Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 7

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538

Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

Where explanation ends: Understanding as the place the spade turns


in the social sciences
Stephen Turner
University of South Florida, Tampa, FL, USA

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: Explanations implicitly end with something that makes sense, and begin with something that does not
Available online 23 December 2012 make sense. A statistical relationship, for example, a numerical fact, does not make sense; an explanation
of this relationship adds something, such as causal information, which does make sense, and provides an
Keywords: endpoint for the sense-making process. Does social science differ from natural science in this respect?
Understanding One difference is that in the natural sciences, models are what need understanding. In the social
Models sciences, matters are more complex. There are models, such as causal models, which need to be under-
Mechanisms
stood, but also depend on background knowledge that goes beyond the model and the correlations that
Causal modeling
Max Weber
make it up, which produces a regress. The background knowledge is knowledge of in-lling mechanisms,
Explanation which are normally made up of elements that involve the direct understanding of the acting and believ-
ing subjects themselves. These models, and social science explanations generally, are satisfactory only
when they end the regress in this kind of understanding or use direct understanding evidence to decide
between alternative mechanism explanations.
2012 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

When is an explanation in social science complete? Are the intuitions remain important even in the most recherch areas of
kinds of things social scientists ordinarily work with, such as microphysics. In social science, matters were different. The intelli-
mechanisms (Hedstrom & Swedberg, 1998) and causal models, gibility of action and belief remained important to history, cultural
actually explanatory or do they depend on something else which and social anthropology, and to models of rational action. But anal-
is the real end-point of these explanations? Another way of posing ogous issues over the status of intelligibility or understanding arose
the problem might be this: When is an explanation complete, com- from two sources: the problem of the explanatory status of statisti-
plete in the sense that it is satisfactory on its own terms? One cal methods which produced results that predicted relatively suc-
answer, which applies both to the natural sciences and the social cessfully but had no theoretical grounding, and the problem of
sciences, would involve understanding, in the sense of intelligibil- evaluating the explanatory claims of problematic models and
ity. We do not have a complete explanation if the explanation itself theories that were produced by consciously imitating what were ta-
is not intelligible, for example if it is merely a correlation or a math- ken to be the predictive goals and formal practices of physical
ematical device that enables prediction. In the physical sciences, science.
intelligibility as a criterion for the adequacy of scientic explana- These issues are deeply rooted in controversies about the status
tion lost its centrality in the face of the problem of action at a of the human sciences that were already well-developed in the
distance, where prediction worked nicely but conicted with in- nineteenth century (Feest, 2010). Understanding was a term
grained intuitions about how the physical world worked with established meanings. One derives from the interpretation
(Laudan, 1981, p. 216). But this was not the end of intelligibility, of texts (hermeneutics) and leads to such notions as the hermeneu-
as we have seen in other contributions to this issue. Physical tic circle, which I will ignore. The other is classically formulated by

E-mail address: turner@usf.edu

0039-3681/$ - see front matter 2012 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.12.001
S. Turner / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538 533

Max Weber as follows: population. The goal is a model that is structural, a loosely
understood term that means that the model captures some sort
Understanding may be of two kinds: the rst is the direct obser- of actually operative causal relationships as distinct from mere
vational understanding of the subjective meaning of a given act correlations or correlations that predict but for reasons that are
as such, including verbal utterances. We thus understand by not genuinely causal, such as accidents of distribution in the pop-
direct observation, in this case, the meaning of the proposition ulation. I will argue that excluding correlations that are not genu-
2  2 = 4 when we hear or read it. This is a case of the direct inely causal depends on background knowledge that, in the case of
rational understanding of ideas. We also understand an out- the core social sciences, ultimately requires elements of the
break of anger as manifested by facial expression, exclamations understanding of action in Webers sense. An analogous issue
or irrational movements. This is direct observational under- arises with economic models, with the same result. The role of this
standing of irrational emotional reactions. We can understand particular kind of understanding in social science models thus
in a similar observational way the action of a woodcutter or contrasts with the case of models in the physical and biological
of somebody who reaches for the knob to shut a door or who sciences, which require only that the model itself be understood.
aims a gun at an animal. This is rational observational under-
standing of actions. (Weber, 1978, p. 8) 1. Causal models in social science and their limits
Direct understanding is non-inferential, in the sense that it does not
depend on reasoning from data, theories, knowledge not immedi- In formal terms, there are no sharp distinctions between social
ately present, or assumptions. It is direct in the sense that it is science models and natural science models: probabilistic relation-
not inferred from other facts. Weber pointed out that normal inten- ships, error, estimation, poorly understood empirical relationships,
tional explanation, which he considered under the label of explan- and conscious simplications which eliminate variables that make
atory understanding, is indirect, and involves inferential elements, little difference for prediction, are found in each. Similar statistical
such as the setting and course of events of which the act or state- methods appear in each area, especially in medical contexts, nota-
ment forms a part: bly epidemiology, which often involve mixtures of behavioral and
biological variables. The key issues with these statistical models
can be discussed in terms of the paradigm case of causal models,
Understanding may, however, be of another sort, namely or directed acyclic graphs representing causal systems (Freedman,
explanatory understanding. Thus we understand in terms of 2005; Glymour, Scheines, Spirtes, & Kelly, 1987, pp. 6367; Pearl,
motive the meaning an actor attaches to the proposition twice 2000; Woodward, 2005, 2007). In this section I will deal with these
two equals four, when he states it or writes it down, in that issues in three steps: to consider the key in principle aspects of
we understand what makes him do this at precisely this these models that distinguish them from models in natural science
moment and in these circumstances. Understanding in this involving laws,2 to describe a simple example from social epidemi-
sense is attained if we know that he is engaged in balancing a ology, and to consider the way the issue of statistical models vs.
ledger or in making a scientic demonstration, or is engaged mechanisms has been discussed in the recent social science
in some other task of which this particular act would be an literature.
appropriate part. (Weber, 1978, p. 8) The in principle issues with these models can be seen in their
This kind of understanding plays a role in science as well, if only the simplest form with the simplest causal model: one containing a
limited role of understanding the theories and scientic activities of single correlation, measuring the variation around a regression line
others. In Webers account, explanatory understanding includes dened by an equation involving two variables, a zero-order cor-
rational understanding of motivation, which consists in placing relation. The relationship dened by the equation is purely statis-
the act in an intelligible and more inclusive context of meaning. tical. It enables one to predict values of one variable from another.
In these cases the explanation involves additional non-inferential It has no direction. It is not possible to say anything causal about
meaning or understanding elements, but also additional causal the relationship on the basis of correlation alone. To convert a cor-
elements, such as, in this case, the causal relation between a com- relation into a causal claim requires adding two kinds of claims.
mand and the performance of the act.1 One involves the causal character of the relation itself. It must
In what follows, I will pursue a more modest aim than resolving qualify as a possible causal relation. The second is that the ob-
the larger issues of the ultimate relation of understanding to expla- served relation must not be accounted for by another causal rela-
nation. Instead I will consider two distinct but commonplace and tion, that it is not spurious, the result of common causes, or
representative kinds of social science models that appear far confounded with the real cause, meaning that it is not the product
removed from understanding: structural equation (or causal) of a correlation between the apparent causal variable and the real
models and a class of models which idealize and simplify complex causal variable. These claims are unusual, and problematic: the lat-
situations, those of economic theory. My aim in each case will be to ter is negative, a claim about the non-existence of relevant causes;
show the ways in which direct understanding in the sense outlined the former is a claim about possibility.
by Weber plays a role in these models, and particularly in complet- The causal relationships that are represented in causal models
ing the model as an explanation. In neither case is this role, or even differ from familiar law relationships in several critical ways.
the necessity of appealing to understanding, obvious from the The rst is non-generalizability. Unlike laws, these causal relations
outset. are not universal: they hold for a particular population or situation
By completing the explanation, I will have in mind the follow- and may not generalize beyond it (Glymour, 1983). They cannot be
ing. In the case of causal (structural equation) models, it is ordinar- converted into laws by specifying the conditions under which
ily understood that the basic point of the model is to warrant the causal relationship holds, because the conditions are not spec-
predictions, but that some predictions generalize and others do iable in advance: new causal relations involving new causal
not, for example because they hold accidentally within a given mechanisms can develop and interfere with the relationship, so

1
For a more elaborate discussion of the non-inferential character of this kind of understanding, see Turner (2011b).
2
Needless to say, I will not attempt to cover the vast literature of the last two centuries on the nature of this kind of statistical causality. A selection of the major texts is in
Stephen Turner, Causality, 2010, Sage. This includes an introduction with a concise (non-formal) explanation of the formal issues.
534 S. Turner / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538

that the original observed relationship will cease to hold. The sec- generalize to White women. But we do not know why. It might
ond is a result of the fact that the variation around the regression be that there is a common cause which produces both obesity
line may not be random: subsets of the populations for which the and infant mortality in Black women that does not affect White
relationship has been dened may not exhibit the relationship women. Or it could be that there is a causal relation that holds,
(this is the basis of Simpsons paradox [Blyth, 1972; Charig, for some unknown reason, only within the Black population. The
1995; Julious & Mullee, 1994; Simpson, 1951]), and indeed, divid- correlations cannot distinguish the two possibilities, or the possi-
ing the population into two subsets may reverse the relationship, bility that some other unknown cause is being confounded with
so that a positive relation from the x to the y axis may appear in race, meaning that it is correlated with race and might also be a
the subsets as negative relationships or the relationship may cause of infant mortality. When can one be assured that there is
diminish or simply disappear. The existence of a correlation, in no common cause or confounder? Whether a particular variable
short, may indicate nothing about actual causal relations. In what hypothesized to be a cause belongs in the model, that is to say is
follows a case of this kind will be discussed. The third difference, causally relevant, is, on the surface, an empirical question: does
which follows from the second, is that the mere existence of a cor- it stand in a relation of no affect or not? But the empirical answer
relation, unlike the existence of a strict law, does not exclude the we can give only provides evidence of correlation: the apparent
possibility of alternative explanations consistent with the same causal relation may be the product of confounding. Moreover,
data. This is the problem of confounding. when there is no observed correlation, the genuine causal rela-
So what does causal mean to these models? As Judea Pearl tion may be obscured by the effects of unincluded and unknown
notes in Causality, the causal relationship found in statistics is a causes. In short, we have a regress, in which each attempt to estab-
negative one: not affected by is . . . the only causal notion that lish a causal relation as structural requires prior causal knowledge.
has found a place in statistics textbooks (2000, p. 139n). This def- This case reveals two important oddities about this kind of
inition begs the question of what affect means in the rst place, cause. The rst involves the demarcation of what falls inside
and there is a good reason for doing so: although there are many and outside the model. Whether a variable should be included in
ways of thinking about cause that work for the positive claim of the model or not is a causal question of the same kind as the ques-
cause, such as through the notion of intervention, they typically tion of whether a relationship between two variables is causal: it is
do not work very well for the negative claim. To put this in its most both an empirical question, of whether there is a correlation, and a
simple terms, to get from a correlation to a strong causal interpre- question about two kinds of possibility, whether the relationship in
tation of the correlation requires additional knowledge: some basis a given direction is itself causally possible and whether there are
for thinking that the correlation is causal, and a very strong basis possible confounders or common causes. The last two questions
for thinking that the relation is not the product of other causes. are not empirical in the sense of the rst. The rst requires only
The raw notion of cause mentioned by Pearl works with both types statistical knowledge. The last two questions require knowledge
of causal claims, the positive and the negative ones. The in princi- of another kind, background knowledge that would warrant claims
ple problem with these two knowledge conditions is that the sec- about whether a particular causal relationship is possiblethe only
ond one creates a regress: to make the negative not the product of way of assuring the does not affect claimor whether the class of
other causal claims requires causal knowledge, knowledge about possibly relevant additional causes is empty.
what is affected by what in the setting of the causal interpretation. Neither can be answered directly, and one can see why with the
The reasoning in causal modeling can be seen in a simple exam- example of maternal obesity and infant mortality. Because of the
ple. There is a known correlation between maternal obesity and in- problem of non-generalizability, unless the relations involve a
fant mortality in the United States (Salihu et al., 2008, p. 2010). law and are therefore universal, there is a question of whether a
Obesity is thus a predictor. However, if one divides mothers into relation which is causal in one situation, such as an experiment,
subsets by race, the relationship disappears for White women is causal in the situation in question. This was one of the issues
and becomes stronger, meaning predictive with less variation (or in the long-running dispute over whether smoking caused cancer:
error), for Black women. To assure ourselves that we have iden- even if the effect could be produced with experiments with ani-
tied a real relationship, however, we need to rule out other pos- mals, there was still the question of whether this was what was
sible causes that would produce the same result. One possibility going on with humans. The prominent statistician Ronald Fisher
would be that the two racial groups received different levels of argued that there was reason to believe that the correlation in hu-
care. One can divide or statistically correct for this variable and mans was spurious: that there were common features that both
see if the relationships still hold. The researchers, using their back- gave people the propensity to smoke and to get cancer (Fisher,
ground causal knowledge of the setting, knew this was possible, 1958, 1959). If these features could be identied, and more detail
and needed to exclude the possibility. There were available mea- could be given about the character of the causal relation involved
sures of the number of pre-natal visits, and so forth. Correcting in these features, they could be further examined; but the possibil-
for these made no statistical difference to the mortality outcomes, ity could not be excluded by either the statistical evidence or the
meaning that there were no differences between groups divided experiments on cases that were not part of the population in
into categories corresponding to these causes. Many other poten- question.
tially relevant variables were also tested, and these also made no Whether there are such causes not included in the model is not
difference. The fact that it made no statistical difference justies an empirical question that we can, in principle, answer. The only
a does not affect claim, thus excluding it from the model. answers we can get are for surrogates for this question, which
What marks the boundaries of the model, of what is causally we can assume give the results of the unanswerable causal ques-
relevant? Excluding possible causes for making no difference is tion.3 We can answer the question of whether there is no affect
central. But establishing a cause, showing that it belongs in a cau- indirectly by assuming that there are no relevant variables other
sal model, requires more. In this case, it is still quite unclear that than the ones we can think of to test. But this amounts to making
the relation in question is causal. In this case maternal obesity af- the causal conclusion depend on the limits of our imagination. We
fects infant mortality for Black women, but this relation does not can test for a wide array of nuisance variables such as race and

3
The status of the assumptions that need to be made to enable the surrogates to produce causal conclusions, and the extent to which the assumptions rather than the data
determine the causal conclusions, is controversial. For an introduction to these issues see the exchanges between David Freedman et al. and Clark Glymour et al. in McKim &
Turner (1997, pp. 81182; pp. 183322) and Freedman (2005).
S. Turner / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538 535

education which are commonly associated with causal variables. But mother being treated differently or acting in ways which increase
this guarantees nothing about those possible causal variables that the probability of infant death? These are empirical questions, and
are not associated. Or we can devise statistical tests that indicate although it might be possible to devise statistical tests of hypoth-
where there are anomalies in the correlations that indicate missing eses constructed based on them, with measurable variables that
variables. Anomalous unaccounted for correlation in a path of causa- corresponded to the mechanisms in the hypotheses, even this kind
tion, for example, indicates the presence of a missing variable. These of evidence is indirect evidence of the operation of the mechanisms
statistical methods, however, cannot be purely statistical: identify- themselves. More direct evidence of the mechanisms operating in
ing and limiting the possible paths of causation requires background these cases would override this kind of statistical evidence. To put
knowledge. So the problem of completing a causal model leads in this in a different way, there is a question of whether obesity has
two directions: to background knowledge of what is and is not pos- the same meaning for Black and White women. And this is a ques-
sibly causal (call this, for convenience, the qualitative part of the tion that can be examined by looking at the beliefs, the inferences
claim), which is indispensable, and to further statistical evidence, others make in their interactions with these women, the conse-
which is not sufcient on its own and itself requires further back- quences of these interactions for the women, and at whether there
ground knowledge to qualify it as causal. are distinctive beliefs, attitudes, and so forth with consequences
What is background knowledge? It is easier to say what it needs for action among these women themselves and those they interact
to do: to warrant the negative qualitative part of the no cause with that have causal consequences.
claim. What knowledge would do that? The rough answer is These questions cannot be avoided, simply because of the prob-
knowledge of mechanisms or possible mechanisms. In some cases, lem of the need to exclude alternative causal explanations that
such as those involving the biological mechanisms in epidemiolog- confound or provide a common cause in order to warrant causal
ical studies, claims about the non-possibility of particular relations claims. But what sort of knowledge is the relevant background
of causal dependence might be warranted by something resem- knowledge of human action? In practice, the analyst knows a lot
bling well-conrmed general laws, or by experimental evidence about what sorts of beliefs and attitudes are possible, meaning that
that is presumed to generalize. In other cases, they might be war- they can imagine them or come to imagine them. In principle, they
ranted by general knowledge about biological mechanisms. In are the possible objects of understandingdirect understanding, in
other cases, they might be warranted by knowledge of the tempo- Webers sense, or what he calls explanatory understanding, moti-
ral character of the relevant mechanisms. But there is a problem of vational or intentional understanding which involves some ele-
logical priority in the relation between the use of temporal order ments that are directly understood. There is a mutual relation
and the appeal to mechanisms. Temporal order is often used as a between direct understanding and imagined or possible beliefs
surrogate for background knowledge of causal order. The example and attitudes: one might conrm an imagined explanation by di-
illustrates the problem with this usage: race may be genetic, and rectly understanding an action, or come to expand what we can
thus temporally prior, but its causal signicance may be continu- imagine by directly understanding. This is where the regress ends,
ous, in social interaction, and the nature of the causal relation and where the explanation becomes, in this sense, complete: there
may change over time as well. In short, temporally preceding can is nothing in the way of justication beyond direct understanding
be used as a surrogate for no affect only when background as dened by Weber. It is non-inferential. Nor is it possible to com-
knowledge of the relevant mechanisms justies it, a point to be plete an inlling explanation for a correlation involving human ac-
made clearer shortly. tion without appealing to this kind of fact, either as part of the
A typical example in the status attainment literature in sociol- proposed explanation or in the course of excluding possible rival
ogy, one of the largest and most successful examples of the appli- explanations.4
cation of these methods, is the concern with the relations of
variables such as grandfathers level of education, measured by 2. The mechanisms dispute in sociology and ideal-types
such things as completion of high school, and grandchilds social
status at age forty. Knowledge about when the process of high The need for this kind of background knowledge, together with
school education occurs and of the biology and demography of par- the superiority of mechanisms over correlational evidence, raises
enthood warrants the exclusion of the possibility that the high general questions about the meaning of statistical causal knowl-
school education of a grandparent would be affected by the status edge in social science. It seems as if possessing knowledge of
of the grandchild. One might class this as well-conrmed general mechanisms makes the statistical claims redundant or simply infe-
knowledge, unproblematically extended to the cases at hand. In riorat best an abstract but largely contentless depiction of rela-
this case, the extension might be justied, but it is justied only tionships that are only fully explained by in-lling explanations
because we know something about how status works in the popu- which involve such things as knowledge of the human actions that
lation, or society, in question, which is to say we have knowledge link the inputs and outputs. This is the conclusion that motivates
about typical mechanisms leading to status level. And this need the discussion of mechanisms that has actually occurred in social
for knowledge about mechanisms is a general problem. Time order science, and particularly sociology, over the last twenty-ve years.
would be misleading if the relevant mechanisms involved contin- The motivation for this discussion was the development of causal
uous effects, for example. models which predicted status attainment, but in which the links
In the case of obesity and infant mortality, one can see how were unclear. The defenders of these models claimed that their ap-
background knowledge works, and why the explanation is incom- proach was scientic and that prediction was the primary aim of
plete. The analyst has predictive knowledge, but a weak under- science. The lack of specicity about the actual causal processes in
standing of the mechanisms in operation. Are there distinctive causal models produced a reaction, in the form of an argument to
physical processes operating in obese Black women? Or is obesity the effect that social science (meaning essentially sociological
a marker of some distinctive social and cultural status, perhaps rather than economic, for reasons that will become clear shortly)
stigmatized, which produces continuous conduct, by the mother, uses of these techniques are not adequate, and that social scientists
the care-givers, or by others, which leads in some way to the

4
It goes without saying that there may be ineliminable underdetermination with respect to explanatory understanding hypotheses. But for Weber at least, there is a point
direct understandingwhere underdetermination ends. This will be discussed again in the last section of this article.
536 S. Turner / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538

ought to seek mechanisms, which are taken to be more fully ideal-types. This may not seem to be a very useful result. Ideal-
explanatory than correlations (Hedstrm, 2005, pp. 1133). types have a confusing literature as well. Yet the history is a reveal-
The idea of mechanisms is not well-dened in this literature, ing one. The critique of the concept of ideal-types reveals that
despite many attempts, but the basic thought is this: there are the original arguments against the concept framed by Hempel
explanatory structures that are neither laws nor correlations, but (1963), which de-legitimated it as a scientic strategy, depended
rather constructions that link inputs and outputs by specifying a on the idea that social science would or at least could in principle
model of how some set of causal or intentional connections to- develop general theories composed of laws. This idea is no longer
gether produce the outputs based on the inputs and is relatively plausible, and subsequent developments, including the new role
robust over some class of inputs or outputs or at least input or out- of rational choice and the problem of its status, point to some dif-
put magnitudes. This robustness makes them relatively autono- ferent conclusions about the ideal-type.
mous objects, which can be said to operate or not operate. In returning to ideal-types we enter into a morass of termino-
Mechanisms differ from causal models in that they have more con- logical confusion. The term ideal-type was originally used to con-
tent. Some of what gures as background knowledge in connec- trast to theory, which in turn was used to refer to overarching
tion with causal modeling, but is not made an explicit part of the perspectives. In terms of the neo-Kantianism in which this distinc-
models, becomes, for the proponents of mechanisms, an explicit tion was framed, the contrast makes sense: theories were concep-
part of the account of the mechanism itself. tual orderings of an entire domain of science which purported to
A typical example of a mechanism is Robert Mertons account of supply additional intelligibility by creating a logical hierarchy be-
machine politics (Merton, 1968, pp. 13036): the Bosses secure tween descriptive concepts that also makes sense of the descrip-
the support of disprivileged groups, such as recent immigrants, tive conceptsfor example the concepts in the domain of
by providing services or enabling access to public services. Support, political authority descriptions, such as sovereigntyby showing
which appears irrational, now makes sense as rational by identify- how they relate to one another. The concepts are taken to be con-
ing the processes by which each side benets. This mechanism stitutive of the domain. Ideal-types, in contrast, are not constitu-
does not automatically develop out of the conditions of exclusion tive of a domain, and do not purport to reveal the inner logic of
and so forth, but needs to be employed by a Boss, in a series of ac- relations of concepts in a domain. This original set of distinctions
tions, in order to work like any complex scheme of exchange. But it was not carried over to Anglo-American writings of the post-war
is also a model or scheme that can be employed analogically by period. The language of the discrepancy between concepts and
others in similar settings. reality, which was associated with a pass neo-Kantian epistemol-
Mechanisms in this sense have the same applies when it ap- ogy (and unintelligible within the positivist account of concept
plies character of causal models: they are there to account for in- formation that identied this term with constructing laws [Hem-
put-output relationships with similar inputs and outputs, but the pel, 1970]), was dropped by such prominent expositors as Parsons
inputs and outputs do not determine the appearance of the mech- (Parsons, 1968, p. 598). Webers specic ideal-type construc-
anism nor produce it. The same inputs can produce the same out- tions, for example of bureaucracy, were simply redescribed in the
puts by other means, and the same inputs can produce different language of behavioral science as theories, for instance Webers
outputs. The epistemic function of mechanisms is this: they are theory of bureaucracy (cf. Gouldner, 1954, pp. 1924). What
free-oating intelligibility-producing devices that ll in between has changed since the critique of the ideal-type in recent philoso-
inputs and outputs in a way that is more satisfyingmore under- phy of science is a shift from a focus on theory to a focus on mod-
standing-producingthan predictors which cannot be excluded a els. This raises another possibility: that the ideal-type is a better t
priori as no affect relations. with the methodological Zeitgeist now than it was then.
When are mechanism explanations complete? They seem to be Ideal-types are apply when they apply intelligibility-produc-
complete when the elements of the mechanism are screwed to- ing devices that idealize by simplifying a complex and messy real-
gether and work to connect the inputs to the outputs. In contexts ity. They work by picking out the elements that appear in multiple
such as epidemiology, the issue is often a matter of identifying a cases, which resemble other cases to various degrees. For Weber,
possible physical mechanism that would connect the condition the source of the concept in its application to social science, the
and the result. Further non-statistical research would be needed key to the concept is that the ideal-type itself is intelligible to a
to validate a hypothesized mechanism. If mechanisms are better greater extent than the messy raw material of disaggregated indi-
explainers than correlations, it would be odd if the elements were vidual action itself. One can speak of the medieval mind, to
merely correlations themselves. Then one would have to ask why choose one of his examples, in an ideal typical way by specifying
causal models are any different than mechanisms. One answer particular distinctive beliefs and motivations that represent the
might be that mechanisms resemble genuinely explanatory mod- vast and diverse morass of actual individual beliefs and motiva-
els that are already intelligible to us. But this would make the intel- tions of the historical persons who lived in the Middle Ages (We-
ligibility that is conferred into the intelligibility given by analogy. ber, 2012, pp. 12829). The ideal-type is an idealization in the
So the answer needs to involve the content of the mechanism, sense that it is clearer and normally simpler than the disaggregated
and some criteria for, or at least some ideas about, deciding that historical reality of belief and motivation it represents. This greater
the elements make sense and add up to something. In the case of clarity is what makes it more understandable. This higher degree of
mechanisms involving human action, the mechanism is fully intelligibility is, so to speak, lent from the ideal-typical case to the
developed only when the linkages are specied in terms of action range of cases it is designed to typify. It thus contrasts to an aver-
explanations which refer to beliefs, pro-attitudes, and relevant sit- age case: the ideal makes more sense than the cases it represents,
uational elements, and sociologists have argued for methodological rather than representing them by abstracting common properties
criteria along these lines (Hedstrm, 2008). of a class and producing a representative case by calculation.
The critique of the ideal-type was given its classical formulation
by Hempel (1963). Hempel denounced the concept as irretrievably
3. Ideal-types confused, and provided his own account of what would make it rel-
evant to scientic concept formation. He reinterpreted ideal-types
If there is nothing more to the notion of mechanisms in the con- as intuitive idealizations (1963, pp. 227, 229) to distinguish them
text of the human sciences than that they are idealizations of com- from idealizations in physics (which he suggested, using the ideal
plex sets of action patterns, we are in familiar territory: these are gas laws as a model, are ideal only in the sense that they involve
S. Turner / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538 537

extreme values not to be found in real cases), and asked about the as the rational actions of the market participant, indirectly through
circumstances that would have to obtain for these idealizations to the fact that it applies to the conduct of people in markets. The
become explanatory. Hempels phrasing here amounts to an accep- intuitive part of the idealization comes from something we al-
tance of the intelligibility-producing (or lending) character of ready understand, such as a rational choice. We can construct it
ideal-types presumably intuitions are intelligible. And this ts as an intuitive idealization, as an act of imagination, similar to
with Webers own view of these same models. The difference is the acts of imagination involved in constructing a possible cause
over how they are tied to reality. For Hempel, they are treated as to be tested as a possible confounder or common cause of a corre-
sources of hypotheses which might be made into empirical theo- lation in a causal model. What does apply mean here, and what
ries: their function is to aid in the discovery of regular connec- sort of connection to individual action is at stake? Just as we might
tions between various constituents of some social structure or conrm an imagined explanation of a persons action by subse-
process. But treating ideal-types as true subject to ceteris paribus quently encountering and directly understanding the person and
clauses, he notes, will not sufce, because these qualications their action, we can construct an ideal-type, such as the ideal-type
make the formulation irrefutable and empirically irrelevant. Con- Weber himself constructs of the person whose economic conduct
sider the claim Q will be realized whenever P is realized all other is motivated by the Protestant ethic, and indirectly understand
things being equal: the pattern of meaningful conduct that we actually encounter in
terms of this ideal-type, by directly understanding elements of
since the protective clause does not specify what factors other
their conduct that conform to the ideal-type. The same holds, of
than P have to be equal, (i.e. constant) or irrelevant if the predic-
course, for rational choice, though here the relation is more atten-
tion is q is to be warranted, the hypothesis is not capable of pre-
uated: proponents of rational choice analysis argue that the analy-
dictive application to concrete phenomena. Similarly the idea of
sis makes the actions intelligible, in the sense of rational, but claim
testing the given hypothesis becomes pointless (Hempel, 1963,
that the application is conrmed by the fact that it enables behav-
p. 225).
ior to be predicted. Nevertheless, there are, in this case as well, di-
The only thing that would make them explanatory would be for rect understandings to which these abstractions attach. Buying
them to function as theories, that is, for them to be claimed to be vegetables in a market is making a directly understood act, and if
predictive. these and similar acts were not already understandable as rational
Hempels account puts economic theory, which he concedes to choices, we would not know why the model applied here.
be the conception in the social sciences that is closest to the natu-
ral sciences, into the category of irrefutable and thus empirically 4. Is there such a thing as direct understanding?
irrelevant (1963, p. 224). Deducing results from postulates which
represent ideal forms of behavior precludes a theoretical basis for The Achilles heel of this account is the notion of direct under-
an appraisal of the idealization involved (1963, p. 228). But he standing itself. I can only note that this is not an idea that is limited
thinks that economic theory can be saved if economic theory could to Weber. Indeed, it is ubiquitous, and even central, to very differ-
be deduced as a special case (1963, p. 226) from a more general ent philosophical traditions. Wittgenstein, for example, speaks of
theory of social action, of the kind which, he optimistically noted, the natural expression of an intention (1958, p. 165, para 647)
was being proposed at the time (1963, p. 229). The effect of this as part of natural history.5 Peter Winch quotes Rush Rhees to the ef-
argument, as Hempel noted, is to collapse ideal-types into the cat- fect that we see that we understand one another, without noticing
egory of theory: Ideal constructs have the character not of con- whether our reactions tally or not. Because we agree in our reactions,
cepts in the narrower sense, but of theoretical systems (1963, p. it is possible for me to tell you something, and it is possible for you to
227). The theoretical systems are then understood in accordance teach me something (Winch, 1990, p. 85). Though Rhees does not
with the standard conception of empirical theory, and thus are say it, the reactions are natural signs, which are, in Webers terms,
testable on the basis of predictions about observable phenomena, directly understood. And there is a question, implicit in Rhees phras-
because, as special cases, their area of application is dened ing, of how one could acquire a concept without this kind of direct
(1963, pp. 228229). Open ceteris paribus clauses mean that any understanding. If we consider the meaning producing device that
predictive failure can be claimed to be the result of external con- was central to Quine, ostensive denition, we come to the same re-
ditions. This is an answer to the completion question: completion sult: what makes ostensive denition possible is the fact that I can
occurs when there is a valid empirical theory. see that your act of sticking your nger in the direction of an object
But the issue of the intuitive part of an intuitive idealization is an act of pointing, and that I can empathize with your picking out
remains. Hempel is concerned with showing that intuitive ideal- the thing being pointed to as an object, and naming it. These descrip-
izations are problematic and inferior to the ideal gas laws, so he tions are a dead-end. No additional causes or explanations are
does not tell us much about how the intuitive element works. needed or for that matter possible.
But if we acknowledge that the kind of theoretical derivation from The discussion of this problem has recently been altered by the
a general theory of human action he would prefer is not a viable discovery of mirror neurons, which operate by preconsciously acti-
option, these inferior intuitive idealizations remain as alternatives. vating the neurons used in performing an action when an action is
In Webers account, to which Hempels discussion is addressed, seen to be performed by others. This is preconceptual, and seems
ideal-types are like causal models and mechanisms. They apply also to be the basis of empathy and the recognition of intentional-
where they apply. They are already understandable, by design: ity in action (cf. Hurley & Chater, 2005; Iacoboni, 2009; Turner,
they are created as a claried form of something we already under- 2011a, 2011b). If we are to take the idea of direct understanding
stand less than clearly. They are claried versions of the kinds of seriously, the distinction between the social sciences and the natu-
understanding he describes as direct and indirect, or explanatory ral sciences with respect to where explanation ends comes down to
understanding. We understand the ideal-type itself more clearly this: explanation in the natural sciences can end with an under-
than actions themselves, because the ideal-type is puried and stood model. In the social sciences, to the extent that models are
simplied, but clearer. We understand the things it applies to, such concerned with conduct that is subject to direct understanding,

5
G. E. M. Anscombe complained about these passages, which she regarded as a slip (1957, p. 5). But they were no slip at all: the idea of natural signs of intention pervades the
texts, as David Rubinstein has shown (2004).
538 S. Turner / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013) 532538

there will always be an additional question: does the model t with Hempel, C. (1963). Typological methods in the natural and social sciences. In N.
Maurice (Ed.), Philosophy of the social science: A reader (pp. 210230). New York:
our direct understanding of the conduct which is being modeled?
Random House (rst published 1952).
The question does not itself imply a general claim that tting with Hempel, C. (1970). On the standard conception of scientic theories. In M. Radner
our direct understanding is a requirement for accepting the model: & S. Winokur (Eds.). Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science: Analyses of
it may be that our direct understanding needs to be set aside for theories and methods of physics and psychology (Vol. IV, pp. 142163).
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
purposes of predictive accuracy, simplicity, or any of a number of Hurley, S., & Chater, N. (Eds.). (2005). Perspectives on imitation: From neuroscience to
other goals, as with science and perception generally. It may also social science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
be that the intellectual operations that employ the results of neuron Iacoboni, M. (2009). Mirroring people: The science of empathy and how we connect
with others. New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.
mirroring, such as simulation, operate under cognitive limitations, Julious, S. A., & Mullee, M. A. (1994). Confounding and Simpsons paradox. British
such as the illusion of conscious will (Wegner, 2002), limitations Medical Journal, 309(6967), 14801481.
which are reproduced in our understanding of others. But the fact Laudan, L. (1981). Science and hypothesis. Dordrecht, Boston, London: D. Reidel
Publishing.
that models in the social sciences are subject to the problem of Merton, R. K. (1968). Social theory and social structure. New York: Free Press
application, the fact that they apply when they apply, and not (previous editions 1949, 1957).
universally, means that social science connects to its subject matter McKim, V. R., & Turner, S. P. (1997). Causality in crisis: Statistical methods and the
search for causal knowledge in the social sciences. Notre Dame, IN: University of
in a different way. The need for background knowledge involving Notre Dame Press.
intentions and beliefs, the need to explain why a model applies or Parsons, T. (1968). The structure of social thought: A study in social theory and special
fails to apply to a particular case of conduct, and the role of inten- reference to a group of recent European writers. New York: Free Press. First
published 1937.
tional elements in mechanisms, as well as the question of
Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge
whether a particular description of an action ts, all require that University Press.
models attach at some point to direct understanding. Rubinstein, D. (2004). Language games and natural reactions. Journal for the Theory
of Social Behavior, 34(1), 5572.
Salihu, H. M., Alio, A. P., Wilson, R. E., Sharma, P. P., Kirby, R. S., & Alexander, G. R.
References (2008). Obesity and extreme obesity: New insights into the blackwhite
disparity in neonatal mortality. Obstetrics & Gynecology, 111(6), 14101416.
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell. Simpson, E. H. (1951). The interpretation of interaction in contingency tables.
Blyth, C. R. (1972). On Simpsons paradox and the sure-thing principle. Journal of the Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series B (Methodological), 13(2), 238241.
American Statistical Association, 67(338), 364366. Turner, S. (Ed.). (2010). Causality (4 Vols.). London: Sage.
Charig, C. R. (1995). Comment on: Confounding and Simpsons paradox. British Turner, S. (2011a). Webs of belief or practices: The problem of understanding.
Medical Journal, 310(6975), 329. European Journal of Sociology, 3, 397421.
Feest, U. (Ed.). (2010). Historical perspectives on Erklren and Verstehen. Heidelberg: Turner, S. (2011b). Collingwood and Weber vs. Mink: History after the cognitive
Springer. turn. Journal of the Philosophy of History, 5, 230260.
Fisher, R. A. (1958). Cigarettes, cancer, and statistics. The Centennial Review, II(2), Weber, M. (2012). The Objectivity of knowledge in social science and social
151156. policy. In Hans Henik Bruun & Sam Whimster (Eds.), Max Weber: Collected
Fisher, R. A. (1959). Smoking: The cancer controversy. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd. methodological writings (Hans Henrick Bruun, Trans.) (pp. 100138). London:
<http://www.york.ac.uk/depts/maths/histstat/smoking.htm> Accessed Routledge (rst published 1904).
27.03.12.. Weber, M. (1978). In R. Guenther & W. Claus (Eds.). Economy and society: An outline
Freedman, D. A. (2005). Statistical models: Theory and practice. Cambridge: of interpretive sociology (3 Vols.). Berkeley: University of California Press (rst
Cambridge University Press. published 1968).
Glymour, C. (1983). Social science and social physics. Behavioral Sciences, 28, Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
126134. Winch, P. (1990a). The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. Atlantic
Glymour, C., Scheines, R., Spirtes, P., & Kelly, K. (1987). Discovering causal structure: Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press (rst published 1958).
Articial intelligence, philosophy of science, and statistical modeling. Orlando, FL: Winch, P. (1990b). Preface to the second edition. In The idea of a social science and its
Academic Press, Inc.. relation to philosophy (pp. ixxviii). Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Gouldner, A. W. (1954). Patterns of industrial democracy. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.) (3rd
Hedstrom, P., & Swedberg, R. (Eds.). (1998). Social mechanisms: An analytical ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall (rst published 1953).
approach to social theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Woodward, J. (2005). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford:
Hedstrm, P. (2005). Dissecting the social: On the principles of analytical sociology. Oxford University Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Woodward, J. (2007). Causal models in the social sciences. In S. Turner & M. Risjord
Hedstrm, P. (2008). Studying mechanisms to strengthen causal inferences in (Eds.), The handbook of philosophy of anthropology and sociology (pp. 157210).
quantitative research. In J. M. Box-Steffensmeier, H. E. Brady, & D. Collier (Eds.), Amsterdam: Elsevier.
The Oxford handbook of political methodology (pp. 319335). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi