequence, the concept implies that the
are established, are socially constructed in interaction social behavior involved is motivated by factors other than the
processes and negotiations among actors that are highly function under consideration (Blau, 1955: p. 81). To this
contingent, contextually and situationally determined, and to insight Schneider added the relevance of ignorance involved,
a large extent dependent on the tacit, inexplicable, and implicit conditioning more effective, nondiscriminatory placements,
character of practical know-how. The interest in the formal when bureaucratic actors simply did not know that their
structure of that social fabric has inspired lots of empirical action was bringing those things about (Schneider, 1962: p.
studies on knowledge production in microsocial scientic 501).
contexts such as laboratories. Within the wide range of the In the sociological study of organizations, ignorance has
sociology of knowledge, the implied epistemological relativism been considered as fundamental resource of any bargaining
of that position remains questionable; in addition, the focus on relationship between strategic actors, characterizing social
local practices of knowledge production often neglects the power as their structural capacity to act by controlling zones of
inuence of institutional contexts and communal procedures uncertainty (Crozier and Friedberg, 1977). James March and
of knowledge evaluation on what counts as knowledge. From Herbert Simon identied organizational norms for dealing
the perspective of an institutionalist sociology of the sciences, with ignorance and uncertainties, anomalies, and risk, in con-
Richard Whitley (1984) has dealt with the question of how structing a self-conrming environment by absorbing partic-
ignorance, uncertainty, and the organization of scientic elds ular questions, inquiries, or communications about these
affect one another, distinguishing between technical versus (March and Simon, 1958). Taking the organized anarchy of
strategic uncertainty. While the former refers to scientists decision making at the university as an empirical example,
disagreement on the reliability and understanding of research Michael Cohen et al. (1972) formulated their garbage can
techniques, strategic uncertainty indicates disagreement about model of organizational choice. The authors underlined that
and pluralism of intellectual priorities, signicance, and ways under conditions of uncertainty, indicated by unclear tech-
of tackling research problems. According to Whitley, high nology, uid participation, and problematic preferences,
technical uncertainty usually entails high strategic uncertainty, decision-making practices in organizations are more complex
but the reverse does not generally hold. Since one of igno- than suggested by classical analyses of rational action in these
rances most important aspects refers to its function in structural contexts. Rather, they suggested conceiving these as
582 Ignorance, History of Concept

contingent outcomes of four intersecting variables: a stream of Particularly, Ungar has characterized a so-called knowl-
choice, of problems, of energy from participants, and a rate of edgeignorance paradox evolving from contradictory dynamics
ow of solutions. Although Smithsons attempt to reconcile of knowledge societies and its consequences as well. He
formal with social and behavioral sciences sometimes appear indicated that, as inevitable by-product of the specialization
as rather abstract analysis, those interested in further research pressures modern knowledge workers are subject to, their
on ignorance in organizational research may nd useful hints production of more specialized knowledge results in more
there (Smithson, 1989: pp. 239ff.). general ignorance as well, entailing increasing entry costs and
Similar to these early ndings in the sociology of organiza- speech barriers to other knowledge domains (Ungar, 2008).
tions, recent science and technology studies have attempted to The shifting balance between personal expertise and common
identify organizational strategies for constructing ignorance by knowledge goes hand in hand with an increased reluctance to
the denial, dismissal, diversion, and displacement of uncom- pursue additional information and a concomitant decline in
fortable knowledge (Rayner, 2012) in tension or outright the stock of general knowledge (Ungar, 2008: p. 312).
contradiction with self-consistent institutional denitions of Focusing on functional knowledge decits as cases where
situations. Linsey McGoey (2012) has investigated the strategic ignorance denitely is no bliss, Ungar also identied chains of
use of ignorance as part of organizational pressures where ignorance, presumably consequential classes of ignorance that
organizations members seek to preserve and cultivate igno- would require reversals throughout these chains in order to
rance rather than to dispel it. She has analyzed strategies how critically combat an overall debasement of public discourse
members mobilize strategic unknowns of a situation as a tool of (Ungar, 2008: p. 314). As part of the marketing of ignorance
social control, command of resources, denial of liability, and as a social problem, particularly successful in coalescence
assertion of expert control in the face of unpredictable with social movements or moral panics, he identied claims
outcomes. In contrast to Abbotts (2010) emphasis on different referring to embedded ignorance found in specialty domains,
qualities of ignorance, and complementary to his remark that ignorance of medical information, and the special kind of
scholarly practices of articulating knowledge claims are ignorance of the young; young people as a group are more often
accompanied by those of acknowledging ignorance, McGoey than others targeted by do not die for ignorance actions, like in
underscored the need to take scales of ignorance into account antitobacco campaigns, with signicant moral undertones; as
in order to recognize its value as an organizational resource: Ungar remarked, similar to the case of medical ignorance, the
(S)trategic ignorance is often more institutionally advanta- problem of ignorance here is often secondary to the real social
geous the more widely it is individually mobilized . because problem. Ungars interest in the societal dimension of igno-
of the shared willingness of individuals to band together in rance within knowledge societies could fruitfully be deepened
dismissing unsettling knowledge (McGoey, 2012: p. 570). by future research taking the social stratication of access to
knowledge, and nonknowledge, into account.
However, one can also imagine potential situations in
Agnotology and the Current Sociology of Ignorance which ignorance indeed may be bliss. Both predictive genetic
testing and genetic engineering of children indicate areas where
In public debates on science and technology, for a long time it might not only be better not to know (Ungar, 2008: p. 314),
ignorance has mainly been considered as the lays counterpart but where there also exists the explicit right not to know
in relation to an experts knowledge. Since the 1970s, however, (Chadwick et al., 1997). Ungar described that although efforts
both new social movements critique of technological risks and to purposively shelter ignorance for moral reasons may be
endogenous developments in science studies have contributed largely doomed to failure, revelations of uncertainties poten-
to an emerging view of ignorance as inherent part of scientic tially undermining the authority of science become more
development (Wehling, 2001: p. 470). Meanwhile, social commonplace as well. Parallel to scientic progress in human
scientic research on ignorance has rapidly grown to an inter- medicine, genetics, and biotechnology, public discourses on
disciplinary research eld, agnotology, with the explicit the right not to know have emerged because of its preventive
intention to establish scientic accounts of formerly unrecog- function (Popitz, 1968) from taking action, for instance, in the
nized knowledge (Proctor and Schiebinger, 2008). It is birth of a child with possible disorder. Seen from the formal
constantly fed by an abundance of empirical studies, many of structure of the argument, a right not to know might entail
them inspired by a constructionist sociology of knowledge. some similarities to that liberal view on ignorance encoun-
These have analyzed the emergence, discovery and conse- tered above, insofar it builds on the opportunity of nondis-
quences of scientic ignorance, like in human genetics and criminatory effects of social action mechanisms implying
biotechnology, in public incidents with substances like chlo- nonknowledge. From a sociological perspective, the challenge
rouorocarbons, dichlorodiphenyltrichloroethane, and dioxin, of the debate lies in the array of implications of that fragile
or consequences of new technologies (for instance, Bschen judicial construct for the role of actors, professionals, and the
et al., 2010). In addition, one can recognize an increasing media in societies usually taking a positive stance toward
interest in the societal dimensions of ignorance as inevitable knowledge (Levitt, 1997). Actors, expected to take responsi-
part of modern knowledge societies (Luhmann, 1992; Ungar, bility for their health and those of their children, in reality do
2008). Three aspects of these rather recent developments in have limited opportunities and resources to exercise choice and
a sociology of ignorance shall be considered here: the knowl- be in control of their lives; thus, it is unsurprising that the topic
edgeignorance paradox, the right not to know, and different arises as the technology to predict risks for individuals runs
epistemic cultures of nonknowledge as dimensions of an ahead of both available treatments and the human ability to
increasing politicization of ignorance. cope with such knowledge (Levitt, 1997: p. 35).
Ignorance, History of Concept 583

Based on a broad study on the role of ignorance in various Garnkel, H., 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Prentice-Hall, Englewood-Cliffs, NJ.
scientic disciplines, and discussing two empirical cases in Goffman, E., 1959. The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Doubleday, Garden-
City, NY.
greater detail, Stefan Bschen et al. (2010: pp. 790f.) identied
Gross, M., 2007. The unknown in process: dynamic connections of ignorance, non-
three different epistemic cultures of nonknowledge as equally knowledge and related concepts. Current Sociology 55 (5), 724759.
valid, rational ways of dealing with nonknowledge: oriented Huber, J., Shapin, S., 2002. Deliberate Discretion? The Foundations of Institutional
toward control, toward complexity, or toward case-based Autonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
experience. They characterized the control-oriented approach Knorr-Cetina, K., 1981. The Manufacture of Knowledge: An Essay on the Constructivist
and Contextual Nature of Science. Pergamon Press, Oxford.
toward nonknowledge by an epistemic focus on controlling Levitt, M., 1997. Sociological perspectives in the right to know and the right not to
experimental conditions and avoiding disruptive factors, like in know. In: Chadwick, R., Levitt, M., Shickle, D. (Eds.), The Right to Know and the
molecular biology. In contrast, in ecology they identied Right Not to Know. Avebury, Aldershot, pp. 2936.
a complexity-oriented culture that obtained a high degree of Luhmann, N., 1992. kologie des Nichtwissens. In: Beobachtungen der Moderne.
Westdeutscher Verlag, Opladen, pp. 149220 (1998. Engl. Ecology of ignorance.
openness toward unanticipated events and uncontrollable,
In: Observations on Modernity. Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp. 75114.).
context-sensitive settings. The remaining culture of non- March, J.G., Simon, H.A., 1958. Organizations. Wiley, New York.
knowledge concentrating on single case-based experience has McGoey, L., 2012. The logic of strategic ignorance. The British Journal of Sociology 63
been developed in professional expertise such as in medical (3), 553576.
case histories, characterized by a low degree of decontextuali- Merton, R.K., 1936. The unanticipated consequences of purposive social action.
American Sociological Review 1, 894904.
zation and a tendency to dene nonknowledge as problem of Merton, R.K., 1957. The bearing of empirical research on sociological theory. In:
an individual expert. The authors suggested that a full recog- Merton, R.K. (Ed.), Social Theory and Social Structure. The Free Press, Glencoe, IL,
nition of diverse cultures of nonknowledge is required as pp. 102120.
prerequisite for socially legitimate, robust decision- making Merton, R.K., 1987. Three fragments from a sociologists notebook: establishing the
phenomenon, specied ignorance, and strategic research materials. Annual Review
under conditions of politicized scientic nonknowledge
of Sociology 13, 128.
(Bschen et al., 2010). Merton, R.K., Barber, E., 2004. The Travels and Adventures of Serendipity: A Study in
While the increasing politicization of scientic non- Sociological Semantics and the Sociology of Science. Princeton University Press,
knowledge is an interesting topic for the sociology of science in Princeton and Oxford.
its own right, the broader recognition of ignorance both as part Moore, W., Tumin, M., 1949. Some social functions of ignorance. American Socio-
logical Review 14 (6), 787796.
of structural conditions of social action and of human Polanyi, M., 1966. The Tacit Dimension. Doubleday, New York.
knowledge processes enhances social sciences efforts to cope Popitz, H., 1968. ber die Prventivwirkung des Nichtwissens: Dunkelziffer, Norm und
with what is necessarily implied in advancing the growth of Strafe. Mohr, Tbingen.
knowledge. Proctor, R.N., Schiebinger, L. (Eds.), 2008. Agnotology: The Making & Unmaking of
Ignorance. Stanford University Press, Stanford.
Ravetz, J.R., 1987. Uncertainty, ignorance and policy. In: Brooks, H., Cooper, C.K.
See also: Afrocentric Approaches to Social Work; Function- (Eds.), Science for Public Policy. Pergamon Press, Oxford, pp. 7789.
alism, History of; Game Theory; Knowledge Society, History of; Rawls, J., 1971. A Theory of Justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Science and Technology Studies, History of; Unconscious:
Rayner, S., 2012. Uncomfortable knowledge: the social construction of ignorance in
History of the Concept; Unintended Consequences: History of science and environmental policy discourses. Economy and Society 41 (1),
the Concept. 107125.
Schelling, T., 1960. The Strategy of Conict. Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Schneider, L., 1962. The role of the category of ignorance in sociological theory: an
explanatory statement. American Sociological Review 27 (4), 492508.
Bibliography Schtz, A., Luckmann, T., 1973. Structures of the Life-World. Northwestern University
Press, Evanston.
Simmel, G., 1908. Das Geheimnis und die geheime Gesellschaft. In: Simmel, G. (Ed.),
Abbott, A., 2010. Varieties of ignorance. The American Sociologist 41 (2), 174189. Soziologie. Untersuchungen ber die Formen der Vergesellschaftung. Duncker &
Berger, P.L., Luckmann, T., 1967. The Social Construction of Reality. Doubleday, Humblot, Leipzig, pp. 337402 (1906. Engl. The sociology of secrecy and secret
New York. societies. American Journal of Sociology 11, 441498.).
Blau, P.M., 1955. The Dynamics of Bureaucracy: A Study of Interpersonal Relation- Smithson, M., 1989. Ignorance and Uncertainty: Emerging Paradigms. Springer,
ships in Two Government Agencies. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. New York.
Bschen, S., Kastenhofer, K., Rust, I., Soentgen, J., Wehling, P., 2010. Scientic Ungar, S., 2008. Ignorance as an under-identied social problem. The British Journal
nonknowledge and its political dynamics: the cases of agri-biotechnology and of Sociology 59 (2), 301326.
mobile phoning. Science, Technology, & Human Values 35 (6), 783811. Unger, P., 1975. Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Chadwick, R., Levitt, M., Shickle, D. (Eds.), 1997. The Right to Know and the Right Not Weber, M., 1917/1919. Wissenschaft Als Beruf. Politik Als Beruf. In: Weber-
to Know. Avebury, Aldershot. Gesamtausgabe, M. (Ed.), Bd. 17. Mohr, Tbingen (Engl. Science as a Vocation).
Clark, B.R., 1960. The cooling out function in higher education. American Journal of Wehling, P., 2001. Jenseits des Wissens? Wissenschaftliches Nichtwissen aus
Sociology 65 (6), 569576. soziologischer Perspektive. Beyond Knowledge? Scientic Ignorance from
Cohen, M.D., March, J.G., Olsen, J.P., 1972. A garbage can model of organizational a Sociological Point of View. Zeitschrift fr Soziologie 30 (6), 465484.
choice. Administrative Science Quarterly 17 (1), 125. Weinstein, D., Weinstein, M.A., 1978. The sociology of nonknowledge: a paradigm. In:
Crozier, M., Friedberg, E., 1977. LActeur et le Systme. Edition du Seuil, Paris. Jones, R.A. (Ed.), Research in the Sociology of Knowledge, Sciences and Art, vol.
Douglas, M., 1966. Purity and Danger. An Analysis of Concepts of Pollution and Taboo. 1. Jai Press, New York, pp. 151166.
Routledge, London. Whitley, R., 1984. The Intellectual and Social Organization of the Sciences. Oxford
Freud, S., 1901. Psychopathologie des Alltagslebens: ber Vergessen, Versprechen, University Press, Oxford.
Vergreifen, Aberglaube und Irrtum. Verlag von S. Karger, Berlin (1914. Engl.
Psychopathology of Everyday Life. Fisher Unwin, London.).

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi