Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 13

New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

www.elsevier.com / locate / newar

Cosmology and local physics


George F.R. Ellis*
University of Cape Town, Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics, Private Bag, 7701 Rondebosch, South Africa

Abstract

The major thrust of present day scientific cosmology is that of examining the effect of local physical laws on the
large-scale structure of the cosmos. However there has also from the earliest times been a counter theme: the study of the
way that global properties of the universe can influence its local properties. The purpose of the present paper is to revisit this
topic.
2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.

1. Introduction (CBR) (Weinberg, 1972; Schramm and Turner,


1998)a theme that Dennis Sciama found most
The major thrust of present day scientific cosmolo- exciting, and contributed to in his inimitable way
gy is that of examining the effect of local physical (Sciama, 1971a,b). And it has reached its climax in
laws on the large-scale structure of the cosmos. This the understanding, following Alan Guths innovative
started with Einsteins application of the local law of realisation of the power of the idea of an inflationary
gravitation, expressed via the Einstein field equa- era of expansion in the early universe caused by
tions, to determine space-time structure in the large energy-condition violating quantum fields (Guth,
(Wald, 1984; dInverno, 1992; Hawking and Ellis, 1981; Blau and Guth, 1987), of how particle physics
1973). This then led to the FriedmannLematre processes in the very early universe could be of
Eddington demonstration of how these equations major importance in determining the large-scale
imply an evolution of the universe (Ellis, 1989, structure of the universe today (Gibbons et al., 1983;
1990), followed by the prediction, on the basis of Kolb and Turner, 1990; Peacock, 1999; Liddle and
classic gravitational theory, of a beginning to the Lyth, 2000).
universe at a space-time singularity (Raychaudhuri, However, there has also from the earliest times
1955; Ehlers, 1961; Hawking and Ellis, 1973; Tipler been a counter theme: the study of the way that
et al., 1980). This thrust attained new power through global properties of the universe can influence its
the understanding of how nuclear physics processes local properties. This was particularly embodied in
in the hot early expansion phase of the universe Machs principle, and was always dear to Dennis
would lead to synthesis of light elements out of heart, inspired particularly by his discussions with
primordial constituents, providing an explanation Fred Hoyle, Tommy Gold, and Herman Bondi when
both for the origin of the light elements and the they were together in Cambridge in the 1950s. He
existence of the 3K Cosmic Blackbody Radiation devoted much thought to this topic, resulting in his
famous vector gravitational model (Sciama, 1953)
*Tel.: 127-21-650-3192; fax: 127-21-650-2334. and various popular books (Sciama, 1959, 1969). In
E-mail address: ellis@maths.uct.ac.za (G.F.R. Ellis). his writings on these topics, he consistently empha-

1387-6473 / 02 / $ see front matter 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.
PII: S1387-6473( 02 )00234-8
646 G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

sized the interconnectedness of the universe (Sciama, global physics; and the relation between initial
1959): each part interacting with each other part, and conditions and local physics. This paper is dedicated
with very distant parts being as important as local to the memory of Dennis, who was an inspiring
regions in these interactions, a prime example being teacher, enthusiastic colleague, and good friend 1 .
Olbers paradox (Bondi, 1960). Because of this
interconnection, in principle one can obtain some
understanding of the whole from any part; indeed if
2. Olbers calculation
one was clever enough and understood enough
physics, one could in principle completely deduce
The basic point of Olbers paradox (Why is the
the nature of the whole from a sufficient study of its
sky dark at night?), actually developed by Halley, is
parts. An example of this line of argument is the
the need for integration over all very distant sources
suggestion that one could, in principle, deduce the
in determining the intensity of integrated radiation
expansion of the universe, and even the approximate
from astronomical sources. These distant sources
value of the Hubble constant, from the existence of
cannot be neglected in flat space-time, because their
bus tickets.
number goes up as r 2 and this compensates for the
A major further theme is the uniqueness of the
decrease in flux from each source, which goes down
universe, which is what gives cosmology its specific
like 1 /r 2 , where r is the standard radial distance in
unique nature as a science (Sciama, 1959; Ellis,
Minkowski space. Doing the calculation in Rober-
1999). Because of this uniqueness, one runs into
tsonWalker universes with r chosen as the area
major problems in distinguishing boundary condi-
distance gives the same result, and the reciprocity
tions from physical laws. What appears to be an
theorem (Ellis, 1971) shows this will in fact be true
inviolable physical law may just be a consequence of
in any curved space-time, for it is equivalent to the
the particular boundary conditions that happen to
result that total intensity I of radiation received from
hold in this particular universe. This might even be
a source (that is, flux per unit solid angle) is
true for some of the apparently most fundamental of
independent of the sources area distance; it will vary
laws at the macroscopic scale, such as the second
as
law of thermodynamics and its associated arrows of
time; but we cannot test this supposition, for we 1
cannot re-run the universe, nor can we investigate I 5 ]]]4 IG
(1 1 z)
any other universe. Conversely, one can propose that
if the universe were different, the laws of physics where IG its bolometric surface brightness, and z its
would be different. This leads to the idea that as the redshift, while the pointwise specific intensity In of
universe is changing, maybe the laws of nature are radiation received (the intensity per unit frequency
changing with it, or at least this might be true for the range) in direction u, f is
values of some of the fundamental constants of
physics, for example the gravitational constant ( (n (1 1 z))
In (u, f ) 5 ]]]] I (u, f ) (1)
(Dirac, 1938). From this line of argument follows (1 1 z)3 G
the need to consider seriously alternative physics as
well as alternative boundary conditions when we where ( (n ) is the source spectrum and IG (u, f ) its
consider the relation between local physics and surface brightness in the direction of observation.
cosmology. Hence, in an expanding universe, very distant
Many years ago, Dennis and I jointly wrote a sources at high z appear much fainter than nearby
survey article on these global-to-local relations (Ellis ones, and so the sky can appear dark even though
and Sciama, 1972).The purpose of the present paper
is to revisit these topics, and comment on what
progress has been made in the intervening years. I 1
See Roger Penroses article, pp. 314315 in Ellis et al. (1993),
deal in turn with Olbers paradox; Machs principle; for a nice account both of Dennis infectious passion for physics,
the arrow of time; the framework for relating local to and his belief in the importance of non-local effects.
G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657 647

every line of sight eventually intersects a source of radiation, because the universe is opaque at earlier
some kind. times, and hence this matter comprises the visual
However, as emphasized by Harrison (1987, horizon (Ellis and Stoeger, 1988). This is the proper
2000), that is not the whole story: in the end, the endpoint of the integral in the Olbers calculation,
dark night sky is the result of the fact that there is for we cannot receive radiation from more distant
not enough radiation in the universe to generate a matter. The temperature of this surface is about
bright night sky. Most of the lines of sight from the T e 5 3000 K, and it emits black body radiation at
earth effectively end up on the surface of last that temperature because the matter and radiation are
scattering of radiation after the hot big bang, because very close to equilibrium at that epoch; by Eq. (1)
although there are numerous intervening galaxies, that radiation is received as blackbody radiation at a
they are mainly transparent (this is clear from both temperature To 5 T e (1 1 z)21 where z is the redshift
lensing studies and QSO Lyman forest observations). of emission. Because of the redshift factor of about
1000 for that matter, we receive black body radiation
at about 3000 K / 100053 K from that surface. There
2.1. Discrete sources and background radiation are small variations to this temperature over the sky
due to gravitational fields and velocity effects, and
Thus, the present day astronomical version of the study of these anisotropies is a major part of present
Olbers studies consists of two parts. The first is the day cosmology (Kolb and Turner, 1990; Peacock,
study of the integrated radiation from all individually 1999; Liddle and Lyth, 2000; Bridle et al., 2000;
unresolvable sources, resulting in a predicted spec- Jaffe et al., 2000).
trum of background radiation at all wavelengths Thus, in the real universe, the Olbers integral
coming from these sources, in particular, optical, does not extend to infinity, and 3 K is the tempera-
radio, and X-ray backgrounds. The detailed theory of ture of the dominant radiation today, and hence is the
this background then resides in detailed astrophysical temperature we measure for most of the night sky
speculations about these sources and their evolution (and for the day sky as well, away from the sun).
(Longair, 1995; Pozetti and Madau, 2000); observa- That temperature is not due to discrete sources, but
tions are incomplete, because of galactic and inter- rather is due to the primeval radiation from the hot
galactic absorption. big bang.
The second part is a dominant theme of present The further new point is the realisation that this
day theoretical and observational cosmology: namely calculation is of considerable importance, apart from
prediction and observation of the CBR spectrum and its use in helping us determine cosmological parame-
anisotropies, resulting from us seeing the point by ters. It implies that the earth is in contact with a
point brightness of the surface of last scattering of thermal reservoir at a temperature of 3 K, which is
this radiation (Kolb and Turner, 1990; Peacock, the sink into which we dispose of our excess
1999; Liddle and Lyth, 2000). Observations provide entropy, generated by all the processes of life. That
an angular power spectrum, and theory relates that to sink is essential to the thermodynamic functioning of
the formation of structure in the expanding universe; the biosphere, and hence to the existence of life on
comparison of theoretical predictions with the ob- earth, for the biosphere functions by receiving the
servations then enable us to get tight limits on black body radiation from the sun, using it to run
cosmological parameters (Bridle et al., 2000; Jaffe et biological and atmospheric processes, and then
al., 2000). Thus, this can legitimately be regarded as radiating the waste heat away to the sky (Penrose,
the culmination of Olbers investigations into the 1989a). If the temperature of the sky were much
integrated radiation emitted by all sources in the higher, and certainly if it were above 300 K, life like
universe. The source here is the uniformly distribut- ours on earth would not be possible. Thus from this
ed matter at the surface of last scattering, which at viewpoint, the reason we observe the night sky to be
later times will either be incorporated into galaxies dark is that if that were not true, we would not be
or will reside in intergalactic space. It is the furthest here to see it! This is of course part of the anthropic
matter we can see by any kind of electromagnetic universe argument, briefly touched on below.
648 G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

2.2. The gravitational version Thus, in effect one renormalizes by omitting the
divergent integral due to a uniform background, and
The same issue of course arises in Newtonian only calculates the remnant effect due to inhomo-
gravitational theory, for that too is an inverse square geneities superimposed on this uniform background
law. The present-day form of this problem arises in [this is implied in the rescaling of variables relative
studies of the large-scale motions of matter induced to the background expansion that is used in the
by the gravitational field of large-scale inhomogen- standard calculations of peculiar velocities, see for
eities in the universe, such as the Great Attractor example Peebles (1971, 1980)]. Thus in this context,
[see for example the POTENT series of studies convergence means continuing the integral until the
(Dekel, 1994)]. In any particular case, the question effects of all more distant matter are isotropic and
here is, has the integral for the gravitational potential cancel each other out when one does the required
causing the acceleration and hence inducing these vector addition of resulting gravitational forces. It is
velocities, converged or not? Do we need to consider assumed here that the further out matter is indeed
further-out matter in our calculation of these inte- isotropically distributed about us on the largest
grals? scales; and this supposition receives some support
There are however, some major differences from from the high degree of CBR isotropy we measure.
the Olbers calculation. Firstly, the integral here is An issue that could perhaps still be reflected on is to
carried out in spacelike surfaces rather than on the what degree the success of the resulting calculations
past light cone, for it corresponds to the Newtonian of large scale velocities can be taken as providing
limit of the relativistic equations, where the con- evidence for isotropy of the universe outside our
straint equations are equivalent to relations that must visual horizon, and perhaps even outside our particle
be satisfied at constant time (i.e. at each instant) in horizon. This question, alluded to in Ellis and
the expanding universe. How this is compatible with Sciama (1972), remains open. The problem is that
the relativistic nature of the field equations was locally we can only measure the total integrated
discussed in Ellis and Sciama (1972). In essence: effect on the motion of matter, and it does not seem
these initial conditions have to satisfy constraint that one can separate out the contributions to the
equations, such as the Hamiltonian constraints, effect from shells of matter around us at different
which are usually expressed as instantaneous con- distances.
ditions. This requirement has to be built into the
initial conditions for the universe, which raises
significant conceptual problems in some cases. Once 3. Machs principle
they are satisfied, they will remain satisfied because
of the consistency of the time evolution equations This discussion leads naturally on to Machs
with the constraint equations (see Maartens, 1997; famous conjecture, largely motivated by his position
Friedrich and Nagy, 1999) for explicit demonstration in the philosophical debates about relative versus
of this consistency in particular cases). absolute motion, that the origin of inertia is interac-
Secondly, in contrast to the Olbers case just tions with very distant matter (Sciama, 1969, 1959;
discussed, there is no natural cut-off to the integral in Bondi, 1960). This issue remains as open today as
this caseone must in principle extend it to spatial ever.
infinity, if the universe is indeed spatially homoge- On the one hand, there are a variety of Anti-
neousand then it diverges! (this is indeed the Machian solutions of Einsteins Field Equations
reason that Newtonian cosmology was not arrived at (EFE)non-singular solutions of the vacuum equa-
until some decades after relativistic cosmological
tions (Oszvath and Schucking, 1962)suggesting to
models were available). But this is compensated for many that these equations do not by themselves
by the third point: although the gravitational field in incorporate Machs principle, despite Einsteins hope
principle diverges, its local effect is of a vector that this would be so (Wheeler, 1968). This kind of
nature (causing a vectorial acceleration of matter), view is supported by cosmological analyses showing
and hence the effects from opposite directions can- that distant galaxies are at rest in the local inertial
cel. rest-frame if the cosmological vorticity is very close
G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657 649

to zero (Heckmann and Schucking, 1956; Ehlers, Machian issues arise in each case: the degree to
1961)and there clearly are both Newtonian and which each is affected by very distant as opposed to
relativistic cosmological models in which this is not local matter. And here an important point arises:
true. The implication is that Machian solutions are a tensor modes are determined by distant matter,
subset of all solutions of the EFE, characterized by because the corresponding characteristic velocity is
some suitable kind of boundary conditions, for the speed of light (gravitational waves propagate at
examples Raines isotropy conditions (Raine, 1981) speed c), but in the case of pressure-free matter (the
resulting from an analysis of solutions of the remark- recent universe) the characteristic velocities of the
able SciamaWaylenGilman (SWG) integral scalar and vector modes are zero (Ehlers et al., 1987;
formulation of the EFE (Sciama et al., 1969). This van Elst and Ellis, 1999, 2000)so they are only
then comes close to supporting Penroses proposal directly affected by nearby matter. However as
(Penrose, 1989a; Penrose, 1979) of the necessity of mentioned in the previous section, this result holds
isotropic singularities at the Big Bang in order that only once one has factored out the background
ordinary thermodynamic properties can hold, solu- geometry and dynamicsand it is precisely that full
tions allowing such singularities being studied in effect (incorporating integrals over all matter) that is
some detail by Tod and Newman (1993). the concern of Machs principle, not just the per-
On the other hand, some peoplenotably Barbour turbation effects around the background geometry.
and Pfister (1995)maintain that Einsteins equa- That is of course both the fatal attraction and flaw in
tions already incorporate the full meaning of what the basic ideait is fundamental in its nature
Mach intended, and there is no need for further (determining the nature of all inertial effects) but
conditions on the solutions in order to have a beyond experimental testing in its full extent (pre-
Machian character. This view is imbedded in a much cisely because of that nature). Overall, the idea
larger philosophical position supporting the relativity remains a source of both inspiration, and irritation,
of all measurements, and suggesting that the passage because it is so hard to tie it down satisfactorilysee
of time is an illusiona position that has received p. 530 of Barbour and Pfister (1995) for 21 different
little support from other quarters. formulations of the idea!
A recent account of the debate on Machs Princi-
ple is given in Barbour and Pfister (1995). This idea
has of course been of enormous importance in the 4. Arrows of time
evolution of the theory of general relativity. Three
related ideas are worth mentioning as being of some One of the most intractable and fundamental
practical interest. problems in physics is the relation between revers-
Firstly, there is the idea of dragging of inertial ible fundamental (micro) physics laws, and irrevers-
frames occurring in rotating solutions of the EFE, ible macro-physics effects and associated phe-
for example the Kerr rotating black hole solutions nomenological laws, with the various arrows of time
(see Section 5 of Barbour and Pfister, 1995). This (radiation, thermodynamical, quantum mechanical,
then ties Machian ideas in to the physics of accretion biological for example) dominant in real physical
disks in rotating black holes, albeit in a rather weak applications (Davies, 1977; Zeh, 1989). It seems to
way. Secondly, there have been a series of accurate be agreed by most that in one way or another this
experiments relating to Machs principle (see Section major discrepancy must reside in the difference
6 of Barbour and Pfister, 1995), based on links between initial conditions and final conditions in the
between Machian ideas and testable features of local universe, which effectively disallow half of the
physics. And thirdly, there is the important distinc- solutions that are in principle allowed by the time-
tion made in studies of cosmological perturbations reversible microphysical equations (see e.g. Ellis and
(Bardeen, 1980; Bardeen et al., 1983) between Sciama, 1972; Penrose, 1989a). There is however an
scalar, vector, and tensor gravitational modes, and alternative view that maybe we are mistaken about
their relation to large scale structure formation and the fundamental laws of physicsmaybe they should
associated velocities (scalar modes), vorticity (vector be formulated in a fundamentally time-irreversible
modes), and gravitational waves (tensor modes). way (Prigogine, 1996). This view has not attracted
650 G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

as much a following, despite the fact that the the idea of an inflationary universe and the initial
irreversibility of physics is clearly already evident in conditions for physical fields required in order to
the quantum measurement process (Penrose, 1989a), obtain a macroscopic second law of thermodynamics
and so is not solely a macro-physical phenomenon. that agrees with the direction of the inflationary
It is clear that the arrow of time is closely related expansion (Penrose, 1989a,b). He argues that this
to the definition and evolution of entropy. The will work only if the initial state is very special
relation of a phenomenological (macro) definition to relative to a random state, where many black holes
microscopic properties is obtained via a process of might occur with huge initial entropies. Hence, the
coarse graining (Penrose, 1981), through which the universe must start off from a highly special state
macro-description (given only in terms of macro- corresponding to small Weyl tensor magnitudes and
scopic variables) explicitly loses information that is an initially isotropic expansion, if the arrow of time
available in the detailed micro description (given in is to work out in terms of the gravitational fieldin
terms of microscopic variables); and then the basic contrast to the random initial conditions suggested by
quantitative question is how many different micro- many theories of inflation, for example chaotic
states correspond to the same macro-state. A macro- inflation (Linde, 1990). It is something of a mystery
state is more probable if it corresponds to a greater that this argument does not seem to be given the
number of different micro states, and time evolution attention it deserves. This may have more to do with
will tend to go from a less probable to a more the sociology of science than the merits of the
probable state, defined in this way (Penrose, 1989a). theory. The strength of his remarks is strengthened
So far so good; this can be made precise in terms of by an appreciation of the trans-Planckian problem of
Boltzmanns H-theorem, proving the second law of some inflationary cosmology models (Martin and
thermodynamics for suitably defined entropy (de- Brandenberger, 2000): namely that the perturbations
fined as an integral over microstate occupancies) on that are supposed to lead, on the inflationary view, to
the basis of microscopic physical laws (see Ehlers, some large scale astronomical structures, can lie
1961 for a beautiful derivation of this result in the deep within the Planck era, where the linearised
case of relativistic kinetic theory). But the problem is gravitational theory that is normally used simply
that this argument applies equally in both directions does not apply; and indeed we might expect some
of time: it completely fails to determine which is the kind of space-time foam description to be accurate.
forward direction of time. It predicts the entropy will Amplifying such inhomogeneity through inflationary
increase in both directions of time! The only plaus- expansion to large scales would lead to anything but
ible basis so far for making a choice, is that the local a smooth structure. This issue remains unresolved.
direction of time is determined by boundary con-
ditions on the physical equations at the beginning 4.1. Gravitation and entropy
(and perhaps also at the end) of the evolution of the
universe (Ellis and Sciama, 1972; Penrose, 1989a). A crucial element that is missing from our under-
This seems to be the logical explanationbut how standing of the growth of structure in the expanding
this master arrow of time uniquely determines the universe, is a suitable definition of the entropy of an
directions of each of the separate physical and arbitrary gravitational field. Of course a huge amount
biological arrows still needs convincing explication. has been written on the concept of entropy of a black
This is one of the most important unsolved problems hole (De Witt and de Witt, 1973; Bekenstein, 2000);
in present day physics, for it represents a major gulf but that does not deal with the fundamentally
between the macro-physics that dominates everyday important question of what entropy is associated with
life, and the microphysics that (on a reductionist inhomogeneities of the gravitational field when no
viewpoint) is supposed to explain that macrophysics. black holes are involved.
The small amount of attention paid to it is presumab- The importance of this topic is that it underlies the
ly due to the intractability of the problem. growth of astronomical structure (galaxies, stars, and
The important application of this idea is in terms planets) in the universe, which in turn allows our
of the questions raised by Roger Penrose regarding own existence. If you take the statements about
G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657 651

entropy in almost every elementary textbook, and obtaining local definitions of the mass of an isolated
indeed most advanced ones, they are contradicted system in general relativity. Recent work by As-
when the gravitational field is turned on and is htekar et al. (2000) may open the way here, and that
significant (Ellis, 1995). For example, in the famous in turn might provide a new approach to the entropy
case of the gas container split into two halves by a issue, because of the well-known relations between
barrier, with all the gas initially on one side, the entropy and energy on the one hand, and between
standard statement is that the gas then spreads out to mass and energy on the other.
uniformly fill the whole container when the barrier is This issue remains one of the most significant
removed, with the entropy correspondingly increas- unsolved problems in classical gravitational theory,
ing. But when gravitation is turned on, the final state for as explained above, even though this is not
is with all the matter clumped in a blob somewhere usually made explicit, it underlies the spontaneous
in the container, rather than being uniformly spread formation of structure in the universethe ability of
out. This is related to the issue of the negative the universe to act as a self-organizing system
specific-heat behaviour of gravitational systems, and where ever more complex structures evolve by
the associated gravithermal catastrophe (Lynden- natural processes, starting off with structure formed
Bell and Wood, 1967; Lynden-Bell and Lynden-Bell, by the action of the gravitational field. If solved in a
1977). The question then is whether there is a generic way, it would also presumably lead to
definition of entropy for the gravitational field itself another view of the nature of black hole entropy, for
(as distinct from the matter filling space-time), and if it would certainly have to tie in to that concept in a
so if the second law of thermodynamics applies to congruent way. It would presumably also relate to
the system when this gravitational entropy is taken the idea of the coarse graining of the gravitational
into account. The answers are far from obvious. field, and hence to the whole difficult averaging
Dyson (1971a,b) claims there is no such entropy, problem in general relativity theory (Ellis, 1984),
while Penrose (1979, 1989a) claims there is, and that which may not be approachable in a covariant and
it is related to some integral of the Weyl tensor on gauge invariant manner (cf. Boersma, 1998; Ellis and
spacelike surfaces. A flurry of recent work has given Matravers, 1995).
local definitions of gravitational entropy in relation Given a suitable definition of gravitational entropy
to the idea of holography in the expanding universe and a proof that it has the required local properties,
(Bousso, 1999), but that literature has not shown the further issue that will remain is how this entropy
how this entropy behaves as structure is formed. can tie in to the master arrow of time given by the
Tavakol and Ellis (unpublished) have conjectured expansion of the universe. At one level, implicit
that gravitational entropy is related to the spatial answers to this are given by the standard theory of
divergence of the electric part Eac 5 Cabcd u b u d of the structure formation in the expanding universe (Gib-
Weyl tensor measured by an observer moving with bons et al., 1983; Kolb and Turner, 1990; Peacock,
4-velocity u a , which certainly seems to have some of 1999; Liddle and Lyth, 2000); however, firstly this
the desired properties, because of the Bianchi identi- has not been explicitly related to a general theory of
ty gravitational entropy, and secondly, as reported
above, Penrose has raised major questions about
1
= a Eab 5 ] =b r whether the usual explanation in terms of an in-
3
flationary model will in fact work, when one looks at
relating that divergence to the spatial gradient of the its implications for entropy (Penrose, 1989b).
matter density r (in linearised gravitational theory),
where = is the covariant derivative operator ortho-
gonal to u. However, that work is incompletewe 5. Finite infinity and local physics
have not succeeded in showing that some suitable
function of this quantity has all the desirable prop- In looking at the evolution of isolated systems,
erties for a gravitational entropy. Of course the such as the solar system, our Galaxy, or the local
problem is related to the well-known difficulties in group of galaxies, it is common to use the idea of
652 G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

asymptotic flatness as the setting for the local


Schucking, 1954), but raises many interesting issues.
system, and to put boundary conditions on local One needs a clear definition of when the bounding
physical fields at infinity. This has been taken to a surface lies in an asymptotically flat region around
very high level of sophistication (Ehlers, 1979), the isolated system but at a finite distance from it,
particularly by use of Penroses concept of confor- which can be defined by requiring: (i) existence of
mal infinity (Penrose, 1963; Hawking and Ellis, suitable local almost-flat coordinates in a neigh-
1973). But that description makes it very difficult to bourhood of the surface, and (ii) limits on the
look at the relation between such isolated systems amount of matter and radiation present there. In the
and the universe in which they are imbedded, cosmological context, (iii) the velocity of the surface
precisely because it ignores the structure of that must not be greatly different from that of the cosmic
universe. In the real universe, there will probably be background radiation, as otherwise that radiation will
no asymptotically flat region at or near infinity, for be experienced as high intensity radiation as it
the real universe is almost certainly not asymp- crosses ^, and so the system will no longer be
totically Minkowskian at very large distances, and isolated. As regards (i), we might for example
indeed it may not be spatially infinite. require the existence of an atlas including a set of
This led me some years ago to ask the question: local coordinates x i 5 (t, r, u, f ) in a region U
How far away is an effective infinity to use in 5 I1 3 I2 3 S2 where I1 5 (t 1 , t 2 ), I2 5 (r 1 , r 2 ) are
discussing boundary conditions for local physical finite intervals with r * [ I2 , such that (a) in U, the
systems of this kind? Since that was written, metric takes the almost-flat form
answers have been given for the solar system
(Smoluchowski and Torbett, 1984; Allen et al., ds 2 5 2 dt 2 1 dr 2 1 r 2 (du 2 1 sin 2u df 2 )
2000) (between 1.5 and 3 light years) and for the 1 h ab (x j ) dx a dx b , uh ab u < ugab u (2)
local group of galaxies (van den Bergh, 1999) (about
1.2 Mpc). So the obvious proposal (Ellis, 1984) is (b) U surrounds the finite system (either the coordi-
that we should put boundary conditions on all fields nates x i in fact cover a larger region of space-time,
at that distance, rather than at infinity itself, leading including the isolated system and it centre, but is
to the concept of a finite infinity ^ : a smooth only asymptotically flat in the region U; or other
timelike surface at a large but finite distance r * from coordinates cover the interior of U and include the
the centre of the system considered, separating it system), and (c) the exterior universe lies outside U
from the surrounding universe, and lying in an (usually this will require a separate coordinate sys-
almost-flat space-time region at that distance. Then tem).
incoming and outgoing radiation conditions can be Such a surface will not be uniquely defined; if one
imposed on that surface ^, rather than at infinity or such surface exists there will be an allowed family of
conformal infinity ( as is usual (Ehlers, 1979). One such surfaces, related to each other by a rather large
can then examine the physics of the interaction group of transformationsfrom (i), they must not be
between the interior and exterior regions by relating too far out, nor too far in; from (iii), their velocities
each to energy, momentum, matter, and any fields must not be too different from each other; and they
that cross this surface. This timelike surface will, in should be suitably smooth; apart from this, they can
conformally flat coordinates, be an extremely long, be chosen arbitrarily. One might allow a density
thin tube (the radius of the tube for the solar system discontinuity across this surface, as in the case of the
will be about one light year, but we will want to Swiss-cheese models, in order to match a fluid-filled
consider incoming and outgoing radiation for many exterior to a vacuum interior; but that will need to be
hundreds of years when we look for example at the handled with caution (and would require a modi-
stability of the solar system). fication of the formulation of condition (i) given
This idea has not been fully developed yet, except above). In that case, the exterior boundary must be
to some degree in the case of the swiss-cheese chosen as comoving. The obvious choice of velocity
models of spherical inhomogeneities of the gravita- for this family of surfaces will be that velocity field
tional field (Einstein and Strauss, 1945a,b; which sets the microwave background anisotropy
G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657 653

dipole to zero; this will be comoving with the matter example (this kind of description is already implicit
to a high degree of accuracy, and the degree to in the Olbers type of calculations that are carried
which this is not true will be an important statement out). A useful step in this regard is a paper by Hogan
about the nature of the interaction of the chosen and Ellis (1991) determining the radiation part of the
system with the universe. electromagnetic field at such a surface at a finite
To develop the dynamical implications of this distance from the source, in a flat background space-
idea, one needs to develop the boundary value time (and hence, by conformal transformation, in
problem for all the fields involved, generalizing the
FriedmannLematreRobertsonWalker [FLRW]
usual proofs to a surface with both spacelike and geometries). This is in contrast to usual definitions of
timelike segments. In a major step forward, Friedrich the radiation part of the electromagnetic field, which
and Nagy (1999) have developed this boundary use a limit at infinity. It would be useful to carry out
value problem for the case of the vacuum gravita- similar calculations for the gravitational field, proba-
tional field. They did not give a physical interpreta- bly best based on the SWG integral formalism
tion to the mathematical variables defined in their mentioned above (Sciama et al., 1969).
theorems, but such an interpretation should be forth- This may also be the best setting for numerical
coming in terms of a preferred family of observers calculations for isolated systems, which often talk
associated with the allowed family of surfaces ^, about integrating to infinity, but in most cases do
particularly when the outer region is defined in a nothing of the sort 2 . As in the rest of theoretical
cosmological context. They also did not consider the physics, it would be advantageous to have a theoret-
implications when this surface lies in an almost flat ical framework that corresponds more closely to
region, as for example specified by Eq. (2) above. actual calculationsnamely an integration to a sur-
The further challenge then will be to use a suitable face at a finite distance from the centre of coordi-
definition of mass defined from data on this surface nates. It is usual to make that surface a null surface;
(cf. e.g. Brown and York, 1993; Hawking and the suggestion here is that it would be better to make
Horowitz, 1996) and then generalize to this setting it timelike, corresponding to the region in the real
the results by Bondi et al., Sachs, and Newman and universe where the exterior is physically separated
Penrose relating incoming and outgoing radiation at from the local system. A null surface does not work
infinity to mass loss and the news function (Pen- well in this context, hence the importance of
rose and Rindler, 1988). Furthermore, the famous Friderichs and Nagys work on the mixed initial
positive mass theorems (Flaherty, 1983) should also value problem. It might be useful seeing if a
be generalized to this case. These will be more conformal version of their theory would be suitable
complex than the existing proofs with the limit taken for numerical work.
at infinity, but in my view the added complication Overall, the point is that no system can be
will not be gratuitous, but will be essential to the completely isolated; the context suggested here
physics of the situation. Additionally, the impact of allows one to monitor the degree to which any local
the constraints on the allowed incoming and outgo- system is indeed isolated, and to examine the nature
ing radiation needs careful analysis (van Elst and of its interaction with the external worldthat is,
Ellis, 2000). This will then provide a rigorous setting with the rest of the universe. The criterion for
for discussing the real physics of the interaction of isolation will be a real physical one in terms of
the interior and the exterior regions, with physical limits on incoming and outgoing effects (matter,
estimates of the magnitude of incoming and outgoing radiation of all kinds, and tidal forces) across the
radiation that crosses this surface, and limits on these separating surface ^, rather than statements on limits
quantities in order that the system can indeed be at an unattainable infinity, as has been customary up
regarded as physically isolated. to now (for example in studies of gravitational
This will then be the proper setting in which to radiation and of the Hawking effect). In my view this
look at the relation of local physics to cosmology,
and hence to look at the other questions discussed in 2

But see Hubner for a conformal method that integrates to null
this paperthe Mach and Arrow of Time issues, for infinity.
654 G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

will make the analysis much more useful, and 6. Initial conditions and local physics
genuinely physical based in terms of relating to real
estimates of the magnitude of these effects. The The setting just described enables one to dis-
difference corresponds to the transition in mathe- tinguish matter and radiation that crosses the surface
matics between calculus based on infinite limits, and ^, in either an ingoing or outgoing direction, from
analysis based on and d bounds. I believe it will matter which does not do so, and hence is associated
have the same kind of beneficial effects. with the isolated system on a long-term basis. Such
matter relates the isolated system to local initial
conditions at the same position (as defined by
5.1. Possibility of newtonian physics comoving with matter) but at very early times, rather
than to exterior fields at later times. This also applies
A particular interesting point then, is what kinds to scalar and vector gravitational modes, for the
of conditions on a surface ^ surrounding a local crucial point was made above: the characteristics for
physical system will be required in order that that these modes are timelike curves rather than null
system can validly be described in terms of Newto- surfaces, and how they behave is determined by
nian physics (cf. van Elst and Ellis, 1998 for an conditions near our world line at very early times.
examination of the associated consistency conditions Thus, the true domain of dependence of such modes
from another point of view). The point here is that is not the usual domain of dependence bounded by
too much interference from the outside will prevent a null curves (Hawking and Ellis, 1973), but rather a
good Newtonian limit existing, for example a local much smaller region close to the matter world lines.
system imbedded in a universe where high-intensity The practical issue is that many local conditions at
gravitational waves abound will not have a good the present time are determined by conditions near
Newtonian description. Thus there will be limits on our world line in the very early universe (Ellis,
the particles and gravitational waves crossing any 1971), and this applies particularly to element abun-
bounding surface like ^, in order that such a dances (based on nucleosynthesis) and baryon abun-
description be possible. dances (based on baryosynthesis). Each are relics of
It seems likely that existence of a surface ^ in an non-equilibrium phases in the early universes his-
almost flat region at a finite distance, such as tory. A specific set of such relics results from
suggested above, may be sufficient to show the specific initial conditions, and determines the nature
possibility of Newtonian-like behaviour (it will not of what can exist locally at the present time (stars,
guarantee it, since black holes may form inside such planets, and living beings have to be constructed out
a surface). It is possible that such existence can only of whatever matter is present locally). The power of
occur if the exterior universe is reasonably similar to the assumption of equilibrium physics in the early
a standard FLRW model, and with almost co-moving universe is that the nature of these relics is very
boundaries chosen in the exterior region. That is, it largely independent of what existed at very early
seems likely that if the universe is not suitably close times, for whatever one might feed in will get
to a FLRW model, then no suitable surface ^ will transformed into an equilibrium mixture (this is the
exist and a Newtonian limit will not be attainable cosmological version of the famous statement that
locally in such a universe. This is an idea that needs the nature of black holes is independent of what is
to be checked. Whether this is the case or not, the put into them). Only conserved quantities will sur-
condition here is a significant one that needs in- vive unchanged; and there are very few of those in
vestigation: when does a universe allow Newtonian- the extreme conditions of the very early universe.
like behaviour in local regions? This is clearly an
important aspect of how global structure affects the
nature of local physics. This corresponds to the dual 7. The existence of life
micro-question: when does a quantum system behave
in an almost classical way, and what kind of A key issue for the future is to clarify in more
cosmologies allow the emergence of classical re- detail the relation of the nature of the universe to the
gimes from the early quantum domain? existence of life, both in terms of initial conditions,
G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657 655

and of the nature of the laws of physics. This is the survive (Tegmark, 1998). Thus, in my view this is
highly contested terrain of the Anthropic Principle. indeed an important part of the range of issues
Strangely, Dennis wrote rather little on this, but it discussed in this article, and the need is to strictly
has been a very active area and certainly is a separate out the unexceptional range of concerns that
legitimate concern within the broad terrain under can be classed as WAP issues, and their use for
discussion. example in terms of relating observations to chaotic
This concept has been regarded with considerable inflation, from the whole range of controversial
suspicion by many because of some rather unguarded concerns raised under the SAP banner. These relate
or ill-thought out statements regarding the nature and to fundamental metaphysical issues that are of a
application of the anthropic principle. There is a different nature than the issues pursued here; they are
clear distinction between the Weak Anthropic Princi- of course important, but are of a different character
ple (WAP) from the Strong Anthropic Principle and need a different kind of discussion of a
(SAP) (Barrow and Tipler, 1986; Balashov, 1991). philosophical and metaphysical character (Ellis,
The former is an unobjectionable selection principle 1991, 1999) rather than relating to the strictly
(we can only view the universe from space-time physical issues discussed in this paper.
regions that allow our existence), while the latter is The WAP issues are very much part of the theme
a highly disputable philosophical claim (the uni- of this paper. As they relate the rest of the arguments
verse must allow the existence of life), argued on a to questions concerning human life and existence,
number of different grounds, for example the need they are of major importance and interest to us as
for observers to exist in order that quantum theory human beings as well as scientists.
can make sense. The problem then is that firstly,
some papers seem to argue the SAP case by an
inversion of normal logic, for example the statement
by Collins and Hawking at the end of an important 8. Conclusion
study of Bianchi cosmologies that the universe must
exist because we are here (Collins and Hawking, As well as the major way that microphysics affects
1973); and secondly there have been some attempts macrophysics in a bottom-up way, there are many
to stretch the concept into quite indefensible territory themes whereby there is a top-down action of the
(Ellis, 1988), in particular Barrow and Tiplers Final cosmos as a whole on local physical systems. Some
Anthropic Principle (FAP): life not only must unsolved problems of physics may be related to this
exist, but once it has come into existence must theme, in particular the arrow of time issue which
continue to exist until the end of the universe is still a major puzzle for theoretical physics. Many
(Barrow and Tipler, 1986). This dubious proposition of the themes discussed here have practical applica-
led Gardner in a famous review to refer to the tions in terms of being related to tests of cosmologi-
Completely Ridiculous Anthropic Principle cal theories, precisely because if the universe has an
(CRAP). influence on local systems, then observing local
These extremes are unfortunate, because they have systems tells us something about the universe. This
obscured important arguments regarding the nature range of themes remains of interest today; there is
of the laws of physics and boundary conditions in the still interesting work to be done on them. These
universe necessary to the existence of life. If one issues were amongst the driving forces of Dennis
leaves aside the contentious claims, such as those career, and he presented them with force on many
mentioned above, one is left with an important occasions.
selection principle that may indeed be essential both
in terms of trying to explain the value of the
cosmological constant (Weinberg, 1989, 2000; Gar-
riga and Vilenkin, 1999) and in relating concepts Acknowledgements
such as chaotic inflation to observations (Linde,
1990). There is also an intrinsic interest in charting I thank Henk van Elst and Roy Maartens for
out what variations in physical laws will allow life to helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.
656 G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657

References Bergia, S., Messina, A. (Eds.), Modern Cosmology in Re-


trospect. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p. 97.
Ellis, G.F.R., 1999. Before the beginning: emerging questions and
Allen, R.L., Bernstein, G., Malholtra, R., 2000. The edge of the
uncertainties. In: Block, D., Puerari, I., Stockton, A., Ferreira,
solar system. astro-ph / 0011037.
D. (Eds.), Toward a New Millenium in Galaxy Morphology.
Ashtekar, A. et al., 2000. Isolated horizons and their applications.
Kluwer, Dordrecht. Ap&SS 269270, 693.
gr-qc / 0006006.
Ellis, G.F.R., Sciama, D.W., 1972. Global and non-global prob-
Balashov, Y., 1991. Resource letter AP-1: the anthropic principle.
lems in cosmology. In: ORaifertaigh, L. (Ed.), General
Am. J. Phys. 54, 1069.
Relativity: Papers in Honour of J.L. Synge. Oxford University
Barbour, J., Pfister, H. (Eds.), 1995. Machs Principle: from
Press, Oxford, p. 35.
Newtons Bucket to Quantum Gravity. Birkhauser.
Ellis, G., Lanza, A., Miller, J. (Eds.), 1993. The Renaissance of
Bardeen, J., 1980. PhRvD 22, 1882.
General Relativity and Cosmology: A survey to celebrate the
Bardeen, J., Steinhardt, P., Turner, M.S., 1983. PhRvD 28, 679.
65th birthday of Dennis Sciama. Cambridge University Press,
Barrow, J., Tipler, F.J., 1986. The Anthropic Cosmological
Cambridge.
Principle. Oxford University Press.
Ellis, G.F.R., 1971. In: Sachs, R.K. (Ed.), Proceedings of the
Bekenstein, J.D., 2000. The Limits of Information. gr-qc /
XLVII Enrico Fermi Summer School, General Relativity and
0009019.
Cosmology. Academic Press, New York.
Blau, S.K., Guth, A.H., 1987. Inflationary cosmology. In: Hawk-
Ellis, G.F.R., 1984. In: Bertotti, B., de Felice, F., Pascolini, A.
ing, S.W., Israel, W. (Eds.), 300 Years of Gravitation. Cam-
(Eds.), General Relativity and Gravitation. Reidel, Dordrecht.
bridge University Press, Cambridge, p. 524.
Ellis, G.F.R., 1988. Essay review: the anthropic cosmological
Boersma, J., 1998. Averaging in cosmology. Phys. Rev. D57, 798.
principle. Gen. Rel. Grav. 20, 497.
Bondi, H., 1960. Cosmology. Cambridge University Press, Cam-
Ellis, G.F.R., 1991. Major themes in the relation between
bridge.
philosophy and cosmology. Mem. Ital. Astr. Soc. 62, 553.
Bousso, R., 1999. hep-th / 9905177, hep-th 9906022.
Ellis, G.F.R., 1995. Comment on entropy and the second law: a
Bridle, S.L. et al., 2000. Cosmological parameters from Velocities,
pedagopgical alternative, by Ralph Baierlein. Am. J. Phys. 63,
CMB and Supernovae. astro-ph / 0006170.
472.
Brown, J.D., York, J.W., 1993. Phys. Rev. D47, 1407. Ellis, G.F.R., Stoeger, W.R., 1988. Horizons in inflationary
Collins, C.B., Hawking, S.W., 1973. Why is the universe isotropic? universes. Class Qu. Grav. 5, 207.
ApJ 180, 317. Ellis, G.F.R., Matravers, D.R., 1995. General covariance in
Davies, P.C.W., 1977. The Physics of Time Asymmetry. Universi- general relativity. Gen. Rel. Grav. 27, 777.
ty of California Press. Flaherty, F.J. (Ed.), 1983. Asymptotic behaviour of Mass and
De Witt, C., de Witt, B. (Eds.), 1973. Black Holes: Les Astres Spacetime Geometry. Lecture Notes in Physics 202. Springer,
Occlus. Gordon and Breach. Berlin.
Dekel, A., 1994. Dynamics of cosmic flows. ARA&A 32, 371. Friedrich, H., Nagy, G., 1999. The initial boundary problem for
dInverno, R., 1992. Introducing Einsteins Relativity. Oxford Einsteins vacuum field equations. Comm. Math. Phys. 201,
University Press, Oxford. 619.
Dirac, P.A.M., 1938. New basis for cosmology. Proc. Roy. Soc. Garriga, J., Vilenkin, A., 1999. On likely values of the cosmologi-
165, 199. cal constant. astro-ph / 9908115.
Dyson, F.J., 1971. Energy in the universe. Sci. Am. Sept. 1971. Gibbons, G.W., Hawking, S.W., Siklos, S.T.C., 1983. The Very
Dyson, F.J., 1971b. Energy and Power, A Scientific American Early Universe. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Book. Freeman, New York. Guth, A.H., 1981. Inflationary universe: a possible solution to the
Ehlers, J., 1961. Akad. Wiss. Lit. Mainz, Abhandl. Math.-Nat. Kl. horizon and flatness problems. PhRvD 23, 347.
11, 793. English translation: (1993), Gen. Rel. Grav. 25, 1225. Harrison, E.R., 1987. Darkness at Night: A Riddle of the
Ehlers, J. (Ed.), 1979. Isolated Gravitating Systems in General Universe. Harvard University Press.
Relativity. Proc. Int. School Enrico Fermi Course LVII. Aca- Harrison, E.R., 2000. Cosmology: The Science of the Universe.
demic Press, New York. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Ehlers, J., Prasanna, A.R., Breuer, R.A., 1987. Propagation of Hawking, S.W., Ellis, G.F.R., 1973. The Large Scale Structure of
gravitational waves through pressureless matter. Class Qu SpaceTime. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Grav. 4, 253. Hawking, S.W., Horowitz, G.T., 1996. Class Qu Grav. 13, 1487.
Einstein, A., Strauss, E.G., 1945. RvMP 17, 120. Heckmann, O., Schucking, E., 1956. Remarks on Newtonian
Einstein, A., Strauss, E.G., 1945. RvMP 18, 148. cosmology. Z. Astrophys. 40 (2), 81.
Ellis, G.F.R., 1989. A history of cosmology 19171955. In: Hogan, P.A., Ellis, G.F.R., 1991. Aspects of asymptotic electro-
Howard, D., Stachel, J. (Eds.), Einstein and the History of magnetic fields. Ann. Phys. 210, 178.
General Relativity. Einstein Study Series, Vol. 1. Birkhauser,
Hubner, P., 2000. From now to timelike infinity on a finite grid.
Boston, p. 367. gr-qc / 0010069.
Ellis, G.F.R., 1990. Innovation resistance and change: the transi- Jaffe et al., 2000. Cosmology from MAXIMA-1, BOOMERANG
tion to the expanding universe. In: Bertotti, B., Balbinto, R., and COBE / DMR observations. astro-ph / 0007333.
G.F.R. Ellis / New Astronomy Reviews 46 (2002) 645657 657

Kolb, E.W., Turner, M.S., 1990. The Early Universe. Wiley, New Schramm, D.N., Turner, M.S., 1998. Big-bang nucleosynthesis
York. enters the precision era. RvMP 70, 303.
Liddle, A.R., Lyth, D.H., 2000. Cosmological Inflation and Large
Schucking, E., 1954. Z. Physik 137, 595.
Scale Structure. Cambridge University Press. Sciama, D.W.S., 1971a. Modern Cosmology. Cambridge Universi-
Linde, A.D., 1990. Particle Physics and Inflationary Cosmology. ty Press, Cambridge.
Harwood, Chur. Sciama, D.W.S., 1971b. Astrophysical cosmology. In: Sachs, R.K.
Longair, M., 1995. The Physics of Background Radiation. In: The (Ed.), General Relativity and Gravitation. Enrico Fermi Sum-
Deep Universe: Saas-Fee Advanced Course 23 by Sandage, mer School 47. Academic Press, p. 183.
A.R., Kron, R.G. and Longair, M.S., Springer, Berlin. Sciama, D.W.S., 1959. The Unity of the Universe. Faber and
Lynden-Bell, D., Wood, R., 1967. MNRAS 136, 101. Faber.
Lynden-Bell, D., Lynden-Bell, R.M., 1977. On the negative Sciama, D.W.S., 1969. The Physical Foundations of General
specific heat paradox. MNRAS 181, 405. Relativity. Doubleday.
Maartens, R., 1997. Linearisation instability of gravity waves? Sciama, D.W.S., 1953. On the origin of inertia. MNRAS 113, 34.
PhRvD 55, 463. Sciama, D.W.S., Waylen, P.C., Gilman, R.C., 1969. Phys. Rev.
Martin, J., Brandenberger R., 2000. The trans-planckiaen problem 187, 1762.
of inflationary cosmology. hep-th / 0005209. Smoluchowski, R., Torbett, M., 1984. The boundary of the solar

Oszvath, I., Schucking, E., 1962. Nature 193, 1168. system. Nature 311, 38.
Peacock, J.R., 1999. Cosmological Physics. Cambridge University Tegmark, M., 1998. Is the theory of everything merely the
Press, Cambridge. ultimate ensemble theory? Ann. Phys. (N.Y.) 270, 1.
Peebles, P.J.E., 1971. Physical Cosmology. Princeton University Tipler, F.J., Clarke, C.J.S., Ellis, G.F.R., 1980. In: Held, A. (Ed.).
Press, Princeton, NJ. General Relativity and Gravitation: One Hundred Years after
Peebles, P.J.E., 1980. The Large Scale Structure of the Universe. the Birth of Albert Einstein, Vol. 2. Plenum Press, New York.
Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ. Tod, P., 1993. Machs Principle and isotropic singularities. In:
Penrose, R., 1989a. The Emperors New Mind: Concerning Ellis, G., Lanza, A., Miller, J. (Eds.), The Renaissance of
Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics. Oxford University General Relativity and Cosmology. Cambridge University
Press, Oxford. Press.
Penrose, R., 1979. Singularities and time asymmetry. In: Hawk- van den Bergh, S., 1999. The local group of galaxies. A&ARv 9,
ing, S.W., Israel, W. (Eds.), General Relativity: An Einstein 273.
Centenary Survey. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p. van Elst, H., Ellis, G.F.R., 1998. Quasi-Newtonian dust cos-
581. mologies. Class Qu Grav. 15, 3545.
Penrose, 1989. Difficulties with Inflationary Cosmology. In: van Elst, H., Ellis, G.F.R., 1999. Causal propagation of geometri-
Fenyves, E.J. (Ed.), Proc. 14th Texas Symp. on Relativistic cal fields in relativistic cosmology. PhRvD 59, 024013.
Astrophysics, Ann New York Academy of Sciences, 571, 249. van Elst, H., Ellis, G.F.R., 2000. Propagation of jump discon-
Penrose, R., 1963. In: DeWitt, C.M., DeWitt, B.S. (Eds.), Relativi- tinuities in relativistic cosmology. PhRvD 62, 104023.
ty, Groups and Topology. Gordon and Breach, New York, p. Wald, R.M., 1984. General Relativity. University of Chicago
565. Press, Chicago.
Penrose, R., Rindler, W., 1988. Spinors and space-time, Vol. 2. Weinberg, S., 1972. Gravitation and Cosmology. Wiley, New
Cambridge University Press, Section 9.10. York.
Penrose, O., 1981. Entropy and irreversibility. Ann. New York Weinberg, S., 2000. The cosmological constant problems, astro-
Acad. Sci. 373, 211. ph / 0005265.
Pozzetti, L., Madau, P., 2000. The optical extragalactic back- Weinberg, S., 1989. RvMP 61, 1.
ground light from resolved galaxies. astro-ph / 0011359. Wheeler, J.A., 1968. Einsteins Vision. Springer, Berlin.
Prigogine, I., 1996. The End of Certainty: Time, Chaos, And the Zeh, H.D., 1989. The Physical Basis of the Direction of Time.
New Laws of Nature. The Free Press, New York. Springer, Berlin.
Raine, D.J., 1981. RPPh 44, 1151.
Raychaudhuri, A., 1955. Relativistic cosmology. Phys. Rev. 98,
1123.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi