Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 27

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Comparative Philosophy: Chinese


and Western
First published Tue Jul 31, 2001; substantive revision Mon Dec 8, 2014
Comparative philosophy brings together philosophical traditions that have developed in
relative isolation from one another and that are defined quite broadly along cultural and
regional lines Chinese versus Western, for example. Several main issues about the
commensurability of philosophical traditions make up the subject matter of comparative
philosophy. One issue is methodological commensurability -- whether and how comparisons
between different philosophical traditions, in this case the Chinese and Western, are to be
conducted. Views run the gamut from those holding that meaningful comparisons cannot be
conducted at all to those holding that the content of traditions must largely be the same.
Other issues concerning commensurability concern specific subject matters of traditions. The
issue of metaphysical and epistemological commensurability involves the comparison of
traditions on their conceptions of the real and their modes of inquiry and justification. Ethical
commensurability involves the comparison of these traditions on the matters of how people
ought to live their lives, whether both traditions have moralities and if so how similar and
dissimilar they are. The separation between these main issues is somewhat artificial, given
that a discussion of methodological commensurability will inevitably involve the comparison
of traditions on metaphysical, epistemological, and ethical matters. There is some heuristic
value, however, in beginning with a general discussion of views on methodological
commensurability with a brief illustration of how these views might be applied to some
Chinese/Western comparisons. Subsequent sections will address Chinese-Western
comparisons in metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics that have assumed special prominence
in the literature.
Doing comparative philosophy well can be very difficult because of the vast range of texts
and their intellectual and historical contexts it requires its practioners to cover.
Oversimplifications, excessively stark contrasts, and illicit assimilations count as the most
frequent sins. One benefit of comparative philosophy lies in the way that it forces reflection
on the most deeply entrenched and otherwise unquestioned agendas and assumptions of one's
own tradition. Another benefit at which its practioners often aim is that the traditions actually
interact and enrich one another. Demands for rigor and depth of scholarship obviously rank
as some of the most important standards applying to philosophy inquiry. The task of meeting
these standards becomes more manageable as the field of inquiry narrows. Such a result can
be legitimate but sometimes myopic and impoverishing.

1. Methodological Commensurability
2. Metaphysical and Epistemological Commensurability
3. Ethical Commensurability
4. Why Do Comparative Philosophy If It's So Hard?
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries

1. Methodological Commensurability
Those arguing for radical incommensurability the view that the questions and answers in
one tradition cannot sustain meaningful statement in the other tradition rely on the
recognition of radical difference in basic concepts and modes of inquiry. Given such radical
differences, they argue, there can be no cross-traditional reference to a common subject
matter and to a truth about that subject matter that is independent of the basic conceptual
vocabulary and theories and justificatory practices of a particular tradition (see Rorty, 1989,
and Shweder, 1989). Looking for a possible Chinese-Western instance of radical
incommensurability, one might go to Daoist texts such as the Daodejing and the Zhuangzi.
When it is said in chapter one (as traditionally arranged and on one translation) of
the Daodejing that The Way that can be spoken of is not the constant Way, or in chapter
two that the sages abide in nonaction and practice the teaching that is without words, one is
finding something different from the usual in Western texts infused with ideals of discursive
rationality and argumentation. Or consider the Lunyu or Analects 1:2, where the importance
of rightly ordered family relations is emphasized for right order in the state (He who has
grown to be a filial son and respectful younger brother will be unlikely to defy his superiors
and there has never been the case of someone inclined to defy his superiors and stir up a
rebellion). The prominent and enduring place of this theme of state as family writ large sets
that tradition apart from Western contractual traditions that have come to emphasize right
order in the state as that which can be ratified by an uncoerced agreement among equals
concerned to protect their private interests. Opponents of radical incommensurability will
level the charge that it presupposes a hyperdramatic contrast between traditions. For
example, the Western tradition has not lacked for skeptics on the power of discusive
rationality, and some of these skeptics have nevertheless believed in a mode of veridical
access to something of supreme significance to a powerful experience within themselves
or to something much larger outside themselves. At the same time, it must be noted that the
positive theme is more recessive in the Western tradition and appears mainly in theistic
versions, as it does in Plotinus (Enneads), Meister Eckhart (Von unsagbaren Dingen) and
Hildegaard of Bingen (Scivias). Similarly, the Western tradition has certainly housed strains
of thought that do view the state as more of a natural outgrowth of small human groups such
as family and community. Even a major modern figure such as David Hume (Treatise of
Human Nature, 3.2.2) explicitly rejects the idea of contract as central to understanding the
origin or justification of social and political bonds. There might still be a difference between
Chinese and Western traditions with respect to which strains of thought become dominant or
at least prevalent, but that difference does not appear to come under the heading of radical
incommensurability.
Samuel Fleischacker (1992) proposes a more moderate version of incommensurability
sometimes we can understand others just well enough to know that we don't understand
them. His argument has roots in Wittgenstein's view that knowledge depends on a
background of shared assumptions and standards of evidence. World pictures are
embedded within cultures. Our world picture involves not only a distinctive set of beliefs
about the world but also an ordering of interests that determines how we go about trying to
have reliable beliefs. This ordering differs from those dominant in other cultures. We in the
West have given precedence to our interests in egalitarian knowledge (wanting and
believing that people have roughly equal access to the truth) and in prediction and control of
this-worldly objects. The world pictures of other cultures embody other interests, and we
may not be able to prove that they are wrong, or indeed, we may be unable to fully
understand why it is that they value the interests they value so highly. Nevertheless, we
understand that they do value these interests highly and think they are wrong to do so. We
make such judgments despite our merely partial understanding because we tend to see a
certain set of interests as the proper guide for a minimally decent or sensible human life.
The idea that the distinctive character of a world picture lies partly in the interests they
embody seems plausible. Daoism and Confucianism, at least after a certain stage in the
development of these schools, exemplify the way that a set of interests intertwine with
beliefs about the world. Both schools exemplify in different ways a conception of
understanding the world that is inseparable from the interest in coming into attunement
with it, to use a felicitous word from Charles Taylor (1982). To become attuned to the world
is to see its goodness and to know one's place in the order of the world. To say that Daoists
exemplify this theme about seeing the goodness of the world is in a way misleading, since
there is in the Daodejing and Zhuangzi a profound mistrust of our conceptual separations
between opposites such as good and bad. However, as has been noted many times, the notion
of nonaction or wuwei does not denote literal inaction but presupposes something like the
possibility of an unforced acting with the grain of things, and that presupposes that it is
possible to become attuned to that grain while in a state of awareness that is not cluttered by
distorting conceptual oppositions. Both Daoist texts straightforwardly recommend wuwei and
in this sense presuppose the goodness of the world and the way its grain goes. Confucian
texts uphold the ideal of a different kind of attunement, under which the world and its order
can be called good without the ambiguity that Daoist skepticism with conceptual opposition
creates. For example, the Mencius (the name is actually a latinization given by Christian
priests for Mengzi) presents a theory that human nature contains the germs or sprouts of
goodness, tendencies to certain feelings and judgments such as manifested by the feeling of
compassion for a child about to fall into a well. These sprouts are in human nature because
they were sent by tian (literally meaning sky but most often translated as Heaven and
perhaps best conceived as an impersonal ordering force of the universe). Taylor thinks that
modern science has severed the connection between understanding and attunement. In
Fleischacker's terms, modern science is predicated on different interests, prediction and
control foremost among these interests. Taylor believes that the severance of understanding
and attunement resulted in superior understanding at least of physical nature. But as he is
careful to point out, no single argument can prove global superiority. If we can take
attunement as an ideal, we have failed miserably, even as our technological control of nature
has increased immeasurably. Perhaps, then, the contrast between a Chinese world picture in
which attunement figures prominently and a modern scientific view predicated on the
interests of prediction and control serves as an example of the sort of moderate
incommensurability Fleischacker has in mind. One question to be raised about this kind of
incommensurability, however, is whether it truly involves lack of understanding between
traditions. Taylor himself draws examples of the theme of attunement from Plato and the
European cultural tradition. Do we really fail to understand the appeal behind world pictures
of attunement? Taylor's complex assessment suggests no inability on our part to understand
the force behind both kinds of world pictures. Even to take the stance that attunement
pictures are comforting illusions (an assessment less complex than the one Taylor adopts) is
to suppose that one does understand the appeal behind them.
Sometimes the case for incommensurability is made by pointing to the pervasive and central
presence of a term in one tradition for which no equivalent term can be found in another
tradition. Such a difference may point to a degree of divergence of interests as suggested by
Fleischacker. However, it is better to explore the implications of this kind of untranslatability
case by case. Erin Cline (2013) has argued for the presence of a concept of justice in
the Analects despite the fact that it contains no word that is equivalent in meaning. Cline
points to concerns expressed in the text that relate to justice: about poverty and distribution
of wealth; about the need for trust in others in striving for a common good that one shares
with them; about how that sense of trust begins in the family; about the need for concern to
expand to all people even if it starts in the family; and about yior rightness as a virtue as
involving fair- mindedness. If there is a contrast between the ancient Chinese tradition as
represented by the Analects and modern Western traditions, it may be more a matter of the
latter being especially focused on matters of distribution of goods by institutions, rather than
that interest being entirely absent in the Confucian tradition. Often, the comparative situation
is a complex one in which philosophers from different traditions diverge substantially in
many ways, yet converge in interesting ways in some of their central concerns. Aaron
Stalnaker (2006) proposes a comparative methodology involving "bridge concepts" that
facilitates exploration of such simultaneous divergence and convergence. Augustine and
Xunzi, he suggests, are both centrally concerned with human nature and "spiritual exercises"
intended to transform the self. But such concepts as those of human nature and spiritual
exercises are not single concepts but a cluster of concepts, and in using them as focal points
of comparison, one should be aware of their complexity and the different as well as similar
ways they might operate in the thought of Augustine and Xunzi.
A different kind of incommensurability that may arise is not incomprehensibility between
traditions but lack of common standards sufficient for settling significant conflicts between
them. Alasdair MacIntyre (1988, 1989) has illustrated the difference between being able to
understand a tradition and being able to translate all its claims into the language of another
tradition by pointing to the possibility of bilinguals people who, for example, might
have been raised within one community and its tradition, and then through migration or
conquest, become a member of another community and its different tradition. Such bilinguals
might very well understand each tradition, and such understanding might include knowledge
of those parts of each that cannot be translated into the language of the other. Such bilinguals
would not encounter the sort of radical incommensurability constituted by
incomprehensibility, but they may be unable to resolve conflicts of belief between the
traditions, instead having to relativize the claims of each in some such form as seems true to
this particular community or seems justified to this particular community. This kind of
evaluational incommensurability, rather than meaning incommensurability, might fit better
the case of world pictures based on attunement versus world pictures that sever the
connection between understanding and attunement. MacIntyre himself presents a possibility
for resolving such conflicts in case one tradition continually fails in its attempts to address
certain key problems or issues. If another tradition has the conceptual resources to explain
why it is that the first tradition continues to fail, then advocates of that first tradition may
have to acknowledge its limitations and even transfer their allegiances. Whether that is the
case for conflicts over attunement is not obvious (See Wong, 1989).
Moving to the end opposite from various forms of incommensurability, we find views
holding that there must be substantial agreeement between traditions. The argument stems
from a conception of the way interpretation works. We proceed on the assumption that the
others we are interpreting live in the same world as we do.We subvert this assumption,
however, if we attribute to them beliefs that substantially differ from our own. As Donald
Davidson (1980) has argued, a belief is identified by its location in a pattern of beliefs, and it
is this pattern that determines the subject matter of the belief, what the belief is about. If we
attribute to others a pattern of beliefs that are different from our own, i.e., false beliefs, this
tends to undermine the identification of the subject matter; to undermine, therefore, the
validity of the belief as being about that subject. David Cooper (1978) applies a Davidsonian
principle of charity to the question of whether different cultures have more or less the same
morality. We can only identify others' beliefs as moral beliefs about a given subject matter if
there is a massive degree of agreement between their and our beliefs about that subject
matter. For Cooper this implies that the moral beliefs we attribute to others must be about
something connected with welfare, happiness, suffering, security, and the good life. Michele
Moody-Adams (1997) gives a more recent version of the same argument, starting with the
premise that understanding others requires that there be quite substantial agreement about
many of the basic concepts that are relevant to moral reflection. She concludes that
ultimate or fundamental moral disagreement is not possible.
The way that an earlier example of putative radical difference can be questioned serves as
some confirmation of this argument from charity for strong agreement between traditions.
Confucian conceptions of the state as family writ large are not especially puzzling even when
we do not subscribe to them. We find similar themes that have arisen within the Western
tradition, and again, it is possible to conceive what the appeal would be. However, these
points also raise certain doubts about the use of charity to argue for strong agreement. The
fact that we can point to similar beliefs within our own tradition and that we can imagine
what the appeal would lie behind such beliefs does not mean that we share those beliefs with
others even as we attribute to them. Even if we were to share with them a belief in certain
values, that would not necessarily mean that we place the same importance on those values
relative to other values we (and perhaps they also) hold. It is often observed that a distinctive
feature of the Chinese Confucian tradition is the very high value placed on filial piety. It is a
common feature of many cultures that one should honor thy father and mother, of course,
and it is not difficult to find analogies within American society to Confucian filial piety. At
the same time, the Confucian tradition is unusual in the stringency of its duties to parents.
The scope of filial duties includes taking care of what parents alone could have given one
one's body. Cengzi, one of Confucius' students, is portrayed in 8.3 of the Analects as gravely
ill and near death. He bids his students to look at his hands and feet, and quotes lines from
the Book of Poetry to convey the idea that all his life he has been keeping his body intact as
part of his duty to his parents. It is only now near death, he says, that he can be sure of
having been spared and thus fulfilling this duty to parents. This very idea, that one must keep
one's body intact as a duty of gratitude to one's parents, has remained a central idea in
Chinese culture. While American culture certainly contains similar themes of gratitude
toward those from whom one has received great benefits, such themes do not necessite
agreement on the centrality and stringency of filial duties in the Confucian tradition.
Important kinds of moral difference, then, may consist in the differing emphases given to
values that are shared across cultural traditions (Wong, 1996b). Thomas Kasulis (2002) puts
a similar point in a visual metaphor: what is foreground in one culture may be background in
another culture.
To accommodate this more subtle kind of difference, proponents of the principle of charity
might point out that charity does not require complete agreement, but only substantial
agreement or agreement on ultimate or fundamental disagreement. A further question
that will pressed against this position is how much agreement is sufficient for identification
of others' beliefs as being about the same subject matter as ours. We do attribute to others
error and simple difference (without judging that someone is in error) of belief about the
same subject matter. We can attribute error to others if we believe them to be in
circumstances that encourage error, and we identify such types of circumstance from past
experience of discovering ourselves to be in error. Furthermore, we attribute simple
difference of belief when we recognize that there is a range of reasonable interpretations or
weightings to be given to evidence.
In his later writings on charity (2001, p. 196), Davidson recognized its ambiguities, noting
that he previously tended to construe it in terms of maximizing agreement in belief and
that a more perspicuous statement of what he had in mind all along is that agreement in
beliefs should be optimized. Rather than the most agreement, we need the right sort of
agreement that enables understanding of others. We should try to reach agreement as far as
possible, subject to considerations of simplicity, hunches about the effects of social
conditioning, and of course our common-sense, or scientific, knowledge of explicable error.
This very qualified formulation of charity amounts to the admission that the principle of
charity itself needs interpretation and hence cannot be the ultimate standard for
interpretation. Henry Richardson (1997) points out that interpreting a philosophical text
requires taking account of the cognitive aims the authors had in writing what they did. Is it
more charitable, Richardson asks, for a translator of Machiavelli's The Prince to resolve
ambiguities and seek to maximize agreement between Machiavelli and ourselves? Or is it
more charitable to set him out as intentionally provocative and deliberately cryptic? It should
be unsurprising that charity cannot fulfill its promise as a firm and clear guide to
interpretation. Charity bids us to render others like us, but we are already a diverse group
who believe and want and value somewhat different things. That is, the range of the
intelligibly human already embraces diversity (think of how impoverished our models of
understanding would be if we could only rely on our individual selves). See Mou (2006) for
a range of articles on the way that Davidson's interpretive principle and other aspects of his
philosophy relate to Chinese philosophy.
An alternative to both the radical incommensurability and strong agreement positions is that
there is no general answer on how much agreement or disagreement is to be found between
complex and hetereogeneous traditions such as the Chinese and Western. As emerged above,
one must distinguish between meaning and evaluational incommensurabilities. Furthermore,
how much disagreement we will find not only depends on the particular subject matter but
also on the answers we find most plausible within a larger context of inquiry: the attempt to
explain others, their actions, practices, institutitions, and history. In such a larger context,
attribution to others of beliefs different from ours may be more or less reasonable depending
on how it fits into a reasonable explanation of them. And what counts as a reasonable
explanation in particular cases will be set within the context of one's larger theories about
persons and societies, among other things. One's explanation of people can reasonably
attribute error or simple difference of belief on an indefinite number of important matters that
might even deserve to be called fundamental as long as it seems plausible to attribute error
or simple difference of belief to them in their epistemic situation as we construe it (see also
Grandy, 1973). Or one's explanation can reasonably imply convergence or similarity of
belief. An intermediate possibility is that the difference or similarity becomes more
prominent as one defines the subject matter in a thicker or thinner way (Shun, 2004).
Does the Chinese tradition recognize individual rights? The answer, as shall emerge below,
may depend on how specifically one defines the notion of a right. If one defines a right rather
thinly as what one has whenever one has justifiable claims on others to assure one's
possession of things or one's exercise of certain capacities, then one can plausibly argue that
there is a common notion of rights between the Chinese and Western traditions (Wong,
2004). If, on the other hand, one thickens one's definition of rights with the idea that they
are justifiable independently of what is a good and worthwhile life for human beings, then
one plausibly argue against a common notion of rights.
2. Metaphysical and Epistemological
Commensurability
One common portrait of the difference between the Chinese and Western traditions posits a
radical incommensurability on the very nature of philosophical inquiry. Chinese philosophy
is wisdom literature, composed primarily of stories and sayings designed to move the
audience to adopt a way of life or to confirm its adoption of that way of life. Western
philosophy is systematic argumentation and theory. Is there such a difference? One reason to
think so is the fairly widespread wariness in Chinese philosophy of a discursive rationality
that operates by deduction of conclusions about the particular from high-level
generalizations. The seventeenth chapter of the Zhuangzi notes that the sage-king Yao looked
for a suitable successor, found the perfect candidate in Shun, and then abdicated so that Shun
could take over the throne. The result was glorious. However, when Kuai imitated Yao the
result was disastrous. Tang and Wu were kings who fought and conquered. But Duke Bo also
acted on that rule, fought, and lost. That is why it is impossible to establish any constant
rule. Inspired by the achievement of insight or wisdom in some particular cases, we create
general rules that we believe will work for many other cases in the future. The unfortunate
result is that our original insights and wisdom are magnified beyond the scope of their
applicability. Confucians are more willing to articulate their teachings in the form of
principles, but such principles seem to function as designators of values or general
considerations that ought to be given weight in judgments about what to do. Never lost is
recognition of the necessity for the exercise of discretion in judgment according to the
particular circumstances at hand. The best rules lose applicability in unusual circumstances.
Rules and values conflict in many circumstances, and there are no super-principles to
supply ready answers. The appropriate resolution to each conflict depends very much on the
situation. In Mencius 7A35, Mencius is asked what the legendary sage-king Shun would
have done if his father had killed a man.Mencius replies that the only thing to do would be to
apprehend him. Shun could not interfere with the judge, who was acting on the law.
However, Mencius continues, Shun would then have abdicated and fled with his father to the
seacoast. As Mencius portrays it, then, Shun's actions strike a balance between the different
values in tension with one another. The refusal to interfere with the judge is a way of
acknowledging the necessity of impartially administering a social order. At the same time,
fleeing with one's father is honoring the value of greater loyalty to family. Shun manages to
honor both values at different moments in his dealing with the situation. Deduction from a
principle could not yield such a balance. We are expected, however, to learn from stories
such as Shun's, precisely because they function as concrete paradigms for judgment-making
in the future. When we encounter situations that pose similar-looking conflicts between
impartial concern and familial loyalties, we have Shun's judgment as a resource and a model.
That model is not the same as a general principle that would deductively yield a judgment
about what to do in the present situation. We must exercise judgment in determining whether
new situations are similar enough to the case of Shun, and we must exercise judgment as to
what actions would be parallel to Shun's actions.
Naes and Hanay (1972) have characterized Chinese philosophy as invitational in its
method of persuasion, meaning that it portrays a way of life in a vivid fashion so as to invite
the audience to consider its adoption. The Analects, for example, portrays the ideal of
the junzi (often translated as gentleman but perhaps more accurately glossed as the noble
person) as realized by persons of genuine substance who are undisturbed by the failure of
others to recognize their merits (1.1: To be undisturbed by others yet not complain, is this
not the mark of the junzi?). In the Mencius (2A2),such a person possesses a kind of
equanimity or heart that is unperturbed by the prospects of fame and success. This
unperturbed heart corresponds to the cultivation of one's qi (vital energies) by uprightness.
One might be able to see such passages as appealing to experiences the audience might have
in its encounters with persons who do seem to possess special strength, substance, and
tranquillity through identification with and commitment to a cause they perceive to be far
greater than themselves. One need not interpret such sayings as attempting to persuade by the
pure emotive effect of certain words, as in propaganda. Rather, they may correspond to a
way of doing philosophy that attempts to say something about values in life that can be
supported by experience, even if not all testimony will agree (Kupperman, 1999). The
Daoists recommend a way of life that they explicitly characterize as one that cannot be
argued for, but their recommendation receives some support through commonly shared
experience. Consider again the notion of wuwei and its illustrations in the Zhuangzi through
stories of exemplary craft. Most famously, Zhungzi's Cook Ding cuts up an oxen so
smoothly and effortlessly that his knife never dulls, and it is if he is doing a dance with his
knife as it zips through the spaces between the joints. He does this not through perception
and understanding but through the qi, the vital energies of the body. His marvelous skill is
knowledge of how to adjust his own movements to the spaces within oxen so that he and the
oxen form seamless wholes. Similarly, Woodcarver Qing has learned to prepare for carving
his marvelous bellstands in such a way that he clears his mind of all distraction and sees the
stand within the timber he has selected. Suggested here is a portrait of acting in the world
that consists of complete and full attention to present circumstances so that the agent can act
with the grain of things (the Cook Ding passage refers to tianli or heavenly patterns). Such a
portrait does resonate with the actual experience of craftspeople, artists, athletes, musicians
and dancers who have advanced beyond self-conscious technique and rule-following, who
become fully absorbed in the experience of working with the material, the instruments or in
the movement of their bodies, and who experience their actions as an effortless flow and in
fact perform at very high levels. In such ways, Chinese thinkers draw a picture of the world
that must in the end be evaluated by explanatory power in some very broad sense. We must
ask whether the picture helps make sense of our experience of the world (again in a broad
sense of experience not limited to quantifiable observations in replicable experiments) and
whether it preserves features of that experience that think are prima facie genuine.
So then, is it right to say that Chinese philosophy is invitational while Western philosophy is
argumentative? One answer is that there is a difference but that it is more a matter of degree
than an absolute contrast. It was Aristotle, after all, who said that discussions about the good
in human life cannot be properly assimilated by the young because they do not have enough
experience of life (Nichomachean Ethics I.3). And Plato despite his insistence on the
centrality of argumentation to philosophy, dispatches the short analytical arguments
presented in Book I of the Republic in favor of lengthy expository portraits of the ideal city-
state and the harmonious soul for the rest of that work. Those portraits sometimes present
only the thinnest of arguments for crucial premises, and at other times no argument at all.
Some of his claims, about the divisive effects of family loyalties and the ill-effects of
democracy, obviously appeal to experience, even if not all testimony will agree. In fact, it is
hard work to find an acknowledged great in the Western tradition to whom such
characterizations do not apply, at least to some degree. Sometimes, as in Spinoza (The
Ethics), the contrast is glaring between the aspiration to prove points by way of deductive
argument from self-evident axioms and the obvious source of those points from experience
of life. It is true that much Western philosophy, especially of the late modern variety, and
most especially emanating from the United Kingdom and North America, attempts to
establish its claims through argumentation that is more rigorous than appeals to experience
and explanatory power in the broad sense. But it must also be noted that there is argument in
Chinese philosophy. Chad Hansen (1992) has pointed out the pivotal role of the philosopher
Mozi, who criticized the Confucians for an uncritical acceptance of tradition and who
explicitly introduced standards for the evaluations of belief. This introduction of
argumentation required response in kind. Mencius gives a Confucian response to to the
Mohists and argues on behalf of his theory of human nature as containing the germs or
sprouts of the ethical virtues, in the form of natural dispositions to have certain kinds of
feeling and judging reactions to situations, such as compassion for a child about to fall into a
well (2A6, and see Shun, 1997 for an extensive analysis of argumentation in
the Mencius text). He defends himself against the arguments of rival theorists who hold that
human nature has no innate ethical predispositions but is neutral (6A). Xunzi, a later
Confucian thinker, attempts to give a refutation of Mencius's theory in favor of his own
theory that human nature has dispositions that get us into trouble and that ethical norms are
an invention designed to avoid that trouble (Xunzi, chapter 23). Methods of argumentation
reach their most sophisticated state of development in Xunzi (See Cua, 1985).
Differences in the way philosophy is conceived may reflect differences in the interests
philosophy is meant to satisfy. Chad Hansen (1992) points to another possible difference in
interests this time in interests that language is meant to satisfy, arguing that the classical
Chinese thinkers did not conceive of the primary function of language to be descriptive and
as attempting to match propositions with states of affairs, but rather as a pragmatic
instrument for guiding behavior. In fact, Hansen sees the Chinese tradition as centrally
concerned with the conflict of daos, which he defines as sets of behavior-guiding practices,
including discourses. Western interpreters have been unable to see this, argues Hansen,
because they have imposed their own concerns with correspondence truth and metaphysics
on the Chinese tradition. They have as a result imposed upon Daoism an irrational mysticism
focused on a metaphysically absolute Dao. Michael LaFargue (1992) also argues that
theDaodejing is not to be interpreted as as concerning some metaphysical entity called
the Dao, but is rather concerned with self cultivation that allows one to have a transforming
experience of deep and peaceful stillness within one's personal center. Wuwei is the style of
action that is rooted in such an experience. David Hall and Roger Ames (1987) give a related
interpretation of Confucius, in part reacting against Herbert Fingarette's (1972) influential
interpretation of Confucius' Dao as an ideal normative order transcending the contingencies
of time, place, history, and culture. Hall and Ames argue Confucius's Dao was not conceived
as a tradition and language-independent reality against which linguistically formulated
beliefs were to be measured as reliable or unreliable, but in fact a cumulative creation of
individuals working from within a context provided by a society's tradition, consisting of
customs, conventions, conceptions of proper behavior and good manners, conceptions of
right conduct and of what is of ultimate value and of what lives are worth living.
These interpretations perform valuable functions in questioning what is sometimes an
unreflective imposition of Western philosophical agendas on Chinese thinkers. The debate
will go on, however. Concerning Confucius, it is true that the Analects often displays an
attitude of tolerance and flexibility in judging where the Dao lies. On the other side, it can be
pointed out that in sayings such as 1.2 (filial piety and brotherly love are at the root of the
virtue of ren or humanity), there is no indication that the claim is limited to Chinese culture
but extended to human beings generally. One way to understand it is to take it as saying that
human beings have to learn to respond to a kind of authority that is not based on force and
coercion, but respect and care. Or consider the consistent Confucian theme that rulers cannot
hold power simply on the basis of law and punishment. There is no sign such judgments are
meant to be limited in scope to one's own time and place. Concerning the Daodejing, it is
clear that there are very strong practical concerns underlying the text. A way of life is being
recommended (as in Hansen), and perhaps that way of life is rooted in a certain kind of
transforming experience (as in LaFargue). On the other side, it could be argued that such
practical and experiential concerns do not exclude metaphysical concerns. Consider chapter
four of that text where Dao is described as being empty, as seeming something like the
ancestor of the myriad of things, as appearing to precede the Lord (di). For something that at
least looks metaphysical in theMencius, consider aforementioned 2A2, concerning the
unperturbed heart that can be achieved by cultivating one's floodlike qi. Such qi is vast and
unyielding, and if cultivated with uprightness will fill up the space between tian (Heaven)
and earth. Perhaps the lesson to draw is not that Chinese thinkers lacked metaphysical
concerns but that they did not separate practical from metaphysical concerns in the way that
contemporary Western thinkers might.
However this issue is resolved with respect to the classical Chinese thinkers, few have
disputed that classical concepts such as that of nonbeing eventually acquired frankly
metaphysical meanings in the Chinese tradition, where it refers at the least to an
indeterminate ground in which the determinate ten thousand things are incipient (Neville,
1989). This embrace of an indeterminate ground of the determinate may reflect the decision
to give the phenomenon of change a fundamental place in ontology, rather than an absolutely
stable being as in Parmenidean ontology and as later reflected in Aristotelian and Cartesian
notions of substance (Cheng, 1989, 1991). The revival of interest in Chinese metaphysics has
partly been fueled by the perception that twentieth century physics has in fact undermined
the strategy of giving determinate being ontological primacy (Zukov, 1979). The Neo-
Confucian Chu Hsi (Zhuzi yulei) reinterpreted ethical themes inherited from the classical
thinkers and grounded them in a cosmology and metaphysics. On his conception of ren as an
all inclusive virtue, it constitutes the Dao and consists of the fact that the mind of Heaven
and Earth to produce things is present in everything, including the mind of human beings.
Another great Neo-Confucian, Wang Yang-Ming (Quan xilu) does seem more pragmatic
than metaphysical, He taught of the sage who formed one body with Heaven and Earth and
the myriad things, but he showed little of Chu's interest in the li or principle of existent
things. The investigation of things prescribed in the Great Learning (Da Xue) was not the
empirical inquiry Chu envisioned but a rectification of the mind with evil thoughts. Perhaps
Chu and Wang represent development of tendencies that were present from the beginning,
and between which there was never conceived to be a mutually exclusive choice.
When we get to Chinese Buddhism, there is more evidence for metaphysical concerns that at
the same time are urgently practical. It is difficult to view as anything but a metaphysical
doctrine the Buddha's view of the self as a floating collection of various psychophysical
reactions and responses with no fixed center or unchanging ego entity. He did not deny that
we think of the self as a fixed and unchanging center, but considered such a self a delusion.
Our bodily attributes, various feelings, perceptions, ideas, wishes, dreams, and in general a
consciousness of the world display a constant interplay and interconnection that leads us to
the belief that there is some definite I that underlies and is independent of the ever-shifting
series. But there is only the interacting and interconnected series. This metaphysical concern,
of course, had deep practical implications for the Buddha. It points toward the answer to
human suffering, which ultimately stems from a concern for the existence and pleasures and
pains of the kind of self that never existed in the first place. The recognition that none of the
things of ordinary life are fixed and separate entities, anymore than the self is, leads to a
recognition of all of life as an interdependent whole and to the practical attitude of
compassion for all of life. In a comparative perspective, one cannot help but be struck by the
similarity between the Buddhist view of the self and David Hume's doubts about the
existence of a unitary and stable self (Treatise of Human Nature, 1.4.6). Consider also Derek
Parfit's (1984) point that acceptance of a Humean or a Buddhist view of the self can lead to
sense that one is less separate from other selves and to a wider concern when my projects
seem not so absolutely different from your projects. However one might regard the
argument for impersonal concern from such a view of the self, the view itself may seem to
have a claim to a our renewed attention. It certainly fits better with a naturalized conception
of human beings as part of this world and not as Cartesian thinking substances that somehow
operate apart from the rest of nature. Siderits (2003) Flanagan (2013) have brought
Buddhism into dialogue with naturalistic analytic philosophy in sophisticated and productive
ways that benefit both sides.

3. Ethical Commensurability
Confucianism is a perfectionist virtue ethic if such an ethic is distinguished by its central
focus on three subjects: character traits identified as the virtues; the good and worthwhile
life; and particularist modes of ethical reasoning. These three subjects are interrelated. The
virtues are traits of character necessary for living a good life. The virtues typically involve
acting on particularist modes of ethical reasoning that do not rely on deducing specific
action-guiding conclusions about how to act from general principles but rather on judging in
the context at hand what needs to be done (see Van Norden, 2004, 2007, Hutton, 2003,
Wong, 2002, and Ivanhoe, 2002 for discussions of judgment and its relation to reasoning and
emotion in Mencius). Consider some of the virtues that belong to the junzi (the noble
person): ren (humanity, benevolence), xiao (filial piety), yi(righteousness), and li (acting
according to ceremonial ritual or more generally propriety). The very concept of yi connotes
the ability to identify and perform the action that is appropriate to the particular context
(Analects 4:10 says that the junzi is not predisposed to be for or against anything, but rather
goes with what is yi). While traditional rules of ritual provide one with a sense of what is
courteous and respectful action given standard contexts, the virtue of yi allows one to
identify when those rules need to be set aside in exigent circumstances (see Cua, 1997). The
previously discussed example in the Mencius of Shun and his father shows how a ruler's
more general concern for his subjects and his filial duties to his fathers must be balanced in
ways that cannot be given by principle but only by reflection on what the particular
circumstances suggest and allow. Finally, consider that another example from the Mencius
about the time when Shun wanted to marry. He knew that his parents, not the wisest nor the
best of parents, would not permit him to marry if told of Shun's intention. Shun went ahead
and got married without telling his parents, an act that normally would be a grave offense
against filial piety. Two reasons are given for the justifiability of this act. One is that the
worst way of being a bad son is to provide no heir (4A26); the other is that letting his parents
thwart his desire to realize the greatest of human relationships which in turn would cause
bitterness toward his parents (5A2). Hence an act that normally would be a grave offense
against filial piety constitutes filial piety in the particular circumstances. Particularist modes
of reasoning are needed, then, to judge when the usual rules apply, to balance conflicting
values, and to specify the concrete meaning of single values in application to context.
The parallels to ancient Greek virtue ethics, medieval virtue ethics, and also to contemporary
virtue ethics in the West are striking, and help to account for the renewal of Western interest
in Confucianism. For example, Jiyuan Yu (2007) argues that the concept
of eudaimonia (happiness, living well, flourishing) in Aristotle and the concept of dao (the
way for human beings to live) in Confucius are parallel starting points in their ethics, and
that the next step in both their ethics is to discuss virtue (arete for Aristotle and de for
Confucius). In general, Chinese and Western virtue ethics converge in focusing on certain
virtues as crucial for ethical development of the person. There are particularly interesting
discussions of courage and the possible role of fear in Mencius and Aristotle (see Van
Norden, 1997, 2007). Particularist modes of reasoning in Confucianism parallel the
Aristotelian notion of a phronesis or practical wisdom that depends significantly on
knowledge of particulars acquired through experience. A good example is his doctrine of the
mean, which holds that virtuous action and feeling consists of avoiding the extremes of
deficit and excess. The doctrine does not imply that we ought always to act moderately and
with moderate feeling. Aristotle says that the mean is relative to us, giving the illustrative
analogy that too little food for Milo is too much for the beginner in athletic exercises
(Nichomachean Ethics, 2.6). Depending on the situation, the appropriate action and feeling
may be extreme on a common sense understanding but appropriate given the agent and the
circumstances. Part of the contemporary revival of virtue ethics is premised partly on a
reaction against the ambition of modern ethical theory to guide primarily through general
principles of action rather than through the specification of ideal character traits. Virtue
ethics also tend to embody the theme that the ethical life of right (and in the case of Chinese
and contemporary Western virtue ethics) caring relationship to others is necessary for human
flourishing. In the Mencius this theme emerges in identification of the distinctively human
potentials with the incipient tendencies to develop the moral virtues (Mencius 2A6, 6A1,
6A3, 6A7). Aristotle held that reason makes us distinctively human and that our reason and
social nature compel recognition of the desirability of the ethical life for human beings (see
Nivison, 1996 for comparisons of Aristotle and Mencius; and Yearley, 1990 for comparisons
of Acquinas and Mencius). Xunzi is equally emphatic about the necessity of right and caring
relationship to others for human flourishing, even though he denies (at least when he is
criticizing Mencius) that human nature contains tendencies to engage in such relationships
(see Ivanhoe, 1991, on the way ethical norms help human beings to flourish; and Nivison,
1996a, 1996b, Van Norden, 1992, 2007, Wong, 1996b, and Kline, 2000, on the difference
between Mencius and Xunzi's theories of human nature; see Goldin, 1999, for a book-length
treatment of Xunzi's philosophy).
The similarities coexist with significant differences, however. There is no parallel in Greek
virtue ethics for the centrality of family life in the Confucian conception of the good life. Part
of the reason for this lies in the Confucian appreciation for the family as the first arena in
which care, respect, and deference to legitimate authority is learned (Analects 1.2; see also
Cline, 2007, 2013 for a discussion of the Confucian view of the family in moral development
and for an interesting comparison to John Rawls' conception of the role of the family). Van
Norden (2004, 2007) points out that the moral emotion of shame plays a crucial role in
Mencius' conception of moral development and that there is no comparable role played by
the emotion in Aristotle. He suggests that the explanation lies in Mencius' greater focus on
moral agency in media res. The way in which particularist reasoning is illustrated in
historical stories such as those about Shun is also a distinctive feature of Confucian ethics.
These stories present paradigms of good judgment and of good individuals, from which
persons engaged in ethical cultivation of themselves should learn. Another distinctive feature
of Confucian ethics is the emphasis it gives to an aesthetic dimension of the good life. To act
according to ritual propriety is not simply to conform to notions of appropriate behavior in
this or that context. It is to act with the right attitude, reverence, say, in the case of serving
one's parents in an appropriately respectful manner, and it is to express such an attitude so
gracefully and without internal conflict that doing so has become second nature (see
Kupperman, 1999 and Cua, 1997). The importance attached to li, to ritual propriety itself,
indicates the Confucian appreciation for the role of culture and convention in enabling
human beings to express ethical attitudes toward each another such as care and respect (see
Cua, 2005 for rich explorations of li in the thought of Xunzi). It is not as if bowing
naturally means deferential respect; it must be agreed through convention that it does mean
something like this (see Fingarette, 1972; see Shun, 1993, for a discussion of the relationship
of li to the important virtue of ren). Mencius and Xunzi engaged in a vigorous, provocative
debate over human nature and whether there are natural tendencies that form the basis for
development of a good person. They debate in a highly sophisticated manner issues as to
whether ethical norms and values are discovered or invented, and their arguments are based
partly on what would make for a plausible explanation of how human beings develop into
goodness and of how they become bad. Taking all these distinctive features together, it is fair
to say that Confucianism offers an especially rich moral psychology (see Nivison, 1996, for
several influential essays on moral psychology in comparative perspective, including
Motivation and Moral Action in Mencius, Philosophical Voluntarism in Fourth-Century
China, Two Roots or One? and Xunzi on Human Nature).
One debate that arises within the comparative perspective, however, is whether the
Confucians had anything that fits the Western notion of morality. The words ethics and
ethical have been used to in this piece to remain neutral on this matter. Some contemporary
thinkers (most prominently, Williams, 1985) have tended to confine the moral to a
relatively narrow set of characteristics associated with Kant's moral philosophy a belief in
universal laws validated by pure reason, a belief that responsibility for one's actions requires
a freedom from determination from external causes and on this view of the moral, it could
be argued that there is no equivalent in Chinese philosophy (see Rosemont, 1988). If such a
contrast is made, then Confucians are acknowledged to have an ethics as opposed to a
morality, where an ethics does embrace questions about value, how one ought to live one's
life, and what the good life consists in. One question to be debated here is whether Western
notions of the moral are so uniform and narrow as to conform to one philosopher's (even a
great one) specific conception of the moral. On the criteria given by Williams, Hume
wouldn't have a morality, even though he used the term. It is true that a dominant strain of
modern Western morality makes use of a crucial distinction between a morally significant
sphere of life that has to do primarily with one's relationships with others and a private
sphere of life in which one has moral time-off that is no one's business but one's own. If
this dominant strain is taken to define morality, then Confucians would have no morality. It
also would eliminate certain utilitarians from having a morality: those who insist that there is
no purely private sphere because any type of action or omission could have substantial
impact on others given the right circumstances.
Another potential contrast arises from the focus in modern Western moralities on individual
rights to liberty and to other goods, where the basis for attributing such rights to persons lies
in a moral worth attributed to each individual independently of what conduces to individual's
responsibilities to self and others. Confucianism lacks a comparable concept, given its
assumption that the ethical life of responsibility to others and individual flourishing are
inextricably intertwined (Shun, 2004). A frequent criticism from the Western side is that
Confucianism fails to provide adequate protection to those legitimate interests an individual
has that may conflict with community interests. On the other side, some advocates of
Confucian ethics criticize rights-focused moralities for ignoring the social nature of human
beings and of portraying human life in an excessively atomistic or individualist
conception of persons (e.g., Rosemont, 1986). Against those who argue that Confucianism
does not protect the individual enough, it could be replied that the Confucian framework of
responsibilities to others can afford significant protections to the individual and arguably
addresses the human need for community and belonging better than rights frameworks
(Rosemont, 1991, 2004). Another criticism from the Western side is that the dignity of the
individual cannot be honored without recognition of individual rights. It has been replied,
however, that dignity can lie in one's human capacity to participate in the distinctively human
life of relationship and in living up to one's responsibilities to others (Ihara, 2004). Moreover,
it is possible that rights in some sense can play a role in the Confucian tradition, even if such
rights are not grounded in the idea of the independent moral worth of the autonomous
individual. Within that tradition, rights may be seen as necessary for protecting individuals'
interests when the right relationships of care irretrievably break down (Chan, 1999). Rights
in the sense of justified claims to be protected in one's speech even when protest and
dissenting against authority can be justified as conducive to the health of the community
(Wong, 2004). Mencius recognized a right to revolution against tyrannical kings (1B8); he
furthermore advised kings to attach more weight to the opinions of his people than to those
of his ministers and officers in making certain crucial decisions (1B7). Xunzi recognized the
need for subordinates to speak their views freely to their superiors (Xunzi, Zigong, Way of the
Son). If we carry the reasoning in Mencius and Xunzi one step further, we see the need to
protect a space in which they may speak freely without fear of suppression, and hence a
derive a right in the thin sense of what one has whenever one has justifiable claims on
others to assure one's possession of things or one's exercise of certain capacities. (This article
focuses on rights in relation to classical Confucianism. For a detailed discussion of rights
discourse in seventeenth and eighteenth century Confucianism, see Angle, 2002). On the
other side, one must be wary of oversimplifications of Western rights-oriented ethical codes.
The social nature of persons is not denied by all such codes (of the major theories only
Hobbes seems to take an unambiguously atomistic view of human beings, and Rousseau
and Locke seem to require no such view).
The fact that there are developments of each tradition that bring each closer to the other may
suggest that each could learn from the other. Even if not all rights-oriented codes are
atomistic, an increasing worry about Western culture as it has actually developed in
practice is the prevalence of an individualism that Tocqueville defined as a calm and
considered feeling which disposes each citizen to isolate himself from the mass of his fellows
and withdraw into the circle of family and friends, such that with this little society formed
to his taste he gladly leaves the greater society to look after itself. Such people, Tocqueville
observed, form the habit of thinking of themselves in isolation and imagine that their whole
destiny is in their hands. They come to forget their ancestors and also their descendants,
as well as isolating themselves from their contemporaries. Each man is forever thrown back
on himself alone, and there is danger that he may be shut up in the solitude of his own heart
(1969, pp. 506, 508). Those impressed with this worry and connect it with gross inequality in
the most affluent nation in the world would do well to look to a tradition that appreciates the
way we thrive or falter within specific communities that nurture or shut us out. Or consider
an intriguing argument by Bell (2008, pp. 4355) that in contemporary East Asian societies
the importance placed on social hierarchy provides an outlet for the rich and powerful
members of these societies to distinguish themselves, whereas in socially egalitarian societies
such as the U.S., the primary outlet is through the accumulation of wealth, and hence the
relative economic equality of East Asian societies as compared to Western societies such as
the U.S. On the other side, a tradition that has tended to value the idea of social harmony at
the cost of sufficiently protecting dissenters who desire to point out abuses of power or just
plain bad thinking by authorities would do well to look at another tradition that does not
value social harmony as highly but has endured and is vigorous.
These arguments for greater compatibility between Chinese and Western ethics do not
eliminate all significant differences between them on the subject of rights. It is possible to
argue that even if responsibility-frameworks are developed and institutionalized to provide
genuine protection to dissenting individuals, they cannot provide as much protection as rights
frameworks when individual interests seriously threaten communal or social interests. And if
Western ethics sometimes provides more protection to the individual against communal or
social interests, this could be seen as unacceptable from a Confucian standpoint. One
possible stance on these kinds of differences is evaluational incommensurability. The stance
is that each tradition is not wrong to emphasize different values, that no judgment of
superiority can be made here. The argument for this may start with the claim that each sort of
ethic focuses on a good that may reasonably occupy the center of an ethical ideal for human
life. On the one hand, there is the good of belonging to and contributing to a community; on
the other, there is the good of respect for the individual apart from any potential contribution
to community. It would be surprising, the argument goes, if there were just one justifiable
way of setting a priority with respect to the two goods, even when we take into account the
justifiable ways in which the two kinds of ethics could be brought closer together. On this
view, comparative ethics teaches us about the diversity and richness of what human beings
may reasonably prize, and about the impossibility of reconciling all they prize in just a single
ethical ideal (e.g., Wong, 1984, 1996).
Daoist ethics are often cited as exemplars of substantial difference with the Western
tradition. Both the Zhuangzi's and Daodejing's commendation of wuwei is a case in point. It
is a commendation of a style of action that consists in being receptive rather than aggressive,
following from behind rather than leading in front, accommodating rather than
confrontational, and being flexible and ready to change with the situation rather than rigid
and operating from general predetermined principles. While the theme of attunement with
the world is present at the roots of Western traditions, no major ethic in the West gives the
ideal of spontaneous, effortless attunement the kind of centrality Daoism gives to it, and
indeed, Slingerland (2003) argues that the ideal of spontaneous and effortless action that is in
accord with the normative order of the cosmos is quite important to the early Confucian
thinkers. Ames (1994) traces the wu-wei ideal as it is applied to rulership in Confucianism,
Daoism, and Legalism.
Another case for substantial difference with the Western tradition rests on the strong
skepticism in Daoist ethics about the benefits of conceptualized distinctions between good
and bad, right and wrong. Yet these ethics make recommendations that add up to putting
forward a way of life. In the Zhuangzi, that way of life involves not taking taking oneself and
one's ideas so seriously. Chapter two contains a story of monkeys who were furious with
their keeper when he announced the policy of three nuts every morning and four in the
evening. The keeper then announced a change: four nuts in the morning and three in the
evening, this time to the great delight of the monkeys. Kupperman (1999) suggests that we
are invited to view our own urgent concerns in the humorous light of the monkeys' concern
about the difference between the two policies. At the same time we are invited to question
our own judgment of the monkeys. Why think the monkeys are silly if our urgent concerns
might look to some other kind of creature the way the monkeys' concerns look to us? The
way of life recommended in the Zhuangzi, then, includes openness to what might escape our
current conceptualizations and preconceptions. We are invited to see that our
conceptualizations of the world are inevitably incomplete and distorting. We attempt to order
the world by sorting its features under pairs of opposites, but opposites in the real world
never match up neatly with our conceptual opposites. Real opposites escape our attempts
to cleanly separate them. Despite our best efforts, they switch places in our conceptual maps,
blur, and merge into one another. That is why chapter two of the Zhuangzi says that the sage
recognizes a this, but a this which is also that, a that which is also this.The
appropriate response to the inadequacies of our conceptual structures is to remain open to
what those structures distort or hide. In chapter five, men who have had their feet amputated
as criminal punishment are scorned by society, but not by their Daoist masters, who see what
is of worth in them. In chapter one, Zhuangzi chastises his friend Huizi for failing to see
beyond the ordinary, humdrum uses of some large gourds. Huizi tried using one of the
gourds for a water container, but it was so heavy he couldn't lift it. He then tried to make
dippers from them, but they were too large and unwieldy. He deemed the gourds of no use
and smashed them to pieces. Zhuangzi asks why he didn't think of making the gourd into a
great tub so he could go floating around the rivers and lakes, instead of worrying because it
was too big and unwieldy to dip into things! Obviously you still have a lot of underbrush in
your head! concluded Zhuangzi. He does not deny that the more ordinary uses are genuine
uses for the gourds, and indeed, they are. Rather, Zhuangzi's point is to clear the underbrush
from our heads and to get an enlarged view of what is of value. Much of the value of Daoist
ethics lies in its warnings against the constricting effects of conventional ethical codes, the
blinkering of vision that comes with what we might otherwise regard as admirable integrity
and dedication. The other side of this warning is an intriguing positive: that there is a way we
can pay attention to the world that allows us to see around our blinkering
conceptualizations, to see what is of value that we have missed, to move with the grain of
things. One of the central interpretive problems concerning the Zhuangzi in particular is how
to reconcile the skeptical themes about the limits of our concepts and theories with the
recommendations for living in a certain way, since the recommendations are framed with
concepts (see Kjellberg and Ivanhoe, 1996, Hansen, 2003, and Wong, 2005 for a variety of
interpretations).
It is not easy to find an analogue to someone such as Zhuangzi in the Western tradition.
There are some important parallels in the Hellenistic Stoics and Epicureans to certain themes
in Zhuangzi. They, like him, emphasized the need to accept the inevitable in human life, the
need to dampen one's desires to achieve tranquillity in the face of the inevitable, and to
identify with the world that makes acceptance and dampening of desires possible
(Nussbaum, 1994). On the other hand, there is contrast in the Stoic belief in logos as the
basis of order in the universe. There are parallels to some Zhuangist themes in Nietzsche: the
skepticism about the adequacy of our conceptualizations of the world and of value; the
warnings against conventional moralities as constricting, and the awareness of how the
application of ethical judgment to others can be a means of asserting power over them (The
Genealogy of Morals). However, Zhuangzi's vision possesses a generosity and inclusiveness,
an embrace of the lowly and cast-off, that seems anathema to Nietzsche's celebration of the
bermensch and his project of fashioning himself like a work of art. Nietzsche proposes
strong, vital desire at the heart of this aesthetic project, rather than the dampening of desire.
He represents a kind of radical individualism that did not find a congenial home in the
Chinese tradition (Solomon, 1995).
In Buddhism, especially Chan Buddhism, there also is rejection of conventional ethical
values as blinkering and distorting (see Hui Neng, Liuxu tanjing, and The Recorded
Conversations of I-Hsan), and also a sense that one can become attuned to the world so as
to move with its grain. This is not surprising since Buddhism was profoundly influenced by
Daoism upon its importation into China. However, Buddhism may have especially
challenging implications for Western ethics in its special emphasis on the elimination of
suffering and on the way it explains suffering by referring to the human attachment to self as
fixed ego entity. As noted above in discussing Parfit's connection to the Buddhist view of the
self, realization that the self is not a bounded and discrete entity may encourage a much more
impersonal view of oneself and one's projects and desires. One's concern widens to all of life,
and one dampens one's desires so as to lessen attachment to the self's cares and concerns.
Some may find this an unacceptably demanding ethic. It may seem to drain all passion from
life, and it requires that we dampen the attachment we have not only to our selves but also to
special others. This negative reaction may fit with Kupperman's (1999) characterization of
much Western ethics as upholding only a limited altruism that allows one a private sphere of
life free from moral demands and in which one gives much more weight to the cares and
concerns of the self and those close to the self. However, as the above comparison with Parfit
suggests, there are themes in Western philosophy that parallel the kind of impersonal
altruism urged upon us by Buddhism. Some utilitarians have strongly held to the theme that
each counts for one in calculating what produces the greatest good, and they have derived
challenging consequences from that theme for the question of what one should be prepared to
give to alleviate the suffering of strangers (see Singer, 1972, and Unger, 1996), arguing that
the way many in affluent nations indulge themselves and their own is simply insupportable in
a world of widespread and severe suffering. Some have seen the sort of impersonal concern
that utilitarianism may demand as an indication that it unsuitable for human beings, who are
so strongly partial to themselves and their own (see Williams, 1981 and Wolf, 1982).
Buddhism presses for the possibility that impersonal concern is humanly possible, and the
fact that it is a vibrant and long-lived tradition with many committed practitioners provides
some support for the viability of impersonal concern as a ideal that is capable of claiming
allegiance and influencing how people try to live their lives (see Flanagan, for a reference to
Buddhism in support of the viability of such an ideal .

4. Why Do Comparative Philosophy If It's So


Hard?
The most obvious sin of doing comparative philosophy is assimilating another tradition to
one's own by unreflectively importing assumptions, frameworks, and agendas into one's
reading of that other tradition. Sometimes too much charity (as a principle of interpretation)
is insufficiently respectful of the distinctness of the other tradition. There are more subtle
dangers. If one is a dissident from main trends in one's home tradition, one is tempted to find
another tradition that got it right. This is fine as long as the desire to find another such
tradition does not lead to distortion or oversimplification of that other tradition (see Hansen,
1992, 2004, for discussions of taking Confucianism as representative of the Chinese tradition
as a whole and of trying to find in Confucianism something one may perceive as lacking in
one's own tradition). These are dangers one can recognize but not always avoid successfully,
because success may require knowing a lot about the other tradition when it is hard enough
to master a single tradition to the point where one can avoid saying silly things about it. Are
the risks worth it?
One reason for thinking so is that comparative philosophy is an instance of a sound and
sensible strategy for doing philosophy. When facing hard problems it is simply a good
strategy to consider a wide range of enduring, respected ideas bearing on those problems. We
of course must be wary of the possibility that the other tradition is not really addressing the
same problem we are, or that it is addressing only part of the problem we are addressing. But
when there is common address of a problem, it is not always the case that one tradition must
be adjudicated as entirely right and the other as entirely wrong. There is a good possibility
that each tradition has something insightful to say about some aspect of the problem and that
each tradition could incorporate something of what the other tradition has to say (see Yu and
Bunnin, 2001). Yu (2007) appropriates Aristotle's conception of the friend as a second self, a
mirror, by which one can come to know oneself better, one's unexamined presuppositions,
for instance. May Sim (2007) argues that Aristotle's metaphysics of the soul supplies a
substantial self that is both needed and presupposed by Confucius' virtue ethics. At the same
time she argues that Aristotle's metaphysics tilts too far towards an individualism that does
not motivate sufficient attention to the culturally laden social relations required by his own
ethics of character and politics of virtue, and so Aristotelian ethics could benefit by taking
from Confucianism an acknowledgment of the ethical importance of ceremony and decorum.
When one crosses traditions in enacting such strategies, there is the opportunity for fruitful
interaction and mutual influence. Already discussed above is the opportunity for fruitful
interaction between rights-oriented traditions and traditions such as Confucianism focused on
the value of relationship and community. Consider another area of potential interaction:
when a tradition as long-lived and as sophisticated as the Confucian tradition brims full with
writing on the nature of agency, human motivation, and the problem of developing ethical
excellence and commitment, one cannot afford to ignore it (see Ivanhoe, 2000, for portraits
of the tradition of Confucian and neo-Confucian thinkers on these subjects). Confucianism
and Daoism emphasize the need to to pay attention to the concrete details of the situation at
hand and displays healthy skepticism about the power of general principle to reveal what sort
of action is suitable to the situation. Confucianism displays an appreciation for the power of
community, custom, convention and ceremony for helping to make vivid and concrete and
meaningful such ethical abstractions as love, respect, and care (Fingarette, 1972, Shun, 1993,
Kupperman, 2004). From these themes, there is much to be learned, especially if one's home
tradition has had a strong focus for a good portion of the modern period on the top-down
deduction of specific ethical judgments from extremely abstract principles. At the same time,
an appreciation for the concrete and for the culturally specific may obscure the possibility of
general and transcultural principles that help to evaluate the concrete and culturally specific,
and the Chinese tradition could benefit from interaction with the Western (Cua, 1985).
Finally, recall the case of the Buddhist ideal of impersonal concern being brought to bear on
a debate in Western philosophy over the viability of ideals of impersonal concern. This
illustrates the point that comparative philosophy can stretch one's sense of possibility, in this
case, of human possibility. That is a benefit in itself.
Comparative philosophy that is done along the Chinese-Western axis can proceed from one
end or the other, in the attempt to bring to bear concepts, frameworks, and insights from one
tradition to the project of making progress on questions and problems in the other tradition.
Kwong-loi Shun (2009) has observed that there has been an asymmetry in the amount of
work done in these two possible directions. There is much more work done that starts from
the Western end and works towards the Chinese end. Shun questions whether there is a good
intellectual grounding for this asymmetry, given that Chinese philosophy promises to
illuminate some aspects of the ethical life that are not as well appreciated or studied in
Western philosophy. The alternative, as Shun puts it, is that that there is no such grounding
and that the [asymmetrical] tendency is just a collective phenomenon explainable in terms of
historical trends that wax and wane over time (2009, p. 475). In speculating about possible
explanations exemplifying Shun's second alternative, it is worth reminding ourselves that the
trends of philosophy are often reflections or distillations of larger historical trends and the
shifting balances of power between different regions of the world. If this is so, we may be
witnessing an incipient correction in the asymmetry between Chinese and Western
philosophy.
Wong (2009) develops a metaethical theory drawing from contemporary forms of
philosophical naturalism, Hume, Mencius, and Xunzi. Stephen Angle (2012) defines two
kinds of comparative philosophy: (a) "rooted global philosophy" is working within a
particular live philosophical tradition in such a way as to be open to stimulus and insights
from other philosophical traditions, and (b) "Constructive engagement," on the other hand, is
an approach that is focused on the interaction of stimulus and insights between two live
philosophical traditions. Angle exemplifies the rooted approach by working within the neo-
Confucian tradition and by being open to exchange with other philosophies, primarily within
the American tradition. At the same time, his position as an American philosopher allows
Angle to focus on mutually enriching interaction between American philosophy and neo-
Confucianism. Joseph Chan is grounded both in Confucian ethical and political thought,
primarily classical, and in contemporary Anglo-American political philosophy. He regards
himself as a Confucian scholar in the sense of one who engages in the activity of making
sense of Confucian thought, and develops, revises, and improves it as a tradition. At the same
time, his proposed improvements of the tradition are related to a broader argument that the
modern language of freedom, rights, and democracy should not and will not replace the
traditional language of virtue, responsibility, and benevolent care, but rather be enriched by it
(2013). Hutton (2006), Sarkissian (2010) and Slingerland (2011) develop responses based on
Confucian moral psychology and virtue ethics to challenges mounted by Gilbert Harman
(1998-99) and John Doris (2002) to the viability of virtue ethics (as conceived in the Western
tradition). As mentioned above, Cline (2007, 2013) argues that insights from
the Analects and from Rawls can be combined to produce a more plausible conception of
how a sense of justice develops starting with the family. All this indicates that the balance of
contribution from the Chinese tradition has strengthened considerably.

Bibliography
Ames, Roger T. (1994), The Art of Rulership: A Study of Ancient Chinese Political
Thought, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Angle, Stephen C. (2002), Human Rights in Chinese Thought: A Cross-Cultural Inquiry,
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Angle, Stephen C. (2012), Sagehood: The Contemporary Significance of Neo-Confucian
Philosophy, New York: Oxford University Press.
Bell, Daniel A. (2008), China's New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday Life in a
Changing Society, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Chan, Joseph (1999), A Confucian Perspective on Human Rights for Contemporary
China, in The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, eds. Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel
A. Bell, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chan, Joseph (2013), Confucian Perfectionism: A Political Philosophy for Modern Times,
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Cheng, Chung-ying (1989) Chinese Metaphysics as Non-metaphysics: Confucian and
Daoist Insights into the Nature of Reality, in Understanding the Chinese Mind: The
Philosophical Roots, ed. Robert E. Allinson, Hong Kong: Oxford University Press.
Cheng, Chung-ying (1991), New Dimensions of Confucian and Neo-Confucian
Philosophy, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Cline, Erin M. (2007), Two Senses of Justice: Confucianism, Rawls, and Comparative
Political Philosophy, Dao, 6: 361381.
Cline, Erin M. (2013), Confucius, Rawls, and the Sense of Justice, New York: Fordham
University Press.
Cooper, David E. (1978), Moral Relativism, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 3: 97108.
Cua, Antonio (1985) Ethical Argumentation: A Study In Hsn Tzu's Moral Epistemology,
Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Cua, Antonio (1997) Moral Vision and Tradition: Essays in Chinese Ethics, Washington,
D.C.: Catholic University of America Press.
Cua, Antonio (2005) Human Nature, Ritual, and History: Studies in Xunzi and Chinese
Philosophy, Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.
Davidson, Donald (1969), Truth and Meaning, in Philosophical Logic, eds. J.W. Davis,
D.J. Hockney, and W.K. Wilson, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Davidson, Donald (1980), Thought and Talk, in Mind and Language, ed. Samuel
Guttenplan, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Davidson, Donald (2001), On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme, in Inquiries into
Truth and Interpretation, 2nd edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Doris, John (2002), Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Fingarette, Herbert (1972), Confucius: The Secular as Sacred, New York: Harper.
Flanagan, Owen (1991), Varieties of Moral Personality, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press.
Flanagan, Owen (2013), The Bodhisattva's Brain: Buddhism Naturalized, Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Fleischacker, Samuel (1992) Integrity and Moral Relativism, Leiden: E.J. Brill.
Goldin, Paul Rakita (1999), Rituals of the Way: The Philosophy of Xunzi, La Salle, Ill.:
Open Court.
Grandy, Richard (1973), Reference Meaning and Belief, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 439
452.
Hall, David L., and Ames, Roger T. (1987), Thinking Through Confucius, Albany: State
University of New York Press.
Hansen, Chad (1992), A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought: A Philosophical
Interpretation, New York: Oxford University Press.
Hansen, Chad (2003), Guru or Skeptic? Relativistic Skepticism in the Zhuangzi
in Hiding the World in the World: Uneven Discourses on the Zhuangzi, ed. Scott Cook,
Albany: State University of New York Press.
Hansen, Chad (2004), The Normative Impact of Comparative Ethics, in Confucian
Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community, eds. Kwong-loi Shun
and David B. Wong, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Harman, Gilbert (199899, Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics
and the Fundamental Attribution Error, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99: 315
31.
Hutton, Eric (2002), Moral Connoisseurship in Mengzi, in Essays on the Moral
Philosophy of Mengzi, eds. Xiusheng Liu and Philip J. Ivanhoe, Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Company.
Hutton, Eric (2006), Character, Situationism, and Early Confucian
Thought, Philosophical Studies, 127: 3758.
Ihara, Craig K. (2004), Are Individual Rights Necessary? A Confucian Perspective,
in Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community, eds.
Kwong-loi Shun and David B. Wong, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Ivanhoe, Philip J. (1991), A Happy Symmetry: Xunzi's Ethical Thought, Journal of the
American Academy of Religion, 59: 309322.
Ivanhoe, Philip J. (2000), Confucian Moral Self Cultivation, second edition, Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing.
Ivanhoe, Philip J. (2002), Chinese Self Cultivation and Mengzi's Notion of Extension,
in Essays on the Moral Philosophy of Mengzi, eds. Xiusheng Liu and Philip J. Ivanhoe,
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
Kasulis, Thomas P. (2002), Intimacy or Integrity: Philosophy and Cultural Difference,
Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Kjellberg, Paul, and Ivanhoe, Philip J. (eds.) (1996), Skepticism, Relativism, and Ethics in
the Zhuangzi, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Kline III, T.C. (2000), Moral Agency and Motivation in the Xunzi, in Virtue, Nature, and
Moral Agency in the Xunzi, eds. T.C. Kline III and Philip J. Ivanhoe, Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Co.
Kupperman, Joel J. (1999), Learning from Asian Philosophy, New York: Oxford University
Press.
Kupperman, Joel J. (2004), Tradition and Community in the Formation of Character
and Self, in Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community,
eds. Kwong-loi Shun and David B. Wong, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Lafargue, Michael (1992), The Tao of the Tao Te Ching, Albany: State University of New
York Press.
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1988), Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press.
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1989), Relativism, Power,and Philosophy, in Relativism:
Interpretation and Confrontation, ed. Michael Krausz, Notre Dame: University of Notre
Dame Press.
Moody-Adams, Michele M.(1997), Fieldwork in Familiar Places: Morality, Culture, &
Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Mou, Bo (ed.) (2006), Davidson's Philosophy and Chinese Philosophy: Constructive
Engagement, Boston: Brill.
Naes, Arne, and Hanay, Alastair (1972), Invitation to Chinese Philosophy: Eight Studies,
Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
Neville, Robert (1989), The Chinese Case in a Philosophy of World Religions
in Understanding the Chinese Mind: The Philosophical Roots, ed. Robert E. Allinson,
Hong Kong: Oxford University Press.
Nivison, David S. (1996a), The Ways of Confucianism, ed. Bryan Van Nordan, La Salle, Ill.:
Open Court.
Nivison, David S. (1996b), Response to Wong, in Chinese Language, Thought and
Culture: Nivison and His Critics, ed. P.J. Ivanhoe, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court.
Nussbaum, Martha C. (1994), The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic
Ethics, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Parfit, Derek (1984), Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Richardson, Henry, Practical Reasoning about Final Ends, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press: 1997.
Rorty, Richard (1989), Contingency, irony, and solidarity, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rosemont, Henry (1988), Against Relativism, in Interpreting Across Boundaries,
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Rosemont, Henry (1991), A Chinese Mirror: Moral Reflections on Political Economy and
Society, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court.
Rosemont, Henry (2004), Whose Democracy? Which Rights? A Confucian Critique of
Modern Western Liberalism, in Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self,
Autonomy, and Community, eds. Kwong-loi Shun and David B. Wong, New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Sarkissian, Hagop (2010), Minor Tweaks, Major Payoffs: The Problems and Promise of
Situationism in Moral Philosophy, Philosophers' Imprint, 10: 115.
Shun, Kwong-loi (1993), Jen and Li in the Analects, Philosophy East & West, 43: 457
479.
Shun, Kwong-loi (1997), Mencius and Early Chinese Thought, Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Shun, Kwong-loi (2004), Conception of the Person in Early Confucian Thought,
in Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community, ed.
Kwong-loi Shun and David B. Wong, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Shun, Kwong-loi (2009), Stuydying Confucian and Comparative Ethics: Methodological
Reflections, Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 36: 455478.
Shweder, Richard (1989), Post-Nietzschean Anthropology: The Idea of Multiple
Objective Worlds, in Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation, ed. Michael Krausz,
Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Siderits, Mark (2003), Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy: Empty Persons,
Aldershot, Hampshire, UK.
Sim, May (2007), Remastering Morals with Aristotle and Confucius, New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Singer, Peter (1972), Famine, Affluence, and Morality, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1:
229243.
Slingerland, Edward (2003), Effortless Action: Wu-Wei as Conceptual Metaphor and
Spiritual Ideal in Early China, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Slingerland, Edward (2011), The Situationist Critique and Early Confucian Virtue
Ethics, Ethics, 121: 390419.
Solomon, Robert C. (1995), The Cross-Cultural Comparison of Emotion, in Emotions in
Asian Thought, eds. Joel Marks and Roger T. Ames, Albany: State University of New
York Press.
Stalnaker, Aaron (2006), Overcoming Our Evil: Human Nature and Spiritual Exercises in
Xunzi and Augustine, Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Taylor, Charles (1982), Rationality, in Rationality and Relativism, eds. Martin Hollis and
Steven Lukes, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Tocqueville, Alexis de (1969), Democracy in America, trans. George Lawrence, ed. J. P.
Mayer, New York: Doubleday.
Unger, Peter (1996), Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of Innocence, New York:
Oxford University Press.
Van Norden, Bryan (1992), Mengzi and Xunzi: Two Views of Human
Agency, International Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 161184.
Van Norden, Bryan (1997), Mencius on Courage, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 21:
237256.
Van Norden, Bryan (2001), Mencius and Augustine on Evil: A Test Case for
Comparative Philosophy, in Two Roads to Wisdom? Chinese and Analytic Philosophical
Traditions, ed. Bo Mou, Chicago: Open Court.
Van Norden, Bryan (2004), The Virtue of Righteousness in Mencius, in Confucian
Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community, eds. Kwong-loi Shun
and David B. Wong, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Van Norden, Bryan (2007), Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese
Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, Bernard (1981), Persons, Character, and Morality, in Moral Luck, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Wolf, Susan (1982), Moral Saints, Journal of Philosophy, 79: 419439.
Wong, David (1989), Three Kinds of Incommensurability, in Relativism: Interpretation
and Confrontation, ed. Michael Krausz, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Wong, David (1996a) Xunzi on Moral Motivation, in Chinese Language, Thought and
Culture: Nivison and His Critics, ed. P.J. Ivanhoe, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court.
Wong, David (1996b), Pluralistic Relativism, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 20: 378
400.
Wong, David (2002), Reasons and Analogical Reasoning in Mengzi, in Essays on the
Moral Philosophy of Mengzi, eds. Xiusheng Liu and Philip J. Ivanhoe, Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company.
Wong, David (2004), Rights and Community in Confucianism, in Confucian Ethics: A
Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community, eds. Kwong-loi Shun and David
B. Wong, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wong, David (2005), Zhuangzi and the Obsession with Being Right, History of
Philosophy Quarterly, 22: 91107.
Wong, David (2009), Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic Relativism, New York:
Oxford University Press.
Yearley, Lee H. (1990), Mencius and Aquinas: Theories of Virtue and Conceptions of
Courage, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Yu, Jiyuan, and Bunnin, Nicholas (2001), Saving the Phenomena: An Aristotelian
Method in Comparative Philosophy, in Two Roads to Wisdom? Chinese and Analytic
Philosophical Traditions, ed. Bo Mou, Chicago: Open Court.
Yu, Jiyuan (2007), The Ethics of Confucius and Aristotle, New York: Routledge.
Zukav, Gary (1979), The Dancing Wu Li Masters, New York: Morrow.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi