Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 183

Jason W.

Brown

Neuropsychological
Foundations of
Conscious Experience
“The leaf does not see
that the root is everywhere”.

Goethe

© Les Éditions Chromatika, 2010 ; www.chromatika.org

Dépôt légal : D/2010/11.353/3

ISBN 978-2-930517-07-0

Printed in Belgium

No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner


whatsoever without the prior permission in writing of the publisher
(editions@chromatika.org).

Diffusion : www.i6doc.com et www.vrin.fr

On order in bookshops or via


Diffusion universitaire CIACO, 1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgique,
duc@ciaco.com
Table of Contents

Foreword ............................................................................................................9
Chapter 1 Perception, Memory and Subjective Time............................. 25
Chapter 2 Simultaneity and Serial Order...................................................51
Chapter 3 Theory of the Symptom............................................................. 79
Chapter 4 Inner Speech............................................................................... 103
Chapter 5 Genetic Psychology and Process Philosophy....................... 123
Chapter 6 Foundations of the Self............................................................ 143
Chapter 7 Solipsism and Other Minds......................................................173
Chapter 8 Microgenetic Theory of the Unconscious
1. Philosophy, Psychology and Psychoanalysis................... 197
Chapter 9 Microgenetic Theory of the Unconscious
2. Categories and the Unconscious........................................ 231
Chapter 10 Psychology of Intentionality.................................................... 265
Chapter 11 Subjectivity and Truth.............................................................. 301
Chapter 12 The Inward Path: Mysticism and Creativity......................... 321
References ....................................................................................................... 347
Foreword

“A man sets himself the task of portraying the world.


Through the years he peoples a space with images…
Shortly before his death, he discovers that that
patient labyrinth
Of lines traces the image of his face.”

Borges, Dreamtigers

The theory described in this book, the outcome of over thirty years
of clinical study and philosophical speculation, gradually devel-
oped in relation to clinical research and evolutionary anatomy.
I would refer the reader to updated papers on microgenesis in
Pachalska and Weber (2008), particularly chapters on anatomy by
Don Tucker, and physiological studies by Talis Bachmann in that
volume. A central theme of my writings has been the subject-ob-
ject relation, which in various guises is the relation of self to world,
mind to nature, experience to reality, memory to perception and
feeling to mechanism. Every philosophy takes a stance on this
problem but it is no less fundamental to psychology, though in
the latter epistemology tends to be implicit in method and bias. I
could say my early work in neuropsychology led me to a subjec-
tivist or internalist approach but it may be closer to the truth to
say the approach realized trends in my own thinking that were
not apparent as the theory took shape. As with the Prelude to Das
Rheingold, what is first came last, leaving the impression that the
conclusions of a lengthy study are its final achievements when in
fact, they were there in the beginning, little by little extracted or
uncovered as the work went on.

Science and psychology take an objectivist or externalist view


of the same material as the subjectivism of the following chapters,
so that some comment is needed to orient the reader to the op-
posing interpretations. Externalism imports objects into the mind
and isolates them from their spatial and temporal context, achiev-
ing an account of mind at the cost of its most essential features.
10 Jason W. Brown Foreword 11

The direct or realist view tends to pronounce the objects of per- was a time before the universe was purged of subjectivity or divin-
ception the constituents of reality, first extracting the subjective ity and mind was pervasive that nature was replete with spirit and
from nature, then from mind. Internalism works with the same mentality. This animistic mode of thinking is still found in dream,
data but leads to an account that retains more of the richness primitive cultures and pathological states. I think it is embedded
of its topic even if it often seems untestable and too speculative. in preliminary stages of waking thought. At present, except for
Both accounts have ontological implications. For externalism, it is symptoms or experiences that display a continuum from inner
simply that objects, mental or external, are substance-like, either to outer, there is a bifurcation of nature into two portions, one
physical or logical solids. For the internalism of microgenesis, a mental, one physical, a way of thinking that derives from, and in
becoming over the temporal extensibility of an object or an entity turn supports, the distinction of self and other, past and present,
— a rock or a mental state — deposits the being that the thing be- feeling and mechanism. The bifurcation dissolves in all-mind or
comes. There is much truth in the comment of William James that all-nature by eliminating one of its limbs, the physical in idealism,
the basic problems of psychology — mind and brain, thought and the mental in materialism, the replacement of nature by mind, or
nature, knowledge and reality — are ultimately metaphysical. the gradual removal of mind from nature and brain, restricting
subjectivity to pains, after-images and other qualia, or assuming
There is one reality but many doors through which it is appre- that consciousness is the last remaining problem before mind can
hended, and each doorway is a perspective that takes the reality it be fully reduced to material brain function.
perceives as the true one. Some of these perspectives, especially
those shared by many observers, are taken for a direct view of the It is essential to regain the full scope and character of subjectiv-
one, others are dismissed as perspectival. For most people, the ity to understand the relation of mind to nature. The first step, it
world of perception is the real world. For some, the question is the seems to me, is to account for the origin of the bifurcation, the
degree to which mind encroaches on the physical or the degree to belief in an independent world and the felt boundaries of mind in-
which the physical is installed in the mind. The debate is whether side the head, or at the surface of the sensory organs. Why do we
the perspective is direct, subjective appearance, a model or repre- believe that mind stops at the ears and eyes and the world outside
sentation, an illusion or false belief. is independent? It seems inconceivable that this marvelous uni-
verse, which has existed for billions of years before we were born,
For the author, knowledge of reality is inferred from its copy or and will continue well after we are gone, is merely an image of a
representation. This takes the subjective to its limits. A long tradi- true reality from which we are forever screened, a reality we will
tion of such thinking includes a negation of the real by denying its never know. Yet everything we see and hear and feel and think
existence, creating an alternate reality in art or mystical contem- and believe — mind in its entirety — is brain activity. This does not
plation, or retreating to dream and fantasy, even psychosis. The mean there is no external reality, only that it is known through
turn from the world to the mind can rest on dis-illusionment, but it its model in the mind. The reasons for the belief that the world of
can be a choice as to the kind of life one wishes to live. A life lived sight and sound is independent of the observer are manifold but
resolutely in the mind is no less vibrant than one in the world. In they bear enumeration and discussion.
my view, the inner life, or an intuition of the primacy of the sub-
jective, is the starting point of philosophy. In an echo of Descartes,
Schelling (1800/1978; p. 31) wrote that “the science of knowledge
cannot proceed from anything objective, since it actually begins
with a general doubt about the reality of the objective.”

Transitional phenomena help us to understand that the divi-


sion of mind and world is not as stark as at first it appears. There
12 Jason W. Brown Foreword 13

1. Development The gaining of reality, or the detachment of perception from the


mind, requires sensory data at the endpoint of this microtempo-
In a capsule, the paradigm for mental development is mitosis, ral development.
division within a membrane. In mind, the first division is subject
and object, which is a psychological mitosis within the subjective When sensory constraints are in abeyance and the world is
field of the organism. The object, or objective world, does not so still present, say when we close our eyes and the visual data that
much confront the subject as it draws outward and objectifies a impinge on the brain are reduced, earlier phases in thought-de-
portion of a subjective ground. This creates an objective and sub- velopment come to the fore. So long as there are auditory or other
jective segment within the same subjective field. The subject ap- sense data to maintain an external world, these phases are ratio-
prehends and responds to an outside world that is an extension nal and adaptive, as in contemplation, deliberation or sustained
of its subjectivity. This is likely the mode of cognition in animals concentration. With a persistent relaxation of constraints, thought
and young children. can range from creative imagination to daydream and fantasy.
With sensory data markedly reduced or eliminated, as in sleep or
The individuation of subject and object in a subjective ground sensory deprivation, there is dream, hallucination or psychosis.
is the initial phase. Gradually, within the subject-portion, a self Sensation at the neocortical phase of the traversal is the final con-
individuates in opposition to the world and in relation to its own straint on the emerging pre-object. Sensation is essential to the
subjective content. At the same time, the object-portion undergoes analysis and externalization of the pre-object. Otherwise, there is
further articulation. The appearance of proto-intentional, then premature termination or an improbable route of actualization.
intentional, goals still remain within the mind’s outer garment. Personal need must adapt to impersonal reality.
The separation of object from subject is a transition from mind
to world over a continuous sheet of mentation. This occurs in a The final effect on primary neocortex is to model cognition
recurrent sequence from a subjective core to an objective surface to mirror the outer world. In pathological conditions, a veridical
that is constrained by sensation at successive points. It leads to an object can be achieved while preliminary phases are derailed.
objectified image that represents or models a world that results In normal perception, the application of sensation through the
from the pruning of maladaptive form driven by the impact of geniculo-striate pathways partitions the holistic pre-object and its
sensory data on an endogenous process of image-formation. space to a fully objectified image that appears distinct from its
antecedent process in the mind of the observer. The foreshort-
ened, palpable subject-centered space of imagery that underlies a
proximate space of object relations — the perimeter of limb action
or the world of the infant — becomes the open-ended, infinite ex-
2. The impact of sense data panse of waking perception. The transition is so abrupt, the model
After activation to a phase of vigilance or arousal, a construct of so accurate, the passivity and detachment so complete that we
the act- and object-to-be that is organized about the body sets believe the outer world to be the source, not the product, of the
the process in motion, keeps it on track and shapes unconscious perception. The restriction of the analysis and exteriorization to
precursors to their outcomes. Sensory data orient the incipient the distal segment of the mental state cleaves the object from the
act-object at archaic formations in brain to an outcome in rational self, from private thought and feeling, to create an external rim of
thought, veridical perception and adaptive behavior. After the ini- mind filled with seemingly extra-psychic objects. But all it takes is
tial phase, there is a relative suspension of sense data as the con- a brief spell of vertigo as the world spins around the observer to
struct passes to a space of dream, symbolic imagery and thought. remind one that the world before us is an image in the mind.
This phase is then propelled to conscious reason and adaptation.
14 Jason W. Brown Foreword 15

3. Stages in memory and perception tion from self to object or other, but feeling in the object is part
of what the object is, part of its becoming or the process through
The initial phases of the mental state arise out of an instinctual which it is realized. The impression of an external relation to ob-
core — the inherited repertoire of drive categories — then pass jects comes from their outward movement and loss. This splits
through a phase of affective and experiential memories that shape the object off as something external, leaving its affective tonality
conceptual feeling in the direction of perception. Early phases behind. The effect is to reinforce the separation of mind and ob-
are felt as memorial, later ones as perceptual, but a memory is ject and support the belief that the world is not ours to create but
an incomplete perception, and a perception is a memory speci- is out there to observe, react to and experience, which of course
fied to an object. The image transports the experiential past to it is, but not in the manner most people believe it to be. If we
the occurrent present. The same transition occurs in all domains ponder how object-worth or value is generated — the feelings we
of cognition, for example, when a word individuates a semantic have for others, for animals, for things, possessions, memories
category. At successive phases and with sensory guidance, whole- — we come to understand that feeling is not applied to objects but
part shifts eliminate the potential irrelevance or maladaption of develops into them. The intensity of feeling for memory, dream,
possible objects to outer conditions. The transition from a percep- the savoring of the past, the concept of memory as incomplete
tion that is like a memory to a memory that is like a perception perception, all conform to the idea that as the memorial becomes
delivers the present of ongoing experience out of the past of its the perceptual, the affect that accompanies the image distributes
own infrastructure. as value into objects.
The traversal of a pre-perception from phases of distant to Generally, feeling is more intense at early phases of drive
recent memory embeds conceptual, experiential and affective and desire, less so at distal ones of object and word-production.
knowledge within what appears to be a naked object. The conven- Moreover, feeling is felt as a pressure behind or directed to the ob-
tional belief that perception precedes memory merely translates ject, not in it. In states of love or fear, emotion concentrates in one
common sense to theory of mind. The natural impulse is to ask, object that fills attention rather than being distributed evenly over
how can we recall something before we perceive it? But if object- the field. The process that leads outward from categories to ob-
formation is parsed to a model of reality over an endogenous jects accompanies a specification of drive to desire, to affect ideas,
phase-transition, the object incorporates as its trace the memo- feelings of interest and then outward in the externalization of the
rial sequence through which the world is realized. In forgetting, object, as value or worth. The qualitative change over successive
earlier phases in the object are recaptured. Memory is thinking to phases is continuous from activation to termination. Feeling is the
the extent it departs from perception, and perception is memory vitality and becoming of the object and the mark of its realness.
to the extent it fails to reach a veridical endpoint.

5. Mind arises in experience of the world


4. Feeling in opposition to objects
The mind is not a tabula rasa, but to the extent it is so conceived,
We seem to attach and direct feeling to an object. The feeling is it is a tablet on which letters are carved in relief by chipping away
felt inside the person as an interior phenomenon communicated at mal-adaption or redundancy. Mind is endowed with instincts
in speech and action but largely inaccessible to others, as their and other primitive categories of knowledge that form part of the
feelings are to us. Most people believe that feeling is associated to animal endowment. The enrichment of mind through instruction
objects, or derives from them, or that there is an external connec- and experience seems inserted from outside. The diversity of the
16 Jason W. Brown Foreword 17

world is not felt to be created by the observer but exists for enjoy- For the most part, the direction of world events is from cause
ment or suffering, in any event, to be perceived, absorbed, felt, to effect, that of mental events is from possibility to commitment.
stored and digested. There is a powerful impression of mind as a In the world, fact is primary and mind-independent, though in-
container filled by experience rather than sensation shaping the fluenced by probability and contingency. In the mind, possibility
mind to conform or adapt to what is experienced. The reflection is the ground of freedom and fact is the final stage of belief. In
of the physical world is taken for the real. The creativity trimmed mind, the progression is from potential to actual, in the world,
away in each cycle of world-creation is attributed to the internal from cause to effect. Consciousness involves a trajectory from self
portion of mind before the world appears. The incessant novelty to object, and thus mediates a transition from the simultaneity
that is the work of nature — the astonishing creativity of life — in of the unconscious to the temporal order of world events. The
the novelty of each perception is a tributary of creativity in the discovery of transitional phases in the creation of temporal order
mind. undermines a sharp opposition of these two frames of time-expe-
rience.

6. Extension and causality: space and time


One of the earliest objections to a conflation of the mental and
7. Transience and permanence
physical concerns the extension of external space. We know there The inner perception of time and the outer perception of space,
are levels of space formation in the mental state, such as the space the feeling of transience in the mind, the coming and going of
of dream, the space of the body, that of the newborn and congeni- mental phenomena, the evanescence of life generally, the passing
tally-blind, so that an extended three-dimensional space, along of things mental and the endurance of things physical, the stability
with its objects, is achieved out of earlier space-forms. External of objects, the insubstantiality of thought, all combine to set one
space is elaborated over a transition in which an initial non-spatial world against the other. All things are in change, indeed, it is in-
field of insubstantial mind is set in opposition to the extensive trinsic to them, but the tree in my garden will outlast my thoughts
space of a substantial world. about it, the telephone will be there long after my conversation
is over, and the generic cows in the meadow will replicate them-
Subjective time, duration and the virtual present, which pre- selves long after my individuality is lost. Stability is the iteration of
clude instantaneity, differ from objective time-order and the like-objects; impermanence is the iteration of dissimilar ones. It
causal sequence of world events (Bohm, 1980). The causal inter- is a matter of the perceptibility of change and the repeatability of
action of external objects is observed but not felt, unless there is occasions. But, the tendency of mind to apprehend the extremes
impact by an external cause, while in agent-causation, an action rather than the gradations accentuates these distinctions and
willed by the self is strongly felt but not observed. Specifically, we makes overcoming them all the more difficult.
perceive the cause-effect relation in the world and we feel it in the
mind. If we act on a decision, it is not the decision that instigates
the action, but the self that makes the decision and feels an agent
to the act. A decision is not the cause of an action, no more than
options that are blocked, abandoned or exhausted are the cause 8. Evolution and cognition
of inaction. In conscious thought we are informed of acts that are The pillars of evolutionary thought are abundance of form and
instigated at unconscious phases. elimination of the unfit as the environment trims away and pre-
vents the reproduction of less-fit organisms. Adaptation entails a
18 Jason W. Brown Foreword 19

pruning of organism so only those best-fitted to the environment the outcomes of his own image formation. The feeling of passivity
will survive. The population dynamic of evolution is realized in to objects is an essential element in the detachment, but agency
the micro-transition of the mental state. The environment in the is dependent on the nature and the phase of the content it ac-
form of sensation trims away irrelevant or maladaptive possibili- companies. Agency can be lost or regained in pathology, as when
ties so what survives — an act, a thought, an object — is best suited an individual feels that objectified thoughts are transmitted to
to its social or physical habitat. The world of the organism, like others. The differing modes of agency in various forms of mental
that of object-formation, is a limiting point on degrees of freedom. imagery — after-images, eidetic images, memory images, and so
The aim of evolution to produce and reproduce an organism best on — illustrate a transition from the voluntary to the involuntary
adapted to some niche in the physical world is the same as the in the passage outward to objects.
aim of thought to produce and reproduce (replicate) an object
best adapted to a momentary niche in the physical world. Both
processes lead to an objectification and a continual re-testing of
fitness.
10. Knowledge and insight
We are constantly guided by knowledge of the world, especially
the pragmatics of life, much of which is attributed to the cu-
mulative wisdom of common sense. Common sense draws its
9. Agency and recipience considerable authority as a tactic for coping and survival that, by
An essential aspect of the indifference of the world to individual genetic or cultural transmission, has passed down over the ages.
mind, and the feeling that the objects that grow out of us are, like The perils attached to ignoring common sense have, no doubt,
the children we bear, independent of their conception, is the tran- eradicated most of the outliers who raised questions about it or
sition from agency to recipience in the outward-going flow. The acted in a way as to deny what seem to be obvious truths. When
feeling of agency is that of the self willing an action. This feeling applied to behavior in the world, common sense is a reasonable
is conveyed into an action to give it a volitional character. This is strategy. The difficulty arises when such beliefs are transferred to
because agentive feeling deposits in the body, not the world. I do a theory of the mind, or become a standard against which theory
not raise the glass — that would be telekinesis — rather, I move my is judged.
hand which then raises the glass. An action belongs to the agent
because it remains in the body and does not fully externalize. In Much of microgenetic theory is a challenge to common sense
object-development, intermediate phases prior to detachment beliefs, though the theory can explicate their origins. The problem
may have a volitional quality. I can will a mental image to occur occurs when a common sense theory of the world is interiorized
and manipulate it as I like. The image is my image. It has not fully as a theory of mind, or of antecedent phases in the mental state,
separated. In instances of incomplete object-development, agency or when early phases or constituents in perception are described
can be carried outward with the image, as in hallucinatory voices in terms of final ones, or the flux of brain activity is depicted from
that command actions by the percipient observer. the standpoint of external solids, or when memorial or uncon-
scious contents are held to be copies of what is selected by con-
As the endogenous phases that actualize an image are guided sciousness. That a model of the real should grow out of fantasy,
by sensory data to veridical objects, there is a progressive loss that objects are recognized before they are consciously perceived,
of voluntary control, which is ceded to terminal sensory con- that the world is an extension of the mind, that succession in time
straints, finally to the world. As the image detaches and is felt to is generated out of simultaneity, or that the pathology of cogni-
be independent of the perceiver, the agent becomes passive to
20 Jason W. Brown Foreword 21

tion displays preliminary normal phases, is not common sense quantum level in physics, or ambiguities that cannot be resolved
dogma. by calculation, or do not obey some of the laws that underlie pre-
diction, can be attributed to the temporal extensibility of nature,
compounded in the mind, and the inability to escape the psyche
regardless of the instrumentalities that are employed. A slight but
significant error will occur owing to the approximation of mind to
Conclusions reality, or to the psychic process through which reality is encoun-
This introduction describes some of the phenomena that account tered. We study the reality given in mind, not a reality mind can
for our experience of reality, and the bases for believing, indeed, perfectly measure, for even in the most accurate representation
rarely questioning, the naive view that the real world is just as it there is inevitably some immeasurable disparity.
appears before us. We have learned that fact in the world is ap-
pearance in the mind, and that the phase-transition in the actu-
alization of the world, as revealed by pathological conditions and
altered states, is a continuum over neural and psychic substrates,
not a sudden break from mind to nature. As in object-formation,
Acknowledgements
feeling goes into objects as interest, value or worth, seeks reciproc- Those chapters published in other sources have been substan-
ity in friendship or in love and suffers grief in loss. Love is feeling tially revised for this book. The sources are:
that is sequestered in one object of inestimable value, the loss of
that object being an excision of its conceptual precursors in the Chapter 1, in: Brown, J.W. (2008) In: M. Weber and P. Basile (Eds)
self. The notion of the unconscious and the perceptible world as Chromatikon IV: Yearbook of Philosophy in Process.
physical spheres surrounding a psychic arena of consciousness Presses universitaires de Louvain, Belgium.
is refuted by the perturbations of neuropsychology that expose Chapter 2, in: Brown, J.W. (2010) Journal of Consciousness
phases that fill the process from unconscious to conscious and Studies, 17: 7-40.
from consciousness to the world. Chapter 3, in: Brown J.W., Pachalska M. (2003) “The nature of the
symptom and its relevance for neuropsychology”.
The psychic landscape before me is not, I believe, an hallucina-
Acta Neuropsychologica. 1 (1):1-11.
tory vision but a representation of reality, though not the reality it
represents. This changes little for me unless, like a schizophrenic, I Chapter 4, in: Brown, J.W. (2009) Aphasiology, 23:531-543.
feel the phenomenal basis of conscious experience, in which case Chapter 5, in: Brown, J.W. (2005) Process Studies 34:33-44.
the model, in its incompleteness or distortion, is exposed for what
Chapter 6, in: Brown, J.W. (2008) Psychoscience,
it is and life becomes intolerable. To know the real is inaccessible
Vol. http://psychoscience.com (electronic).
is an intellectual challenge or limitation, but to feel it is unreal is to
live in the transition from dream to wakefulness. Chapter 7, in: Brown, J.W. (2008) Riffert, F. and Sander, H.-J. (Eds)
Researching with Whitehead: System and Adventure. Karl Alber
Apart from an entrapment in the mind, the temporal extensi- Verlag.
bility of physical entities, as inferred from that of the mental state, Chapter 9, in: Brown, J.W. (2010) “Microgenetic theory of the
entails that knowledge of a thing is knowledge of the change by unconscious”. In: Andersson, S., Carlsson, I. and Johnsson, P.
which the thing exists. This means that being is not a frozen sub- (Eds) Creativity and Maturity: A Volume Dedicated to Professor
stance or slice but a becoming, a before and an after, that brings Gudmind Smith on the Occasion of his 90th Birthday, January 29,
the thing into existence. It is probable that uncertainties at the 2010. p. 103-127, Wallin and Dalholm, Lund.
22 Jason W. Brown

Chapter 11, in: Brown, J.W. (2009) Tattva Journal of Philosophy


1:84-99.
Chapter 12, in: Brown, J.W. (2008) Creativity Research Journal, 20
(4) 365 - 375.
I want to express my continuing gratitude to those friends who
have patiently heard me out on many of these topics and offered
their own often conflicting but ever insightful opinions. They
include David Bradford, John Cobb, Marcel Kinsbourne, Bruce
Duncan MacQueen, Bob Rieber, Gudmund Smith and Michael
Trupp. This is also an opportunity to mention those teachers
around the world with whom, in the past, I have been fortunate
to work and from whom, by example or contrast, I have learned
so much. These men, directors of the most important laboratories
of their day, now mostly forgotten, include Norman Geschwind
in Boston, Henri Hecaen in Paris, Gudmund Smith in Lund, A. R.
Luria in Moscow, Alexander Fradis in Bucharest, Anton Leischner
in Bonn, and George Miller in New York.

I especially want to express my gratitude to my dear friend


Maria Pachalska for editing this book, creating many new figures
and her advice, support and inspiration over the years.

Finally, I offer this book to my darling wife, Carine, for the quiet
passion she brought into my life of detachment, for giving herself
to be loved and for teaching me the intensity of a life in the pres-
ent that I could only write about.

Jason W. Brown
66 E. 79th. Street, New York, NY 10075
drjbrown@hotmail.com;
www.centerforcognition.org
Chapter 1
Perception, Memory and Subjective Time

“In the sphere of phantasy


we have uncovered the origins of ideas of time.”

Brentano

“It is impossible to meditate on time and the mystery of


the creative passage of nature without an overwhelming emotion
at the limitations of human intelligence.”

Whitehead

1.1. Introduction
This study describes a theory of time, or subjective duration, in
relation to the microgenetic theory of memory and perception.
The theory, presented here only in summary form, developed out
of the study of neuropsychological cases (Brown 1988), and has
been expounded in many other publications (e.g. Brown 1991;
2000; 2005). It would not be an exaggeration to say that the con-
cept of perception that grew out of work in aphasia is the linchpin
of all subsequent theory. Since it was first proposed in the 70’s,
and even to this day, it has met with strong resistance, even ridi-
cule. In those days, there was an overwhelming consensus that
sensory data were processed in the primary cortices, transmitted
to secondary and tertiary areas for the construction of the data
into auditory, tactile or visual objects by way of association-chains,
and projected into external space for perception. This idea of cor-
tical feature detection and object assembly, which has dominated
research in psychology and neuroscience, entails that objects are
composites of sensory data in relation to conceptual mechanisms
for memory and recognition. The naïve realism of direct percep-
tion simply ignores the micro-structure of object formation.
26 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 27

In microgenetic theory, a conscious object is the outcome of cognition. It turns out that mind/brain process is a continuation of
an endogenous process of progressive individuation, in which fetal patterns of growth; put differently, microgenesis exhibits and
sensation acts to prune or delimit alternative possibilities, rather extends to cognition the pattern of growth in morphogenesis.
than being ingredient in the object construction. The object is not
assembled from sense data but individuates or specifies over a Some key points for discussion in this study are the duration of
transition of phases from “core” to “surface”. This account pro- the present, the nature of change, the occurrence of stability for
vides a radical and also a liberating departure from conventional objects and for mental contents, as well as the stability required for
theory and the association anatomy (Flechsig, Meynert, Hubel and the repeatability of the self. The microgenetic concept of memory
Weisel) on which it depends. The concept that perception is pro- follows the perception theory in reversing the standard direction
ductive, not receptive—as first fully drawn out by Bergson—made of process. The transition from self to world is from contents that
possible a new, internally coherent interpretation of a variety of are memory-like to those that are perception-like, from the per-
perceptual disorders in relation to problems of action and motor sonal past to the impersonal present. The theory of memory is
speech. The features of an object are the end-result of the object aligned with that of perception. Within the momentary “structure”
formation, much as finger movements are the outcome of the of the mind/brain state, an object actualizes over phases in decay.
action development. The analysis of pre-object wholes into their The concept of decay, however, supposes a trace that gradually
featural detail reverses the inferred direction of the perceptual degrades. This is a transposition to memory of substance-thought
process. This theory is the explicit or tacit underpinning of all my in psychology. In contrast, microgenetic theory maintains that de-
writings in neuropsychology, as well as in its extension to topics cay is incomplete revival, i.e. memory is realized at successively
in the philosophy of mind. If the theory of perception falters, so earlier phases in the recurrence of the present state.
does all the rest. Conversely, if the theory is shown to be accurate,
The stages of memory that standard theory treats as separate
as recent studies seem to indicate, the enterprise to which it is
components are, for microgenesis, phases uncovered in this “de-
secured should be worth a closer look.
cay” (incomplete revival). These phases are the same as those
The starting point of the theory is the notion that an object- traversed in the original perception. If perception does not begin
formation begins with conceptual primitives that lay down the but ends at primary cortex, memorial phases in the perception
core self and its drive-representations, which are then derived will be prior to the consciousness of the object. The developing
to an empirical self and its conceptual feelings, then to images, object is not first perceived and then conveyed to short and long
and to objects and external space. Each phase is transformed to term stores, but traverses phases in memory on the way to con-
an ensuing phase until the final one actualizes. In the normal scious perception. It seems counter-intuitive that an object should
waking state, the endpoint is that of a conscious object world. In be recognized before it is seen, but on reflection, how could it be
pathology, an intermediate phase can actualize as a premature otherwise? If we do not know what we are looking at until after we
endpoint, or it can serve as the nucleus of an error. The derivation see it, mind is passive to every new perception, dragged along by
occurs as a succession of context-item or whole-part shifts that is whatever object enters the field.
constrained at various points. The internal constraints are those
The temporal lag in perception allows adequate time for a
of habit and the just-preceding state. The external constraints are
preliminary extraction of meaning from stimuli. The passage of
those of sensory data. The transition from unconscious core to
a forming object through a phase of meaning-relations gives the
conscious surface follows the pattern of growth from the archaic
final object as an item that exemplifies a background category. An
to the recent in brain evolution. Prior writings have taken up the
object, say a chair, is not consciously perceived and then relayed
fine structure and anatomical correlations of this system and the
to a field of object concepts for recognition, but is specified out
relation of the evolutionary and maturational growth process to
of a hierarchic system of categories. The temporal lag entails that
28 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 29

perception is not “on-line” with physical world events, that every tend to imagine that we are standing above looking at ourselves
object is an image and that direct perception is a myth. It cor- moving along a line. This “spatialization” of time conforms to the
responds with the lag in the consciousness of voluntary action. time-elimination of space-time of relativity theory. Cognitive sci-
The early decision in a voluntary action, prior to consciousness ence has also eliminated time in the isolation of separate cogni-
of making the decision, implies that the recognition of an object tive and brain modules.
and action on the object are in synch antecedent to conscious-
ness. Finally, the theory of perception and memory leads to an Bergson argued that time (duration) is an iterated point. His
interpretation of the minimal or absolute mind/brain state and account resembles that of the Buddhist theory of ksana, the aris-
the nature of the immediate present. An overlap of mental states ing and perishing of point-instants in a causal series (Stcherbatsky
gives stability and continuity to the experience of self and world. 1930/1992; Brown 1999). In my view, subjective time is neither
However, this overlap introduces problems of some complexity particle nor wave, but in some sense both; wave-like in an actu-
(see below) having to do with the paradox that things exist as ep- alization over the temporal extensibility of elementary physical
ochs, and that incomplete epochs do not have partial existence. entities or brain states, and particle-like in the modularity of the
state once it actualizes. The metaphor that captures this way of
It should be noted that the theoretical approach of microgen- thinking is not a river, but a fountain that recurs over the collaps-
esis, or process-theory more generally, is gaining new adherents ing flow of the previous surge. The final spray of the fountain can
in cognitive psychology, while its initial formulation and ground- be likened to the perception of the object world. It too arises from
ing in clinical studies have received scant attention. This chapter a core and perishes at its surface, then recedes (decays) or is in-
is intended to acquaint the reader with some implications of the completely revived in the ensuing burst. The fountain does not
approach for philosophy of mind. Hopefully, it will also stimulate move in space but constantly replaces itself.
a closer examination of some claims in the current literature for
the originality, even the “revolutionary” status, of “new” concepts Similarly, there is no movement in subjective time; rather a
of self, perception and consciousness, while their priority and continuous iteration of actualizing states. The sequence of ac-
greater specificity in microgenetic theory have been largely over- tualizations can be interpreted as a progression “in time”, with
looked. change from one moment (now) to the next. However, to pursue
the metaphor a little further, in a fountain the change is in the
transition from depth to surface, or from onset to offset, not from
one terminus to the next, nor from one entire sequence (men-
tal state) to the next. We can distinguish the genuine change that
1.2. Time occurs within the mental state, and the apparent change that
In microgenetic theory, subjective time, memory and perception seems to occur—the causal sequence of world events—from one
are all intertwined with the account of the mind/brain state. A perception to the next. The approach to time has some relation to
theory of perception entails a theory of memory: both require a Whitehead’s ideas on the topic (Brown 1998), though he appeared
concept of the mind/brain state, and time or duration is an essen- to believe that time-series was not within an act of concrescence
tial ingredient. For most people, time is a medium for the self to but in successive acts of thought.
travel in physical spacetime, a kind of line along which we move
The concept of two modes of time—an A and B series—is well
and grow and age. Generally, time is viewed as a succession of
established in philosophy (McTaggart 1934/1968). The before/af-
discrete instants that are imagined in relation to clock-time. This
ter or earlier/later series of physical passage is distinguished from
gives the instantaneous or atomic theory. Others think of time as
the past/present/future series of mental states. In the former,
continuous, flowing like a river. Bergson (1988 ed.) wrote that we
one can say that some events are earlier than others and some
30 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 31

later, but not when they occur. The latter requires a perspective in A fundamental problem in psychology is the nature of the now,
which the past and future are conceptualized in relation to a pres- the virtual or specious present (James 1890), that arches over the
ent. Human time-awareness is organized about a now. In this now, physical passage of the before/after series. The present, as a feeling
and essential to its occurrence, the past is realized or revived as of duration, is the basis of the stability of mind and object world.
the state unfolds. The better part of a present object is its memo- In physical passage, past and future do not exist, only the knife-
rial infrastructure. The idea of the future develops in the forward edge of change in a presumed causal succession. The microge-
direction of the intentional, the drive from past to present, the netic concept is that a simultaneous, unconscious core, organized
uni-directional becoming of the state or its subjective aim, as well about ancestral formations in the brain and conceptual primitives
as the conviction that the present moment is not the last. In some in the mind, distributes into, and creates, temporal order in the
respects, microgenetic theory gives the psychological weight of world. This implies that a perceived sequence of events develops
clinical data to the insight of Husserl (1905/1964), in that each out of phases in which those events are co-temporal, rather like a
moment includes the past (retention), present (presentation) and composer “hearing” the entirety of a work all at once in his mind
future (protention). However, while the past is revived in every before he commits it to paper or performance. Even if the present
present, and exists as recurrence, futurity is not-yet-existing and is specious or phenomenal, an understanding of its origin is criti-
dependent on the feeling of a surge in each state in the transition cal to a facile mind-brain reduction. Cognitive psychology, having
from the self to the world. thrown time out of the window in the isolation of discrete neural
and mental components, now attempts to bring time in through
St. Augustine, one of the greatest minds to tackle this prob- the back door in an ad hoc device, a “binding mechanism” that
lem, would have liked René Magritte’s painting, “The Bridge of supposedly unites the manifold of isolated entities, the temporal
Heraclitus,” which portrays the tension in the before/after series of relations of which should not have been severed in the first place.
Parmenidean and Heraclitean time. Time is flowing in the famous If we return to the metaphor of a fountain, or a tree, it would be
river of Heraclitus or instantaneous as argued by Parmenides and like viewing from above the myriad drops of water, or leaves, and
subsequent thinkers. The former view, represented by the com- imagining a mechanism that binds them together without consid-
pleted shadow of the broken bridge, asks if continuous time is il- ering the momentary genesis of their appearance.
lusory. The latter view, represented by the bridge partly concealed
by clouds, fractures time into instants, and asks if instantaneous Most people think of time in objective terms. William James es-
time is an artifact. The obscuration of the bridge raises the pos- timated the duration of the specious present as up to ten seconds,
sibility that instantaneous time is no less illusory than continuous which falls within the range of immediate and short-term memo-
time, and supports St. Augustine’s uncertainty. For microgenetic ry. Ernst Pöppel (1988) argued that it is about two seconds, based
theory, the metaphor is a fountain, rising again and again and on pause analysis of speech, phrase durations in poetry, even Noh
reviving antecedent states. Subjective time is continuous within drama, and the reversal time for Necker cube and other illusions.
a mental state, while the modularity of the state (see below), or This way of thinking about time, especially the phenomenal pres-
the jump from one state to the next, is consistent with the instan- ent, tends to put subjective time into an external container.
taneous theory. The feeling of duration, as will be discussed, is
created in the actualization process. It is of interest that the gaps, It may seem surprising that a neuropsychology of time barely
or “intervals”, between states are timeless for an individual mind, exists. While there is a large corpus on the psychology of time dis-
and thus do not exist, though one cannot exclude the possibility crimination, fine temporal judgments, fusion thresholds and so
of a multiplicity of other minds in the interstices of our own. on, the literature on brain-damaged subjects is very small; indeed,
it could be read in one afternoon. Hoff and Pötzl (1936/1988), in-
ter alia, described time acceleration and deceleration, in which
32 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 33

time seems speeded up or slowed down, with a posterior brain 1.3. Perception
lesion. Schilder (1936) gave anecdotal reports of time estimation
in Korsakoff patients with severe memory deficits. The patients First I want to point out that the microgenetic model of perception
might claim they were in the hospital for two weeks when they was proposed over 25 years ago from clinical case material (sum-
had been there for three months. One experimental study of in- marized in Brown 1988).
terest was by Richards (1973) on the bi-temporal amnesic, H.M.,
At the time, and for many years after, for most researchers
with a near total loss of memory subsequent to surgery, except for
the theory seemed preposterous. There was little support in the
some procedural skills and affect memory. Richards studied the
experimental literature and there were many seminars and con-
ability of H.M. to make judgments of short durations, extrapolat-
ferences where my presentations were subjected to scathing criti-
ing them to longer durations. He argued that in H.M., a year might
cism. This was true not only for the reversal of flow, but for the role
be experienced as a month or so. This seems plausible in that
of sensation as constraining (sculpting) an endogenous develop-
we do not normally have a sense of one or five years of duration,
ment rather than going into the object construction. However, in
but once we recall the events that occurred during that time, we
the last few years, a number of prominent researchers, though fa-
punctuate the “unfilled” interval and the feeling of duration then
miliar with my work ignore it and claim to have “discovered” what
seems to fill out, so that we have some feeling for its “length”. The
they describe as a radically new, even “revolutionary” concept of
amnesic is unable to articulate duration with remembered events,
perception that is basically the same as the microgenetic account.
so the feeling of duration collapses to a brief interval. However, if
The theory was quite radical when it was first proposed, while
judgments of the duration of a sleep in which the subject does not
the “revolutionary” model that is now bandied about is merely a
awaken are accurate, and if people, as they often do, can awake
gathering consensus on the microgenetic account that has been
just before the alarm clock goes off, duration can be estimated
re-formulated in an experimental vocabulary. What, then, is the
even with a lack of memory for sleep, suggesting there are some
microgenetic theory of perception?
limitations to this interpretation.
The standard connectionist model (Fig. 1a) describes how sen-
The problem of the specious present is clearly related to mem-
sory data are thought to arrive in visual cortex, where specialized
ory, but memory is closely linked to perception, so that an under-
cells, or feature detectors, receive information regarding lines and
standing of these problems is attendant on a theory of the percep-
angles. A preliminary construct is then assembled to a three-di-
tual process. The microgenetic account of perception can help to
mensional object in a transition from V-1 to V-4, where the re-
solve some of these problems, but it does require a suspension of
sultant construct is associated to systems in limbic-temporal lobe
belief in the up-to-now received wisdom of neuropsychology and
for recognition, i.e. matching to memory images, and to parietal
cognitive science, and an openness to another way of thinking
lobes for updating the object in relation to its changing spatial en-
about the perceptual process.
vironment.
34 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 35

endogenous process of whole-part transition to form a model of


the world. The standard account (a) is linear and concatenated
and unrelated to evolutionary growth trends. The microgenetic
account (b) is recurrent, and reflects the direction of evolutionary
growth of the forebrain.

Color and motion detectors add to the mix. This is standard


theory. Basically, the seen properties of an object, its shape, color,
movement, etc., are inserted in the brain as mechanisms or com-
ponents that extract those same properties from the object, and
then reassemble it from the elements into which it has been de-
composed. The object is then projected into external space.

It is important to recognize that connections from V-1 to V-4


are all reciprocal. In fact, there is some evidence that the corti-
cal connectivity in a direction from V-4 to V-1 is much heavier,
possibly ten times as heavy, as that from V-1 to V-4. This suggests
that the processing direction is from V-4 to V-1, not the other way
around. Moreover, the connectivity from V-4 to V-1 with respect
to neocortical layers is similar to that from pre-frontal to pre-mo-
tor to motor cortex, also consistent with an efferent flow from
V-4 to V-1. Microgenetic theory (Fig. 1b) reverses the perceptual
process that has been dogma in neurology for over a century. It
argues that a perception begins in the upper brainstem with a
two-dimensional construct organized about the space of the body.
About one third of the fibers of the optic nerve go to the upper
brain stem, a substantial connection that was formerly thought to
mediate the pupillary reflex. The claim is that this input fashions
an initial configuration, in which action and perception are part
Fig. 1. Two models of how visual perception occurs in the mon- of the same construct, which is then transmitted, in the direction
key brain (after Deacon 1992). In the standard assembly model of forebrain evolution, to successive planes of limbic growth. (The
(a), there is a “forward” progression from primary visual cortex evolution from the cyclical structure of a sensory-motor reflex arc
to association areas, as the object is constructed. In contrast, the to a simultaneous act-object, which distributes into action and
microgenetic account (b) reverses this direction, with the per- perception over levels surrounded by physical tiers of sensory
ception developing from upper brainstem (not shown) through constraints and motor keyboards is described in Brown, 1991;
limbic regions and from V-4 towards V-1. The standard model is cf. Weiszaecker, 1939/1958.)
a construction theory. The microgenetic model is a specification
theory. In (a), sensation provides the building blocks of percep- From the clinical standpoint, in the passage through limbic for-
tion. In (b), sensation serves to constrain, delimit or sculpt an mation there is a relative suspension of input, so that the emerg-
36 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 37

ing pre-object can pass through systems of affective relations The classical model entails a construction or assembly of sen-
and experiential and personal meaning. At this phase, there is an sory bits into larger complexes, while microgenesis is a specifica-
egocentric or volumetric space. The image is fluid, dreamlike and tion model in which sensation acts to constrain an endogenous
hallucinatory. Space is foreshortened with a palpable quality. The image. One is a bricolage of elements, the other an elimination
image is extra-personal yet felt as intra-psychic. The image and its of the irrelevant in the service of adaptation. The former is a syn-
space then pass to systems in the parietal lobe where, perhaps by thesis of multiplicity as parts as assembled into wholes. The latter
way of thalamo-cortical projections, the configuration is further analyses wholes (potential) into parts, leading from unity to diver-
constrained to a three-dimensional object-centered Euclidean sity. As in evolution, where exuberant form is trimmed away by
space. The gestalt-like object is external but not yet detached, and the environment so only the fittest survive, the final object is real-
is still experienced as part of personal space. In some respects, ized by the elimination (failure to individuate) of all other routes
the phase of a proximate space of the arm’s reach is similar to of development save that which occurs. The classical cortical in-
action space, which deposits in the body. The relation of the limb processing approach can be compared to modeling with clay, as
to the object is important. Hallucinations tend to disappear when opposed to the microgenetic account, which is like sculpting out
the person reaches for them. Typically, we ask parietal cases to of marble, as Michelangelo said, to chip away what is unnecessary
draw or manipulate objects to bring out the defect. This space is to expose the form hidden in the block. This account developed
also that of the action-perimeter of the congenitally blind. Finally, from studies of normal and pathological language, which were
the object receives the massive input at V-1, with analysis of the then extended to action, memory, feeling, and other aspects of
gestalt into its featural detail, full exteriorization, and detachment cognition. A strength of the model is its coherence across cogni-
from the self. tive domains. It is also consistent with, indeed it has inspired, an
account of subjective time, change, agency, the derivation of drive
According to this model, the perceptible world is realized to value, and many other topics in theory of mind.
through V-1. It is lost when V-1 is destroyed, as in cortical blind-
ness or hemianopia, though earlier phases in the perception are Regarding the model in Fig. 2, in going from limbic forma-
still preserved. This was first shown by Bender and Krieger (1951) tions to V-1, one also goes from long-term to short-term to iconic
in what came to be called blindsight. Semantic information can memory (see below), from potential to actual, from past to pres-
be extracted from blind fields by priming techniques. In highly ent, from subject to object—or self to other—and from mind to
original work, Tony Marcel demonstrated the ability to access world. On this view, the world is like the skin of the mind. Like
word meanings with presentations to the blind field. It should multi-layered skin in which cells at the surface die off to be re-
be noted that from the beginning the theory claimed that sensa- placed by those from below, mind also sheds its surface objects.
tion did not go into the assembly of an object, but constrained An act of cognition that is mediated by brain tissue derived from
(sculpted) a process that is wholly endogenous. An external object primitive ectoderm creates objects that perish for the next round
is an image at the outermost reach of the mind. While in the stan- of actualization. V-1 realizes the final phase of an object, but em-
dard model, archaic structures come into play at a post-perceptual bedded within that object are antecedent phases, including the
stage, microgenetic theory is consistent with the direction of brain limbic space of dream.
evolution. The mind/brain state consists of a rapid transition from
core to surface with multiple tiers of physical sensation acting to
delimit the process so that the object that actualizes is the only
one possible, given the limits on its development by sensation as
the object adapts to its niche in the external world.
38 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 39

analysis goes from wholes to parts, in which the parts become


wholes for another whole-part transition. The wholes are not mere
sums, and the parts differ qualitatively at each phase. The whole-
part transition is the fundamental algorithm of the mind/brain
state.

The mental state is a bottom-up surge in milliseconds over


evolutionary growth planes. An object has a certain temporal
thickness that incorporates these phases; it takes some “time”
for the object to develop from base to surface or from mind to
world in the system, though subjective time does not exist until
the process is completed. (See Brown, 2005 for discussion of the
temporal extensibility that evolves from elementary entities to the
mind/brain, and the relation of process over this extensibility (be-
coming) to the entity (being) it creates.) It is questionable whether
the before/after of the succession of phases exists before the tra-
versal is complete and the entity becomes what it is in a minimal
Fig. 2. The microgenesis of visual perception, showing levels of duration of existence. The “temporal lag” in perception, like the
object and space realization with corresponding stages of sensory readiness potential and other studies in action, or even the image
constraint (Brown 1988, for anatomical details). The constraints resulting from binocular disparity, indicate that acts and objects
are physical, and do not enter the object-formation. The process is are not “on-line” with the physical world. The transition from
wholly internal or endogenous. limbic planes toward V-1 is also the transition from hallucination,
to illusion, to perception. Pathology at the limbic phase exposes
constructs that are mediated by this segment, i.e. hallucinatory
phenomena in perception, affective experience and meaning-re-
An object is not the endpoint of a conveyer belt or assembly lations in errors that occur with focal brain lesions. At the parietal
line, but is a mental state, or act of thought, that incorporates all phase, there are illusory phenomena, with distortions of objects.
of the phases in its generation. These phases—antecedent to the The distinction of hallucination and illusion—ostensibly between
object, not secondary to it after it has been perceived—account for an endogenous image and the distortion of a real object—reflects
the context, memory, feeling and experience that stand behind the phase in the process where the disruption has its maximum
and are part of the perception. impact. Hallucination refers to a proximal phase, illusion a dis-
In this process, which occurs in a fraction of a second, there tal one. The closer the disruption to the perceptual endpoint the
is also a transition from context to item or from whole to part. more “physical” the properties of the image. The earlier in the
Sculpting involves the elimination or inhibition of cells and con- process the disruption, the more psychic, dream-like or fantastic
nections, while whole-part transitions involve the delimitation of the image. This reflects the degree to which sensory constraints
actualities. There is continuity from patterns in evolution to those delimit the emerging image to model what is “out there” in the
in morphogenesis, and from the latter to the microgenetic pro- physical world. On the microgenetic view, the distinction refers to
cess. The morphogenetic processes of parcellation and neoteny the degree to which the image objectifies.
lay down “force lines” that become the process of cognition. This
implies that mental process is a form of growth (Brown 1996). The
40 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 41

1.4. Time, perception and the mental state


As mentioned, the model of perception was an outgrowth of work
in aphasia. When it became clear that the aphasia model applied
to perception, action, memory, feeling and so on, it was evident
that the theory involved an Urprocess or Bauplan, such that all
aspects of cognition could be explained on a common basis. The
theory also gave flesh to the concept of the mind or brain state.
Philosophers readily discuss mental states, by which they mean
perceptions, propositions, moods, and so on, but the process
over which the state develops or its microstructure is studiously
ignored. Wittgenstein (1953) famously wrote that to “talk of pro-
cesses and states and leave their nature undecided [is …] the deci-
sive movement in the conjuring trick.” The microgenetic account
of the mind/brain state contrasts with the philosophical usage,
Fig. 3. Microgenetic levels in object formation with reduction of in which a mental state can refer to some content in the state di-
sensory constraint: normal and pathological imagery. vorced from its antecedent phases or concurrent context, such
as an image, a proposition, and so on. Microgenetic theory is the
first account of the structure of a mental state in relation to brain
activity. The theory offers a detailed account of the uni-directional
At the level of primary (visual) cortex, pathology gives rise to
process of becoming that lays down the state, and specifies the re-
phenomena that resemble after-images, e.g. palinopsia, where
lation of the phase-sequence to evolutionary and morphogenetic
there is a physical quality to the image, such as increasing size
growth patterns in the structure of the forebrain. The transition is
with projection distance, lack of constancies, or the image appears
that from an unconscious core through a private mental space to
as a film over an object rather than replacing it. It is important to
the external world in a continuous sheet of mentation. We live in a
note that one cannot hallucinate and perceive in the same locus
bubble of personal experience in which successive mental states
of space at the same time. The reason for this is that hallucinatory
are constantly being replaced. The theory of the mind/brain
space is the precursor of object space. An object is a fully real-
state and its replacement entails a novel account of perception
ized, fully-constrained, sculpted or adapted hallucination, while
in relation to evolutionary growth trends. The theory is the basis
hallucination is a disruption within the object-development that
for understanding the duration of the present and the nature of
reveals experientially-driven phases in the formative process. Fig.
subjective time.
3 is a schematic representation of the progression from dreamless
sleep (upper brainstem) through limbic and ensuing stages of hal-
lucination, illusion and other forms of imagery. The normal series
of images is on the left side, the pathological series on the right.

Fig. 4. The overlapping of pulses of consciousness (after James


1890). Each successive pulse develops over the preceding one.
This gives the continuity and identity of the self.
42 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 43

In his Principles, William James took up the Humean problem In Fig. 5, one sees the mind/brain state at a given time, T1.
of how one can account for the repeatability or identity of the self. If we conceive the mental state as a bottom-up derivation that
As is well known, Hume failed to uncover a self on introspection, is replicated with slight deviation, T1 represents the absolute or
but he admitted that he could not explain the sense of identity, minimal duration of a perception, a cognitive moment, a pulse of
choosing to leave this problem to others. James described what he consciousness or a mental state. In line with the account of James,
termed “pulses of cognitive consciousness,” which appear to be T1 is embedded within the state at T2. The argument is that as
equivalent to mental states. In Fig. 4, A represents such a pulse of the trace of T1 fades in state T2, or is incompletely revived, the
consciousness. At B, the next moment, A is a residue over which “vertical” disparity between the perception at T2 and the fading
the new state, B, develops. C unfolds over states A and B. James image of T1 is extracted as a “linear” duration. In other words, the
believed that the overlap of iterated mental states might explain outermost reach of the perceptual process at T2 is compared with
the feeling of identity. While James limited his discussion to the the lapse of the previous state, T1, within T2, and the disparity is
identity of the self, an account of the stability of the self is also an felt as duration over lived time. This duration is experienced as a
account of the stability of objects. Just as the self is replicated in virtual span over the unfelt passage of physical instants.
each overlapping state, so do (visual) objects achieve stability in
the recurrence of the state and the effects on the state of external Conceivably, the disparity between T2 and T1 is similar to the
and internal constraints. perception of depth in the spatial sphere that results from binocu-
lar disparity, as a virtual object resolves the different monocular
As far as I am aware, James did not relate this model to the spe- images. Depth perception is created as an illusory image of space
cious present. In an interesting paper in 1923, Wolfgang Köhler analogous to the illusion of duration. One is created by a dispar-
suggested that the duration of the present develops in the com- ity in spatial images, the other by a disparity in temporal images.
parison of a fresh impression with the fading trace of the prior Along these lines, Whitehead wrote that the third dimension of
one. It may seem obvious that the duration of the present is a space is the ghost of transition. A two-dimensional slice without
comparison between the immediacy of present experience and depth has no temporal thickness. In some sense, the third dimen-
some point in the recent past, but that past point must be in the sion has to have duration or temporal extension. Indeed, I believe
present, for as a point in the past it no longer exists. Köhler did not there is a profound relation between the psychology of depth per-
explain how this phenomenon might occur. ception and that of duration. The perspectival quality of the sub-
jective present that is the illusory bridge across sequential objects
corresponds to the perspective of depth in the illusory resolution
of simultaneous visual objects.

Before each mental state terminates the next begins, i.e. states
overlap. The overlap underlies the identity and continuity of the
self. This is obligated if the prior state is to survive as the ground
of the present one. If a state arises before the preceding state has
terminated, the initial phases of both states will collapse to a sin-
Fig. 5. The absolute Now and the phenomenal Now. T1 is the gle transition before the distal phase of the initial state actualizes
absolute minimal duration of a mind/brain state. This T1 state and perishes. How this works depends on a paradoxical feature
decays, or is incompletely revived, in T2. The disparity between T1 of the temporal extensibility of entities, including the mind/brain
and T2 is experienced as the duration of the present. state. A mental state is not a temporal entity until it actualizes; it
does not yet exist as a thing in the world. The paradox is that the
44 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 45

sequence of phases achieves existence retroactively once the final or the passage from temporality and existence to a past entity that
phase occurs. In the course of its actualization, a state that has no longer exists and is out of time. The more superficial phases
not yet terminated has not yet actualized, and thus has not yet linked to neocortex achieve subjective time order out of the rela-
perished. The lack of perishing enables early phases in the state to tive simultaneity of the core.
constrain equivalent phases in the next recurrence.
As noted, the overlap of states, in engaging the earlier phases,
A present state (T-2) that overlaps a preceding one (T-1) is con- allows a degree of constancy at the base that is essential to iden-
strained inter alia by activity patterns of T-1. These patterns are tity (character) and continuity. The perishing at the endpoint of
still active in the forming present even if the present state does the actualization, as the object externalizes by way of primary
not exist (Fig. 5). The actualization of the final phase actualizes neocortex, permits novel objects to appear in the rapid shift
the entire state, which exists momentarily before it dissolves to from one perception to another. This novelty is merely the shift
a timeless past. (In prior writings this feature of the overlap was from one percept to another; it is not the conceptual novelty that
not sufficiently appreciated and the seamlessness or continuity derives from branching, fusion and propagation at earlier form-
of states was attributed to the timeless gap between successive building, meaning-laden phases. The continuance of the core
phase-transitions. Since genuine change occurs within the state, due to the overlap of initial phases explains the “persistence”, i.e.
not across states, the changeless “interval” would not exist for recurrence, of implicit beliefs and values, or character, while the
the individual and states would collapse into their predecessors.) rapid vanishing at the perceptual surface “clears the slate” for the
As soon as a state T-2 exists it perishes and is lost as a ground next perception. On this view decay is not gradual forgetting but
for ensuing traversals, though the immediately following state is incomplete revival.
nearing actuality when the prior state perishes. Early phases in
the state, not having perished, are not lost until the final phase,
at which point the early phase has melted into the ensuing one.
The completed state continues to exist in some sense in that state
even though it has vanished as a past occasion. In this way earlier 1.5. Time and memory
phases in the just-preceding state provide a seamless ground for Referring to Fig. 6, think of the mental state as having a dura-
the ensuing state. tion of about 50 to 100 milliseconds. For purposes of clarity in
the illustration, the process is depicted as a line, but it should be
The difference in the “persistence” of memory for deep or ear- recalled that the state is a point that recurs. At point T1 the state
ly phases in the state (LTM) and the fleeting occurrence of phases arises and fades, i.e. is incompletely revived. The state is replaced
closer to the surface (iconic and STM) is generally attributed to the each moment, the new state overlapping the previous one. We
consolidation of the former and the rapid fading of the latter. In speak of the recession of a state—say the state T1—as its decay
the framework of microgenetic theory, however, “persistence” is “over time”, but each ensuing state revives some aspects of the
recurrence. A state that persists is one that recurs with little change. T1 depth. The duration of the present is extracted from the floor
This is especially so for the early phases in the mental state that of the T1 decay at a subsequent state, T2 or T3. The forward edge
are mediated by upper brainstem, hypothalamus and archaic lim- of the process is fixed by an actual object, but the floor beneath
bic structures, the latter associated with the core self, drives and this edge, the decay of T1, to which the forward edge is compared,
long term memory. The rapid fading of the terminal phases that may be flexible. The present does not have a fixed duration. James
are mediated by the perceptual cortices occurs because the state, wrote of fuzzy boundaries. In meditation, the present may ex-
having actualized, perishes for the next recurrence. The perishing pand. In states of confusion, it may contract.
of the state is the disappearance of a present entity into a past one,
46 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 47

external object. The revival of T1 at this point, say at T2 (Fig. 6),


is referred to as short-term memory. Short-term memory retains
many of the “physical” characteristics of the original perception.
At a subsequent state, say at T3, the trace has decayed to a phase
beneath the floor of the present, so that only the “gist” of the
original perception, its semantic or conceptual properties, can be
revived. This phase is referred to as long-term memory.

Since all experience occurs within a single mental state, one


does not go from iconic, to short-term, to long-term memory com-
ponents. What is actually occurring is that as the trace fades, its in-
complete revival by ensuing states recaptures phases in the origi-
Fig. 6. The decay and revival of successive mental states. The nal transit. Specifically, when a state such as T1 relapses to LTM,
overlap of each revival over the immediately prior state makes the state is peeled away to uncover early memorial phases that
past experience available to present cognition. Perception devel- were traversed in the original perception. The presumed transfer
ops out of phases in memory. Components of memory reflect of a perception to iconic, short and long term stores is actually an
decay levels in the occurrent state. At T2, the T1 state has decayed uncovering of those phases in the original perception. It will be
to short-term memory, preserving some (physical) features of the recalled from the above discussion (Fig. 2) that the perception is
original perception. At T3, T1 has faded even more, perhaps be- derived out of phases associated with affective, experiential and
neath the floor of the conscious present, to long-term memory, conceptual relations, i.e. long-term memory, through intermedi-
which shows relations of affect, personal experience and mean- ate phases closer to adaptation, i.e. short-term memory, finally
ing. The central point illustrated by this figure is that the present to an external object. The phases traversed in the original object-
at T1 is derived out of long-term, through short-term, to iconic formation are recovered, or uncovered, in the reverse order when
(pre-attentive buffer) memory, and then into perception, so that the state decays (Brown and Pachalska 2003).
in the subsequent decay, or incomplete revival, of T1, these previ-
ously buried phases are exposed. Specifically, the original “input” According to this theory, in which an object develops out of
is not, as required by standard theory, secondarily conveyed to phases associated with long-term memory to those associated
short- and long-term stores. Rather, levels in short-term and long- with short-term memory, the phase of object-meaning is traversed
term memory recur in the course of the perceptual decay, i.e as before the object appears in consciousness. One recognizes an
incompletely revived phases. object before it is consciously perceived. This contrasts with the
classical model, indeed, with common sense, which supposes
that an object is consciously perceived before a person knows
One needs to keep in mind the preceding discussion as we what it is. However, this is inconsistent with directed perception,
move to a consideration of memory. Initially, the fading of the and probably incompatible with survival. By the time the organ-
trace is minimal, to the point where its revival can be almost com- ism sees and recognizes the object it is probably too late to react.
plete. One can speak of iconic memory or eidetic imagery when An implicit recognition must accompany a preparation for action
the antecedent state is revived to an almost veridical object. As before the object is consciously perceived.
the T1 state continues to fade, its revival still retains some physi-
cal features of the initial perception. Put differently, the revival Another aspect of this model worth emphasizing is the concept
achieves a level of realization that is closer to the properties of an of a progression from a spatial or simultaneous core to temporal
order. Though in the past I have written of the core as timeless, I
48 Jason W. Brown

now prefer to speak of it as simultaneous rather than non-tempo-


ral. This is partly a function of the fact that temporality does not
exist until the state actualizes, i.e. until one has an entity, whether
a particle or a mental state. The temporal extensibility or duration
of becoming is required for the thing to become what it is, and
it must first become what it is before it can exist. In this process
of becoming, one goes from wholeness or unity to seriality and
diversity. The diversity takes on temporal order as the state mate-
rializes, creating serial order out of the “timelessness” of the un-
conscious (Hartmann 1868). This is also consistent with Freud’s
account of the unconscious. Whether or not the unconscious is
truly timeless—whether it even has psychic correlates—the point
is that change occurs in the microgenetic traversal as the phase-
transition is derived to an object (act, thought, etc.), not in the
shift from one state to the next. We think of change as a causal
transition from one object to another in the world, but that is ap-
parent or illusory change. The genuine or authentic change is the
laying down of the state. The Buddhists write of an arising and
perishing of each flashing moment of life or nature (Brown 1999).
Whitehead proposed an actualization (concrescence), a perishing
and a re-actualization. Studies in neuropsychology, on which mi-
crogenetic theory is based, give clinical and anatomical weight to
these speculations.
Chapter 2
Simultaneity and Serial Order

2.1. Introduction
To common sense, the perception of serial order is not a prob-
lem, since we have a direct perception of the changing sights and
sounds of the world, which simply impinge on the mind/brain
in the order of their occurrence. For many cognitive scientists,
serial order is just the causal sequence of events in the world mir-
rored by events in the mind. From the standpoint of movement,
serial order is explained by associative chains, just one thing after
another, whether a person playing a game of basketball or chess,
or a computer playing a sonata. What chaining does not explain is
the memory of antecedents and the anticipation of consequents,
which is no less essential to perception as to memory. The theory
of causal chains applied to actions and (perceptible) events in the
world extends, by implication, to memory, which is conceived
as recurrent perception. However, chaining cannot explain the
chunking of serial wholes prior to their sequential enactment, the
apprehension of the whole of an event, from beginning to end in
vision or audition, hearing stretches of language or music, phrases
and melodies, even an entire work, a poem or piece of music in
the mind.

Temporal chaining and spatial assembly derive from the same


theory. The concept of causal chains entails that the brain not
only directly perceives an object sequence but pieces the object
together from its perceptible features, such as color, size, shape
and movement. Functional components for such features are in-


The term, sense-data, is used for the data of sensation, extrinsic to perception,
i.e. sensory constraints, not as in philosophical texts ingredient in or equivalent to
perception. The term transition is used for process within the mind/brain state,
while passage is for process in a physical or mind-independent world. Phases in
the mind/brain state conform to the transitions that underlie the mind and to
passage in an entity, the brain, which is mind-independent in that brain activity
is extrinsic to consciousness. Objects are internal or external contents of mind.
Entities are mind-independent.
52 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 53

ferred from what is observed in perception. Parts of objects are Categories individuate particulars that float in the soup of per-
internalized in the machinery of their construction, just as bricks ceptual space. An object is singled out by attention, the focus of
and mortar are the constituents of a wall. We see the wall put to- which can go from field to object, or from an object to a particular,
gether from its parts, and assume that objects in perception, such a feature or an attribute. The object is whatever is attended to, a
as the perception of the wall, are put together in the same way. We landscape, a horse or a fly on its back. Elements in perception
see color and postulate a functional area or system that adds color are contrasts at different levels of detail, not building blocks. The
to the final object. We see motion and postulate that it is perceived space between objects is not a vacuum or void, at least not in vi-
by way of detectors that add motion. The finding of brain cells that sual perception, but is itself an object, albeit lacking in density. We
detect motion leads to the assumption that change and serial order perceive an enormous gestalt in which figural elements specify
are outcomes of the operations of functional units dedicated to according to interest or value. This leads one to ask, is the pat-
their detection. This implies that objects are aggregates of smaller tern of whole to part in mind, in its complexity, a microcosm of
elements in the physical world, in the physical brain and, finally, in universal law?
the mind of the perceiver. The isolation of atomic solids in space
— wholes as sums of parts — is comparable to the isolation of solid Conventional theory is at risk when objects are conceived as
objects in time — duration as a compilation of instants. events, for then change is prior to stability. When I close one eye,
then the other, or tap my eyeball and the world jumps to one side,
An object moves or changes in relation to the world around it, I do not think the world is moving. When my eyes flicker in mi-
and at every moment there is a changing relatedness of the world. crosaccades or move in voluntary gaze, and the world remains
The inter-locking motion of the totality is missed when interest motionless, I do not think the world is a static picture. When I lift
settles on one object or its features. If one postulates a brain area my hand to my eyes, it does not increase in size to the extent an-
or function for objects, is there such a correlation for the space ticipated in optical geometry. In such instances, motion or change
between them? The inability to study the entire field, and the in- and its absence are attributed to the mind, to constancies, to cat-
clination of science to ever-greater precision and analysis, explain egories, to the eyes or to feedback systems that control eye move-
why the study of the mind/brain tends to isolate the simplest ment, all of which have evolved to keep the world and the self as
psychic or neural elements and proceed from there to a theory stable as possible. This raises the question, does the dynamic of
of the complex. But starting with elements conditions theory and actualization lead to a world that, even as it changes, is artificially
reinforces the notion that a field is an aggregate, or that the world- stabilized or is the changing image of the world a succession of
manifold is a composite held together by external relations. All static pictures?
these accounts are of a piece with the concept of succession as a
causal chain in mind or world, while the real questions are how The capacity to arrest change and apprehend solids, or to
the mind/brain perceives succession, the nature of implicit and perceive change as something that happens to an object, or to
explicit change and the relation of past to present. perceive objects as instigators of change, is fundamentally the
problem of change itself. The perception of objects as things, not
events, or the perception of an event as the change an object un-

More generally, the activation of neurons by external stimuli does not mean dergoes, or the sequence of object occurrences, or the collection
the neurons are responsible for the perception of those stimuli. Levitan (2006) of states of the same object (or self), is possible when a series of
gives the example of regions in left hemisphere shown to be active in the percep- actualities — or mental states — contracts to an object or expands
tion of musical structure that are also active in the perception of sign language.
to an event. To perceive the momentary history of an event as a
If acoustic noise and silent motion activate the same regions, clearly the experi-
ment is tapping into something more general than the stimuli. This is no doubt whole, or as a collection of slices, entails that snapshots of vary-
true for most, if not all, studies that purport to map brain areas to cognitive func- ing thickness are perceived in a certain order. Every instant an
tion.
54 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 55

object changes, inwardly, outwardly, in relation to the field and 2.2. Conscious and unconscious
the observer’s perspective. These snapshots, if that is what they
are, have to be summed or averaged over some duration just to Change in the motion from one event to another in the observ-
be perceived. er’s world reflects the temporal order of events as they actualize
in the mind. We know, inter alia, from the lag in perceiving an
In order for an object to exist as a “solid”, or for a solid to be- object or from the image that results from binocular disparity,
come an event, it must recur over successive durations. This is true that perception is not on-line with physical nature. We perceive
for all perceptions, though it is more emphatic in some modalities mental images that model physical events, not the physical events
than others. It may not be obvious that a tree, like any visual ob- themselves, which are inferred from the images. Object and space
ject, must be perceived over a succession of occasions for it to be are the outcome of the sculpting and externalization of phases
perceived at all. To perceive a continuous series, not a succession underlying image-formation. The transition to objects from the
of flashes, and to be aware of the succession, temporal order must intra-psychic and unconscious to the conscious and external is
be sustained by the recurrence of the object. As mentioned, this so obvious and so often stated it should be accepted as a starting
is no less essential to visual perception than to audition. For vi- point for speculation. Let us begin with the transition in the men-
sion, we usually say the object is just there and perceived as it is, tal state from depth to surface or onset to termination in relation
while in audition, the difficulty is finessed by saying that words or to time and change.
tones are held in memory over a period of time. To hear language
or music supposes that temporal-order in memory accounts for Many thinkers since von Hartmann (1868/1931) and Freud
time-order in perception. The usual idea is that the order is first have claimed a transition from timelessness to temporal order.
perceived and then transferred to short-term or working memory. Since timelessness is non-existence, and the unconscious does
But, since an “instant” no longer exists when the next occurs, not have the instantaneity of a durationless slice, it is preferable to
working memory is merely a technical term to mask explanation. speak of simultaneity, which has extension or thickness. If uncon-
What does it mean for something to be held in memory if the im- scious process in a conscious person is conceived as a subliminal
mediate past no longer exists in actuality? If the past must be re- transition, i.e. if the psychic unconscious is beneath or outside
vived in the present, how is order maintained, revived, perceived? consciousness though essential to it, and if the unconscious exists
If the past fully perished and could not be revived, every object when the mental state actualizes, what would be the form of an un-
would be a momentary and unfamiliar novelty, as would the self conscious transition that actualized without becoming conscious
that perceives it. Without an implicit memory of antecedents (chapters 9 and 10)? On the microgenetic account, consciousness
there would be a stroboscopic succession of disconnected selves is always preceded by, and enfolds, an unconscious transition,
and worlds. Clearly, the past must be within the present — indeed, so that an attenuated mental state could exist without realizing
the major part of the present — for both the stability of an object consciousness, For most psychologists it is the other way around,
and its change over time. i.e. experience first passes through consciousness in order to be
revived in the unconscious. A memory is the record of a percep-
tion, as the imagery of a dream is a memory (true or distorted) of
prior conscious experience. On this view, which is not uncommon
among those hostile to psychoanalytic excess, in which content
in the un-conscious is dependent on, is a copy of and secondary


Whitehead (Cobb, 2008) is close to this idea when he writes of the first stage
of concrescence as the conformal inclusion of past occasions supplemented by
conceptual feelings.
56 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 57

to consciousness, without which, qua unconscious, it would not What is the status of the unconscious in the absence of con-
exist, the unconscious is merely a physiological storehouse of past sciousness? Since a mental state is not conscious until its anteced-
conscious experience. ents are transformed, the unconscious achieves a retroactive exis-
tence on becoming conscious. Access to unconscious cognition in
For microgenetic theory a memorial unconscious underlies conscious subjects is limited, for it is transformed by sensation to
and is antecedent to conscious experience (Fig. 2.1.). Consciousness adapt to conditions in the physical world. Symptom-formation in
is an endpoint of unconscious process — actually, a relation of cases of brain damage is helpful in this respect. So is dream, but
early to late phases in this process (Brown, 2008a, Pachalska et the paradox of dream is that the unconscious takes on existence
al 2009). An image develops out of memory to externalize as an only when the individual awakens. If dream and REM dissociate
object, while a perception sinks or decays beneath consciousness. with no definite markers of dream in a sleeping person, certainly
Microgenetic theory holds that the perceptual rim is uncovered not of its content, the only direct knowledge of the unconscious is
to reveal underlying memory or dream, as pre-terminal phases when it becomes conscious, at which point we can no longer say
re-actualize to varying degrees of completeness and in conformity it is unconscious. Does a dream that fails to achieve conscious-
with immediate experience. In brief, instead of perception laying ness exist in actuality? One would have to postulate “degrees” of
down memory, memory lays down perception. Further, it is neces- actuality, with acts and perceptions having more actuality than
sary to avoid a preoccupation with the contents of the unconscious thoughts, thoughts more than dreams, and dreams more than
— memories, images, dreams — for it is the process of unconscious dispositions.
mentation, not the content into which the process deposits, that
is common to organisms lacking human consciousness. Content Perhaps one should speak of differing states of actuality, or the
varies, process is uniform. extent to which particulars are specified in a given mental state.
Existence is more readily applied to the external, the distinct and
specific, rather than the internal, non-specific and categorical.
Existence is being, but whatever becomes, i.e. actualizes, achieves
being for the moment of its existence. If we believe that thoughts,
images and dreams exist, a thing does not have to be real, substan-
tive and external to have existence. The transition from concept to
Fig. 2.1. The transition, or process of becoming, from core (self) object is one of increasing clarity and actuality. Concepts seem
to perception (world) frames a mind/brain state. Consciousness vague and impalpable, objects real and substantive, but we would
is the relation of early to late or depth to surface in this process. not want to say concepts do not exist. Here, the idea of existence
Visual and verbal imagery, including conceptual or intentional clashes with that of the real (Brown, 2004). We might not want to
feeling, arise at intermediate phases so long as an external world say that dream images are real, but would we say a dream, even if
is realized. The arrow represents sensation acting on the phase of unreal, does not exist?
imagery to externalize and adapt the state to the physical world.
The phase-transition is non-temporal until it terminates. The
mind/brain state and immediate present develop in a fraction of
a second, replaced by overlapping states. 
Behaviors such as sleep-talking, somnambulism, cries, laughter, which imply
mentation in the individual who is sleeping, challenge this argument. However,
in personal studies of sleep-talking, in which individuals are awakened and asked
about their dream, concordance to the dream report is inconsistent. Anecdotally,

The focus on content rather than process led researchers to prematurely this is also the case when someone is awakened during bouts of crying or laugh-
discard the regression hypothesis in early language and cognitive development ter. This implies that on waking, the simultaneity of the imagery is retrofitted to a
(Brown, 1996). linear narrative.
58 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 59

A dream is an endogenous perception that lacks sensation to as the nature of simultaneity and succession, have not received
carry it outward. If the difference between dream and waking per- sufficient attention.
ception is degree of exteriorization, and if exteriorization occurs
when sensation is applied to endogenous images, is this sufficient Not just the simultaneity of the unconscious can be posited,
for objects to have greater existence than images or dreams? It is but that of the mind/brain state as a whole, which is simultaneous
also the case that the existence of a thing depends on the duration over the epoch of its existence. Entities have a temporal extensibil-
over which it actualizes. If a non-conscious mental state can have ity over which they become what they are. In mind, late phases are
an animal, even vegetative, existence, the subjective duration of not the outputs of early ones which, having been traversed, disap-
the state depends on what is realized. If the actual is epochal and pear, but rather early phases are embedded in late ones and all
if existence is existence in time, each actuality has a unique tem- phases actualize together on completion of the final phase. There
poral character. are conditions in which the core might be the endpoint of the state,
say when processes mediating subsequent phases are inactive or
destroyed, as perhaps in coma or dreamless sleep. There are cases
in which an intermediate phase actualizes briefly as a pathologi-
cal symptom, but a phase in transition does not exist in isolation.
2.3. The perception of change A phase is not a temporal object. An object is the minimal cycle
The shift from cause to effect has usually been postulated as si- of phases that constitutes one epoch. Thus, a hypothetical atom is
multaneous, though for some it is successive. Causal sequence not a collection of slices in the orbit of an electron or the sum of its
in the world is perceived as a transition of a continuous event or positions at every slice, but is one complete revolution. Existence
event series. If the process account of this shift is correct, i.e. as is all or nothing, and the existence of the all is simultaneous when
the appearance of a transition from one conscious endpoint to an entity becomes the being that it is.
another, with change occurring in the derivation of the endpoint
How is temporal order in consciousness achieved? Is it by un-
in an epoch of consciousness, the causal shift would be simulta-
packing the spatiality of the unconscious to the seriality of its ter-
neous if occurring within an epoch and successive if occurring
mination? Is it a result of the replacement of individual states? If
across epochs.
serial order derives from simultaneity or potentiality, simultaneity
Some writers have looked at the shift from the simultaneity would forecast succession in the derivation of a state. If a succes-
of spatial cognition to the successivity of the temporal in speech sion of states is required, experience is still confined to the virtual
or action. This has also been framed in terms of a shift from the present of a single state. The now, the present moment, arises in
(spatial) right to the (temporal) left hemisphere (e.g. Teuber, 1956; the disparity between the endpoint of an actualization and a phase
Luria, 1966), or from posterior to anterior brain processes in to which the past is revived, so that successive states are required
language, as inferred from aphasia (e.g. Jakobson, 1968). There to stratify the phase-transition as well as to sustain it.
may also be a transition from the simultaneous to the serial in
If serial order in consciousness is coupled to the phase-tran-
the microgeny of a mental state. If the inception of the mental
sition leading to consciousness, as deduced from the state on
is simultaneous, and temporal order occurs at the conscious
completion, with memories of recent events revived in the order
endpoint, simultaneity and seriality refer to earlier and later in a
of their occurrence — the transition activating earlier, then later
single epoch. While the shift from spatial to temporal, or simulta-
phases in memory up to the final perception — the sequence of
neous to successive, has been discussed in neuropsychology, the
activation could provide the basis for a line in time from the im-
philosophical difficulties and implications of such a shift, as well
mediate past to the present endpoint. When we listen to speech or
music, the words and tones continue to resonate for some period
60 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 61

of time as each new sound is perceived. This is explained by the tal state develops from the totality of an epoch or an iteration of
strength (degree) of revival — usually cast as decay — of preceding totalities, in the transition from initial simultaneity (core), through
states in novel ones. The earlier events are incompletely revived the before and after of the phase-transition, to the now that arises
in relation to their pastness or, perhaps, the feeling of the relative with a conscious endpoint, the state incorporates three modes of
pastness owes to the degree of revival. A transition leading through time-discourse:
memory to perception that is apprehended as a horizontal se-
quence from past to present would explain sequencing in action, — Simultaneity, which entails temporal thickness or extensibil-
music, language, in the world and in the mind (Fig. 2.2.). Since the ity,
duration laid down by the phase-transition enfolds the memorial
— Physical passage in the becoming of the mind/brain state,
remnants of prior states that provide the posterior boundary of
which gives mind but is itself mind-independent, and
the now, both perceived and remembered event-series fall within
the present duration. In that this account explains order in both — A subjective present (past, future) that gives being or exis-
memory and perception, it has a parsimony not found in rival tence to the transition.
theories.
The simultaneity (1) that is the spatial whole of the core, or
the epoch it generates, leads to and embraces a transition over
phases (2) that is the bridge to temporal order. This transition, and
the duration of the present that is its outcome (3), correspond to
the two series of McTaggart (1927). Since the transition does not
exist until it is complete, at which point the entire transition actu-
Fig. 2.2. The perception (P) at Tn is replaced at Tn+1 by another alizes, every temporal moment or mind/brain state — whether a
perception (Q), which may resemble or differ from that at Tn. static picture or an event-sequence — occurs against a backdrop
Perceptual stability depends on resemblance; change depends on of simultaneity.
difference. Within the perception (arrow, R), the mind/brain state
at Tn+2 revives Tn+1 almost completely, such that the image of P Ordering depends not on perceived succession but the implicit
at Tn+2 is prior to the object (Q), and so on. Over a brief succession role of succession in the layering of memory and the replacement
of mental states, P, Q and R represent images of past perceptions of one state by the next. But is it possible that serial order is just
revived to a decreasing extent in the oncoming present, and grad- the perception of linkage made fluid by the rapidity of shifts? This
ed according to this revival. An eidetic image is a near-complete assumes that a mental state, as an epochal whole, is simultaneous
revival. A memory image is a vague recurrence at some psychic through its phases, with change in the causal shift from one epoch
distance from a present object. At Tn+3, the series of images, P, to the next, i.e. in the linkage of states, not their replacement or
Q and R, forms an order antecedent to the perception (S). The overlap. We are conscious of the final contents of a state, not the
perception and memory of serial order depend on the perception transition from state to state or depth to surface, nor are we aware
developing out of memory. Serial order occurs within the present, of interstices in the linkage. Even if temporal order is not disso-
but depends on succession for the layering of prior experience. ciable from oncoming and antecedent states, any account based
on rapid succession must return to events within the state itself.
As mentioned, the mental state lays down serial order yet has
a spatial character, actualizing as an epochal whole. The simulta- Consider the phase-transition within the state in relation to re-
neity or spatial totality of the present epoch distributes into the placement across states. If order is laid down in the distribution of
order it realizes. Regardless of whether temporal order in a men- spatial objects, or if it is derived serially from the outpouring of the
62 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 63

core, the array of objects in the world would be a static grouping as in episodic tagging or stacking in forgetting, at least for short-
with a leading edge of change, i.e. micro-events fused to an event- term memory. However, what accounts for serial recall in memory
sequence in the overlap. An object would then be an incipient must apply to perception.
event that becomes continuous when the next state appears. The
perishing of the state would support the anticipation of the next
and avoid a succession of pictures. If the clock duration of a mental
state of 50-100 milliseconds is insufficient to generate serial order
within the state, like the flash of a tachystoscope (stroboscope), 2.4. Perception and memory
it might permit a perception of forward momentum. Order and In order to understand temporal order in perception it is neces-
continuity would then depend on the overlap of recurrences. sary to understand the relation of perception to memory. An in-
complete perception has the character of a memory. The decay of
Is conscious succession — the sequence of events in observa- perception to short-term memory, which is dogma in psychology,
tion, or the motion of the world in perception — an illusion of is ordinarily conceived as the transfer of perception to a store that
causal transition? Is it like the phi phenomenon, in which illusory retains many of the physical features of the original stimulus. One
change results from the rapid replacement of static images? A se- problem with this theory is that it posits a trace that is degraded
ries of causal pairs may explain fusion from one state to the next, rather than one that is incompletely revived. The persistence of a
but not memory of preceding pairs to give a continuous event dead past is the heart of the problem under study. As soon as an
or narrative. Some have noted differences between real and ap- object is past, it no longer exists except as an echo in memory. The
parent motion but others (e.g. Frisby, 1973, in Schiffman, 1976; concept of perception as externalized memory, or forgetting as
p. 262) have argued they “are mediated by the same movement incomplete revival, puts the relation of memory and perception
detecting mechanism”. There is an inter-dependence of intensity in a different light. On this view, the transition is from long-term to
of stimuli, distance between them and time (Schiffman, 1976). short-term memory to perception. The trajectory is the opposite
In a movie, continuity requires a frequency of around 40 milli- of that assumed in psychology. A perception grows out of phases
seconds per frame, which is close to the estimated duration of a in memory uncovered as incomplete recurrences within a mo-
mental state, thus the rate postulated for the replacement. This mentary actuality.
rate is likely governed by a pacemaker and is relatively constant,
but there are individuals with brain damage in whom events ap- The greater part of perception is memorial, the endogenous
pear to be speeded up or slowed down (Hoff and Poetzl, 1988ed). infrastructure of which is modeled by sensory data to represent
The acceleration and deceleration of events in pathological cases, objects in the world. To understand subjective time and serial or-
as in the speed of a film projector, might reflect the frequency of der, it is necessary to conceive perception as a form of exteriorized
replacement. memory. Russell (1921) wrote of the relation of image to object,
but Whitehead (p. 69) pointed directly to the memorial basis of
The conclusion of this line of thought is that states are not con- perception: “there is no essential reason why memory should
catenations but superimpositions on the remnants of predeces- not be raised to the vividness of the present fact; and thus from
sors that are embedded as memorial residues (Fig. 2.2. above). the side of mind, what is the difference between the present and
The graded decay of memory is its graded revival in conformance the past”? Again, (p. 73): “what we perceive as present is the vivid
with the occurrent state. We see a tree as persistent because of fringe of memory tinged with anticipation”. The difference owes
the similarity across recurrences. If the recurrence differs from its to the effects of sensation on an endogenous process of image
predecessor, the object is perceived as changing. In psychology, formation.
decay (revival) is assumed to account for serial order in memory,
64 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 65

The claim here is that serial order in memory underlies serial ters is in tension with the generality of categories. Separation in
order in perception. The recall of the order of past events, so-called time is naturally important. I would probably not recall whether,
episodic memory, develops in a setting (some would say out of a on a first visit to Paris, I went first to the 5th or 7th quarter. In am-
store) that is simultaneous until it partitions. Whether memories nesia with shrinkage of past (and present) duration, the inability
are conceived as associative chains, circuits, networks or configur- to revive events, even implicitly, fails to articulate and expand past
al potentials, whether they are localized or distributed, until they duration. Empty duration collapses on itself.
are activated they are dormant possibilities, not actualities or exis-
tents. An event in memory is a potential for activation. The search Do events in episodic memory have markers or relational in-
for the memory store, trace or engram, has a long disappointing dices of the perceptual history of their occurrence? To assign a
history. This is because the accuracy of recall is determined by temporal tag to events, or postulate a scanning device (Lashley,
the extent to which the phase-sequence of the initial encounter 1951) merely offers a mechanism as much in need of explana-
is revived. In what other sense can we even write of the existence tion as what it purports to explain. In citing the Würzburg school,
or temporal location of the memory of a long-forgotten face that Lashley implied, as is developed in this paper, an hierarchic sys-
is suddenly revived in a chance encounter? In what sense is a tem of unconscious schema or constructs out of which serial order
memory in the brain waiting to be activated? On the other hand, develops. His example of the final word of a lengthy sentence dis-
how does something come into existence from non-existence? ambiguating the meaning evoked the problem of languages such
as German, in which a sentence may not be understood until the
A difference between episodic memory, in which an event is final verb. This suggests that an episodic sequence in memory, i.e.
ordered in time, and semantic memory, which is for knowledge the temporal order of past events in a mental state, or the basis
rather than events, that is, for thought or language rather than per- on which we say A came before B, and B before C in the past, is
ceptual experience, is that episodes become parts of categories, the same problem as the temporal order — A,B,C — of ongoing
shifting their allegiance from occurrence to family resemblance. experience (Fig. 2.2.).
An event absorbed in a category, say by repeated exposure, loses
its exceptionality. The recurrence strips the event of episodic Lashley noted the problem of syntax and word order and
context for the relational system of thought. If I travel a certain many subsequent accounts have focused on language production
route only once, I may remember it as an event in time. If I travel and errors. The difficulties illustrated by such phenomena as co-
the same route every day, it becomes part of my knowledge, and articulation, pronominal reference or Spoonerisms, and the vari-
is recalled as a specific occasion only if something unexpected ous computational models they have led to, may seem plausible,
happens. The unexpected creates novelty by decontextualizing an but they make no attempt to relate the model to brain function
event from a family of like-occurrences. and neuropsychology, nor do they address the more fundamental
issues of a lost past that reappears in an actual present.
The temporal locus of a memory can be accurate in immediate
recall, as in hearing and recalling a telephone number, but even In perception, event-order is immediate, objective and exter-
here it is imperfect, and it becomes more fallible over time. I can nal, in memory it is fuzzy, often effortful, internal and imaginal.
say that my first trip to Paris preceded one to Barcelona, though This distinction, which is one of memory and perception, of in-
the revival of other events may be required to reconstruct the se- ner and outer, mind and world, not serial order, helps us to know
quence and locate a specific event in the correct order, especially whether an experience is a memory or a perception. We get a
if there are frequent visits to both cities. The specificity of encoun- glimpse of its fragility in deja vu. A unified theory is obligatory if


There is discussion of the impact of Lashley’s paper in Bruce (1994). See
Houghton and Hartley (1995) for a cognitivist interpretation of Lashley’s ideas.
66 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 67

perception, as Whitehead put it, always contains an element of relations between mental states are assumed to fill the eventless,
memory. Merleau-Ponty went further when he wrote that we re- timeless gaps in succession and account for the continuity or
member events into perception. (See also, Bergson, 1896/1959). continuous identity of perceptual objects. In dream, similarity of
shape, function, signification and family resemblance appear to
Probably, the experience of an animal is closer to the percep- conserve identity and serial relatedness. In a strong, Laplacean
tion of a succession of scenes, bodily adjustments and anticipa- causation, the world unfolds in time like a movie. Given a state of
tions than an apprehension of order over an extended series. It is the world at any moment, all ensuing states follow of necessity. If
doubtful that an animal is aware of a chase. Rather, there is a suc- the causal future of the world unfolds like a film from a reel, could
cession of acts and objects and a tacit computation of trajectories a temporal series in the mind unfold out of simultaneity?
that are positions in static pictures without an apprehension of the
ongoing sequence. We do not believe an animal has a past to com- At any moment we live in the bubble of the immediate mo-
pare with a present for the recognition of serial order. Obviously, ment. Preceding states are a past that no longer exists; ensuing
animals learn from past experience, and there is implicit revival, states are continuously becoming present (how the replacing
even to the conditioning of response bias, for the recognition of state retains patterns of the state it replaces is discussed below).
danger and opportunity, as for the perception of change, but we Serial order depends on succession, but mere correspondence is
do not presume the animal is conscious of its past. There is sensi- not explanatory. The absence of a past in dream may absorb suc-
tivity to change even as the world is changing, e.g. the movement cession in the thickness of the state on waking but all images in
of a mouse to a hawk, a deer to a lion. A sudden shift in the detail dream or perception, present or past, exist in the present.
of a static picture resonates more than overall change in the array.
Similarly, humans are more sensitive to difference than sameness Some might argue that the entire past of the individual is re-
on experimental tests, possibly because sameness as a static pic- vived in the present. The Lebensfilm phenomenon in near-death
ture is the background out of which difference resolves. experience, in which one’s life is said to pass before the eyes, sug-
gests this possibility (Schilder, 1950). McCulloch (1965) was lead
2.4.1. A note on dream report to similar conclusions based on hypnosis and other data. To what
extent is the seriality applied to dream an effort at meaning and
The argument that memory and perception have a common ba- plausibility as the awakened self grasps at narrative? If passing im-
sis entails that processes underlying serial recall are the same as ages are immediate on waking, i.e. if the entire dream is within a
those for serial order in perception. If the awareness of a series of single mental state, how are images aligned in the order of their
recalled events is comparable to the awareness of ongoing events, occurrence?
one approach to the resemblance is through the phenomenon
of dream recall, in which the memory of a dream appears to be The content of dream differs from ordinary recall in its novelty,
coupled to the dream sequence, especially in a lengthy and com- digression, derailment, substitution and symbolism, all features
plex dream. However, we also have the impression that the dream of early cognition. Consider a dream of a past vacation in relation
is first apprehended as a whole, with the constituent events taking to its conscious recollection. On the usual interpretation, recol-
on order as they fade. In dream and ordinary recall, as in percep- lection is for events that were initially conscious, and thus, even if
tion, serial order is embedded in the present state, even if a suc- spotty or incomplete, events are revived with a greater correspon-
cession of states is necessary for the embedding. For some, causal dence to the objective sequence. In contrast, dream is a secondary


This notion is wonderfully evoked by Philip Roth in the depiction of a non-
sensory after-life with total recall of past experience for an eternity that is time-
less.
68 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 69

elaboration of what was first in consciousness, with the quality to a lesser extent, the dream content, in contrast to perception, in
and order of events subsidiary to their meaning. The microge- which order is felt to be independent of the observer.
netic interpretation deepens this understanding in claiming that
conscious experience traverses a memorial infrastructure, which The order of events in a dream, or in more distant memory,
is tapped in memory and recurs to a varying extent in dream. is relatively inessential, while in perception it is inescapable.
Content beneath the original perception that is revived in memory Memories come and go in relation to current life experience but
is uncovered in dream, with the lesser degree of realization and the exact order or dating of a memory is less important than its
lack of sensation giving the unreality and precarious recall. content or effect on current behavior. Order is prominent in dream
because the dream is closer to perception, but perception cannot
This account of order in dream-recall is reminiscent of in- occur without implicit order. Serial order shows decreasing em-
spired thought in creativity, when a work is apprehended all at phasis from perception to (very) short-term memory to working
once, then composed or worked out over time. The description of memory to dream and to long-term memory.
Mozart hearing a work all at once in his mind, though disputed,
conforms to my experience (Brown, 2005) and that of other writ- Could one say that the order in dream on waking, or in mem-
ers, composers and artists (Koestler, 1964). Composition occurs in ory, is reconstructed from the imagery, while in perception, order
dream or transitional states, such as the Kublai Khan of Coleridge, is time-creating. Put differently, serial order in perception mir-
or Wagner’s Prelude to Das Rheingold. In fact, the ability to revive rors objective time consistent with its external locus, while in the
a poem or piece of music composed in dream is perhaps the best subjectivity of dream and memory, temporal order is less precise.
indication that waking recall preserves the order of visual and au- Again, this confirms the thesis that external images in perception
ditory images. are realized out of internal images in memory, with serial order oc-
curring as an implicit thread — or explicit narrative — of change
In creative insight, in dream, trance or transitional states (Brown, from one image to another. There is a deep commonalty in the
2008), the potential for order may occur in spatially-given parts. ability to recall the event-series of a dream, the ability to recall a
An example can be found in studies of iconic imagery when, say, series of events in memory, and the ability to perceive an ongoing
a 3 X 3 matrix of 9 numbers is briefly presented and the subject sequence of events in the world.
asked to recall them. Usually, a few are recalled each time as the
remainder fades, but it can be shown that in each exposure any In perception and re-perception (memory), as one moves in-
set at any location has the potential to be recalled. The numbers ward, time gives way to space, succession to simultaneity, and se-
are apprehended all at once but they cannot all be recalled in one rial order becomes more elusive. The order of a subjective series
exposure. The necessity to report items in a series gives an order (dream, memory) is not the residue of a perception, rather, the
to the report, but the order, not present in the stimulus, is chosen objective series is founded on the subjective one facilitated by
by the subject. The relevance to dream would be that on waking, sensation. The absence of sensation permits the pre-perception
the focus on a few images is at the expense of the many irrespec- to develop along endogenous lines. The categories that prefigure
tive of where in the dream one begins. Any part of the dream the object give rise to unexpected images mediated by shared at-
can be remembered, but recalling what is focal in consciousness tributes, as in metaphor.
tends to occlude the remainder. In creative work as well, it is not
The memory of a face presupposes seeing the face before, but
unusual that the Idea spills into portions irrespective of the final
a face is specified out of categories and is or is not recognized,
order. Cut-and-paste revision sorts out order as composition is
i,e, is familiar or not, before it is consciously perceived. In recall,
renewed. The waking self is felt to impose order on the Idea and,
the image of the face, to a varying degree of clarity, recurs when
completion to an external object no longer is possible. This leads
70 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 71

to the inference that the memory of the face is actually an un- the observer — the meaning and value of external objects is the
covering of its terminal layer in perception. The difficulty for the thread of feeling that accompanies their outward migration, while
perception-first account is that order is retained in short-term and the process through which an entity recurs has the rudiments of
immediate memory when the effects of sensation are over, an psychic experience. This distinction is crucial in that the presumed
order that is essential to perceiving events in the first place. The independence of external objects prevents a fuller understanding
challenge to the memory-first account is that episodic recall and of serial order as an exemplification of mind’s outward growth.
temporal order in perception must arise out of a process of im-
plicit learning in which the present is influenced by the past with- With regard to agency, which directs attention to an inten-
out awareness of the duration spanning the succession. In either tional object and is thus an implementation of value in action, the
case, a more fundamental problem concerns the transition from contrarian thesis and the kernel of truth in anthropomorphism
spatial to temporal and the realization of temporal order within a is that feeling arises as energy in elementary entities to reach its
mental state in relation to state-succession. apogee in human value (Brown, 2005). The seeds of meaning are
planted in mind-independent entities, in temporal extensibility,
2.4.2. Unconscious categories and conscious parts whole-part relations and primordial sentience, which evolve over
millions of years to human modes of thought. In this process, na-
Causation is the engine of conscious succession, as meaning is scent patterns of primitive existents are gradually transformed to
in dream. Serial order develops in the transition from relations of a high level of incursion in human mentation. We see this in the
meaning to those of causation, or from spatial relations to temporal genesis of meaning out of lower forms, its installation in objects
order, or from a position in a spatial pattern to a locus in a temporal and, in causal necessity (Hume), in the outward transmission of
series. This transition passes through agency as an intermediate feeling and meaning.
phase. The categories and meaning-relations of unconscious pro-
cess have a spatial character — this is why the unconscious is said The claim that unconscious wholes translate to the succession
to be timeless — while objects in the external world are tempo- of conscious parts, in memory, in perception, in dream-recall
ral but largely devoid of meaning. Agent causation, deliberation, and in creativity, can be reconciled by attributing the whole to a
reason, decision, choice, commitment, are psychic phenomena category and the ordered items to its members or parts (sub-cat-
midway in the conveyance of the psychic relations of meaning to egories). An object is a final particular but also a category of parts,
the physical relations of cause and effect. as well as of the recurrences or snapshots buried in its stability
or fused into events. An action (or utterance) — in its derivation
From a psychological standpoint, the relation of self to action over a hierarchy of rhythms from postural and axial systems to the
in agency is the ground of object-causation, not the other way distal innervation — is equally a category, the parts of which are
around. We do not perceive order in the world and internalize it phases in its derivation. The transition from spatial to temporal
as psychic causation. Instead, the impulse in voluntary action is parallels this fractionation, as virtual wholes elicit concrete mem-
transferred to objects as they externalize. For Guyau (1988ed), the bers or parts.
child’s reach for an object is the seed of causation and the idea of
the future. The internal or psychic limb of this process is the self In any category, prototypical items exhibit the most salient
and its intentional arc. The external limb is causal efficacy and properties, e.g. chair, sparrow, while other items are atypical or
the implementation of the intentional aim. For some, causation less familiar, e.g. ottoman, rhea. If the category furniture partitions
is mechanical passage. For others, it is guided by meaning, as in to chair, table, sofa and so on, the members are elicited in a tem-
destiny, fate or the hand of deity. The common belief that things poral order that seems arbitrary. However, the list is not arbitrary
happen for a reason is, for externalists, the fiction of personal in that it reflects word frequency, familiarity, emotional intensity,
meaning inserted in nature’s machine. For the internalist — to associative strength and psychic distance. Asked to give items of
72 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 73

furniture, one does not ordinarily begin with ottoman, so there is realized. If a single mental state encompasses an event or brief
are constraints on the order of recall. If one takes a spontaneous succession, all phases in the state, early and late, actualize to-
category such as a vacation, the sequence of events, or items in gether before any phase is perceived. The state can be thought
the category, seems less arbitrary, such as planning the trip, pack- of as a spatial whole parsed to succession on completion. Now,
ing a suitcase, the mode of travel, the voyage, the destination, and if events are perceived in the order of their occurrence, and the
so on, which have a causal or logical order. Does this sequence state is non-temporal until it actualizes, how is order preserved?
exist in statu nascendi before the vacation begins? How is a melody heard if the preceding tones no longer exist the
moment of the present one? A melody is a good illustration of
We think of distance from the center to the periphery of a cat- this difficulty, since tones obviously perish, while visual objects
egory in abstract spatial terms, but eliciting members from typi- appear to persist unchanged, but it is the same problem.
cal to atypical to marginal or overlapping transforms the virtual
space of a category to relations of serial enactment or recitation. Listening to speech or music is an example of holding an
When the images in a category such as that of a particular dream ordered stretch of speech or musical sounds in memory. But to
are aligned on waking, the category or meaning is discovered in explain serial recall by saying we remember the tones or words,
the narrative. Often, it is only after the narrative occurs that we or that retrieval recurs over the path of the perception, merely de-
begin to understand the categories of thought that were driving scribes the problem, since a memory of the past (tone, word) is a
the imagery. memory in the present. Moreover, the process that accounts for
change also accounts for stability. Thus, the recurrence of a rela-
tively unchanging visual object such as a chair gives the impres-
sion of permanence in the world even if the object is imperma-
nent in the mind, i.e. the stability of the chair is sustained by the
2.5. Seriality and the store similarity of its recurrences, while change in an auditory object,
If perception develops out of a non-temporal core, how is a se- which depends on the revival of past sounds, tones or words, gives
quence of events in the world maintained or forecast at an un- the impression of impermanence in the world and persistence in
conscious phase? The stacking of to-be-realized events in non- the mind.
temporal planes supposes that a mental state is layered like a tea
garden, with events peeling off in the order of their registration. Knowledge plays a role in the perception of temporal order,
Otherwise, tones or words head in the past and revived in the pres- which points once more to the memorial or conceptual under-
ent would merge together in one discordant sound. We assume pinnings of perception and serial time. A series of environmental
the sequence of observed events in a single state corresponds to sounds does not stick in the mind like a melody, and a melody stays
that in reality. However, within a mental state, or with respect to with the listener inter alia in relation to its familiarity. In complex
the actualities the state delivers, if the first in a brief series persists music, the more the piece is understood, the more the listener
until the last registers, the first will fade into memory when the will recall what is heard. Less coherent music, the less a sequence
last is perceived. In this scenario, events are like pigeons on a wire, can be anticipated, the less revival is facilitated. Even the recall of
in which the first flies off, then others, but none actually leave (ex- digits in a telephone number is accentuated if they are syncopated
ist) until the last in the series, i.e. the whole sequence, is traversed or given rhythmically, or with familiarity in the sequence. Widely
(Fig. 2.2.). separated tones are less easily revived. Intervening silence corre-
sponds to intervening states. Music lacking melody or continuity
Put differently, phases in a mental state exist when the state is heard as a succession of rapidly fading sounds. Environmental
terminates, the sequence assuming order when the final phase noises show even less recall. In language, a sentence persists (re-
74 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 75

curs) in the mind in relation to fluency and meaning. Contents perceptually, on a past and future in relation to a phenomenal or
are revived out of categories. The conceptual relatedness of ele- specious present (Brown, 1996 et seq.), while objective time is that
ments or their semantic coherence enhances revival. Conceptual of earlier and later; and (4) derives from the unconscious succes-
structures, categories, meaning-relations, help to support serial sion of phases laying down temporal order, unlike the world that
order which, in each modality, depends on antecedent states be- is the ‘gathered-up’ outcome of this transition (passage).
ing revived to varying degrees of incompleteness.
Sprigge (1974), after Whitehead, argued that change from one
The concept of a storehouse of innumerable memories, some event to another is experienced in succession, that mental change
explicit, others implicit, some with the potential for activation is not real change and that only the extra-psychic is changing.
yet destined to be forgotten, others lost or irretrievable, is widely Doubt about real change in the mind/brain comes from the fact
accepted, though the nature of the store or trace eludes descrip- that a mental state, as an epochal whole, in a Platonic moving im-
tion. Even if a cell is re-activated by the same stimulus, most re- age of eternity, cannot be divided into successive parts. The world
searchers do not think that an event is located in a single neuron, is a stationary image with the continuity of motion depending
though in holographic theory the trace is everywhere (Pribram, on the rate of replacement. It is difficult to conceive that change
1991). We conceptualize the “to-be-realized” as encoded in wide- and multiplicity in the world are apprehended simultaneously in
spread systems of neurons and filaments that cohere according the unconscious. This agrees with Sprigge’s argument that in real
to probabilities latent in the connectivity. Memories emerge in the change one experience gives way to another, and that an ensuing
synaptic strength of configural possibilities occasioned by experi- content ‘takes up the story told by the first content’, or that serial
ence. A memory in the connectivity implies a circuit or configural order is in the replacement, not the state. The problem with this
potential. In microgenetic theory the trace is the entire sequence account is that, while it may work for perception, as in the phi phe-
up to the penultimate phase through which the perception actual- nomenon, it does not adequately explain serial order in memory,
izes. If every mind/brain state in its entirety has the potential to and there is no reason to think these are unrelated phenomena.
be revived, what is ingredient in the trace? Is it what was formerly
in consciousness, its unconscious precursors, the immediate and If order in the world successively comes into view, can non-
remote context, related events, relevant thoughts, shared mean- temporality at the onset be reconciled with successivity at the out-
ings, feelings? Are billions of attenuated memories entrained in come? In the epochal theory, temporal order is the unfolding into
every cognition or is the connectivity quiescent or virtual in the time of spatial diversity as novel worlds recur in succession. Either
latency of synaptic contacts? the core is partitioned to a seriality not anticipated at the onset,
or temporal order in consciousness is a copy of that in the core,
with unconscious events serialized in situ prior to actualization. A
temporal order embedded in a simultaneity, with the potential for
order at the surface, would yield a spectator who, in theory, could
2.6. Simultaneity and succession intuit the order of events before they actualize. However, individu-
Object-causation is a narrative of change in the external world als who descend inwardly in meditative practice or mystical states
based on the replacement of internal episodes as one series of report unity or oneness, not serial order or multiplicity.
events replaces another. World-events realized in the mind are
ordered into past and present. From a subjective point of view,
change (1) depends on the elaboration of temporal order in the
mind; (2) appears when simultaneity becomes actual, so that
order is spatially given in advance of perception; (3) depends,
76 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 77

while existents are novelties that do not mutate, for they are re-
placed as they arise.

The revival of proximal, unconscious phases before the state


actualizes — before those phases have existence and temporality
and, therefore, before they can perish — allows early cognition to
recur across states. On the other hand, the distal or world-close
Fig. 2.3. Phases in short-term or working memory are gener- phases vanish before they fully re-actualize. This, so to say, ‘wipes
ally revived in ensuing states in the order of their registration, i.e. the slate clean’ for oncoming objects, recalling Freud’s magic writ-
in relation to their resemblance to the oncoming state and, thus, ing pad analogy. On this interpretation, the persistence of early
their capacity for revival. Images closer to the current perception, phases and the evanescence of late ones, i.e. the consolidation
i.e. those in short-term memory that almost achieve re-perception, of long-term memory and the transience of short-term memory
are most likely to be revived in the current state. The mind/brain and perception, reflect the reinforcement of not-yet-existent con-
state at T-1 is replaced by an overlapping state at T-2. The core of figural patterns at early phases and the perishing-on-termination
T-1 is overlapped at T-2 before T-1 terminates, i.e. before the epoch of late ones.
exists. This explains the recurrence of early phases in T-1 associ-
ated with individuality, self, character, dispositions, long-term and We are aware of change in the world, as well in ideas and feel-
experiential memory, and the “persistence” of core beliefs, values ings, but unaware of the process through which inner and outer
and personality. Later phases perish on completion of the entire develop. The experience of change lies in outcomes and replace-
state to make way for novel perceptions. The re-activation of ear- ments. For the observer, the mental state is all there is. This means
lier phases by the overlapping state explains the sustained per- that genuine change occurs within the state, even if the layering
sonhood behind succession. Early phases are ingredient across of the past, in imagery and perception, requires a series of states.
states; later ones are malleable to a greater extent as endogenous If the outcome of a state is given at the onset, change within the
process is shaped by sensation. state would be prohibited by its epochal character. An external-
ized world enjoys novelty in delimiting the endogenous. There is
William James (1890) was the first to postulate overlap in the the novelty of the unexpected or creative, as in the departure from
succession of mental states, which he termed pulses of cognitive world attachment. Observed events are outcomes of the becom-
consciousness. If the overlap is for early phases, later ones will ing through which they are generated, the changing physical sur-
perish before the tip of the oncoming state arrives (Fig. 2.3.). More round, and the individuality of response.
precisely, the early unconscious phases associated with long-term
memory, character and the self are revived in the oncoming state The changelessness of an epoch is a logical entailment of its
before the present state concludes. Since the epoch does not exist holistic character, but the outcome of the epoch cannot be or-
until the transition is complete, phases trailing in the derivation dained at the onset because the facts of the final world depend
would recur in the forward edge of the overlap; indeed, these on sculpting by incoming sensory data that guide the state to
phases would be continuously modified by ensuing states before completion. In addition to these effects, the transit of proximal
they become actual. This is a solution to the non-existence of the phases of endogenous process — less constrained by sensory data
unconscious, for while unconscious phases never exist, they are — through experiential memory and intentional feeling — medi-
constantly being replaced before existence is possible, while con- ated by limbic formation — are a source of spontaneity, originality
scious phases exist but are continuously perishing. The paradox and the creative imagination.
is that the non-existent survives and is perpetually transformed,
Chapter 3
Theory of the Symptom

3.1. Introduction
The brief outline of microgenetic theory and the nature of the
mental state described in the preceding chapters is further ex-
plored in the examination of the pathological errors that were the
original basis of the theory. If errors in language or perception can
be shown to arise from normal processes underlying the men-
tal state, i.e. if errors reveal normal cognitive process, the model
of pathological cognition is equally a model of cognition in the
normal state. This chapter offers an account of the origin of the
error, and shows how it arises from a brief retardation and incom-
plete specification, in the actualization process. The account of
symptoms, like that of microgenetic process generally, is related
to patterns of phylo- and onto-genetic growth. The argument is
that patterns of morphogenesis in the developing brain corre-
spond with the population dynamic of evolutionary speciation
and the dynamic of cognitive process in the mature individual.
Evolutionary and maturational growth patterns continue into
adult cognition as the process through which actualities in mind
and world are selected.

The symptom is essentially a fragment of preliminary cogni-


tion that is ordinarily transformed to an ensuing phase. In this
respect, the symptoms of brain pathology are fragments of un-
conscious phases that are usually inaccessible to waking cogni-
tion. The importance of the symptom is that it details the micro-
temporal process underlying surface performances, i.e. charting
the infrastructure of the unconscious, a topic taken up in a later
chapter.

Only a few common symptoms have been chosen to illus-


trate this theory, but a survey of the full range of local symptoms
from a microgenetic perspective (Brown, 1988) suggests that the
account is applicable to all pathological phenomena except, per-
80 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 81

haps, those impairments resulting from massive brain injury. The brain activity is a capsule of the overall relation of mind to brain.
model began with the symptoms of language disorder in apha- Specifically, the relation of symptom to an area in the brain or a
sia. When it became evident that an account of the aphasias was distributed system corresponds to the relation of an act or thought
similar to that for action, perception and other cognitive activities, to the brain state that generates it. The explanation of the frag-
a general theory of mind, or the mind/brain state, became pos- ment in relation to a region of the brain is an explanation of brain
sible. Hopefully, the coherence of the model, its wide explanatory and behavior generally.
power and relation to normal mentation will not fail to impress
the reader as a plausible basis for the later speculation on philo- As will be shown, the symptom is not a bizarre occurrence
sophical topics that depend on these early descriptions in human unrelated to the normal, but reveals preliminary or “pre-process-
neuropsychology. ing” phases in the elaboration of normal function. We commonly
see links from normal to defective performance, such as halluci-
nation in dream, psychosis and focal brain lesion. In studies of
sleep-talking, normal individuals produce almost the entire range
of aphasic errors in the course of a night’s sleep (Arkin and Brown,
3.2. The symptom as a neuropsychological 1971). The similarity of errors to stages in normal development
problem led to the regression concept of symptom formation, in which
symptoms were interpreted as the re-appearance of earlier stages
There are several problems in neuropsychology that are both fun- in language or thought development.
damental and recurrent. One of these is the nature of the image,
such as the verbal image of inner speech (Chapter 4) or the visual In neuropsychology, a symptom due to focal brain damage,
and auditory image of hallucination. This issue is fundamental such as a language or perceptual error, is an opportunity to study
because the relation of image to object goes to the heart of the altered performance in an individual who in other respects is nor-
transition from inner to outer. A demonstration that an object is mal. The study of focal symptoms is essential to an understanding
an externalized image, or that images are attenuations at different of the brain correlates of mentation and behavior, which is not
points in the process of object-formation, would go far to settle the usually possible in diffuse illnesses such as Alzheimer’s disease
epistemological debate over idealist and realist versions of percep- or in traumatic brain injury. Nor is it possible to correlate brain
tion. Another problem is the nature of the present discussed in region or functional system with maturational stages in child-
Chapters 1 and 2. The duration of the present is important for hood, for the brain develops as a whole and the lines of cleavage
many reasons, including a possible role in agency (Brown, 1996) between different formations are less precise than in adults.
and because the virtual span over physical passage is a fundamen-
tal obstacle to a naive reduction of mind to brain. If the study of symptoms were not instructive with regard to
the normal, clinical study would be a waste of time. Some psy-
Still another, and perhaps even more fundamental though chologists, invariably with little exposure to, or knowledge of,
neglected problem is the origin and nature of the symptom. A the pathological cases, are dismissive of the value of symptoms,
symptom is a pathological behavior that deviates from the ordi- often comparing them to the sparks that fly out of a damaged
nary or expected. Even a transient disturbance such as forgetting machine, or at best, as approximations or guesses, But for those
a name is a clue to the nature of pathology. While the symptom who have studied the clinical material closely, and thoughtfully,
points to a pathological condition, and in this respect would seem there is clearly a regularity, even a lawfulness, in the pattern of
remote from an understanding of normal thought and behavior, symptom formation, as well as in the change of symptoms with
in that it is a fragment of behavior pointing to a disrupted phase deterioration and recovery. Still, after many years of describing
in the mind/brain state, the relation of the psychic fragment to symptoms, and the myriad symptoms that have been described,
82 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 83

we do not have a coherent theory on their nature, how they arise mind. The attempt to make psychology a “scientific” discipline
and change, and their relation to brain function. Without such a had the effect of discounting patterns of error formation and the
theory, clinical work that concentrates on qualitative aspects of qualitative side of psychological change in favor of more quantita-
brain and behavior remains in the realm of unscientific discourse. tive methods of assessment, whether batteries of tests or probes
This has been its fate over the past few decades, with error-analysis of specific functions. Interest shifted from errors to deficits, from
relegated to the status of anecdote. Along with the rise of cognitive mistakes to omissions, leading to a pre-occupation with disso-
“science”, psychology came to view symptoms as subjective, vari- ciations and atemporal slices of behavior averaged or summed
able, qualitative, fleeting and non-reproducible, perhaps a guide over samples. The various local models had little or no coherence
to an experimental study but otherwise of little scientific value. It among them. For example, a model of font recognition could be
is not difficult to trace the history of this idea. advanced without an attempt to explain the relation of the model
to phonology, lexical semantics, attention, or perception more
When neuropsychology was in a descriptive phase, the inter- generally. Mental components were inferred ad hoc from the re-
pretation of symptoms tended to emphasize their entrainment in quirements of cognitivist theory.
a process-based theory of the mind/brain. One can point to the
genetic theories of Piaget, Werner and others, of Gestalt theory, The argument was that deficits had the virtue of being re-
and the concept of a micro-temporal unfolding over stages ad- peatable and quantifiable in scores, and thus conformed to the
vanced by clinicians such as Lotmar, Monakow, Pick, Bay, Conrad, requirements of a scientific theory. Thus, a score of 9/10 on one
Goldstein and Schilder. These workers viewed the symptom as a test implied a relatively intact mechanism, while a score of 2/10
disruption in the transition from thought to speech or action, or implied that the mechanism or connections to or from it were
in the development of thought to imagery and perception. For damaged. In case studies, the same method was used to explore
example, the different types of semantic error were shown to con- the structure of restricted performances, re-iterated at progres-
form to phases in word selection, as disturbances in the transition sively finer levels. Spurious methods of brain imaging, such as
through fields of word-meaning relations. Goldstein (1948) argued that of subtraction in metabolic mapping, were used to support
that the aphasias represented stages in the transition of thought to the account of modular organization in brain and psyche. On this
speech, as did Pick (1931/1973), while Lange (1936) and Schilder view, there is no explanation of a symptom, only the destruction
(1951) approached thought-development and percept-formation or degrading of a function by damage to a site or its connectivity.
from the same point of view. Tachystoscopic methods (Smith, Once the brain area is “identified,” the problem is solved, and no
2001, for review) were employed to demonstrate micro-temporal obligation is felt to account for the relation of brain to function.
transitions in object-formation. We see a similar mindset in the rush to correlate psychological
phenomena, even complex ones such as love or the sense of right
All this work has been largely forgotten, or is deliberately ne- and wrong, with a specific brain area, even a gene. This is merely
glected, in the rise of cognitive psychology. The shift from process a reduction to a lower “physical” level without explanation of the
to substance theory was one from continuities, transitions and process by which the gene or brain area generates the phenom-
internal relations to logical solids, discrete brain areas or compo- enon, not to mention the diachronic and synchronic relations of
nents, and the binding of functional units by external relations, the function in question.
whether psychic or neural. In line with computational theory, a
profound shift occurred in psychological and brain models, from This emphasis on quantity over quality is completely backwards.
the dynamic accounts of the early workers to the box and arrow The symptom is not an ancillary decoration to a scientific psychol-
diagrams or circuit board models of contemporary theory, what ogy, but has direct import as a preliminary phase in language or
the philosopher Mario Bunge termed the “Lego” theory of the cognition. The symptom is itself the result of an experiment in
84 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 85

nature, in no need of additional experimentation. Specifically, 3.4. Theory of symptom formation


the symptom points to an embedded phase in the generation of
a surface performance. In contrast, a deficit or omission tells us Most accounts of the symptom are simple mechanical explana-
little about brain process, though it provides some boundaries to tions based on a combination of positive and negative effects, or
theoretical speculation based on symptom-analysis. displacement and re-location, such as excitation, inhibition, re-
lease and compensation, or the assumption of the damaged func-
tion by intact remote or neighboring regions. The symptom has
been interpreted to represent a degraded function or an earlier
stage in acquisition. This idea has been most fully explored, and
3.3. Some theories of the symptom refuted, in language pathology, where grammatical defects have
Many years ago during a stay in Moscow with A. R. Luria, he cited been examined in relation to stage of acquisition. In the percep-
Kurt Goldstein’s paper, “What is a symptom?”, as one of the most tual domain, visual (auditory, etc.) hallucinations have been at-
important articles written in the field, and argued that a theory tributed to the excitation (epilepsy) or release (damage) of centers
of the symptom was a pressing need in neuropsychology. Luria that store images. Or, the image is conceived as an earlier stage in
did not have a definitive theory, rather different perspectives ac- perception, released by damage to (visual) cortex. However, such
cording to the problem under analysis. His ideas were mostly bor- interpretations do not address the nature of the image, its con-
rowed from others. The account of paraphasia followed Pavlov, textual and historical quality, its meaning, its relation to dream,
who proposed an equalization of associative strengths, i.e. an waking experience and normal perception, nor to other types of
elimination of association biases, such that one word was as likely imagery and the transitions from one form to another. A theory
to occur as another, though paraphasias are not random guesses. of hallucination is also a theory of illusion, of eidetic and memory
At times he endorsed Wernicke’s view that paraphasia occurred imagery, dream imagery, imagination or thought images and af-
when the posterior lesion disinhibited Broca’s area and allowed it ter-images, since one form can pass into the other.
to run on chaotically. Vygotsky’s hierarchic theory was also used
These simplistic accounts of the symptom grope at a theory
for certain conditions and, following Hughlings Jackson, regres-
without much thought of the essential nature of the alteration or
sion played a role in the distinction of the automatic and volitional
its relation to normal function. In this the symptom as a pathologi-
in restitution, as well as in some clinical disorders, such as verbal
cal phenomenon is treated much like normal phenomena, i.e. as
regulation. The symptom was also conceived as a disruption in a
a solid entity like a neuron with effects at the synapse, where the
functional system. This idea, first proposed by Anokhin, involved
thing-like nature of the event is associated with a neural substrate
not a loss of elements but a re-organization to a different level. In
and the excitatory or inhibitory forces that play upon it rather than
some ways, the idea recalls Penfield’s analogy of the effects of a
explored as a qualitative change in relation to spatial and temporal
brain lesion to removing a violin from the string section of an or-
context. None of these theories accounts for the common observa-
chestra and listening for the change in the music. Luria’s concept
tion that many pathological symptoms occur as occasional events
of qualitative reorganization has been greatly distorted in the idea
in normal individuals, that is, the relation of normal to pathologi-
of the brain as a network of discrete and inter-connected compo-
cal function, such as the relation of waking to dream hallucina-
nents, or a circuit board in which multiple areas or functions, each
tions, or the observation that normal people in states of fatigue
separately vulnerable, contribute to a given task.
or distraction may forget a proper name or noun. The relation of
error to target is ignored, e.g. why an aphasic names a table as a
chair. This is also true for patterns of symptom-formation such as
why the word “chair” is produced and not the word “butterfly.” In
86 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 87

contrast to the muddled view of locality and the effects of destruc- missed is that patterns of symptom-formation can be understood
tion or re-location, microgenetic theory centers on the symptom in relation to the micro-temporal development of an act of cogni-
as a disruption of a phase in the realization of an act, object or tion. What is important is the process revealed by the symptom,
utterance (Brown, 1988; 1996). It is a snapshot of a concealed or not the staged elements it deposits (see below).
submerged process with relations to antecedent and consequent
phases. On this view, a theory of the symptom is the first step in a
theory of normal cognition.

It might be noted that in certain respects microgenetic theory 3.5. Some representative types of errors
has affinities with the interpretation of psychopathology. Freud Consider the process of naming and its disruption in posterior
argued that symptoms were not additions to the repertoire of be- aphasia. An aphasic asked to name an object or picture may pro-
havior but revelations of underlying structure. While this is easier duce various types of errors depending on such factors as laterality,
to accept in disorders such as the neuroses than in cases of brain age, lesion location and so on. Without going into details that have
damage, the argument is similar. One simply has to get over the been covered in other works (e.g. Brown, 1988), among the errors
simplistic idea that damage to the brain “knocks out,” destroys or that are observed are those of wide semantic distance or experi-
damages a function localized in that area. The concept of symp- ential relatedness, e.g. bullfight for guitar, those in the object cat-
toms as destroyed components is closely linked to the concept egory, e.g. piano for guitar, and those of a tip-of-the-tongue state,
of the brain as a computational system with functions localized where some features of the word are available, such as initial letter
to specific regions or circuits. The remedy is a concept of brain or sound, and syllabic length. There are errors in which the correct
and psyche in terms of fields or fractals instead of cities and high- word is selected with impaired phonemic encoding, e.g. predisent
ways. for president. Errors can represent blends of normal forms; there
can be combinations of error types, e.g. semantic plus phonemic
The symptom, then, is the link from the pathological to the
errors. In all these instances, there is a progressive zeroing in on
normal; it is a piece of preliminary cognition that surfaces, for that
the target word or object over planes in forebrain evolution, i.e.
moment, as a terminal product. With focal lesions, there is no ar-
the actualization maps to stages in phylogeny. The disorders of
rest of language (object, act) production, no blockage or obstruc-
language were the basis for early ideas on this topic, in which the
tion; the derailment is carried through to subsequent phases. For
process of language production, in its perceptual mode — and this
example, a lexical-semantic error (chair for table) that arises ear-
is true for all mental phenomena — is interpreted as a whole-part
lier in the utterance undergoes normal phonological processing at
or context-item transform that goes from fields of conceptual or
a later phase, e.g. the incorrect word (object) choice is articulated
meaning relations to relations of form or morphology as targets
in correct phonological form. Accordingly, an error is conceived as
individuate out of lexical- or object-categories.
a brief attenuation in normal mentation that is carried through to
a distal termination. When this theory was first proposed, it was In the visual sphere, as in agnosia with lesions of older brain
thought to be similar to the regression model. While the idea of areas such as mesial temporal neocortex, there are disorders of
regression in its classical description by Hughlings Jackson and object-meaning comparable to those of paraphasia, in which ob-
Roman Jakobson, i.e. that pathology unpeels the onion-skin of jects are mis-identified within the object category, such as calling
development in the reverse order of acquisition, has not survived
close scrutiny (Carramazza and Zurif, 1978), the kernel of truth
in the idea has been missed in its rudimentary formulation. As
will become clear in the discussion to follow, the point that was
88 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 89

a plate a cup. The error involves the object concept, not language. tion and/or vocalization. The normal initiation of action that is
The patient can name the object by touch, and can copy a drawing inferred from disorders of axial and proximal motility shifts to
or picture correctly but does not recognize it. With parieto-occipi- (symptoms referring to) more recently evolved stages where the
tal lesions there are errors of object form in which the patient un- act is adequately initiated but derailed in its implementation, as
derstands the object-concept and can describe from memory the in limb apraxia, or phonetic substitution. This passes to the final
shape and function of the object, but cannot identify the object vi- realization (or disruption) of fine, rapid finger movement and ar-
sually (or aurally, etc.). In this type of agnosia, there is a disruption ticulation. The development that goes from archaic to recent in
in the discrimination of form, e.g. a knife is called a screwdriver. evolutionary structure corresponds with the transition from axial
With lesions at late stages in microgeny and phylogeny, errors to distal innervation, from bodily space to the external world, from
point to an involvement of object features, in which even simple symmetry to asymmetry, from low frequency kinetic rhythms that
line drawings cannot be copied in spite of good visual acuity. The mediate inter alia walking and respiration, to higher frequency os-
transition from object meaning to object form is also observed cillators or harmonics that mediate selective kinetic patterns such
in disorders of imagery, such as the distinction of hallucination as those involved in prosody or asymmetric limb movement, to
and illusion, which relate to disruptions at successive phases in the effectuation of action in the world, including articulation.
percept-formation. Disorders of object perception can be thought
of as the external or third-person aspect of the same process as These symptoms and many others that occur with disordered
disorders of imagery, which concern an internal or first-person language, perception, memory, feeling and so on, also show a pro-
perspective. gression from simultaneity to succession, or from spatial to tem-
poral order, as acts and objects originating in midline bodily space
On this view, an image is a briefly attenuated object-develop- individuate outward into the world. The fundamental operation
ment, a perception is a fully externalized image. The derivation is a cascade of context-item shifts, in which a single operation
of an object (action, utterance, etc.) is uni-directional, recurrent is iterated at successive phases. This contrasts with the multiple
and in the direction of evolutionary growth. In vision, the process operations required by modular, localization and componential
leads from a spatial construct in upper brainstem through fields theories. Put differently, unlike the multiple processes acting
of affective, experiential and conceptual meaning, to those of ob- on separate components in modularism, microgenesis entails a
ject form and feature. This sequence corresponds to, indeed, has single fractal-like process that is iterated over successive phases.
been reconstructed from, the effects of lesions on evolutionary This, in outline, was the shape of the theory at an early stage.
formations correlated with errors in image- and object-develop- The mapping was from pathological to normal performance
ment. The fundamental insight is that growth is or becomes the over evolutionary growth planes without reference to maturation
process of cognition. Since every act of cognition retraces the or ontogeny. Then, an insight as to the role of early ontogenetic
same course, the derivation of all cognitive functions, and errors mechanisms clarified the process by which symptoms occurred
in the derivation, will follow the same pattern. and their relation to regression theory.

In action, involvement of older regions of anterior forebrain


gives akinesis and mutism or catatonic-like states. This complex,
or the normal construct inferred from its pathology, is organized
about the axis of the body. This phase fractionates to one of im-
paired initiation (inertia) of the legs, or (difficulty) initiating action
with the upper limbs or in vocalization. Lesions of more recent 
The theory is fully documented, with a wide range of symptoms in relation
structures display selective symptoms in lower or upper limb ac- to brain lesions, and from a clinical, pathological and anatomical standpoint, in
Brown (1988).
90 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 91

3.6. Morphogenesis and symptom formation behavior of a developing brain. The morphology of the brain at
any stage in development is an artificial slice through process,
The relation of symptom to normal function is best approached by with behavior its four-dimensional structure. In other words, mor-
way of a detour into ontogeny; specifically, morphogenesis, which phogenetic process lays down form qua morphology early in life,
is the growth process in the fetal brain that translates the genetic and form qua behavior later in life. The similarity of the process
code to structure and function. We know there is no simple corre- of growth to that of cognition becomes clear when we consider
spondence between the code and brain morphology. Even if 50% morphogenesis not as an open-ended linear succession but as a
of the human genome is devoted to the brain, this cannot account recurrent pattern, in which new form is laid down over antecedent
in a 1:1 manner for the trillions of cells and connections. Thus, structure. This shift in perspective helps us to see how the same
developmental biologists tend to focus on correspondence rules process that is responsible for the growth of the brain continues
or algorithms that govern the translation of code to structure. At as the process that is responsible for behavior. Put differently, a
the molecular level these are complex events involving the tim- single reiterated process that deposits structure early in fetal life
ing, rate and contextual effects of gene combination, as well as a continues in recurrent cycles to deposit behavior in post-natal life.
variety of epigenetic factors. Behavior is four-dimensional morphology or structure over time.
Memory is the obvious link from structure to function. Early in
In neurology, growth and morphology have usually been con-
development, the persistence (recurrence) of brain structure is a
ceived as problems distinct from function or behavior. The com-
kind of organic or “physical” memory. The “memory” of experi-
mon view is that developmental process lays down brain structure,
ence then becomes the structure through which experience is
which then outputs function. For many psychologists, stages in
filtered. Experience develops out of categories — early memorial
evolutionary growth are as irrelevant to cognition as stages in the
processes — that are engraved in patterns that underlie mature
construction of a computer. The sequence of assembly or instal-
cognition. The “permanence” of a learned or remembered item is
lation of components, in evolution or in manufacture, is deemed
the structural aspect of thought.
unrelated to the operation of the mechanism, whether a brain or
a computer, whether carbon or silicon, mind or software. Clearly, There have been prior speculations along these lines. Karl
function is active and dynamic, so the concept of a fixed circuitry Pribram (1991) alluded to this possibility from work suggesting
requires a demarcation and solidification of the mental so that it that patterns in embryogenesis persist as force lines that deter-
can be deposited in specific locations in a computation network mine the nature and direction of processes in perception. Others
(brain), with the function then interpreted as the output of the cir- have commented on the possibility that ontogenetic sculpting re-
cuitry. In fact, what is needed is a dynamic concept of both struc- lates to learning and information processing. But when the theory
ture and function in relation to phyletic and ontogenetic growth was first advanced (Brown, 1994), little more had been published
trends. Specifically, an organic theory is needed that relates brain on the topic. In this chapter, I will consider two “mechanisms”
growth and cognitive function to trends in evolution and develop- involved in morphogenetic growth that can account for both er-
ment and the genesis of the mind/brain state. rors and advances, failure and success, in human development.
These mechanisms, parcellation and heterochrony, can be related
If we consider morphology and behavior, structure and func-
to brain lesions and the process of symptom formation and more
tion, in relation to the growth process, and if we think of growth
importantly, illustrate patterns in the actualization of the mind/
in terms of a population dynamic and the cognitive process as
brain state.
the configured properties of populations of cells, it may be pos-
sible to correlate growth and cognition. The first step is to consider
brain development not as antecedent to morphology, i.e. growth
does not lay down a fixed anatomy but rather, morphology is the
92 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 93

3.7. Parcellation tion with loss of fine discrimination. Specification by elimination


is an innate characteristic of morphogenesis, but sensory experi-
Parcellation is the theory that early in fetal brain growth there is ence drives the process into maturation without altering its fun-
exuberant proliferation and migration of cells, an initial over-abun- damental properties. At some point in morphogenesis, perhaps
dance with multiple overlapping connections that is followed by an after the basic connectivity is established, specification continues
attrition of cells and connections through competitive interaction through inhibition in a connectivity that is relatively stable. That
to achieve synaptic specificity. In almost every area of the brain is, inhibition plays the role in function that elimination played in
that has been studied, exuberant cell growth is accompanied by growth.
cell loss as structure takes on definition (Ebbeson, 1984). Initially,
the elimination pertains to cells, then to the connectivity. For Inhibition leads to the same outcome as elimination, namely,
example, Changeux (1985) found in the juvenile mouse that the greater specificity of innervation, though unlike elimination, inhi-
multiple climbing fibers innervating the Purkinje cells drop out bition is potentially reversible. There are many examples in nor-
as the cell arborizes, leaving a single innervation. One of the most mal development. Visual evoked potentials can be recorded over
dramatic example of elimination in development was reported by a wide area of cortex in juveniles but gradually zero in on the vi-
Rakic (1992) in macaque. Using electron microscopy, he found sual cortex in the adult. In pathology, the potentials re-generalize.
that by the age of sexual maturity there is a loss of over 2 trillion Coghill (1964) described successive inhibition of spinal reflexes
synapses in neocortex. in the differentiation of motility. In pathology, there is dis-inhibi-
tion and re-generalization with mass reflexes. Progressive inhibi-
tion may account for the concept of diffuse right and focal left
hemisphere function (Semmes 1968), as well as the progressive
specification of the left language areas (Brown and Jaffe, 1975).
Selective inhibition in childhood development individuates the
global movements of hands and face (the cherubic face of young
children). Wall (1988) noted that cortical cells with wide recep-
tive fields in juveniles undergo progressive inhibition to establish
specificity, and re-generalize in pathology with disinhibition of
latent synapses, perhaps as a mechanism of compensation by
intact areas.

The equivalent of parcellation in growth, or surround inhibition


in physiology, is the whole-to-part or context-to-item transforma-
Fig. 3.1. Hypothesis of epigenesis by selective stabilization. tion in cognition, the specification of parts out of wholes by way of
Spontaneous or evoked activity in the developing neuronal net- constraints on developing form. Such a process in language, per-
work controls the elimination of excess synapses formed during the ception and other modes of cognition is supported by the ubiquity
stage of transient redundancy (adapted from Changeux,1985). of terms such as individuation, differentiation, specification, fig-
ure-ground, holistic-analytic, surround-center and frame-content
The process of parcellation is innately driven but is sustained theory. These are different ways of describing the whole-to-part
in the infant by sensory input at birth (see: fig. 3.1.). Studies have transform, where wholes are not sums but configured anteced-
shown that visually deprived animals do not develop the fine con- ents, and parts are realizations, not constituents. This transform
nectivity typical of the normal visual system. A more diffuse or re- is the basic pattern of the system, first by way of elimination, then
dundant connectivity accompanies an ambient mode of percep-
94 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 95

inhibition, then by context-item specification. The sculpting by way a selective retardation or prolongation of a juvenile stage that can
of constraints at successive phases in the transitional sequence is be a springboard of evolutionary growth. An example would be
the driving force of microgenetic process. A single process guides the lengthening of the period of sexual maturity over the primate
evolution, development and cognition, not multiple processes series leading to man, from two years in the lemur, seven in the
acting at different points. The argument is that parcellation by great apes, to about twelve in humans. Delayed closure of the cra-
elimination, specification by inhibition, and the elicitation of items nial sutures is a neotenous feature that permits the expansion of
from contexts by constraints at successive phases in cognition are a similarly neotenous brain. In this instance, the prolongation of
all instances of a common process in which growth lays down the a stage of growth in the fetus or juvenile is the basis for evolution-
patterns that drive cognition. Moreover, the concept that cognitive ary advance. This also illustrates the evolutionary principle that
form is trimmed by the elimination of maladaptive routes of ac- growth and innovation occur from earlier, more plastic, holistic
tualization is consistent with the evolutionary principle that unfit and homogeneous stages of potential, not as endpoints of speci-
forms are pruned by the environment. fication. Gould (1982) put it nicely in writing that evolution is a
branching bush, not a ladder of progress.
The thesis advanced here is that exuberant production of cells
and connections in fetal growth is constrained by elimination
early in life to achieve specificity in connectivity. Then inhibition
replaces elimination to achieve greater specificity on a relatively
settled morphology. The morphogenetic and physiological shift
from generality to specificity is gradually etched into the brain in
context-item or whole-part transitions from one category to an-
other in the specification of acts and objects. The trimming of ex-
cess to achieve anatomical specificity continues in the constraints
on form to achieve functional specificity. The shift from category
to member or whole to part repeats evolutionary and morpho-
genetic patterns. The parsing of excess for adaptive fitness in the
competition for environmental niche corresponds with the actu- Fig. 3.2. The juvenile chimpanzee (A) resembles the human in
alization of mental objects to adaptive saliency by constraints on the vertical alignment of the cervical spine, the rounded cranium,
alternative form. The mind/brain state concentrates in every act high forehead, flattened muzzle, lack of supra-orbital ridges and
of thought the population dynamic of evolutionary speciation. thinner skull bones. The figure illustrates the idea that the prolon-
gation of a juvenile stage can underlie an evolutionary advance.

Neoteny has both adaptive and maladaptive consequences


(see: fig. 3.2.). The former can be illustrated by expanding on a
3.8. Heterochrony little-noticed theory of dominance published many years ago
(Brown, 1978) that provides an alternative to the bigger-is-better
Parcellation is the pattern of process in development and behavior.
concept that is its sole anatomic rival. In pre-human primates
Heterochrony is the rate or timing of this process. Heterochrony
there is relative symmetry of function. One can rephrase this by
is the idea that different organ systems develop at different rates
saying there is bilateral representation of many functions and
in brain development or evolution, and that a difference in the
contralateral representation of others, such as motor function.
timing of development can lead to shifts in evolutionary out-
There is little or no asymmetric or lateral representation, i.e. dom-
comes, including adaptations, errors and aberrations. Neoteny is
96 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 97

inance, as occurs in humans. There is some evidence for laterality maladaptive. This is where the symptom comes in. A symptom is
of hand movement in primates (McNeilage, Studdert-Kennedy a kind of negative adaptation, a behavior that is maladaptive with
and Lindblom, 1987) but no bias to left or right hemisphere. respect to the immediate surround. While many errors would
seem anomalous in any environment, the abnormality reflects a
In microgenetic theory, the Wernicke and Broca zones that lack of fit to the situation. The failure of performance to adapt to
mediate phonological processing individuate out of background external conditions is important. For example, hallucination and
association or integration neocortex. The claim here is that in- language errors are normal in dream, not the waking state.
dividuation creates a phase in cognition intermediate between
integration and primary cortices (Fig. 3.3.). Lateral representation To understand the symptom, it is necessary to first consider
results from a subtraction of the functional connectivity mediat- parcellation and neoteny in relation to errors of development.
ing bilateral representation. Dominance is not an addition to the Serres (1860, cited in Gould) described the neotenous origin of
prior stage but an outcropping of an earlier one due to the prun- anomalies when certain parts lag behind in development and
ing of homologous regions. Specifically, new growth occurs not retain at birth the characteristics of earlier stages. He noted that
by terminal addition, but by way of parcellation (inhibition) at the anomaly pointed to the stage in development that was unduly
penultimate phases. The Wernicke and Broca zones arise in the prolonged. In other words, a birth defect refers to the retardation
prolongation and specification of a juvenile phase in fetal growth. of a stage in fetal growth. The thesis of this paper is that an error
In this instance, parcellation and neoteny combine to give lateral in cognition points to a brief neoteny, or retardation of microge-
asymmetry. netic process that is comparable to the retardation in fetal growth
responsible for errors in ontogenetic process.

For example, neoteny at a certain stage in limb bud develop-


ment would explain why the digits do not fully individuate and the
infant is born with a fist-like hand. The local process is retarded
just prior to the individuation of the digits, but the development of
the organism — including the defective limb — proceeds unabat-
ed. The defect points to a local segment of development where
the individuation of the digits should have occurred, but did not.
When foreshortened digits appear with webbing or syndactyly
Fig. 3.3. The emergence of the Wernicke and Broca zones with- and normal nail bed formation, the presumption is that the re-
in the «integration» neocortex is a neotenous expansion in brain tardation occurred at a stage after the initial partition, while the
development giving cerebral asymmetry as an effect of parcella- ensuing phase of nail bed formation occurs normally on the distal
tion. The growth stage is prolonged (neoteny) and the connectivity portion of fingers that are incompletely specified. The anomaly
relating to right hemisphere is selectively inhibited (parcellation), and its continued development to birth indicate that a slowing of
such that an asymmetric plane of left sided language representa- development does not obstruct the process, but carries the defect
tion, or lateral representation, develops between bilateral and con- through to completion. The defect is a marker of the stage in de-
tralateral representation. velopment where the retardation occurs. Put differently, an error
is the signature of an upstream segment in the growth process. In
This is an example of a positive adaptation. Evolution and this case, neoteny leads to a defect of development. Compare
development are double- edged swords. The same process that this with the positive effects of a retardation in the closure of the
gives a beneficial adaptation can produce one that is harmful or cranial sutures that allows for a greater expansion of the juvenile
98 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 99

brain. The closure is prolonged but still occurs at a later stage. The While the theory can explain most neuropsychological errors
retardation of closure, or its prolongation, coincides with a period (Brown, 1988; 1994; 2005), it can best be illustrated by the com-
of active brain growth, also a neotenous feature. The combination monly observed effects of a lesion on an error of naming, such as
of open sutures and sustained growth allow for the expansion of discussed earlier, say a patient with a left posterior lesion who calls
the human brain after birth. a table a “chair”. How can this be explained? On the microgenetic
account, the process of lexical realization, or the specification of
The claim is that the principle effect of a focal brain lesion is to word meaning, develops to the point of the object category, e.g.
retard process, not destroy function. The lesion induces a change furniture, where the potential to specify the word table is equiva-
in a configuration that is a type of traveling wave. If an act of cog- lent to that for the word chair. A momentary retardation at this
nition is conceived in relation to evolutionary and maturational phase can be conceived as a brief neoteny. The result is incom-
growth, a symptom is a kind of micro-developmental error. A focal plete specification of the developing content. The fractionation
lesion of the brain exposes pre-processing phases. The effect of to the target is prolonged at a phase just prior to full selection. If
a brain lesion can be likened to that of a rock in a stream, which there is selection of the word “chair”, i.e. the neural configuration
delays, diverts or perturbs the flow but does not block it (Fig. 3.4.). corresponding to that word, it then passes to an ensuing phase
The relation of symptoms to eddy currents and whirlpools has of phonological realization. The wrong word emerges, but has
been explored mathematically in Hopfield simulations (Hoffman, undergone normal phonological encoding. Subsequent phases
1987). The nature of the error is determined by the location of of phonological realization occur on deviant semantic form.
the disruption in language, perception or action. A disparity in the However, the word is not really deviant; it points back to a phase
timing of a process that advances like a wave front leads to a local where either chair or table might have been elicited. The error
delay that is “out of synch” with concurrent parallel streams. samples the semantic context that has failed to achieve the requi-
site specificity in a word appropriate to (that fits or is adapted to)
the situation. On this theory, even the «correct» word, table, might
be construed as an error in certain contexts. The noun is holo-
phrastic; it does not have the referential or denotative specificity
of a fully individuated lexical item (Grober et al., 1980).

The aphasic error, chair for table, results from a focal retarda-
tion in process (neoteny) and an incomplete specification (parcel-
lation) of the lexical item, but the derailment undergoes normal
subsequent processing, showing that double dissociation can oc-
cur in a serial model (Brown and Pachalska 2003). However, a brain
lesion differs from a rock in a river in that — unlike a river, where
the current moves on — cognition is recurrent, more like a foun-
Fig. 3.4. The lesion delays a segment of process (neoteny). The
tain, so that the disruption is encountered on each new traversal.
delay accompanies an incomplete specification (parcellation) of
This accounts for the variability of errors, as well as their regularity
the lexical or phonological item (see text). The neotenous form
or clustering within distinct categories. The aphasic error reflects
continues to a normal endpoint. The incompletely individu-
the prevailing context at the phase of disruption. The difference
ated lexical item undergoes subsequent phonological process-
between developmental errors in children and acquired errors
ing. Conversely, one can have phonological defects with normal
in adults is neoteny in the formation of a system as opposed to
semantics. This shows how a double dissociation can occur in a
neoteny in the reinstantiation of a system that is already formed.
serial processing model.
100 Jason W. Brown

In children with errors of language development, the semantic


context is impoverished, so that errors tend to be simplifications
that are more predictable. Contextual cues are less effective. The
maturational aspect is evident when a three years old child is said
to be at the stage of a normal eighteen months old.

In sum, the individuation of parts (e.g. lexical items) out of


wholes (e.g. semantic categories) can be related to a concept of
errors in which a focal lesion induces a brief delay in one segment
of the stream of cognition, while parallel streams undergo normal
processing. The theory of the symptom is based on evolutionary
and ontogenetic principles and supports the microgenetic con-
cept. While speculative, it is coherent with a substantial body of
data and observation (Brown, 1988), and provides an explanation
for a variety of clinical errors that are often dismissed as meaning-
less guesses or random noise. This concept of the error in terms
of specification and timing, i.e. the pattern of process and its rate,
allows a reformulation of the regression hypothesis. Microgeny
does not retrace ontogeny; pathology does not recapitulate stages
in acquisition. It is not the stages that recur but the process leading
to the stages. In a word, the recapitulation pertains to the process,
not to the actualized elements it deposits.
Chapter 4
Inner Speech

4.1. Introduction
The concept of an error as a brief attenuation and the relation of
errors to normal performances are a guide to an interpretation of
the inner life of thought. Introspection is usually conceived as a
higher or late stage in cognitive development, as the self begins to
examine itself, but to my knowledge there is no neural or psycho-
logical account of how introspection occurs, indeed, no account
of the mind/brain state, whether directly or in relation to internal
and external events. Introspection involves the self in relation to
verbal and perceptual imagery, so a theory of introspection re-
quires an account of imagery in relation to speech and perception.
For this reason, for the transition from inner to outer, the relation
of self to images and objects, indeed, for an understanding of the
process of visual and verbal thinking that is, or should be, the core
of a theory of mind, a neuropsychological model of inner speech
is of central importance.

For microgenesis, introspection is not a cognitive add-on but a


branching, a deviation or accentuation of preliminary phases in
the mental state. Specifically, introspection is the enhancement of
phases antecedent to objects. In this respect, it is like a symptom,
in which memory, thought and verbal imagery remain internal
rather than discharging into speech, perception or action. The final
act or object is present, but in abeyance. When a transient thought
or memory occurs, the outer world is still active in consciousness,
or in deep concentration, in sustained thought or meditation, or
in creative withdrawal. Without an external world, the phase of
visual or verbal imagery that underlies introspection takes on
the quality of dream. The inner world is accentuated to the ex-
tent that the impact of the outer world is diminished. Thought,
fantasy, reverie and the creative imagination represent different
aspects of this withdrawal; dream or hallucinatory psychosis oc-
curs when the outer world disappears. Waking hallucination is an
incomplete perception in a specific modality, i.e. the perception is
104 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 105

lost in a specific locus or throughout the visual (or auditory) field. his description of the word-concept was similar to the writings
Hallucination replaces the absent object, as dream occurs in the by Charcot and other French authors on ‘‘inner speech’’. For
suspension of percept-development in all modalities. Dejerine (in Hecaen & Angelergues, 1965), interior language was
‘‘une veritable voix interieure’’, with a strong association to au-
The symptom as a local coming-to-the-fore at a pre-terminal ditory verbal hallucinations (Brown 2004b). Dejerine, who was
phase in pathology is a capsule of inner speech or introspection strongly associationist in his thinking, wrote that inner speech in-
as a more generalized coming-to-the-fore of preliminary phases volved an intimate union of motor and auditory images and that
in normal cognition. The distortion, fusion, metaphoric extension true aphasia involved the loss of inner speech. For Wernicke, also
and category-sampling that are evident in symptom-formation an associationist, the auditory and speech motor components of
are the nucleus of creative or productive thinking in introspection. the word-concept corresponded with the posterior and anterior
The following account of inner speech is a natural continuation of language areas, while the word-concept itself, or ‘‘inner speech’’,
the preceding chapters on perception and the genesis of novelty was attributed to the arcuate fasciculus, a bundle of fibres that
(symptoms, adaptations) in the prolongation of early phases while connects these two areas (Eggert, 1977). This pathway has been
final ones still to actualize. associated in connectionist theories with the transmission of lan-
guage from its formulation in the posterior portion of the brain
The interpretation of inner speech calls into play the relation to
to its production in the frontal lobe, while an interruption of the
perception, hallucination and aspects of speech production. The
pathway has been thought to give rise to conduction aphasia.
active or agentive mode of inner speech in relation to a voluntary
utterance is contrasted with the passive or receptive mode of in- Kurt Goldstein (1948; see also, Henderson, 1992), who was a
ner speech in relation to auditory hallucination and perception. A student of Wernicke with a more holistic view than his teacher,
subtle shift in perception or action determines the active or pas- was less convinced of the anatomical location of conduction apha-
sive quality and the relation to inner and outer objects. The shift sia, and referred the disorder to a phase in the transition from
is a qualitative change that transforms one phenomenon to an- thought to speech. He noted that the concept of inner speech
other. An auditory image or hallucination that prefigures speech traced from both philosophical and psychological sources. In the
perception, or arises when perception is disrupted, is a difference former, W. von Humboldt created the term ‘‘innere Sprachform’’
of kind, not degree. This discussion of inner speech in relation to for the inner experiences of the individual who speaks or under-
self, image and object should assist the reader to follow the ra- stands language. This is in contrast to the use of inner speech in
tionale of more speculative chapters on self, consciousness and the psychological literature to refer to experiential content elicited
intentionality, all of which are derived from neuropsychological by hearing speech that precedes speaking.
studies such as those described in this chapter.
Goldstein modified Wernicke’s definition to include the total-
ity of processes and experiences that occur when we are going to
express our thoughts in external speech and when we perceive
heard sounds as language. Inner speech was of special impor-
4.2. Historical Studies tance to an understanding of the process through which thought
In Wroclaw (Breslau), in 1874, working as a young assistant at develops into speech. A disorder at the stage of the thought-
the university, Carl Wernicke published his first work on aphasia. speech transition, which he termed ‘‘central’’ aphasia, was viewed
However, it was not until many years later that he developed the as intermediate between amnestic aphasia, a disorder of abstract
notion of the Wortbegriff, or word-concept, as a combination of thinking, and motor aphasia, a disorder of the instrumentalities
acoustic and motor speech imagery. Wernicke pointed out that of speech production. He attributed the primary symptom of the
106 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 107

disorder, phonemic paraphasia, to a disruption midway between hemispheric pathways, is presumed to maintain synchrony in the
word finding and articulation. Goldstein did not equate inner phase transitions across widely distributed systems, not to convey
speech with thinking (De Bleser & Marshall, 2005), which was pri- linguistic content from one site in the brain to another. Arguments
marily identified with the abstract ability, such as that impaired against the role of the arcuate fasciculus in conduction aphasia or
in amnestic aphasia, but he did argue that it was an important inner speech (Brown, 1975) have yet to be refuted.
aspect of central aphasia.

From the earliest days of Wernicke’s studies the auditory and


motor components related to what we now call the Wernicke
and Broca zones, but the auditory component of inner speech 4.3. Theory of inner speech
was more strongly emphasized, and related by Goldstein and More precisely, if the bias in the conjoined development of anterior
the French neuropsychologists to auditory-verbal hallucinations. and posterior language areas is to the anterior zone, or to speech
There is considerable evidence that both the posterior (percep- (Figure 1), and the perceptual development is in the background,
tual) and the anterior (motor) language areas are involved. The i.e., the distal (perceptual) segment is not emphatic and the action
great student of inner speech in relation to the motor speech com- side is accentuated, there will be ordinary motor speech. The ac-
ponent was A. R. Luria, who was concerned with the relation of cent on speech, or the inattention to auditory perception, explains
internal to external or motor speech. Luria described a variety of why it is difficult to speak and listen at the same time.
methods to investigate the role of inner speech in verbal regulation
of speech and behavior, including bite-block techniques, which If speech development is attenuated prior to vocalization, and
I witnessed during a stay in his laboratory, as well as EMG and the posterior development is not constrained to perception by au-
other clinical methods. Dynamic aphasia, and the controversial ditory sensation, there will be motor and perceptual equivalence,
afferent aphasia, were related to a disturbance in the regulatory and the verbal imagery will be that of inner speech. The process
function of inner speech. Weigl (1964) also reported findings from of language perception contributes the linguistic content; the pro-
this perspective. Some writers have written of inner speech as un- cess of speech development contributes the feeling of agency.
expressed speech, or speaking to one’s self without verbalizing;
that is, as a motor pre-verbitum plus the auditory image. In the If the anterior development is attenuated with a bias to the
cognitivist literature (e.g., Baddeley, 1986), covert verbal rehearsal posterior development there will be a receptive attitude to audi-
is an essential part of working memory. However, Luria rejected tory verbal imagery. This is the normal experience in reverie or
the view of the behaviorists that inner speech was merely an ut- on falling asleep when we seem to be passive listeners to our own
terance minus its articulation and emphasized, after Vygotsky, its internal monologue. It is also the basis on which verbal hallucina-
differences with overt speech, especially the self-referential and tion develops, when the passivity to one’s own speech imagery
predicative quality. reaches the point where the image is felt as alien or external. I
have frequently had the hypnagogic experience of an internal dis-
In this paper I will first present the microgenetic theory of in- course, in which I felt the passivity of the verbal image undergo
ner speech, then the evidence regarding the role of the anterior ‘‘detachment’’, with brief uncertainty as to whether the verbal
component of inner speech, next the posterior component, then image was a subjective content or had objectified as a perceptual
the relation to the latter of imagery and perception. Finally, I will equivalent, i.e., an hallucination.
attempt to demonstrate how both systems contribute to inner
speech and related phenomena. The role of the arcuate fasciculus
as postulated by Wernicke, as with other transcortical and inter-
108 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 109

However, the involvement of non-speech motility could just as


well indicate that the motor speech area is part of a wider frontal
system for action, while the effect of a bite block could be a re-
sult of interference in the performance of competing dual tasks.
As mentioned, Luria based his thinking on the work of Vygotsky
(1962), who argued that inner speech is the interiorized ego-
centric speech of childhood, which externalizes again as an aid
in performance when children are given difficult tasks (see also
Fig. 4.1. A = speech (verbal action), P = language perception. Flavell, Green, Flavell, & Grossman, 1997). Vygotsky described
(1) A full derivation of A that discharges into motility gives normal inner speech as predicative, since the topic of a sentence would
speech. (2) An incomplete development of A and P gives inner already be known to the speaker. Luria’s claim that inner speech
speech. (3) The derivation of an endogenous content into percep- is disrupted in agrammatism was taken as further evidence of a
tion gives auditory hallucination. (4) The substrate of a halluci- link between inner speech and the Broca region.
nation becomes auditory perception when it is constrained by
acoustic sensation. It is said that Kurt Goldstein suffered a stroke with a global
aphasia for about a week before he died, giving him the oppor-
Finally, in speech perception, motor speech is in abeyance and tunity to determine whether or not his theory was correct. While
the auditory image is sculpted by auditory sense-data to an exter- I am not aware of any descriptions of Goldstein’s aphasia, some
nal object. signs of inner language can be found in other cases with total
aphasia. Studies of hemiplegic writing (Brown, Leader, & Blum,
1983; Friedland, 1990; Whurr & Lorch, 1991) suggest the presence
of inner language in cases of global aphasia or severe non-flu-
4.4. Studies on the motor component ency. With the use of a prosthesis for the right upper extremity,
and with some training, patients are able to write grammatical
In neuropsychology, the association of inner speech with the fron- phrases with their paralyzed arm, although unable to speak or to
tal lobes, and its disruption in motor aphasia, is largely due to the write with the intact left hand. The performance is not accompa-
work of Luria (1961), who conceived inner speech as ‘‘a special nied by a full awareness of accuracy. Patients are often surprised
stage involved with the transition from thought to the speech ut- at their performance, and have difficulty initiating written state-
terance (in which) … the inner sense is transformed into a system ments or requests, in agreement with a loss of the ‘‘regulative’’ or
of expanded, syntactically organized speech meanings’’ (Luria, voluntary use of language. The finding does indicate the presence
1961). Luria was impressed by the failure of motor-aphasic patients of residual language in patients with extensive damage to the mo-
to regulate non-verbal motor activities as well as external speech. tor speech area. The source of this residual language is uncertain,
He noted that merely suppressing the tongue, or having normal whether through the right brain or through posterior or neighbor-
participants or motor-aphasic patients hold their mouth open or ing systems in the damaged hemisphere.
bite on a block, impairs speech as well as other motor tasks. This
suggested an impairment of inner speech in motor aphasia. The In studies in my laboratory by Ross (1983) of letter cancellation
disruption of inner speech in aphasia or in normal participants on reading tasks, non-fluent aphasic patients, unlike deaf people,
supported the idea that inner speech has a regulative function on were shown to have the same pattern as normal participants. For
overt speech and behavior. example, they were more likely to cancel the letter ‘‘h’’ in the
word horse than in the word the, and still less likely to cancel it
110 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 111

when silent, as in the word ghost. This finding suggests that inner naming (Brown & McNeill, 1966). As in normal individuals who
phonology is to some extent preserved. The patients also showed search for a word, the aphasic patient with a temporo-parietal le-
sensitivity to function words, inconsistent with accounts of a loss sion who is unable to produce a noun can often give the initial let-
of function words in the agrammatism of anterior aphasia. The ter or sound and indicate whether it is a long or short word, often
question of what is going on in the mind of the patient with mo- giving the number of syllables in the word. This suggests that the
tor aphasia is an old one, still unanswered. It does appear from lexical frame and segmentation of the word are to some extent
the limited research on this topic that inner language is available preserved in spite of the errors in language production.
in some form, even in severe motor-aphasic patients, but that its
volitional (and regulative) ‘‘use’’ is lost. To have inner speech pas- Other studies tend to confirm this observation. In unpub-
sively, as a verbal image or hallucination, is close to not having it at lished studies many years ago in my laboratory, we found strong
all. A motor-aphasic patient who experiences inner speech as pas- semantic priming in global aphasia, indicating a comprehension
sive would be unable to ‘‘use’’ it in behavior or to direct an active of the meanings of words in patients who otherwise could give
vocal or motor performance. This interpretation is consistent with no evidence they could understand them. Other studies of word-
the proposal offered in this paper that the linguistic content of meaning comprehension in aphasia with posterior brain damage,
inner speech develops in relation to temporal lobe structures for including priming, masking, inference, and other techniques, re-
auditory perception, while the active or volitional quality of inner inforce the impression that cases with a disruption of speech and/
speech is related to frontal lobe structures for speech production. or comprehension still have some interior language, although the
nature and extent of the residual ability are difficult to assess. It
More recent PET and functional MRI studies suggest that the would be of interest, for example, to see the results in such cases
left inferior frontal gyrus and temporal cortex are engaged in of rebus studies that sample internal naming, e.g., seeing a picture
tasks that involve self-monitoring, which has been associated with of a cow and a boy and selecting a picture of a cowboy.
inner speech (McGuire, Silbersweig, & Frith, 1996; Shergill et al.,
2001). A loss of inner speech in a case with lesion of this area has More recent studies have confirmed the association of inner
been reported (Levine, Calvanio, & Popovics, 1982). Similar find- speech with the posterior language areas. The loss of self-moni-
ings were reported by Verstichel, Bourak, Font, and Crochet (1997) toring in fluent jargon aphasia or severe semantic paraphasia is
in frontal-aphasic patients. Taken together such observations indi- consistent with its importance for self-awareness (Baars, Ramsey,
cate that inner speech is related to frontal lobe activity, especially & Laureys, 2003). Vogely and Fink (2003) described fMRI activa-
to the left hemispheric speech areas. This would account for the tion in parietal areas when participants were asked to assume the
loss of inner speech or its disruption in motor aphasia and the visual standpoint of another person, stressing the importance of
importance of frontal areas in the regulation of speech and be- these areas to the first person perspective.
havior.

4.6. Verbal hallucination


4.5. Studies on the perceptual component Apart from arguments based on the symptoms of aphasia, an
Research in patients with posterior aphasia is also relevant to in- important source of data concerning inner speech comes from
ner speech. We have known for some time from studies of the psychotic or brain-damaged cases with auditory hallucination
tip-of-the-tongue (TOT) phenomenon that the initial sound and and presumed temporal lobe dysfunction. Verbal hallucinations
syllabic length of a word are available to patients with difficulty in may occur as an aura in temporal lobe epileptic patients and they
112 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 113

are common in word-deafness with damage to the auditory cor- It seems clear that verbal hallucination is related in some way
tex. Hoff and Silberman (1933) induced verbal hallucination and to inner speech, but there are important differences. First, un-
‘‘echo’’ phenomena by applying ethyl chloride to an exposed au- like the posterior aphasias, verbal hallucination does not show a
ditory area in the right superior temporal convolution. Ishibashi, prominent left temporal asymmetry, although it is probable that
Hori, Endo, and Sato (1964) noted that stimulation of auditory cor- dominance in speech perception is less pronounced than in speech
tex in schizophrenic patients can induce auditory hallucination production. The greater bilateral representation for semantic
and diminish chronic hallucinations. Burckhardt (1891) reported than phonological processing may account for instances in which
that excision of auditory cortex in schizophrenic patients leads to metabolic studies have shown bilateral or asymmetric changes.
a reduction in auditory perception and in verbal hallucination. Then there is the passive quality, the feeling that the voices are
coming to the person from an external source. The receptive qual-
Based on electromyographic studies, Inouye and Shimizu ity of auditory hallucinations is in contrast to the usual experience
(1970) emphasized the auditory aspect and its prominence in of inner speech as active or volitional. In schizophrenia, verbal
dream and auditory hallucination. EMG studies have shown sub- hallucination often begins as inner speech. Gradually, there is a
vocal articulatory movements during inner speech and auditory waning of the active quality of talking to one’s self, with increas-
hallucination (Lagache, 1934). Auditory hallucinations tend to be ing passivity to the voice, to which the person begins to respond.
suspended during respiratory pauses. De Morsier (1938) noted Eventually, the voice externalizes in hallucinatory conversation,
that auditory hallucination and speech tend not to occur at the and it may even take on an agency of its own in command hal-
same time, nor do patients hear external speech while they are lucinations. There is also the fact that verbal hallucinations may
hallucinating. Audiometric studies show ‘‘lacunae’’ in patients occur with multiple voices of a different age, accent, or gender
during bouts of auditory hallucination. In the so-called ‘‘echo of from the person. Presumably, this is somehow explained by the
reading’’ in psychotic patients, verbal hallucination follows read- recall of voices previously heard, even if the voice quality is altered
ing by a second or two as a kind of shadow. The patient reads or is unfamiliar. Such observations introduce the problem of how
a passage, silently or aloud, then hears the passage read to him memory relates to hallucination and speech perception.
in his own voice a moment later, perhaps similar to a delayed
auditory feedback experience. Lhermitte (1951) has described In sum, since its earliest description inner speech has been
cases of paraphasia with paraphasic auditory hallucinations, and thought to have an auditory and a speech motor constituent. The
Hecaen and Ropaert (1959) described a case of palilalia with pali- perceptual component provides the linguistic content; the ante-
lalic hallucinations. Auditory verbal hallucinations are associated rior component, inter alia, determines the degree of agency. The
with increased activity in both left and right temporal cortex (e.g., auditory component has been explored in posterior aphasia and
Bentaleb, Beauregard, Liddle, & Stip, 2003). hallucination. To more fully understand this phenomenon one
needs to examine (1) the relation of hallucination to memory and
These observations show that: (1) inner speech is damaged in to both speech and speech perception, (2) the relation of verbal
posterior aphasia, (2) posterior-aphasic participants show evidence imagery to speech, (3) the passive character of hallucination, and
of residual semantic and phonological capacity, (3) aphasic errors (4) the active character of inner speech.
can occur in auditory hallucination, (4) stimulation of auditory
cortex can produce verbal hallucination, (5) verbal hallucination
and speech perception are affected by stimulation or ablation of
auditory cortex and, as a conclusion, (6) inner speech and verbal
hallucination most likely have a common basis.
114 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 115

4.7. Memory, hallucination and perception dreamed of reading an old science text and, precisely at page 109,
found the next four pages separately bound and inserted in the
Since my early writings on perception (Brown, 1982, 1983, re- book. The pages were floral and quite different from the scientific
printed in Brown, 1988, 2004), an essential component of the portion. They contained a poem of about eight lines, with only
theory was the idea that the structure of a perception consisted of a few words or lines in the middle of each page. In the ensuing
a transition over phases in memory (see chapter 1). The sequence scene I was looking at a statue of the man who wrote the poem
goes from long-term through short-term to iconic memory to ob- (?myself), with the poem inscribed at the base. I awoke and could
ject perception, such that a perception is an objectified memory only remember the first two lines of what seemed to be a wonder-
constrained by extrinsic sensation, indeed, a dream shaped to a ful poem. The lines were:
vision of reality, with objects remembered into perception and
recognized before they are consciously perceived. The theory, Run thee a poem in thy time
developed on the clinical material, is consistent with findings in
blind-sight, i.e., vision without a visual cortex, or those studies on Pay not a fare to the rhyme or the meter.
increased semantic priming in global aphasia.
However brief, this was not at all a poem I could have written
For some time I assumed that verbal hallucination in dream did awake. The symbolism, the felicity, and double meanings were
not fully actualize to a phase of phonological processing through evident immediately on awakening. ‘‘Run thee a poem’’ meant
the Wernicke zone, since phonology, as measured in studies of write a poem and live a beautiful life. ‘‘In thy time’’ meant in my
rhyme and monitoring for initial or embedded syllables, is se- life and in my own way. ‘‘Pay not a fare’’ meant pay no attention
verely disrupted in cases with damage to that area. Phonological to others and do not be concerned with money, while the playful
errors are common in sleep talking (Arkin & Brown, 1971). Word avoidance of the obvious rhyme illustrates the theme of freedom
meaning, not phonology, appears to dominate in the language in the verse.
imagery of dream, just as visual imagery contains symbolic and
meaning-laden images. In a personal dream, I offered a room
(Zimmer) in a German hotel to an American editor with a German
publishing company whose name was Zimmar, and awoke quite 4.8. Agency and recipience
satisfied with the pun. More surprising, however, and consistent
with the idea that the Wernicke and Broca areas are functionally Let me turn to the difference between the passivity to auditory hal-
active in dream, was a dream of a courtroom with a play on ‘‘dock- lucination and the feeling of voluntary control over inner speech,
et’’ and ‘‘pocket’’ money. This suggests that phonology is available a feeling that is less an intention applied to a performance than
in the verbal hallucinations of dream, again unlike the pattern in an intrinsic feature that can change as the performance changes.
aphasia where phonology is usually disrupted. There have been The point is that agency does not generate a thought or an ac-
celebrated examples of poetic (musical, etc.) composition dur- tion but is generated by the act itself. Readers familiar with the
ing dream, although some have argued that this occurs chiefly debate between Wundt and James as to the contribution of action
in transitional states. The Kubla Khan of Coleridge is perhaps the to consciousness will recall that it centered on the feeling of inner-
most famous example (Lowes, 1927). Other examples are given in vation from the action discharge, which we now know depends
Koestler (1964). on re-afference or recurrent collaterals and distal feedback. An
individual deprived of sensory feedback without visual guidance
Another personal example illustrates that poetic composition is unable to initiate an action or, if able to act, is unaware of the
can occur in dream rather than in the transitional state. Some action that occurs. I would agree with Wundt that the feeling of in-
years ago when I was working on a book on time and free will, I
116 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 117

nervation is the principle contribution of action to awareness, the Klüver (1933). Hallucinations occur spontaneously with no feeling
rest being perceptual. But I would also agree with James, that this of control. The hallucination externalizes when the constraints of
is insufficient for the feeling of activity in the absence of sensory sense data are insufficient to transform the image to a veridical ob-
feedback. If the individual is to have the feeling of self-initiation ject, as in sensory deprivation experiments. Like a hallucination,
and the ability to distinguish active and passive movement, both an image that is driven by sense data to externalize as an object is
the action discharge and the sensory recurrence are necessary, also accompanied by a feeling of passivity. It ‘‘detaches’’ and is felt
indeed essential, for without discharge there is no re-afference. as independent of the observer. Agency is linked to image type,
Actual movement is not necessary, as shown by the feeling of but also depends on incipient speech without which the feeling of
agency for a phantom limb. Of relevance to this argument is that agency is probably not possible. Critchley (1955) speculated that
‘‘movement’’ of the phantom and its illusory control induce or are the mental life of the patient with motor aphasia consisted largely
associated with metabolic activation of contralateral motor cortex. of passive imagery.
The phantom may also disappear with a stroke in that area.
In sum, the full range of volitional feeling is displayed accord-
In some instances a person is unsure whether an action is or is ing to type of image, from the deliberate quality of thought im-
not voluntary. This experience is common with nocturnal jerks of agery, to the voluntary control of memory and eidetic images, to
the legs. We see it in chorea, when the person completes a spon- spontaneous or involuntary hallucination, which may still be felt
taneous movement of the hand into what seems like a deliberate as subjective, to perceptions that are fully external and seem to
action. This is not necessarily to camouflage an involuntary move- come to an observer from outside. It is from such observations
ment, but because the individual may be unsure if the movement that one can claim that intention does not stand behind a thought
is self-initiated. Uncertainty over the active or passive quality of or action but is bound up with a specific cognition. In experimen-
an action occurs with limb movement on stimulation of motor tal and clinical studies, auditory hallucinations are closely related
cortex, which often is not felt as voluntary. With inner speech the to auditory perceptions. Given the relation between inner speech,
derivation over the frontal speech system and its feedback at suc- hallucination and perception, the relative depth of realization in
cessive phases conveys the feeling of self-initiation. perception and action, or the dominant segment of the actualiza-
tion, determines whether a verbal image is apprehended as volun-
If the mental content of an action and, by implication, the tary, passive (hallucination), or mind-independent (perception).
consciousness of verbal imagery or inner speech, is largely per-
ceptual, one should be able to explore agency in perception as
well as action. In fact, all of the forms of agency and recipience are
seen in different types of visual imagery. A thought or imagination
image feels volitional. One can imagine an elephant standing on 4.9. What is inner speech?
a pin, or a mouse crawling over its back. One feels that the image The basic outline of the components and substrates of inner
can be ‘‘manipulated’’ at will. Arguments over the propositional speech was described a century ago and has not changed mark-
nature of thought imagery inadvertently make the point that lan- edly to the present time. Recent studies using imaging and other
guage or sub-vocal speech is essential to the feeling of agency or techniques have served to reinforce the earlier findings, yet the
self-initiation. nature of inner speech remains as mysterious as ever. How in-
ner speech relates to overt speech or to auditory perception and
Eidetic and memory images are less volitional but do have
hallucination is still unsolved. The problem is important in that,
the feeling of an active search. I can decide to recall a face or an
arguably, inner speech is essential for introspective awareness
event and feel that I deliberately call up the memory image. The
(Kinsbourne, 2000), for awareness of error and for the conscious
transition from the eidetic to the memory image was discussed by
118 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 119

control, regulation, and monitoring of speech and behavior. In a motor to a perceptual bias. The construct that prefigures both
my 1988 book, Life of the Mind, a theory was advanced to explain acts and objects now discharges into the object development. The
these phenomena. To my knowledge, no one has since put for- verbal images that ordinarily precede action and contribute to the
ward another account that is equally integrated and coherent, nor feeling of agency, when action is attenuated, permit a perceptual
one that brings together the diverse observations reviewed in this bias and are experienced as (hallucinatory) objects (see Chapter
and earlier papers and books, or the relation to brain areas that 1). In passing to a perceptual development, inner speech dissoci-
mediate speech perception and production. ates from the self of agency, and actualizes in voices distinct from
the patient. This may proceed to the point that the patient not
We know from research going back over 75 years, and con- only hears but also obeys a (self-generated) command to injure
firmed in cognitivist studies, that imagery and perception share someone or to commit suicide. The fact that the voices are ac-
common mechanisms. The stronger claim is that imagery devel- cusatory owes to the passive feeling of the self in relation to its
ops over the same system as perception. An image is an attenuat- own verbal imagery. The passivity is similar to that in perception
ed perception, or an accentuation of penultimate segments in the or some forms of visual imagery, and complements the agentive
process of perception, while a perception is an exteriorized image feeling of action. The content is incomplete, less fully analyzed,
that is constrained by sensation to model the physical world. As and remains intrapsychic, accompanied by other fragments of
a visual image or hallucination is a phase in visual perception, preliminary cognition, e.g., the dream-like sense of (paranoid)
verbal imagery is a phase in speech perception. Verbal imagery victimization by hallucinatory voices.
(inner speech) can focus on memory, meaning, or phonology; it
can be vague or explicit, metaphoric or rational according to the In chronic cases the incompletely specified perception is ac-
degree of specification in the process of object formation. The dif- companied by a propagation of delusions that can become en-
ference between a verbal image and a speech perception is that capsulated and systematized in symbolic or metaphoric modes
auditory sensation sculpts and so shapes the endogenous image of thought. The feeling of passivity to images or ideas may lead
to a model of an auditory object. Perception is the extreme of the the person to perceive his inner voice as another person, a god, a
passive attitude to one’s own memorial experience as it is ana- devil, who instructs him to carry out actions that he cannot refuse.
lyzed and externalized by the shaping effect of sense data. It is, after all, his own voice he hears, even if it does not sound like
his voice. For this reason, among others, it may be more difficult
Specifically, inner speech develops as a perceptual series linked to resist the command than if the voice arose in, or was referred
to phases in the action development. The core of a combined act to, a ‘‘real’’ person. It is easier to say no to the other than to one’s
and object, of speech and speech perception, can individuate with self. In hypnotic trance, the instructions of another person may
an emphasis on either direction. An utterance has a perceptual take on the status of obligations. Since it is perceived in a trance
development leading to Wernicke’s area that elaborates the per- state as an incomplete auditory object, the voice of the hypno-
ceptual content or mental experience of the utterance, and a par- tist is heard as an inner voice that does not fully externalize. The
allel action development leading to the Broca area that elaborates perception remains an inner voice but since it is regulated by
intentional feeling, motility, and speech. The phase transitions in sensation (the hypnotist’s voice) it is not apprehended as a hal-
anterior and posterior regions are maintained in synch by cortico- lucination that arises endogenously. Command hallucinations
cortical pathways that keep the ‘‘bottom-up’’ derivation of phases and hypnotic suggestions display the confusions that can occur
coupled within and across the hemispheres. between auditory perception and inner speech. Many of us have
no doubt had the experience, on falling asleep, that a volitional
We see this with clarity in pathological states when the active
monologue of inner speech becomes passive, perceptual, and/or
self becomes passive and responsive to the inner voice of obliga-
hallucinatory. The fluid transition from image to object, and back
tion. In schizophrenia and other states, inner speech shifts from
120 Jason W. Brown

again, corresponds to a fluctuation of the feeling of agency and


external reference. Such phenomena also show the basis of com-
mand hallucinations in the bias of inner speech to a perceptual
development or the usurpation of inner speech in the recurrence
of a hypnotically induced auditory command.
Chapter 5
Genetic Psychology and Process
Philosophy

“Historically speaking, materialism and mechanistic metaphysics


— as distinct from mechanistic science — designate the doctrine
that matter is the efficient cause of life and mind, and that
‘cause’ occupies a position superior in reality to that of ‘effect’.
Both parts of this statement are contrary to fact. As far as the
conception of causation is to be introduced at all, not matter but
the natural events having matter as a character, ‘cause’ life and
mind. ‘Effects’, since they mark the release of potentialities,
are more adequate indications of the nature of nature than are
just ‘causes’.”
Dewey (p. 262, 1925)

5.1. Introduction
Microgenesis, like ontogeny and evolution, is a theory on the
origins of present events, not a predictive theory as to future
outcomes. The origins of events — whether over evolutionary,
maturational or psychological time — are inferred from present
occurrences. In this respect, they deviate from the scientific para-
digm in which effects are postulated from causes. This does not
necessarily make genetic theory non-causal or non-scientific. The
prediction of effect from cause is not logically so different from
the retrodiction of cause from effect though there are important
psychological differences. In the first instance, the future effect
does not yet, and may never, exist; in the latter, the putative cause
is past; it has occurred but no longer exists. Predictive theories
branch outward from causes to multiple possible effects, whereas
retrodictive causes converge to the present effect.
124 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 125

Predictive theories tend to be tightly controlled and limited to im- With this distinction in mind, which is the primary difference
mediate data, as in a scientific experiment. One can forecast a fu- between genetic and scientific theory, this chapter takes up the
ture vacation, or predict that a strong hurricane will cause flooding relation of process philosophy to genetic psychologies, including
on the coast, but the temporal window must be relatively narrow microgenesis, as exemplified in the writings of Werner, Smith and
for one to predict with accuracy. The greater the duration between Piaget, and the mutual enrichment that might follow on a closer
cause and effect, the weaker the cause and/or the more contingent union of the philosophical and psychological accounts. First, I will
the effect. In contrast, retrodictive theories look to a more distant consider some further aspects of the relation of causality and po-
past in which an attempt is made to isolate a specific event or a tential that impact both fields of inquiry with the hope that deeper
more complex pre-history. The effect in question, i.e. the present study will lead to a more precise formulation of basic principles
state, is the outcome of a convergence of prior causes — accidents, that can ground a theory of becoming in psyche and nature, one
contingencies — distributed over a greater duration. There is also that if not scientific in the usual sense, is concordant with the data
the question of how and why a particular state developed out of of experience. However, if process philosophy is to truly be an
past states, especially with a lengthy series of intervening events. “adventure of ideas”, it must invite the novelty that was the creed
For these reasons, because complexity devolves to specificity, or of its founder even if this entails a revision of principles that have
proclivity becomes actuality, the past of a retrospective theory is become almost axiomatic. It should also, where it can, seek em-
often conceived less as a cause than as a potential that gives one pirical grounds without succumbing to the simplistic agenda of
of a multiplicity of possible actualities. mechanical psychology. On the other hand, genetic psychology is
a diverse field with little cross-talk among its members. The field
is in some disarray and lacks an essential, i.e. unitary, philosophi-
cal framework.
The shift to a theory in which a specific cause has many possible
antecedents to one in which a specific cause has many possible
consequents is the shift from a hermeneutic of coherence to a sci-
ence of correspondence. The transition from potential and actual Subjectivist claims in philosophy can begin with either physical
to cause and effect collapses the past into the present as possibil- or psychological universals. Whitehead approached psychology
ity becomes fact. The specification of potential to a given actuality from the world of physics. Microgenesis began with psychology
replaces the branching of a given cause to some future possibil- and reached a limit in fractal mathematics. A subjectivity of the
ity. Put differently, the shift from unknown possibility to known inorganic that is continuous with human mind is a theory of mind
fact in retrodictive theories is the opposite of predictive ones that continuous with physical nature. A coherent philosophy that be-
go from known fact to unknown but hypothesized possibility. In gins with nature or human mind builds on theory of cognition or
contrast to ordinary causation, where a cause causes an effect, nature, whether mechanical or subjective. A “mechanical” nature
in retrospective theories the rumination on duration instead of leaves quantum features unexplained, not to mention psychic
immediate consequence conceives an effect not as the result of states, while subjectivism grapples with the theory of substance
a cause but its replacement over a series of intervening states. and causation. The path that leads from nature to mind can im-
We see this strikingly in ontogeny, where an organism changes port causal objects to the mind, or export duration and potential
each moment imperceptibly, causing itself to become the next to nature. The appeal to process thinking of a genetic psychol-
moment in its existence. The same phenomenon appears in the ogy rooted in subjectivity is that patterns in the actualization or
replacement of mental states. The causal factor in genetic theories becoming of the mental state can be mapped to features in the
is that of causal persistence, i.e. replacement, which is not a linear concrescence of physical entities that would otherwise be opaque
sequence of cause-effect pairs. to causal science.
126 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 127

Causation is accepted for the most part unquestioningly as the ated from prior states and discontinuous with a causal continua-
basis of all scientific work. The causal relation inheres in the ob- tion in nature. Rescher (2006) writes that “acts of will are mental
jects of the science, as well as in their relation to the observer. eventuations that mark the completion of a process of which they
For process theory, causation is a fundamental difficulty that do not constitute a part…”, though the force of the distinction is
must be confronted, no less for philosophical speculation than mitigated in that it is labeled as conceptual, not ontological. The ap-
for genetic psychology. The growth of the child cannot be easily proach uses object causation as a model for agent causation, even
formulated in a causal discourse; mechanisms come into play at in distinguishing the latter as leading to a stoppage independent
successive stages or are occluded or vanish as new ones appear. of its predecessors and not part of an ensuing series. However, a
In the growth process, the child gradually becomes an adult by different picture emerges if instead of taking object-causation as a
continuously replacing itself with a novel version of what it was model of the mind one begins with a theory of agency as founda-
a moment earlier. The causality most appropriate to the genetic tional. On this view, physical events are like mental states in that
model is that of “causal persistence”, defined as replication with they have a subjective (intrinsic) aim to completion, with the final
minimal novelty between replicates. effectuation conceived as internal to the process through which
it unfolds. The “eventuation” is not, as Rescher would have it, the
end-product of a production line. An act that is the outcome of a
period of deliberation is one in a series of mind/brain states that
Whitehead’s understanding of causality is relevant here. In a hu-
a self or observer takes to be a termination. Since events have no
man psyche, each momentary occasion prehends or absorbs pre-
clear boundaries and states overlap, the point of termination is
ceding occasions. What a person becomes moment by moment is
arbitrary.
largely conformal to the personal past. However, the new occasion
also prehends other events in the ever changing environment
and integrates these prehensions with those of the personal past.
Much remains the same, but there is always change as well. One can say the froth of a fountain cannot exist, or can only exist
artificially, without the surge of which it is part. The ending is part
of the story, the last word part of a sentence, and that part of a
thought. Closing the cover is an act of cognition just as reading the
last word. Every act or object — and every physical entity — is part
5.2. Causation of the whole of its development. This is not so clear when events
The two basic ways that causation is understood are object and are stretched out over time such as positing that deliberation is
agent causation. The doctrine of cause and effect between objects separate from the decision it leads to. But each outcome has a
that is fundamental to much of science, e.g. billiard-ball causation, genetic undersurface, states develop and are replaced. An end-
has given the philosophy of mechanism. The causal interaction point does not differ from a prior state, since every entity is an
of solids in the world is imported to the mind in the interaction epoch replaced by another epoch, including inaction and silence.
of brain areas or mental components. This notion of causality is What is fractured is a logical, not ontological sequence. Physical
deeply rooted and felt to be intuitively true but it has proved dif- events or mental eventuations are surface appearances of micro-
ficult to pin down. temporal process, phase-transitions of internal relations of which
outcomes are superficial marks.
One strategy for resolving the difference between object and agent
causation entails a distinction of acts of will as “eventuations” or Consistent with this view, the psychic precursor of (the feeling
conclusions of thought that are preceded by deliberation, dissoci- of) object causation is an ingrained sense of agent causation that
precedes the feeling of transition in object causation. The agent-
128 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 129

causation that embraces the micro-temporal structure of the in the distinction of cause and effect, a strategy that cannot regain
mind/brain state should be the basis of a theory of object causa- the complexity lost when the elements were dismembered. In
tion, not the reverse. The infant’s control of its limbs and action revealing the fundamental properties of the stage out of which it
on objects gives the feeling of causal power. The infant seizes a evolved, the complex better informs a theory of the simple than
moving object or one that is displaced. To follow a trajectory is the reverse.
to anticipate. The primitive motion is to the future. The sense of
causal power in the infant who reaches for a rubber ball is perhaps
no more than the behavior of a cat that reaches for a rolling ball
Further individuation of self and object leads to greater au-
of wool, but with the individuation of the self, consciousness of
tonomy and a feeling of a self opposed to inner and outer con-
this power develops to awareness of agency, or self-initiation, with
tents. The direction of this relation promotes intentional feeling.
its roots in organic process. The necessity in causation (Hume)
Purposefulness achieves its aim when it terminates. The aim, not
that arises in infancy recurs as a psychic residue that informs and
given beforehand, incorporates the potential it actualizes. As feel-
empowers agency in mature cognition. The grasp and control of
ing takes on direction, what is implicit in drive becomes explicit
an object that is the seed of agency is less a projection of human
in desire. In human thought, the derivation of affects and ideas
thought onto nature than a delimitation of unconscious potential
out of conceptual-feeling gives intention its direction. The im-
into conscious actuality, just as indeterminateness in physical na-
mediate action of simple purposefulness transforms to conscious
ture resolves into material fact. The momentary genesis of an act
intention when an idea individuates in the self, and the external
of cognition — or genetic process in general — is a model for the
world abides in the background. The interposition of conscious
actualization of a physical entity. Mental state and physical entity
ideas, verbal images and feelings when the outgoing stream is ab-
develop over and actualize a temporal extensibility or minimal
breviated is obligatory for a conscious self. Unthinking action on
duration of existence.
objects involves a subject-object relation, not a self. Intention is
awareness of goal or the “aboutness” of this direction, an attempt
to mark off a closure that was satisfied in the immediacy of direct
The importation of simple causation to the mind is a classical in- action. In sum, agency in organism is the basis of object-causa-
stance of explaining complexity as a compounding of the simple. tion. Intentionality in organism is the basis of a theory of (con-
This is, for example, the strategy of those who argue that mind is a scious, but incipient) agent-causation. In all these matters, natural
collection of reflex operations, basically cause-effect pairs. But one process insinuates itself into human thought.
does not easily go from the simple to the complex. The simple is
never as simple as it seems, and the assumed simplicity obscures
the process through which complexity develops. A reconstruction
As the self individuates, it perceives a world of particulars distribut-
of the complex after it has been reduced to its elements — or from
ed in space and time, and interprets the particulars as a succession
elements postulated to be constituent — is usually not possible. A
of causes and effects when, in fact, temporal order individuates
pile of bricks is no more or less complex than one brick, though
in consciousness from unconscious simultaneity (chapter 2). The
an artwork of a pile of bricks, or a wall, is a conceptual pattern
distinction of cause and effect in object-causation complements
distinct from an arbitrary assortment. The artwork or wall is a
the distinction of self and world in agent-causation. Each mode
unitary whole in which separate elements are bound together
of thought reflects a different metaphysic, one of mechanism, the
contextually by the intrinsic relations of the mental state. The as-
other, of organism. In the latter, objects are categories of “events-
sumption of elements in the psyche bound by external relations
with-meanings”, in the former, demarcations to which meanings
in the mind as in the world generates and severs those elements
130 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 131

are added. It is an error to dismiss the latter as pre-scientific, for it effect and moves backward to the cause, since the effect is evident
displays psychic qualities not evident to scientific thought. and can be identified. Another way of saying this is that an actual
object, an actuality, entails a cause, and that even if the cause is
multi-factorial (XYZ in the above example), its components are as
discrete as the effect, so that the transition from cause to effect is
Consider Piaget’s demonstration to Einstein that relativity theory
like that from one actual object to another.
is closer to the common space-time of young children rather than
the separate space and time of the adult. Similarly, the felt curva-
ture of dream-space that differs from the open expanse and exten-
sion of waking perception foreshadows theory in modern physics.
The irrational, even mystical, has a significance in its proximity to 5.3. The Actualization of Potential
organism. The need for an awareness of the unconscious struc-
When potential is thought of as the “cause” of the actual, no such
ture of mature theory was expressed by Dewey (1925, p. 317): “as
precision of antecedent cause is forthcoming. This way of think-
long as our own fundamental psycho-physical attitudes in dealing
ing entails that definite effects are not the outcomes of discrim-
with external things are subconscious, or attention going only to
inable causes. Definiteness is in the effect, not the cause. In the
the relations of external things, so long will our perception of the
transition from potential to actual, the presumed specificity of a
external situations be subject at its root to perversion and vitia-
present object is exchanged for the uncertainty of the potential in
tion.”
past ones. The efficacy of potential coincides with the priority of
whole to part, or on a larger scale, in the relation of community to
individual or of nature to individual organism.
Nevertheless, there are acute difficulties with both object and
agent causation; in the former, the demarcation of cause, the doc-
trine of external relations, the transition to effect or the role of
However, the doctrine of potential has its own difficulties, chiefly
contingency and accidental causation. These problems resist solu-
that potential is unspecifiable. In the mental life, potential corre-
tion because they are analyzed by the very methods of the theory
sponds (after Dewey) to the fringe of feeling-qualities, premoni-
they subtend. A theory that cannot explain its core assumptions is
tions and inchoate meanings — the stuff of intuitions — that guide
vacuous, not merely incomplete. Persistent incoherence is close
the selection of acts. Those processes in the natural world that
to unacknowledged refutation. Similar problems bedevil agent-
are the antecedents of these unconscious phenomena are no less
causation but here contingency embraces freedom, and the rela-
inscrutable. For Whitehead the “cause” as the real potential for
tion of cause and effect is still more obscure.
the new actual occasion is the entire “actual world.” But cause in
this sense does not determine what the effect will be, since the
effect is also causa sui.
Object causation and agent causation give priority to the cause,
whether going from cause to effect, or inferring effect from cause.
In the conventional account, specific causes bring about specific
Genetic psychology is a subjective record of individual self-realiza-
effects. In medical science a certain disease is caused by virus X,
tion generalized to and across others. For genetic psychology, the
or by X in combination with gene Y, or by X and Y with a pre-exist-
past is revived in the present, which is felt as the outward crust of
ing constitution Z. The specificity of the cause is taken as equiva-
an inward history. The future is not what the present moves into,
lent to the specificity of the effect, especially if one begins with the
it is another present that the past deposits. There is a natural in-
132 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 133

clusion of the past, which makes up the major portion of the pres- of the inclusive potentiality, which includes pure potentials not
ent, a past that is as important for the present as what the present derived from its actual world.
holds for the future. An orientation to the past gives an inward
focus on genuine change as reflection and retrospection take pre-
cedence over anticipation and prediction. Each approach involves
A past entity can be considered a causal point. Microgenesis is
an implicit theory of (subjective) time. The excavation of the an-
a theory of becoming in which the final phase is not pre-pack-
tecedents of known effects, or the consequents of known causes,
aged or forecast at its onset. Actualities do not provide surface
takes the present as an actual datum in relation to an anterior or
templates for ensuing actualizations but are cleared away (perish)
posterior extension. There is an infinite regress in the uncovering
for novel objects, while the entire process traversed in the actual-
of earlier causes that are more like possibilities or probabilities
ization, but especially the initial segments, provides the ground
than discrete occurrences. The retrospective approach is linked to
for the next traversal. I look to one side and see a house, then
the transition from potential to actual, the prospective approach to
the other side and see a tree. The actual object has changed. The
a transition from cause to effect.
perception must be erased so a novel one can ensue. What recurs
is the conceptual and experiential ground common to the series
of actualities. This ground is part of the potential of the state as of
The introductory citation implies that effects are the concrete the actuality. Since the scope of potential is wider than that of the
facts we actually know while causes are their anticipations or the actual, the actual object as an endpoint, i.e. the world as perceived,
potentials behind them inferred or vaguely sensed. The actual is delimits possibility and cannot form a comprehensive ground for
describable, but its antecedents are uncertain unless viewed as the ensuing potential.
collections of outcomes. If an actuality were the cause of a subse-
quent actuality as in linear or chain theory, it would be ingredient
in the potential for the next round of actualization.
A consideration of the causal role of constraints on the actualiza-
tion or concrescence of the mental state suggests the need for a
different way to think about potential and actual in relation to
In some forms of process thought, such as for Whitehead, an ac- cause and effect, namely, that the former are phases in a single
tual object, on perishing, becomes part of the real potentiality for existent, as opposed to elements in causal succession, in which
the next round of actualization. The world at state B actualizes cause and effect are distinct existents. Potential does not exist until
out of the world at state A. This view entails that the actual occa- it becomes actual, and it is then not causal but ingredient. The
sion in one moment — with all other actualities at that moment transition from potential to actual can be construed as causal if
— constitutes a potential for the ensuing occasion. On this inter- it is divisible into intervening phases, but this would not apply if
pretation, potential consists of perishing actualities and the actual potential and actual are part of a single entity. Potential perishes
has causal efficacy. A potential comprised of perished actualities in actuality, not successively at each phase in a path to the actual.
gives new actualities that integrate elements of real potentiality in At each phase, potential is part of the actuality it leads to, i.e., part
diverse ways. If the potential for a new occasion were exhausted of the epoch of actualization, or successive phases in a single mo-
by the real potential provided by past occasions, the novelty in mentary existence.
new actualities would be limited to the reordering of elements in
the past. Whitehead did not think this accounted for novelty in the
world. In his view, every entity actualizes by its own “decision” out
134 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 135

5.4. Genetic psychology dynamic that precipitates the event. This internal, forward-going
dynamic is an essential feature of “genetic” thought.
With the foregoing by way of prologue, we can proceed to a con-
sideration of genetic psychology in relation to process theory. In
both, process is prior to substance, becoming to being, change
to stability. An ontology of becoming emphasizes the sub-surface The transitive in process philosophy is iterated in epochs (Wallack,
change through which substance (being) actualizes rather than 1980). The novelty in recurrence corresponds in genetic psychol-
substances that change. As flux and non-repeatability were es- ogy with the creative in mind and organism. At a macro-level,
sential to the metaphysics of Heraclitus, duration and continuity the evolution of species by proliferation, competition for survival
were fundamental to that of Bergson (1923; also, see Capek, 1976), and elimination is a model for growth in fetal brain develop-
while concrescence, prehension and subjective aim were, inter ment, where exuberance is competitively trimmed to specificity.
alia, essential to Whitehead’s system of thought. In a process ap- The population dynamic of evolutionary change is internalized
proach, objects are states of flux that only appear to be solids. The as the parcellation (see: Brown, 2003) or “neuronal Darwinism”
flux is not random or chaotic but has a direction. The direction of (Edelman, 1987) of morphogenesis and specialization or individu-
the flux is its becoming or the genetic history of the object, which ation. These patterns or force-lines of development become the
is the concealed dynamic through which the object is generated. context-item transformations that actualize a cognitive world.
Adaptation in phylo-ontogeny is the basis of microgenesis in cog-
nition. An act, a thought, arises out of a multitude of possibilities
that are progressively limited (sculpted) by internal and external
As momentary centers of flux, objects are unstable. As soon as constraints, e.g. by the antecedent microgeny over which the
an object exists, it is past. A this, an is, becomes a was, a that. occurrent state develops, and by the selective pressures on that
Transition leaves objects in its wake but is not itself grasped like an developing state of sense-data arriving from the environment.
object, for the act of grasping cancels the transition. The direction Constraints limit the developing object to the fittest object for that
of the transition gives the feeling of momentum. Unconscious moment in the perceptual field, as analogous constraints in evolu-
becoming in a forward motion actualizes the felt present, but the tion result in organisms adapted to their surrounds.
dynamic feels like a striving into the future. The feeling of striv-
ing, which is a manifestation of the loss of present objects as the
next set is created, is what remains of creation after perishing
takes its toll. Objects come and go but the process of creation The similar patterns of morpho- and microgenetic process are
recurs. Dewey alludes to the incessant striving, though he does clear. In a mature cognition, the endogenous constraints of the
not provide details of its infrastructure. He writes, “unless there just-prior act are comparable to genetic influences on growth,
were something problematic, undecided, still going-on and as yet while the exogenous constraints of the external world (sense-data)
unfinished and indeterminate, in nature, there could be no such are comparable to the effects of the micro-environment on gene
events as perceptions”. An event, he argues, implies “a system expression. A perception survives a brief evolution in a journey to
of meanings focused at a point of stress, uncertainty and need actuality. The connectivity of an embryonic cell survives a compe-
of regulation. It sums up history, and at the same time opens a tition for binding sites with other neurons. The organism survives
new page; it is record and promise in one; a fulfillment and an an environment bent on its destruction. All acts are adaptive,
opportunity.” Objects are events that crystallize perceptual mean- even maladaptive ones. Thus, while dreams do not conform to
ings. An event has its own dynamic, which Dewey thinks is the the world, they are adaptive in sleep to the exigencies of the psy-
openness and creativity of passage, but there is also the intrinsic chic life. In psychotics, waking dreams, i.e. hallucinations, serve
subjective needs as in sleep, but resist the extrinsic constraints of
136 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 137

the surrounding world. They are adaptive to the psyche but not 5.5. Studies in psychology
the world.
Genetic psychology is the study of micro- or macro- trends in the
development of the mind. The genetic approach provides a back-
ground for microgenetic theory. I will briefly consider the work of
In all genetic process, at the level of the cell, the organism, a popu- three schools of psychology that have made important contribu-
lation, or the derivation of an act of thought, there is a uniform tions in different populations and with different methodologies.
process of arising and perishing, creation and destruction, actual- The best known of these schools is that of Piaget (e.g. 1969), who
ization and recurrence. This process, beginning with an epoch of has described the growth of knowledge in a transition of develop-
‘energic feeling’ in an elementary particle (Brown, 2003), and re- mental stages, each an obligatory transit in the growth of mind.
garded over different time scales, gives the evolution of organism For example, around the age of 7-11, there is a shift from the ego-
and societies, the life-history of the individual and the deposition centric to the concrete-operational view of the relation of the self
of the mind/brain state. to the world. The child is able to incorporate the perspective of
the other into his own point of view. There is also a shift from a
syncretic and intuitive phase to one of deduction and reasoning.
To speak of the “mechanisms” guiding this process tends to en- Judgments of value have more influence on the earlier egocentric
dorse a mechanical view of nature. The putative mechanisms are phase than on the later one of communicable thought (Piaget,
the regularities extracted from recurrent patterns of change. The 1955). Such stages in the growth of mind or intelligence form the
genetic code is not a detailed blueprint for the construction of an bases for the investigation of the maturation of specific functional
organism but governs the unfolding of organic form. The num- domains, such as perception, language, logic etc. When a novel
ber of genes is insufficient for a one-to-one correspondence that response appears, its underlying operations are studied. When
could determine an exact phenotypic feature, much less a spe- the response diminishes in importance with age, antagonistic fac-
cific cell and its connections. Polygenes and timing mechanisms tors are assumed to intervene. A response that is invariant across
limit the degrees of freedom in the growth process, increasing the age is said to reflect innate factors, though the sequence of stages
likelihood of a given outcome. Growth is guided by regularities must itself be governed by innate forces, even if there is consider-
that keep the process on track. An explanatory reduction to gene able variation according to learning and experience.
or gene combinations tends to avoid an account of the transition
from a base sequence of amino acids to a final morphology or be-
havior. The same conjuring trick is used to collapse the symptoms Piaget conceived intelligence as a continuation of perception, or
of brain damage to lesion sites, or to reduce a normal behavior, obeying the same laws as perception. While Piaget accepted the
e.g. a syntactic rule, face recognition, etc., to local or distributed genetic notion of a progression from whole to part and the prior-
brain areas. The reduction of an outward form to a gene or brain ity of process over substance, he did not resolve process theory
area gives a weak correlation in the vain expectation that to-be- with substantive modes of thought. Nor was there a coherent ac-
discovered inter-level causal mechanisms will account for what is count of objects and relations. He wrote, “elements are not given
lost in the reduction. from the beginning because they do not exist independently of
the relations which unite them… (and that the relational method
is a) striving towards the construction or composition of a whole,
not starting with elements but with the relations between them,
which is not the same thing.” The more profound problems of
internal and external relations, or of wholes and parts, did not
138 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 139

achieve an adequate analysis. Piaget distinguished causal expla- are used to reconstruct the neural and psychological process of
nation in physiological science from psychological explanation, percept formation.
which deals with “systems of significations” or of significant ac-
tions which are inter-related by ‘implications” in the broad sense
of the term
A third approach to genetic psychology places emphasis on the
relation of developmental stage in maturation and perceptgenesis
to its attenuation in mental retardation, in pathology and primi-
There have been attempts to relate Piagetian stages to the pat- tive thought. Heinz Werner (e.g. 1945; 1957) is most closely as-
tern of myelinogenesis (e.g. Lecours, 1975), but the correlations sociated with this school. As with other genetic thinkers, Werner
are imprecise. The brain matures as a whole, and specific func- asserted the primacy of process over substance. He argued that
tions cannot be related to the development of anatomical systems development proceeds in an orderly manner from a state of glo-
with great accuracy. The relation to pathological breakdown bality and lack of specification to one of increasing differentiation,
(e.g. Ajuriaguerra et al, 1963) supposes that functional stages are articulation and hierarchical integration or “genetic” stratification.
stacked in the acquisitional sequence and unpeel in the reverse Werner disclaimed an association with evolutionary psychology,
order in pathology. In cases with posterior brain damage, I tried for the latter deals with the history of mankind and what is early
many years ago, without success, to demonstrate a destructura- and late in the historical scale, while the former deals with the pat-
tion according to Piagetian stage-theory. Such an effect, were it to tern from low to high mentality. He listed several features charac-
be confirmed, as postulated by Heinz Werner, Hughlings Jackson, teristic of developmental psychology, specifically, the progression
Roman Jakobson and many others, is referred to as the regres- from the syncretic to the discrete, the diffuse to the articulated,
sion hypothesis. This concept was for many years a mainstay in the indefinite to the definite, the rigid to the flexible and the labile
the study of development, but it has been called into question to the stable.
(Caramazza and Zurif, 1978), at least in its simple form (Brown,
1996).
Werner’s importance has receded with the cognitive shift in psy-
chology, but there has also been a caricature of his thesis that
In contrast to Piagetian accounts, which deal with the whole comes of taking too literally the comparison across different
child and its relation to the world, perceptgenetic research (e.g. populations. The savage, the child, the psychotic and the brain-
Smith, 2001) has focused on the fine microtemporal processing damaged are not equivalent in terms of the thought content. One
of a perceptual object. Smith and his colleagues have employed a cannot compare a child with an imaginary playmate, the native
host of innovative methods, many involving rapid tachistoscopic with his crocodile gods, the schizophrenic with his visions to
exposure, to explore otherwise concealed stages in the perceptual performance errors in the brain-damaged. The similarity is not
process. These techniques are thought to expose early stages of in preliminary contents as endpoints, or those that surface, or
affect and meaning that are ordinarily buried in the final object. remain submerged or transformed in normative cognition, nor
The implication is that phases of meaning, emotion and memory do such phenomena re-appear in pathological breakdown. What
are enjoined early in the object formation, with the final object these diverse populations do have in common, in some if not all
being the outcome of a rapid traversal over layers in cognition respects, is a pattern or mode of thought, one that is pre-rational,
which, in some way, correspond with the maturational history of paralogical, or syncretic. The prominence of metaphoric, magical
the individual. The perceptgenetic approach has close affinities or animistic thinking points to a phase traversed in every ratio-
with microgenesis, in which the symptoms of focal brain lesion nal thought. The commonalties in patterns of mental process are
140 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 141

guides to regularities in the process of self-realization. They help relation to stages in memory, but not the content of what is said
us to understand the fundamental “laws” of thought, irrespective or remembered.
of the contents which the process deposits.

The one exception is psychoanalysis, which takes the actual (or


In sum, these varied approaches — over different time scales — latent) content of an act of cognition and attempts to explain its
share the concept of an action or perception as a derivation over origins in unconscious process. However, the theory is not fully
levels or stages in cognition. The derivation is the intra-psychic process-based, since explanation is in terms of the interaction or
phase of the object-formation, the object being the endpoint of a conflict of logical or mental solids, with the dynamic of feeling (ca-
formative (micro- or macro-developmental) process. The progres- thexis) injected as the glue of the varied elements. Psychoanalysis
sion is uni-directional, like growth, and obligatory. It leads from is also problematic in that its constructs have not been successfully
antecedent phases in conceptual, affective and memorial experi- related to those of other fields of psychology, much less process
ence to the presentational immediacy of acts and objects in the thought. Some writers have tried to extract from psychoanalysis
world. It goes from the wholeness and potential that originate the a theory of perception or memory (e.g. Schilder, 1950; Rapaport;
process to the multiplicity of world objects and conscious images in Gill, 1967) but these innovations have succumbed to orthodox
in which it eventuates, i.e. from self to world, and from ego- to ob- interpretations.
ject-centeredness. The momentary “growth” of a perception from
an intra- to extra-psychic locus is a microcosm of the maturation
of the mind in that it resembles process across other domains of
A psychology that begins with mental content takes for its starting
cognition. The microgenetic contribution to genetic psychology
point an object that has completed its development. The object
is a more precise formulation of the phase-transitions underlying
is assumed to be the product of part-functions inferred from the
this process, and their correlates in evolutionary brain structure.
object itself. Additional elements, i.e. rules, operations, functional
Microgenesis distills the different time scales into repeatable ep-
mechanisms, are postulated to explain for the content. These
ochs in the relation of patterns of forebrain evolution to patterns
eventually reduce to the atomic elements from which the part-
in object-generation.
functions, and from them the final contents, are assembled. The
entire process is content-like, with process inserted to string the
contents together like beads on a chain. The linguistic and analytic
Microgenetic theory has demonstrated that too great a focus on schools of philosophy have generated, in cognitive psychology, a
the content of a performance is detrimental to the understanding veritable industry to support this teaching. In contrast, process
of the process through which the content is deposited. The con- philosophy has not sought connections to genetic or process ap-
tent of an action, an utterance or a perception is “thing-like” and proaches in psychology, veering to metaphysics instead of empiri-
of a different order than the process through which it develops. cal science. The conceptual overlap of process philosophy and ge-
Genetic psychology gives a description of cognitive development netic psychology is such that a dialogue between the fields should
over the long or short term in terms of epochs that recur, but it be mutually enriching. Genetic psychology provides a direction
only provides a limited explanation of the contents that develop and brake on philosophical speculation, which in turn provides
out of this process. This is its strength and its weakness. For ex- novel or renewed insights for psychological study.
ample, the psychology can account for the process of form or
meaning-development in a perceptual or linguistic object, or the
Chapter 6
Foundations of the Self

“And up and down did rolling swing


The all and one eternal Thing”
Goethe, Satyrs

6.1. Self and Consciousness


In this chapter and others, awareness is defined as the relation of
a subject to external objects and bodily states. A subject is the sub-
jective whole of the organism, excluding its external portion. An
object is the external portion of that whole, perceived as outside
the organism. An object is a perceived event. An entity is a physi-
cal event postulated to exist outside perception. The external or
objective world is defined as a segment of the subjective that has
objectified. In contrast, the physical world is the world of physical
entities.

A subject is antecedent to the object. The relation is the uni-


directional process of becoming through which subject and then
object actualize. Awareness is the waking state of small children,
not unknown to animals and the foundation of consciousness.
One can have awareness without consciousness, since the former,
from an evolutionary, maturational and microgenetic standpoint,
is the earlier state. But, one cannot have consciousness without
an implicit state of awareness, since consciousness arises on this
foundation.

Conscious perception differs from object-awareness. In the


latter, the subject-as-a-whole is aware of external objects. In the
former, a self is conscious of objects. The self is a segment in the
stream of outgoing subjectivity aware of its own priority and sub-


The original meaning was self-Csness; e.g. Locke wrote, “consciousness is the
perception of what passes in a man’s own mind” (Essay II, I, 19).
144 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 145

jectivity. Consciousness is the relation of a self to inner and outer ized I had arrived at a point with no memory of the interval. Is this
objects.10 The relation arises in the process through which images like a hypnotic state? Is it an instance of a dissociation of self and
and objects objectify. The relation of the self to inner objects is subject, of consciousness and awareness?
introspection or reflection. The relation of the self to outer objects
is exteroception or perception. We ‘think up’ the world we perceive. This thought-up world is
a model of an inferred physical world that impacts on the brain.
A perception by a subject differs from a perception by a self, The accuracy of our model of the world can be tested but it is still
even if the ‘same’ object is perceived. Objects carve out the bound- a model. Walking, touching, tasting are kinds of tests. The model
ary of a subject. There are no inner objects, only different states of reality depends on the type of organism and the adequacy of
of subjectivity, e.g. anger, hunger, etc. The subject is what is left sensory data. The world may be thought-up, but without the con-
after its world is subtracted. In contrast, the self is buffered from straints of sensation, thought alone cannot sustain the world. The
the world by a subjective field. The self withdraws into this field rationality of thought depends on its proximity to the world, i.e.
in reflection, or remembrance. This field can be a private hell or to the accuracy of the model. The approximation to an objective
it can offer respite and sanctuary. Because the self is in relation to world determines the content of the state, e.g. daydream, reverie,
its own subjectivity, it does not have the immediacy of action that fantasy, hallucination, delusion, etc., phenomena that actualize
occurs in a subject. The self, along with images, thoughts, feel- at different points in the object-formation. Without an objective
ings, etc. is most emphatic when a delay in behavior dilates the world, thinking is dreaming; psychosis is an intermediate phase.
automaticity of direct awareness.

An image or idea is a segment en route to a perception or an


utterance. In a rapid traversal, action and perception dominate
consciousness. If I am not thinking of anything in particular, I am 6.2. The Intuition of the Self
still conscious of the world as the circumference of my point of We all have a sense of our self as the center of gravity of char-
view. When a thought or image comes into prominence as the acter with a feeling of its continuity and repeatability over time.
dominant focus of attention, external space recedes to an ambi- We do not feel the existence of a self is problematic, nor that it is
ent field that grounds the inner figural content.11 an illusion or mix of momentary impressions. The self cannot be
isolated on introspection yet it grows and endures as a relatively
For example, in writing this chapter, I am dimly aware of the
stable entity over all the changing acts, thoughts and desires of a
grassy knoll and trees around me as an endpoint of the men-
life. While we have many modes of self-expression according to
tal state. Even ‘lost in thought’, my world is implicitly there.
the occasion, each momentary self is felt to be a manifestation of
Otherwise, my thought would be the terminus of the state and
the one genuine self. The inability to identify or define the self as
the world would disappear. At times lost in thought, I have walked,
it fluctuates with the situation does not persuade us of an absence
even driven, some distance as if in a trance, when I suddenly real-
or lack of personal identity. Experience is “taken in” and respond-
ed to by a self that stands behind as observer or agent. A feeling
10
See note 9 supra of identity, individuality or personhood, binds successive states of
consciousness together or, as I would prefer to say, the feeling of
11
Consistent with Cobb (1973), who wrote, “conscious attention shades off by
degrees into unconscious inattention, the latter constituting by far the larger self-identity is the ground for the succession, providing unity to
part of the experience of the dominant occasion… (and that) backgrounds that perceptions in the observer’s field. According to the modality, the
are vaguely discriminated consciously have as their backgrounds others that self feels “situated” at the center of its experience, as in pain, or at
are completely unconscious but which are also capable of so developing as to the circumference, as in vision. The visual world is not a jumble of
become conscious.”
146 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 147

objects but a coherent picture. This is less so in dream, but then, or objects in the field. Feeling flows out of the self to concentrate
the dream-self differs from that of wakefulness. The self is host in the object, replacing other lines of development. When feel-
and source of the varied thoughts and acts of a life, and except for ing overwhelms the partition of the core to the empirical self, the
illness, in which it is threatened with loss, has a development that mental state may recede to foundational drive-categories.
is more or less continuous.

The self’s experiences are not felt as impersonal events that oc-
cur at the same time or in the same brain. Hume’s bundle of im- All acts and objects develop out of a self that is laid down prior
ages is a cohesive whole each waking moment and over intervals, to conscious action and perception. The priority is the antecedence
such as sleep, intoxication or altered states. Events in the mind of earlier to later in the mental state. Objects are necessary for the
and acts in the world, as well as external objects, are felt as my self to actualize; they depend on the self as their source. Equally,
events, or as happening in or to me. Even events that are distinct the self degrades when objects disappear. We assume, falsely, that
from the self impact in a way that has consistency and organiza- the self, as observer, is an adjunct to an object, or that percep-
tion. We recognize the randomness of events and, to an extent, tion is an accessory. This entails that self and object are separate
their unpredictability, but at the same time we acknowledge a entities with discrete brain loci or networks. To study perception,
lawfulness and causal order, even if it is obscured by contingency. language or action without including the observer (or agent)
We say the self, through interpretation, gives meaning to random- leaves out the essential aspect, namely, the guiding or organizing
ness. However, meaning is not applied to events that impinge from substrate and origin.
outside; events arise through planes of meaning-laden images. All
For a self to attend to its derivations is quite natural and remote
objects arise in this way, some felt as part of the observer, others as
from attending to itself, which requires the agent to be the object
its possessions, still others as extrinsic. Thought is an activity that
of the same mental state. This turns the initial phase of the mental
issues from the self, even as thought thinks up the thinker. The
state into its terminus, or involves a regress from distal to proxi-
same process that lays down the core and empirical self continues
mal that occurs chiefly in meditative or mystical states, in which
into thought, act and object, the latter being a part of the self that
the self is more intuited than examined. The bundle of percepts
thinks them up.
accessible to Hume’s intuition is a manifestation of the earliest
Inner events and outer perceptions are generated with the phase in partition. The self that Hume could not describe is a
self of that occasion. This does not mean that a perception of a category prior to the images that were accessible to his introspec-
green object evokes a green self, though severe pain is identified tion12. Moreover, such inner percepts or images are not random
with a self in which pain is pervasive. In perceiving an object, the assortments; they assume a direction and coherence by virtue of
self, indeed the entire perception, is generated with the object. the self that precedes them. Deeper than its implementations, the
Some phenomena seem to be produced by a self that voluntarily self fractionates to images that then pass (are transformed) to acts
summons them up, others confront the self or coalesce with it. and objects.
A feared or loved object can be identified with a fearful or loving
The self feels it is an agent to objects that are its own ramifica-
self. With intense feeling in pain, fear, panic, love, with a relax-
tions, even an “owner” or possessor at the center of a personal
ation of boundaries, the self can become one with its perceptions.
universe. Some states of mind and body are felt to belong to a
Feeling may so dominate a self that it is replaced by the object
self that suffers or enjoys them. There is a powerful sense that all
that seems to induce it. Severe pain fills the mind to the point that
other objects are scarcely noticed. Intense fear or love focuses on
the object or situation at the expense of other feelings, thoughts An attempt to describe an imageless phase in thought was the program of the
12

Würzburg school of psychology.


148 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 149

personal images, even occasions in the world, belong ab origo to Dreams can be experienced in this way, as images inserted
the self, even if they are shared with others. The sense of owner- into the mind with the self a spectator. The passivity to dream
ship — my house, my car — expresses the value that flows distally and to certain forms of imagery results from the lack of self-image
into inanimate objects as an accrual through an economic vetting separation due to incomplete actualization and a loss of volitional
of what flows naturally into animate ones, such as in a person that feeling. The sense of agency is the link from self to image in visual
is loved. To attempt to possess an object is to affirm its belonging- and auditory imagery, as in the verbal imagery of inner speech.
ness. The impression of a self as the owner of acts and images is The loss of agency in dream or hallucination deprives the self of
reinforced in the variance of the world and mental contents in the the feeling that it generates the image. The self is then assaulted
face of the self’s relative stability. or possessed by the image instead of producing it. The agency
of inner speech or the preverbitum is transformed outward into
In a normal brain, all mental phenomena or bodily events an hallucinatory voice. A subtle interplay of such attitudes and
are experienced as belonging to the self, a dependency seen in feelings occurs in relation to image type and degree of objectifi-
pathological disorders. In psychosis, thought-possession and de- cation. In the controversial state of multiple personality, which is
lusion occur in an individual frightened by and subordinate to his probably a factitious condition, personalities are neither distinct
own image-productions. Thoughts seem to come from outside nor uncoupled from the core self. A variety of conditions relat-
like alien intrusions, or they objectify like objects, while objects ing to the normal and pathological brain refute the non-self of
become thought-like. The once-sharp transition from concept philosophical writings and the Anatman theory of Buddhism; as
to object, or mind to world, is indistinct. The unity of self, image Danto put it, the notion of cravings without a craver. In exposing
and object is on display in that change in one entails change in the fragility of belongingness, they erode arguments on external
the other. Such disorders are not to be dismissed as meaningless relations to objects and are clues to the nature (of the illusion) of
perturbations. The inner relations of phases in mental process are the self.
observed in the terror that is experienced when the illusory sepa-
ration of mind and world is ruptured. Though some writers, e.g. McTaggart (1916), have argued that
“the self is a substance with attributes”, it is widely accepted that
The sense of ownership is confirmed when the self feels de- the self is not a “thing” or substance, though this would explain its
tached from its own thoughts. The voices that speak to the schizo- relative stability. A substantial self grows by accretion with extrin-
phrenic, the thoughts that come to him from outside, the objects sic relations to acts and ideas that can be severed without conse-
that take on psychic properties all reinforce the observation that quence. While a self of internal relations seems anchorless, it has
inner and outer are outcomes of psychic process. In phantom limb, the stability of a category even with a fluid relationality. Such a self
as in some forms of body agnosia, or stimulation of brain areas for is not detached from objects but ingredient. For the former, the
movement and vocalization, bodily and psychic events may seem feeling of ownership is problematic; for the latter, it is the feeling
detached. Limb movement on excitation of motor cortex does not of detachment. These difficulties are bound up with the psychol-
have volitional feeling. We have some idea of this experience from ogy of agency and receptiveness.
nocturnal jerks of the legs, when we are uncertain if movement
is voluntary or spontaneous, i.e. self-generated or extrinsically in-
duced. Such movements are like objects in relation to the self. The There are two categories of the self, a deep core or unconscious
intermediate position of such phenomena — clearly endogenous self aligned with values, implicit beliefs and character, and a lim-
but neither image nor object — accounts for their unreality, or the inal, conscious or empirical self that adapts to momentary needs
uncertainty of their psychic origin. and future expectations. One hears a person say, I was not myself,
by which is meant the “I” or ego of a given situation did not reflect
150 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 151

the underlying beliefs and values of the “me” or the core. That 6.3. Development
many search for the genuine self or sense of identity speaks to the
intuition of an abiding core that underlies its varied manifesta- Mind divides into subject and object but separation is ubiquitous.
tions. The distinction is embodied in the unconscious and time- Every entity is a contrast. In organism there is mitosis, birth. Mitosis
less self of the “me”, and the conditional or temporal self of the is the model of individuation as complexity grows from within.
“I”, one constant and authentic, another transient and adaptive; Germinal processes are the forerunners of the cognitive process.
one that endures changing events, another hostage to the passing The shedding of superficial layers of skin from multi-layered ec-
scene. Yet there is no accepted account of core and empirical self, toderm is analogous to the actualization and perishing of percep-
how they develop, their relation to mind or brain and the basis of tions over layers in the brain that are also derived from ectoderm.
identity (Figure 6.1). The phyletic and morphogenetic pattern of exuberant growth, and
competitive elimination by sculpting or parcellation, continues in
the selection by way of inhibitory constraints on context-item or
whole-part transitions in the microgenesis of thoughts, objects
and feelings. This trimming of redundancy to achieve a specificity
of connectivity in the developing brain becomes the cascade of
whole-part shifts that, by inhibitory filtration through constraints
of habit and sense-data, is guided to specify potentiality at each
phase into the most adaptive resolution.

The origin of mind is postulated to begin with the minimal


duration of existence, or temporal extensibility (see discussion in
Sprigge, 1983), of a physical entity (Brown 2005). An expansion
within the temporal extensibility of complex entities eventuates
in a duration that enfolds feelings and concepts in a mental state.
I would argue that consciousness is the outcome of a continuous
series from inorganic to organic as complexity and organization
Fig. 6.1. The fine structure of the mental state. The core self increase in an epoch of existence that expands to accommodate
is derived to the empirical self, which in turn leads to objects in it. The initial state of mind is a division of intrinsic relations in the
the world. Corresponding with the object-development there is a epoch to a subjective and objective moiety, an early segment giv-
transition from drive through desire to object value. The affect- ing the organism, a later segment the perceptible world, a parti-
charged category of the core self is the initial drive-representation. tion that divides mind into subjective core and objective surface.
This is derived to conceptual feeling, then to object value. The
For the suckling, the world consists of a global object, the
transition from core to world is a continuum; the entire sequence
breast. Action and perception are bound together in a single per-
constitutes a momentary mental state or an act of cognition. The
formance. Sucking is enacted in the axial space of the body. An
correlation with forebrain anatomy has been discussed in prior
external field close to the body, relatively undifferentiated and
works (see Brown, 1988 et seq.).
incompletely detached, extends to the immediate surround. The
pre-object is gestalt-like; its features, e.g. the mother’s face, smile,
are not clearly articulated. The breast is grasped and sought for
— thus extrapersonal — but still within the sphere of organism.
The initial distinction of subject and object registers in behavior
152 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 153

not thought. With a distinction in thought, there is a shift from linear time. Con­sciousness of time-order mirrors the perception
awareness to consciousness. of whole events. In contrast to the presumed instantaneity of
physical transition, the present subsumes events as temporally
Initially, the unconscious core is equivalent to the whole of the extended wholes. The world is laid down as the final in a series
subject. Gradually, an implicit core develops within the subjective of tiers in space formation. The transition from self to object is
field. The core, an early phase in the epoch, is the seed of per- continuous (Fig. 6.2.) though the mind/world boundary is felt as
sonality, the first sign of which is probably a delay before action. absolute. The gap from mind to world evolves as a coping or sur-
In higher mammals and young children, perhaps expressed in vival strategy that hardens into folk belief and ‘common sense’.
temperament or attachment, the core shows the first tendency to
individuality. Prior to its appearance, behavior seems regulated by
mechanism: instinctual drive, environmental signal, consumma-
tion. The core is unconscious mind, dependent on drive and the
immediate occasion. With an accentuation of the core in relation
to the object world, individuality and awareness show a gradual
advance over the mammalian series. At some point, one speaks
of the ‘personality’ of the animal, as that which distinguishes it
from others of its type. The human infant shows the seeds of in-
dividuality. Out of the core an empirical (explicit, conscious) self
is shaped by beliefs and values. The self, guided to actuality by Fig. 6.2. Self, image and object are phases in the trajectory of
sense data, is conscious of internal and external objects, fixed in the core to extra-personal space.
the present yet able to attend to events in the past and plan for
those in the future.

As partition continues, object- and lexical-concepts, images


and feelings, punctuate the subjective pole. At the objective pole, 6.4. Consciousness and the mental state
value penetrates objects with greater specificity and refinement.
The unconscious, the self, mental contents and the perceptible
The present expands to encompass events of greater duration, en-
world are phases in the mental state. These phases and the se-
closing a perceptual narrative of self and ex­perience. The bodily
quence of their engagement, which are not readily accessible
space of the core expands to the perimeter of the arm’s reach, i.e.
to reflection, are a first order inference from patterns of mental
a ‘manipulation’ space, then beyond this perimeter to an exter-
disorder. For example, an account of the structure of the uncon-
nal world that ‘detaches’ from the observer. The action space of
scious (von Hartmann 1893) was inferred by Freud (1957) from
young infants transforms to the independent space of the con-
‘neurotic’ and other alterations of everyday behavior. The self is
scious adult.
inferred from the preservation of identity over successive states
The articulation of private (image) space by conceptual feel- (e.g. James 1890) and its alteration in pathology (Brown 1999).
ings accounts for choice, decision and trial action. Feeling accom- The transitional process that leads from unconscious precursors
panies the object in its journey from core to world. A feeling in to conscious objects is inferred from abnormalities of thought,
the self such as desire fractionates to a feeling in (with) the object perception and behavior (Brown, 1988). Without the evidence
such as worth. The core is unconscious simultaneity embedded of pathology, speculation would be restricted to what the mind
in bodily space. The end-point of the outward-going develop- knows of itself and would miss completely the micro-transition
ment is non-self (other, object) in three-dimensional space and that is its basis. The process of actualization or the relationality
154 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 155

of change in duration that constitutes the mental state is imper- psychological investigations of the development of the self in chil-
ceptible. Self-knowledge is fixed on content, opaque to the process dren, e.g. self-recognition, knowledge of private states or those of
through which content actualizes. others, and apart from speculative treatises on self and subjec-
tivity (e.g. Schelling, 1800/1978), there is little or no study of the
Accordingly, the initial construct arises in a brainstem or hypo- intrinsic basis of self-development in relation to brain and other
thalamic pacemaker and passes to archaic planes of limbic cortex aspects of mentation. The self is often conceived as a metaphor
that mediate the core self. Here are the configural correlates of for a unified collection of elements, reminiscent of Buddhist com-
forgotten memories, the irretrievable residues of early experience, mentary on the identity of a chair, which exists as the category
‘drive representations’ and the core beliefs and values instilled of parts that serve as categories for other parts. One property of
in childhood. This phase of personal memory, emotion, value the self is unity of experience, yet current thinking in psychol-
and belief establishes the biases, dispositions or presuppositions ogy presumes a multiplicity of interconnected brain and psychic
that ground character and the fundamental traits of personality. elements with unity the result of an extrinsic device for binding
Intrinsic patterns of instinctual drive tempered by value in the de- brain and mental events, such as a grandmother (command) cell
veloping configuration come into prominence with a relaxation of or brain rhythm. On this view, multiplicity is unified by a neuron
sensory input in the transit to limbic formation. The core retains or set of neurons, or by a rhythm or oscillator entraining modules.
the potential for diverse expressions of the personality, though in These are extrinsic mechanisms that, like the old pineal theory,
time it, too, is restrained by habitual tendencies in thought and are presumed to bind a manifold of elements.
behavior.
A process theory of the formative structure of the self in rela-
The physiological structure of the mind, i.e. the brain state, is tion to categories in the mental state does not have the problem
postulated to consist of a transition over successive stages in brain of an extrinsic function or device. The realization of unconscious
activity. The succession follows the pattern of growth in forebrain core to a self conscious of images and the world occurs over a se-
evolution, a single derivation constituting the minimal mind-brain ries of category-item or whole-part shifts, each partition providing
state (see below). Phases in the brain state are a second order infer- sub-categories for the next. The core arises as a simultaneous act-
ence on the origins of the mental state, an inference justified by object, an incipient action organized about the axial musculature
the generally lawful pattern in which mind and brain degrade. and a pre-object close to, or part of, the space of the body. This
Further, everything we know about the brain indicates that it is construct is activated in upper brain stem, hypothalamus and/or
the substrate of mind and the proximate source of experience. limbic system. The ethological concept of releaser captures the
The physical world that impacts on the brain would then be a immediacy of the core to instinctual drive. The template is aligned
third order inference within the bubble of phenomenal immedi- with constructs inherited from animal mind, parsed by early
acy. This physical world is known indirectly, but it must resemble learning to individuality.
the model elaborated in the mental state for we could not survive
in a radically different world. We further infer that we live in the The onset of a simultaneous (pre) action/perception differs
same physical world as bats, insects and microbes, a world we from the sequential nature of reflex, as in a sensori-motor loop
can measure but not experience. However, the limits on human (Weiszacker, 1939/58). The simultaneous construct arising in the
knowledge are not just those of access to the world and the vari- joints of brainstem reflex was proposed many years ago (Brown
eties of experience and perspectives; they are built into the very 1986), but the reflex model found a greater audience, even to
processes that make experience possible.

It is easier to deny the existence of the self than to explain


its nature, or the mass delusion of its existence. Yet apart from
156 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 157

the point of conceiving the mind as a complex reflex design.13 Fig. 6.3. The core develops in the internuncial pool of brainstem
The fundamental step in the appearance of mind out of reflex is reflex, shifting the closed loop of serial transition to simultaneous
replacement of seriality by simultaneity, with the core and its deri- phases in act and object formation. The core individuates in par-
vations surrounded by sensori-motor tiers (Fig. 6.3). The arousal of allel over endogenous phases in mind, surrounded by external,
incipient mind in the internuncial pool of upper brainstem occurs non-psychic tiers of sensory constraint and motor implementa-
as a primitive drive-representation, and continues into acts and tion.
objects in separate yet parallel and reciprocally-connected paths.
This entails that modalities of perception are specified out of a
synaesthetic multi-modal potential. The commonalty of action
and perception prior to individuation is the source of the unity of
later partitions. Consistent with the speciation of generic forms in 6.5. “I” and “me”
evolution, unity at the onset distributes to diversity, which is an The “me” is the initial separation from the other. There are in-
outcome, not a starting point.14 termediate phases from the unconscious or implicit “me” of
awareness to the “me” of conscious introspection. In the child,
the “me” precedes the “I”. Does the “me” announce a division of
child from world? Is the child’s “me” the whole of its subjectiv-
ity, i.e. the child as a person? Is it the beginnings of a self? The
self-referential behavior of apes seems to say, “give that to me!”
Before this, the subject is carved out to an increasing degree from
its environment. The “isolation cry” of infant monkeys, correlated
with mesial limbic-derived neocortex, a region associated in fMRI
studies with self-referential behavior, is the rudiment of a primi-
tive utterance… an ancestor of the self calling out, “help me”.

The distinction of “I” and “me” is more on the order of actual


and potential than knower and known (James, 1890). The knowing
self — the liminal “I” at the threshold of consciousness — knows
what it gives rise to. The subliminal “me” that remains beneath
as potential for the “I” , unconscious and inaccessible, is aligned
with the tacit knowledge or capacity (competence) to know. The
known self is not actually known, it is felt, intuited, sought after,
even as it participates covertly in thought.
13
Since the seminal work on reflex by Sherrington, Cajal, Herrick and others,
the synaptic model, in which A connects to B, B to C, and back to A, has provided
In spite of the ubiquity of the “I” and its desires (needs, hopes,
a theoretic framework for the study of complex systems in mind/brain; even fears, etc.), when one is asked what exactly is this “I”, the most
now, it is a distant cousin to box and arrow diagrams and circuit boards. Yet some common reaction is puzzlement or a description of what the per-
of its most distinguished disciples, e.g. Eccles (1970) have argued that cognition son or others think the self is like. To say one is sad, conflicted,
is more likely explained by field or wave effects than all-or-none excitation and
etc., is to announce a feeling or state of mind at a given moment;
inhibition on the model of the synapse.
not describe the self. The statement, “I am sad”, means I have an
14
Does the uniformity of the core relate to still deeper Jungian archetypes from experience of sadness, not “I have a sad self”. At most it implies
which all individualities develop?
158 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 159

that one (ordinarily transient) property of the self is sadness. The stituent or derivation of the self, and a medium of thought. It can
cogito has an agent and an action. It describes the agency and be experienced in relation to speech or speech perception, as
the felt connection to the act, but the agent — the “I” — is inferred something that happens to the self like an auditory perception,
from the activity of thinking. The point is, the “I” cannot be delved or as something the self does like a speech act (Chapter 4). In the
into or adequately defined beyond a description of its states. passive condition, inner speech is “heard” by the self rather than
produced by it. If the phenomenon intensifies, it leads to auditory
Does the core self of childhood inhabit the mature self, or is it hallucination. In the active condition, inner speech seems like an
erased and forgotten? The forgotten experiences and ingrained arrested utterance (preverbitum) that is a product of the “I”. This
values of youth, the relation to others, animal knowledge and “I”, identified with the conscious self or ego, is felt as an instru-
instinctual tendencies grow to configurations that guide adult be- ment of its agency.
havior. The child is truly father to the man, for the mature self is
latent in biases laid down in the juvenile brain. The healthy child The silent, “I feel, I want.” of inner speech is experienced as a
is aligned with its destiny when it is striving to be an adult. The unit. Like the “I” in “I think”, it does not fully convey the wholeness
healthy adult feels what is authentic in character by not letting go of self. One could think one thing and say or feel another. For the
of the child. self, the “I” is prominent less in action than states of indecision.
Every action delimits the self’s potential. What one says, except in
When the child says “I”, a new world appears. Does the “I” states of strong belief or emotion, does not adequately satisfy the
imply a self or is it a verbal gesture? The child needs no concept possibilities of self-realization. Even in states of strong emotion,
of other minds to call people by their names, or use the “you”. when the self is not hindered by uncertainty, a person may apolo-
A person or an object seen in a “different light” — one says, with gize for an outburst, saying, “I don’t know what came over me”, as
“new eyes” — is not seen again the same way. Once the first-per- if the self is distinct from, and overcome by, its own emotions.
son develops, it is not readily given up. Indeed, it grows stronger,
fortified against every assault. If the “I” is obscure, the “me” is impenetrable. We get a sense
of the effort to access the unconscious when a dream, and the
The “me” can give rise to many possible “I”s but the “I” of that self of that dream, fade on awakening. The dream lapses to the
moment is a commitment. We see a transition from the implicit shadows leaving a bare intuition of what it may have been like.
unconscious to the conscious explicit in all areas of cognition, e.g. On waking, the person may say, “I was terrified (excited, happy,
a word that individuates from the “mental lexicon”, a recollection etc.). He may offer that “such and such was happening to me”.
from the “memory store”. We see the correlates of this dissocia- The “me” is not the self of the dream, which is passive. It is not the
tion (transition) in pathology, e.g. procedural learning in amne- knowledge base postulated by James; not an active self or agent
sics, perception in hemianopia, semantic priming, preserved (see below). The existence of a core self, as with all unconscious
inference in total aphasics. The transition from concept to object, events, is inferred from what becomes conscious. The existence
store to item, lexicon to word, or unconscious to conscious, is not of a core is based on the multiplicity of evanescent selves against
a transfer of like to like, as if the depth were a mere container. The a backdrop of a more constant character, and the tacit or uncon-
transition of category to instance, or whole to part, occurs over a scious beliefs and values that deposit the conscious self.
qualitative series of covert phases. Conscious particulars are not
dormant constituents waiting for activation; they become what Such observations raise the question of the relation of psychic
they are in a passage to the definite. events to the terms used to describe them. Do terms create events
or do events call up the terms? Do the terms point to events for
Thoughts come into the mind like objects, passively. Inner which language is inadequate? Are they markers of development
speech (verbal imagery) is often conceived as the principle con- that help in the partition of the psyche? Do words such as “I”, “you”
160 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 161

and “me” identify, label, reveal or delimit psychological states? Do constraints on the actualization. The idea of a conscious veto is
they just serve linguistic roles? Is the other specified perceptually merely consciousness of constraints close to the termination.
in the “you”, partitioned inferentially as a self with thoughts and
feelings? Selves that survive into consciousness, as well as those unborn,
have a share in the core. The share of a potential thought or feel-
Finally, one can ask if the “I” is agent or constituent. How is an ing that has not yet been experienced is the ground of creativity
act or a statement “connected” to the self? A self that is strongly and self-discovery. What are the limits of the unconscious self?
felt when words are not its medium implies that it is not identical The non-actual contributes to the fringe of character behind the
with the inner flow of language. The self does not carry the whole self of the occasion. Does this background make contact with the
force of the personality, but is an occasion of its employment. It universal or a frontier with nature?
is like asking, when I snap my fingers is my “whole self” behind
the act. Rilke put this quandary well when he wrote, “I want my The ever-present “I” is the dominant element of discourse; I
own will, and I want simply to be with my will, as it goes toward think, I feel, and so on. Even a neutral statement such as “grass is
action”. green” implies, “I profess, believe, claim etc., that grass is green”.
The self is the unacknowledged agent (or victim) for all personal
events, which are its predicates. Thought is predicative. The self,
or the topic of thought, is in the background since it is already
known to the thinker (Vygotsky, 1962). The “I” precedes its predi-
6.6. Self and non-self cate and is only included with it as a kind of endorsement. The
Many a self that never materializes is latent in the core. One who self is quietly enlisted as a substrate in the subject-property or
only contemplates suicide may yet have the inclination. Some topic-action relation.
who have never contemplated suicide might kill themselves in
The self declares its individuality in carving out the person in
adversity. What is conceived, considered, rejected, whatever goes
relation to others. A subject requires an object. Selves require oth-
into an idea, a feeling or a decision, issues from the “me” or core
ers for their own individuation. To be selfless is not to be without
self. The “not-me” is not what is outside the “me” but what is alien
a self, but to revive the other in the self before it individuates. The
to the “I”. The core self is grounded in the wholeness of organism.
reaching-out of genuine compassion begins with an exploration
It is undecided what is outside the “me” since, like the uncon-
of the underpinnings of autonomy. Cobb and Sherburne (1973)
scious, it has no posterior limit. The “I” partitions the core, setting
write, after Whitehead (PR 288), that all real togetherness is de-
the explicit self against the “non-I”, including in its potential all
rived from the indefinable togetherness that is found in a single
past and possible selves.
experience. Self and other are generated within the now of the
Much of the “non-I” is what is latent in the core. As the core crys- present. In genuine compassion, the self is a predicate for the
tallizes into a conscious self, other possible selves are bypassed or other. This is pronounced in visionaries or in psychotics obeisant
subdued. What survives is what is obligated by the situation. The to their own images. Probably, some commotion in a life is nec-
core does not deliver any conceivable self, only what is permis- essary to give up striving and become the felt object of another
sible given the person’s habits, predispositions and experiences. person’s need.
The conscious self arises each moment out of an implicit struggle.
Except in pathological conditions, behavior “attached” to the
At every phase in the transition to an object, alternative possi-
“I” can be cut off and the “I” remain intact. The “I”’s actions can
bilities are eliminated by intrinsic (habit) and extrinsic (sensation)
be prevented, many beliefs can be attacked or modified without
great sacrifice, the “I” can be disgraced, praised, condemned,
162 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 163

undermined and undergo radical change, but it is not effaced un- whether the real is equivalent to the non-illusory and if so, what
less its neural correlates are damaged. It is difficult to imagine a reality takes the place of the illusion?
person without an “I”, an ego. Even the most unselfish, broken or
compassionate of individuals begins a sentence with “I …” Consider brain and perception like a celluloid film and moving
picture. The celluloid is felt to be more real than the movie because
Systems of praxis such as Buddhism are based on giving up it does not represent something other than what it is, whereas
the “I”. Self-denial is a different order than dissolution. It is one events in the film have no actual correlates. We might think a
thing to argue there is no self and quite another not to have one. documentary is more real than an ordinary film, but we are still
Similarly, to think the world is illusion is one thing; to feel it is an- looking at images, not “real” objects. Since all films (and objects)
other. The disappearance of the “I” that is the goal of meditation are images, it is not the imaginal or perceptual quality that counts
(Brown, 2008a), could it be achieved, would leave a state of aware- for the unreality. There is a presumption that some mental objects
ness in non-conscious mind. Some claim this mind is one with — ideas more than dreams, words more than ideas, objects more
nature, and that the subject/world separation is lost. Loss of self than words — are more real than others, independent of whether
is a return to lack of specification. In meditation, the expansion or not the self is illusory.
of the present accompanies a dilation of the “I”, with loss of the
consciousness of time-order. In a present without past or future,
events are simultaneous. The simultaneity of an expanded now
may recapture an awareness in which the self, external space and
time order are undifferentiated. In the retreat from consciousness 6.7. The self in dream
to awareness, concepts are said to be relinquished, but with no The dream of the Brahma is interrupted every so many years by
self, there is no consciousness of oneness. Perhaps the state is brief episodes of awakening after which the Brahma again falls
comparable to animal awareness. asleep and a new world begins. Does life consist of two dreams
only one of which seems real? If a dream anticipates the wak-
To insist the self is illusory is to evoke the experience of non- ing perception of the other, am I foreshadowed in other people’s
self, not feel the absence of self. What sort of experience would dreams? William James wondered if his dreams were getting
this be? If I accept the illusion of self, what am I left with? A self mixed up with those of others. Freud also mentioned communi-
that believes it is an illusion? If I am convinced my self is an illu- cation in dream. Sleep-talkers converse!
sion, what is there to take its place? The illusion of a self that is
conscious of being illusory would seem to arise on the intuition of Dreams not only recur, they may have historical continuity
something deeper, more genuine or real. The origin of the illusion similar to waking life. The core self, and its derivation to the self
of self has rarely been discussed, though along with the reality of of dream, might be affected as much by events in the dream as
the world, it is the most powerful illusion we have. those of waking experience. However, the passivity of the dream
self does not usually allow for the interpretation of an event as
The self distinguishes the illusory and the real by comparing an external assault. Dream is not felt to endure the accidents of
one illusory object with another, e.g. relating the self to objects life that make living so perilous. In waking, what others say or
or brain physiology, and asserting one of them as real (Brown, do has an impact. In dream we do not hold others responsible. If
2004a). But the “real” is an object of consciousness. It is perverse we are besieged by others in the dream it is not altogether clear
to treat the self as illusion and its objects as real. If an illusory self their actions are volitional. We infer intent to others in a dream
could not have knowledge of the real, objects perceived by an illu- but if we are not ourselves agents, how can we dream that others
sory self are also illusory (Vaihinger, 1924-1965). This depends on are acting volitionally? It may be that agency accompanies the im-
164 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 165

age outward, as in psychotics who are passive to an hallucinatory a knife-edge of change, lacking the duration that arches over suc-
command. If one has no control over the events of a dream, how cessive events in waking consciousness. The conscious present
can others in the dream exhibit such control? Here we are at the has a revived past, or one in decay, to anchor the disparity be-
boundary of purposefulness and intentionality (see below). tween “memory” and “perception” that is essential to the virtual
duration of the now. The theoretical significance of the dream is
The dream self (see Revonsuo, 2005) differs from the waking in showing how the simultaneity of the unconscious, and the be-
self as an image from a perception. The feeling of passivity to an fore and after of the dream, anticipate the temporal order of the
image shifts to a feeling of volition, and then to a fully indepen- world. Dream is an intermediate phase that, without a perceptual
dent object. As the object individuates, the passive self of dream surface, is a before and after or earlier and later, with a present
transforms to the feeling of agency in wakefulness. The bifurca- filled by, but not in relation to, a personal past.
tion out of the self to a “detachment” of objects, and agency on
them, reflects a bias to perception or action. In the transition to More than in waking life, the dream self swims in a soup of
consciousness, there is also an elaboration of serial time. The its own creation. We assume the content of dream reflects the
dream has no past or future. The self may resemble that of an thoughts and feelings of the dreamer, even if we do not attribute
earlier time or a fantasy that is not temporally “tagged”. It is closer the character of the dream self to the core. The dream content and
to the imagery of waking consciousness than the unconscious but the dream self are interpreted as distorted products of the psyche.
it is not the “me” that underlies the conscious self. Unlike the self Like the dream image, the dream self is a content, not an agent
of the dream, the “me” of the core is unknowable. The dream self or source. Psychoanalysis depends very much on this assump-
is closer to a conscious self but it lacks external objects to ground tion. Fears, wishes and their symbolic distortions are thought to
the flow of images. The images are perceived as external and real reveal the hidden nature of the self, as participant or onlooker.
in the dream because there is no further exteriorization within The self of the dream is equally conditioned by symbolic ances-
which they are bundled or to which they can be compared. try. In contrast, what one consciously perceives would not appear
to tell us much, if anything, of the observer’s life. However, if the
The recurrent imagery of dream and myth and their common dream self and its images are preliminary to the conscious self
themes, symbols and modes of thought (e.g. Jung, 1928; Lévy- and its objects, some thread of connectivity from imagination to
Bruhl, 1985) imply the existence of unconscious archetypes. Does perception should be evident. The objects we choose to look at or
the core rise out of a common ancestral pool or is the family re- avoid are a guide to our interests and values, as is their meaning,
semblance in ancestral pattern driven by innate schemas active which is imported into objects from antecedent phases in their
to a varying degree in each person in the originating constructs? formation. Creative imagery and aesthetic perception exploit this
The pattern suggests that the generality of the schemata adapts continuum.
to the locality of culture and experience in a journey from the
inheritance of the animal core to the uniqueness of individual
consciousness.

Without external objects, the self has a before and after, but 6.8. Self and person
no past or future, no time order, no agency. The before is truly
To say, as Sartre did, by fiat rather than theory of mind, that a
past and no longer exists, while the past of memorial experience
person is the sum of his acts, ignores the zone of privacy that
is the present content of a dream. Hallucination tends to be more
underlies occasions of satisfaction. Even from the standpoint of
vivid than waking objects. Similarly, the present of dream-imagi-
moral conduct the account is wanting. Though trivial, it is more
nation, in consequence of the lack of “real” objects, looms larger
accurate to ascribe the core to a physiological ground from which
than the present of ordinary wakefulness. The dream-present is
166 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 167

the empirical self arises than to conceive it as the quantity of its 6.9. Self and category
outcomes. Moreover, the person is not on immediate display. One
still has to infer the reasons, motives, feelings, conflicts, that lie The description of states of the conscious self gives a narrative of
behind an act. character and needs. The saga of a life is an irresistible tale, espe-
cially to the one who lives it. The personal history, the stacking of
A person is his existence, and existence is more than action. episodes and their mutations, creates the category of a continu-
Existence embraces the becoming through which entities actual- ous self. The repeatability of the category in overlapping pulses
ize. Entity-formation is becoming. The category (duration) over (James, 1890; Brown, 2004) contributes to the self-identical nature
this formativeness is being. The objective or externalized segment of personality across events. In this way the identity of a categori-
of the mental state — an act or sequence of muscular excitations cal self is preserved over successive acts of cognition.
— is not the output of an assembly belt or production line. One
does not dispense with the preceding stages once the final one is The relation of the “me” to the “I”, the core to the liminal
reached. Nor is an object assembled from the parts, which instead self, can also be compared to that of concept to object. A con-
are the result of analysis to an objective goal. An act of cognition cept gives rise to, and can be inferred from, the properties of an
is an epoch with overt and covert phases, consisting of a formative object. Similarly, the attributes of the self are inferred from its
sequence of rhythmic levels constrained to “physicalize” an event. actions, as the properties of a horse constitute the defining fea-
Qualitative change in the dynamic of the act is no less part of the tures of the concept of “horseness” The term horse makes explicit
act than its perceptible outcome. Similarly, the antecedent events the concept behind it, which becomes still more explicit with a
leading to the object are not causal phases that vanish when their particular horse. A concept is derived from a category, ultimately
work is over, but are ingredient in the mental state of which the from categorical primes in the core. The self-concept, like other
object is an outcome. concepts, incorporates experiential, perceptual and meaning rela-
tions. Concepts are richer and less factual than objects, and for the
We could say, a person is the sum of his states, the major por- ordinary person less real (e.g. Collingwood, 1924).
tion of which is inaccessible even to him. Is this like saying the
world is the sum of its states since the world began? Can we think The category of the core delivers the self and conceptual feel-
of the world like the mind as an overlap of epochs rather than an ing as sub-categories. Consequent derivations are tributaries in
accumulation of slices? To think otherwise reduces each slice to a categorical “structure”. Inner and outer events — thoughts and
the minimal duration of, say, a chronon (Whitrow, 1972), which acts/objects — are implementations of concepts that issue from
ignores the change within duration and the process it conceals. the core. Consider a table as an exemplary piece of furniture. A
The epoch of a state cannot be dissected to causal parts since the lamp is in the same category (furniture) but a less familiar ex-
“parts” exist as parts of the whole of the epoch. ample. The identity of the self is like that of a prototypical item
in a category of possible states. The habitual self recurs in this
The conscious self is still early in the mental state; motil- wider category that “contains” potential archetypal (unconscious)
ity, speech, objects, are later, yet the state is an indivisible whole selves given the experiential history of the individual. The most
comprised of a totality of phases. The potential of the core, the representative or prototypical (conscious) self is the most com-
thoughts, feelings and images of the conscious self, the final com- mon derivative, or exemplar, for that individual. The habitual or
mitment in speech, action and perception, are “gathered together” dominant self contrasts with its less familiar or atypical manifesta-
in a single traversal from tendencies or dispositions to concrete tions, as a table does with a lamp, including aggressive, romantic,
particulars. The entire mental state is an atomic unit that includes foolish, impulsive, spiritual, and other selves that are possible giv-
conduct, the inner life, and its antecedents in thought, dream and en the person’s capacities and experiences. The dominant self is
the unconscious. replaced by an atypical self at the category boundary in a state of
168 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 169

intoxication, hypnosis, religious conversion or pathology. Should mind. Since the self undergoes natural and pathological change
an unfamiliar self recur at the expense of the prototypical self, it and final extinction, it would seem that only in the realm of spirit
gradually becomes an habitual mode of expression. The new self can it be construed as ideal or eternal.
then forms the nucleus of a novel category and can rightly be said
to be the self of a new person. Time and space are specified out of the core: space as objects
grow out of concepts, time as duration is incremented by events.
In a similar way, a peripheral member of a category (furniture) Time penetrates space in the virtual duration of events, space
such as a lamp can become the center of another category, such penetrates time in the fiction of changeless existents. The unity
as a source of illumination. The new category forms around the and tension of the temporal and spatial is the relation of the dy-
boundary item and excludes members of the former category for namic to the static. We also see this in the choice of an object or
novel objects such as lightning and the sun. When the self under- event ontology (Brown, 2005a), in the contrast of duration and
goes a radical shift, it incorporates attributes appropriate to the instantaneity, or of change and stability.
new personality, retaining some vestiges of the prior self in over-
learned skills and traits of character.
Subjective time develops in a transition from the simultane-
ity of the core to temporal order in the world. Inwardly, time is
counted in duration, externally in increments. Temporal order
6.10. Time, space and the self is realized as the unity of the core objectifies into the multiplic-
ity of the world. The simultaneity of duration is “unpacked” into
Categories are not containers into which like items are placed, but
an event-manifold. A global pre-object distributes a succession
involve inter alia complex aspects of space and time. In one sense
of perceptual events. The actualization of entities is the aim of a
a category can be said to be timeless, for it remains essentially
unidirectional process of self-realization. In mind, self-actualiza-
unchanged with respect to its inclusion criteria, even as novel
tion realizes event-categories at the outer (external) pole of the
members are added. A new animal or plant that is discovered
subjective.
or manufactured must respect the properties of membership to
remain in the category, or it will form another category at the In this temporal realization, space transforms outward over
boundary of the old one. levels on an axis from the body through the immediate surround
to an independent world. The intrapsychic space of the vegetative
While a category can be conceived as timeless, concrete ex-
life is preliminary to the extra-personal but intrapsychic, egocen-
istents in the category will vanish as do all particulars. However,
tric space of dream, which itself is preliminary to an indepen-
as tokens of those particulars, i.e. as sub-categories, they too can
dent Euclidean space of object-relations. The self cannot survive
be said to persist as timeless representatives of their types. If the
without object-space and event-time. It rapidly degrades when
abstract category is timeless, the core and conscious self, as proto-
objects are lost, as in sensory deprivation or snow blindness. The
typical exemplars of the person, are conditioned on the time and
corollary of a loss of objects is a failure in self-realization. This is
space they generate, and on which they depend. The categorical
striking in cases with destruction of the visual and auditory areas
self of a person might be construed as timeless, ideal or immortal
of the brain, when the waking self regresses to that of dream or
for those individuals whose attributes or accomplishments are re-
psychosis (Brown, 1999). The duration required for events to be
membered. Yet even for those innumerable others who are forgot-
perceived as stable objects is also the basis for the perception of
ten, it is the timelessness of the category that inspires the belief
events. The persistence of an object over some minimal duration
that individuals persist after death as souls, or as ideas in god’s
to be perceived for what it is entails a recurrence within succes-
170 Jason W. Brown

sive nows. A tree that exists for a millisecond is not perceived at


all. Sustained recurrence creates objects, novelty in the recurrence
creates events. All objects are events in which change (recurrence)
is more or less imperceptible.

Duration is the “glue” of continuity that carves events out of


flux. Time is not a uniform flow but a replacement of changing
objects across intervals, themselves changeless, thus non-existent.
The continuity of the self, of inner and outer, and the recognition
of sameness or difference, owes to the overlap in a succession of
present moments. Specifically, the overlap of the present (now) in
the replacement of a categorical self and its objects is the basis for
the near-identity of recurrences. The scenario of incessant change
with relative stability of inner and outer is comprehensible in
terms of categories sufficiently flexible to accommodate deviance
and sufficiently habitual to cancel brief atypical replications.
Chapter 7
Solipsism and Other Minds

“We are still a long way from understanding


what it signifies that nothing has any existence unless
some small and oh, so transitory — consciousness has become
aware of it.”
Carl G. Jung (1961)

7.1. The case for solipsism


Solipsism is an extreme form of idealism in which the self or indi-
vidual mind is the whole of reality for the person, and the world
including the brain has no independent existence apart from its
mental representation. This position, referred to as physical nihil-
ism, of which there are several variants, is the logical conclusion
of an idealist framework in which the self can only know the inner
and outer contents of its mind. More precisely, only the conscious
focus is known, since unconscious or pre-conscious contents and
the unattended portion of the conscious field, as well as the cat-
egories and processes through which mind develops, are outside
this focus and do not exist for the individual. Solipsism maintains
the non-existence of a world outside personal mind, as well as the
non-existence of prior, as well as generative and fringe states of
the self and its world, indeed, all experience not in present con-
sciousness.

This would mean that the whole of a person’s mind and large
portions of personal experience and memory are non-existent un-
til they become conscious. While mental contents come and go in
consciousness, in a strict formulation of the theory, unconscious
events outside the conscious focus do not exist. This implies that
my kitchen table exists and does not exist according to my con-
sciousness of it at a given instant, indeed, that the self of this mo-
ment passes in and out of existence over intervals of dreamless
sleep. These difficulties arise in the tension of psychic objects with
material entities, or in the need for a self-identical personality and
174 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 175

object-permanence when the flux of the mental life is posited physical referents, others do not, though the direct knowledge of
against the assumed substantiality of the physical world. psychic objects compensates for their phenomenal quality, even
if the greater part of this knowledge is unconscious. Another dif-
Naturally, past, future and material entities are implied in pres- ficulty is that sanity is incompatible with a felt appreciation of the
ent-consciousness. Events in the present that are unconscious or psyche in objects.
incipiently conscious must also be implicit for the present to exist.
Every psychic experience is surmised to rest on a micro-temporal If things exist only in ongoing consciousness, the nature of
process in which previous and ongoing events account for object present-consciousness is important. If the posterior boundary of
continuity and identity. The perception of a table entails implicit the present is an indiscernible fringe of a prior mental state in
knowledge of the object-concept for its recognition. A self does decay, the present that encloses consciousness of self and objects
not exist without the beliefs, values and traits of character or per- cannot be directly apprehended, much less seized on as direct
sonality that make it what it is. Unconscious categories and prior experience. We can experience events in the present but not the
experience are incorporated implicitly in the momentary state. present independent of events. Without events, there is no pres-
The fact that an object exists at the instant of its perception rests ent, the present being as much a creation of events as a “contain-
on a multitude of implicit events or dispositions of which only the er” for them. The appearance of events in present-consciousness
outer shell is evident. is fundamental. Santayana (p. 14, 1923) wrote that “any solipsism
which is not a solipsism of the present moment is logically con-
The existence of objects in consciousness is not consciousness temptible”. If existence applies to the objects of consciousness,
of existing objects. In the more extreme claims of solipsism, in dreams and waking hallucinations can be said to exist, unlike un-
which all that is exists in conscious experience, the paradox of liv- attended kitchen tables that do not exist until they are perceived
ing in a subjective world is that knowledge limited to the psyche is or thought about. The implication is that an appearance exists
the cost of the ability to experience it. Only conscious objects have while physical reality is imaginary, or that appearance is more real
immediate psychic existence. This begs the question of what it than the physical events it portrays, or that to exist and to be real
means for psychic objects to exist. Do thoughts, dreams, fantasies are different states of affairs.
exist? Does every passing image exist? Could one say, the thought
of a unicorn exists even if what it refers to does not? Is this an Cognitive studies distinguish the contents of mental states or
existence of the thought, the reference or the neural process it representations, or the relation of subject to representation, or of
presupposes? If the latter, existence applies to the inferred sub- representation to external object, e.g. “organism/environment
strate of a thought, i.e. the brain, rather than the thought, which is transactions” (Fodor, 1981). Such terms conceal an epistemology
inconsistent with solipsism, and comparable to the existence of a that is thrown about incautiously, promoting an agenda in which
material world, but not its mirror in mental objects. representations are manipulated by rules. But whether or not op-
erations on representations are psychologically real has little to do
The irony is that existence is claimed for an illusory world of with whether the perceived world is real. The construal that only
psychic experience and non-existence for the “real” world of exter- psychological states of intrinsic meaning are solipsistic ignores
nal entities, except as they fall within the field of perception. If we the denotative meaning of external objects. It is mainly the exis-
deny the existence of mental objects, or claim that the mental is il- tence of objects “outside the head” that is in question. Were the
lusory, on what grounds are material entities inferred? If the chair solipsist to claim that only conscious intra-psychic events exist,
before me is phenomenal — like a waking dream — how can a real while external events of which the self is conscious do not, the
chair be inferred from its subjective image? The (presumed) sub- position would be incoherent. The reciprocal claim that external
stantiality of material entities is vitiated by their inferential status. objects exist while internal ones do not, is unacceptable but not
What reality corresponds to a specific image? Some images have
176 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 177

incoherent. In spite of the break from concept to object, solipsism knowable. The direct knowledge of a thing is not equivalent to its
entails that knowledge is not limited to concepts, but applies to existence. We perceive and have immediate knowledge of sticks
objects in the world, or that the transition from concept to object bent in water and rainbows, which we do not think exist in the
is continuous. way we perceive them, or in the manner of perceived tables. We
know, even if we do not perceive it to be the case, that sticks do
Along these lines, the attempt to distinguish a computational not bend in water, and we know that rainbows do not have mind-
from a naturalistic psychology does not venture far from a com- independent physical correlates, such as we postulate for tables.
mon materialist base. To paraphrase Hans Jonas, because the Conversely, while our knowledge of physical entities such as pri-
lifeless is now the knowable, it has become the true and only ons or sonar is indirect, they have a greater claim on existence
foundation of reality. Life and mind are assumed to evolve out than a rainbow or bent stick in water. Yet, some personal images
of the dead universe of materialism. Yet unlike machine models, such as spirits or ghosts, dreams and the objects of a delusional
biological theory has the potential to enlarge evolutionary natu- consciousness, exist for the individual more vividly than shared
ralism to incorporate a process dynamic that transforms the enti- perceptions.
ties of materialism to a fuller conception of mind. The seeds of
the psychic are in physical entities at the most elementary level. The argument that the directly perceived exists and the infer-
Foster (1994) put this well when he wrote that, “the idealist is not ential does not is unsustainable since even the directly perceived
committed to saying that there is no fundamental reality external follows a temporal lag, i.e. there is no direct perception. Moreover,
to the human mind. All he is committed to saying is that if there the present and its contents are supported by a host of implicit
is such a reality, it is not itself physical and only contributes to the processes without which they too cannot exist. The immediate
existence of the physical world through its actual and potential past must in some sense exist to explain the momentary pres-
influence on human experience.” ent. A perceived effect implies a prior cause, even if the cause
is a memory that does not exist outside present consciousness.
Similarly, a perceived cause that implies a future effect has no
meaning unless the not-yet-existing effect in some sense exists.
If I drop a ball, barring an intervening event it will impact on the
7.2. Knowledge of reality ground. If I die or faint before the ball hits the ground, for solip-
Jung (1961) followed Kant in writing that, “…we are hopelessly sism there would be no impact, as if I were to wake up from a
cooped up in an exclusively psychic world” though, like Kant, he dream of a falling ball.
did not deny the existence of a noumenal or extra-psychic real-
ity. Inner and outer objects are a window to the real world, the The central question concerns the nature of existence. Does it
existence of which, were it demonstrable without psychic color- differ for psychic and physical events? Does the immediate knowl-
ation, would still not refute the solipsistic premiss that we can edge of the mental, or access to it, have a greater claim on reality
only know, directly, the contents of the present state. We may be than an indirect knowledge of its sources, causes or antecedents?
confined to psychic experience but knowledge and existence are Does a passing thought, a mood, a dream or an illusion, have the
dissociable concepts. The existence of the objects of direct knowl- same quality of existence as a concept, a word or a perceptual
edge can be split off from the presumed non-existence of things object? Do mental phenomena exist in the usual sense of self-suf-
indirectly known. ficiency and permanence as physical entities, or is their existence
dependent on the inferred brain activity with which the psychic is
The problem of existence is tangential to the position that correlated? That knowledge of mental contents differs according
only the self and the objects of present consciousness are directly to the conscious state does not readily translate to a difference in
178 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 179

existence. Some phenomena appear more real than others, but Implicit beliefs become explicit in psychopathology when
greater realness is not equivalent to greater existence; indeed, re- the supports of an external world are no longer tacitly accepted.
alness admits of degrees, but reality and existence do not. Pathology exposes the psychic underpinnings of a community of
shared beliefs. The psychotic feels privy to the thoughts of others,
The adequacy of a perception to the entities it represents is and believes others can read his thoughts. The consciousness of
inferred from its adaptation, which is tested by action. Survival mind in others that is implicit in everyday discourse becomes ex-
alone is evidence that a physical world exists, in that objects are plicit and emphatic, and the individual is vulnerable to lose what
shaped as copies of real entities. Life cannot be supported in a hitherto he had not even thought about. To become conscious of
psychic world that is indifferent to a real one. The reality (not real- what was previously automatic brings the phenomenon into focus.
ness) of an image owes to the sensory data that delimit it to a It also exposes the fragility of the world and how easily it decom-
model of reality. This does not mean that the solipsist who jumps poses. The person recognizes — or the experience is a reminder
to avoid an on-coming car must, in the action, renounce his belief — that mind as feeling accompanies the other in a migration out-
in a psychic world. The perception of the car has so adapted to its ward from self. The conveyance of personal mind into others is
inferred reality that the realness of the image is no less compelling acutely felt in its withdrawal, e.g. when the psychotic believes he
than if it were a material entity. A threatening image is avoided knows the thoughts of others. The belief that one can know what
whether or not it models a physical entity. We are frightened by others are thinking in psychotic or delusional cases is the coming-
hallucinations and dreams because we infer, implicitly, that they into-consciousness of the buried flow of mind outward, that moves
correspond to (are) something real. The difference between hal- into, and creates others, out of the self, i.e. others and other minds
lucination and object perception is that while perception no less are self-creations. In contrast to ordinary intuition, there is a felt
than hallucination is fully endogenous, unlike hallucination, per- recognition that external mind is not external and exclusive to the
ception is shaped by sense data. The perception models what is other, but is conveyed into the other from the self. The individual
“out there”. The psychotic reacts to hallucinations as normal sub- feels that other minds are bound up with their perception, or that
jects do to perceptions, only more strongly, regardless of whether other minds are as much a product of the self as other bodies.
or not they are “real”, i.e. map to a physical world. The ability to This inference becomes emphatic when the animating spirit of
distinguish a mental image from a perception, or to transform an the other is threatened with loss. In depersonalization, the other
image to a perception, is critical to survival. is perceived as a mindless puppet or mannequin. The withdrawal
of psyche (feeling) from objects is the first stage in a regression
The veridicality of a perception is evidence for a physical world
back through the object-formation, from object (feeling, value) to
to which acts and objects adapt, and to which they correspond.
antecedent concept (desire, wish).
The existence of a present in a “real” world points to a physical
reality to which the present has adapted. The objects of the pres- The other is an object and a process. The objective portion is
ent are like successful organisms in evolution. They fit a niche an externalized concept that flows out of the self. The processual
in the environment. A veridical perception is the outcome of a portion is the feeling that accompanies this externalization. This is
micro-evolutionary process of perceptual fitness. Acts and objects a becoming into being. From the standpoint of the self, the mind
— James might say — are the outcomes of pragmatic (adaptive) of the other is elaborated on the feeling that flows into and invests
beliefs as in the animal faith of Santayana. The belief in a shared it. Feeling does not just animate objects; it is the basis of their ex-
world and the reality of others in that world, though not givens, istence and realness. The other, as an inferred physical entity, has
are adaptive strategies, the precursors of which are “wired” into a separate life of feeling, which in compassion, anger or love, en-
our brains. livens the self. But from the self’s perspective, feeling transported
outward in perception actualizes the other and is the affect-founda-
180 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 181

tion of the mind in the other on which conceptuality develops. The but no feeling of any feelings enjoyed by the tree itself. This leads
other, as object and feeling, is derived from the conceptual feeling me to, in Buber’s terms, a purely I-It relation to the tree”. While
generated by the self. In the primitive response, in the drives, in there are those who are sensitive to the numinous quality of ordi-
pursuit, in fear or in love, we become aware of the shared feeling nary things, this reflects the common attitude. For most people,
that underlies subject and object, later self and other.15 the affective tonality of a tree is left behind in its journey outward.
The tree exteriorizes the conceptual feeling of the observer but
An explanation for the psychotic perception of a depersonal- for most observers, the concept is dominant and the object is per-
ized other is that constraints on the distal portion of the object- ceived as naked of intrinsic feeling. We sense this latent feeling
formation that shape the perception permit the object to be in the beauty of the tree, or in the feeling of the sublime. As with
seen as it is, but a brief retardation in the surge to definiteness trees, objects such as jewelry and clothing can be felt to have in-
permits a mentality that is ordinarily submerged in this develop- trinsic value. Many people would be confused if asked whether a
ment to become prominent. The external object is no longer felt jewel is intrinsically beautiful or valuable, or if its beauty and value
as detached but retains the mentality of its immediate ancestry. are attributes applied by the observer.16
The importance of psychosis is that it displays, in the suffering
of the afflicted, the true nature of mind. The onset of object- or In psychosis, the other recedes to its origins in the self.
reality-loss, i.e. de-realization, with loss of feeling in the other, i.e. Conversely, the self is felt to participate in the mind of the other,
de-personalization, may reflect the impact of a brief slowing (neo- which is no longer independent. Psychosis is the grief that comes
teny) at proximal segments in the object-formation. The adequate of true knowledge of the nature of things. Implicit phenomena
perception of object form reflects the shaping-effect of sensory that normally pass unnoticed come to the fore. There is erosion
constraints on the distal segment. Put differently, neoteny early of instinctual feeling, loss of conviction in the realness of ordinary
in the perceptual process (Brown, 1994) exposes phases of object- experience, a conceptuality of the external and an objectification
meaning and accentuated thought-content, while constraints at of the conceptual, all of which are part of the true knowledge —
later phases drive the object to veridicality. The object is seen as and horror — that the boundaries of mind and world are inexact.
it is, but it is laden with meaning and drained of affect. The other
does not become inanimate like a tree, for even a tree is emptied The nature of our knowledge of mind in others is a topic of de-
of feeling and deprived of realness. Once the realness of objects is bate in philosophy, but this awareness is tacitly in the background
lost, even inanimate ones, the object becomes image-like and the of everyday discourse and behavior, only becoming explicit when
person begins to doubt its reality or existence. feeling in the other is removed. The retreat from other into self
awakens the individual to the loss of what hitherto had not even
Griffen (1989) writes, “… in conscious sensory perception the been thought about. To become conscious of the automatic is to
emotional nature of the datum is largely lost. In seeing the tree bring the phenomenon into focus. The loss of an affective life in
before me, for example, I have a clear idea of the image of the tree others in the inward descent of feeling is a loss of their individuality
and realness. This alteration precedes or is the first stage of object-
15
The varied forms that feeling can take in desire, value, esteem, worth and so
loss. In this respect, it exposes the fragility of the world and how
on, and the relation to animate and inanimate objects and the evolutionary stage easily it can decompose. The person also intuits that in the normal
of the organism, are discussed in Brown (2005). The energic process in all enti-
ties, from electrons to minds, traces a subjective path to an actuality that perishes
as an object for an ensuing occasion, whether the fraction of a second in the hu- 16
Color may be intermediary. We feel the color red. It is a perception but closer
man mind or a billionth of a second for a sub-atomic particle (Griffin, 1989). This to feeling than its object. Since object boundaries are boundaries of hue, color
process, which is the Creativity of Whitehead, the energy or feeling that flows may signal the conceptual feeling that anticipates the object. In cortical blind-
through and creates all things, evolves to the higher feelings of developed organ- ness, color returns, e.g. as a diffuse perception of redness, prior to objects.
isms.
182 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 183

state, mind as feeling accompanies the other in an outward migra- given to us as a manifestation of the self. Self and world are center
tion from the self. The withdrawal of feeling as the initial stage in and periphery of an act of self-realization. Action is known largely
a passage down the object-formation, from value (realness) in the by its representation in perception. However, unlike perception,
other to desire (wish) in the self, elicits the image of a self as the which is a witness to change, action brings change about. In this
core of an orange gazing at the peel, with mind and world a “space way, in making contact with others, it is a bridge to decisiveness.
capsule” of personal imagery. As Whitehead (PR 45) wrote, “the In altering the world, action makes it real.
percipient occasion is its own standard of actuality”.
Freedom and effectuation seem to rupture the psychic bub-
ble. But a consciousness that is active or intentional implies the
recognition of limitations, not unfettered freedom, and the first
limitation is the shaping of perception to a verisimilitude that
7.3. The grounds of solipsism trumps the unrestrained imagination. Action specifies one ac-
In its most extreme expression, that only the thoughts and objects tuality among others. The world of perception is what remains
of the conscious self exist, solipsism is a clash of common sense after reality carves up possibility. The numbing familiarity of the
with speculative reason. In the less extreme form that we know world seems to impinge on the observer, who feels detached from
the objects of consciousness directly and those of physical nature his own objects. In dream, though we are passive to images, we
indirectly, the theory is less objectionable, though many are un- are astonished by what we create. Without agency, the waking or
comfortable with this formulation and seek a way out of what is dreaming self is helpless to the products of its own imagination.
conceded to be logically coherent theory. If solipsism is tied to the
Agency is a phase of choice in the transition from dream to
objects of consciousness, the notion, expressed by Santayana, that
object, from symbol to concept, from inner to outer, from the
it may characterize the mind of many animals misses the point
fantastic to the real. Choice is the novelty in a consciousness that
that the insularity of consciousness is the price of the individua-
strives to definiteness. It is positioned where the free-play of the
tion necessary to its realization. Solipsism is the understanding,
psyche conforms to the causal impersonality of the world. The si-
following James and Whitehead, that we live in a drop or pulse
multaneity and thickness of dream confront the contingency and
of conscious experience, and that this pulsation leads from the
serial order of wakefulness. Every act is conditioned by a past that
general or uniform to the precise and specific, to an end-point
delivers novel possibilities, not settled facts. Novelty begins with
of progressive individuation that begins with the separation of
a deviation in replication or an inaccuracy in recall. Memory is
subject and object. The difficulty arises in the opposition of self
not exact repetition. Even an eidetic with “photographic memory”
to world, even if one argues that the self is the outcome of an
has a mental image in recall, not an object. Thought is memory
individuation that traces to a ground of experiential relations in
to the degree it is reproductive; memory is thought to the extent
which all potential others are embedded. The recognition of this
it brings forth new material. Memory is not merely incomplete;
ground as the common source of individuality may be an antidote
it undergoes transformation (Betlheim and Hartmann, 1951).
to the solipsistic dilemma, but it lies beneath the individuation
Memories are re-shaped in the present, in the growth, decay and
that makes solipsism a problem.
assimilation of ancestral forms as they encounter sensory data.
There is a sense in which psychic confinement represents loss The immutability of the past is an abstraction. To a greater or
of freedom, or that true freedom can ultimately break through the lesser extent, the past conforms to the present as it is realized.
veil of an imaginary world. The solipsistic quandary is largely re- An implicit past is the major part of the present. In dream this is
lated to perception and the receptiveness that accompanies lack especially apparent when the propagation of affective and sym-
of agency. Hallucination and dream come unbidden. The world is
184 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 185

bolic forms actualizes categories that, in wakefulness, are shaped processual dynamic, and the feeling of reality is guaranteed by
to veridical objects. cross-modal coherence, in dream as in waking, physical entities
might well become mental solids in the act of their perception.
For some, findings in microphysics suggest that choice is the The theory holds that all entities including the brain are becom-
consciousness of a window into alternate universes of a multiplic- ings-into-being, dynamic in their actualization and substantive in
ity of possible selves. Some have claimed that phenomena such as their actuality.
déjà vu are intimations of divergent lines of existence. For such ac-
counts, the universe remains solipsistic, but each self and its world The micro-temporal recurrence from core to surface in the
are multiplied indefinitely, with all possible choices conceived as actualization of the mental state and the shift from unconscious
copies of selves that follow a separate life path. Each instant the to conscious perception or from dream to wakefulness, and the
psychic bubble partitions to a multitude of other selves, which reverse, the retreat back to the self and its antecedents in creative
then fractionate to a manifold of similarly insular minds. This way and mystical states (Chapter 12), is an evolutionary model of the
of thinking is compatible with microgenetic theory though not mind in which abundance is trimmed to precision. The coherence
necessitated by it. of the account depends on the impress of an inferential reality
in relation to which the mind is a model or representation. This
The microgenetic concept of phase-transitions that re-actual- coherence is itself a powerful argument for the existence of real-
ize self and world in epochs locates change in the laying down ity, not to mention that not even in the wildest dream could one
of momentary states. The theory provides neuropsychological create a world of such surprise and complexity. Searle (1980) has
detail to an idealist conception of overlapping surges of conscious written, “It is the operation of the brain and not the impact of the
experience. Each transition creates a world. Between transitions, outside world that matters for the content of our internal states.”
timeless gaps — virtual intervals — are the potential domicile of in- However, cutting all sensory input in animals results in loss of
numerable non-penetrating universes (Rees, 2000). It is one thing awareness. The free operation of the human brain deprived of
to hypothesize replications of the mind/brain each fraction of a sensory data from the outside world, e.g. in sensory-deprivation
second, and quite another to suppose that the unrealized choices studies, results in dream-like, even psychotic, states. Without sen-
in each replication multiply to billions of other lives in as many sation, mind would not develop at all, and dream, should it occur,
alternate universes. This is an extreme of solipsism in which each would be devoid of imagery. The question for solipsism is not the
self and self-specific consciousness think up a separate universe existence of a world beyond the psyche or the encapsulation of
that otherwise would not exist. In contrast to microgenesis, per- a mind through which a world is imagined, but the way mind is
sonal reality would be unconditioned by the choices of others, shaped by sensation and the true nature of reality outside of psy-
who are little more than simulacra that come and go in psychic chic experience.
time and space.

Either the outside world exists or it does not. If it exists, and if


the act of observation occasions the existence of an object, the in-
determinateness of physical process would materialize an object
in consciousness as a definite outcome. For example, if perceiving
a chair creates the chair, the wave-like flux of an unobserved chair
is transformed in perception to a particle-like substance one can
sit on. The dynamic possibilities in the career of a chair crystal-
lize to a palpable solid in the perceptual imagination. If mind is
an engine of category-formation, in which being is created by the
186 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 187

7.4. From here, where? embryonic mind is part of the process of nature that is modeled
in waking consciousness.
The case for solipsism is an example of philosophy arguing the
self-evident. Yet for those seeking a crack in the psychic module, Thought, self and perception originate in a deeper mutuality,
i.e. to escape the fate of even a neutral17 solipsism, there would such that progressive individuation and a movement to autonomy
seem to be (at least) two possibilities. The first involves grasping an reinforce the solipsistic impulse in life and thought. Unless the
externality that is antecedent to individuality, both in the growth problem is evaded by direct or naïve realism — justly naïve for
of mind and its momentary realization. In ceding the perceptible there is overwhelming evidence that perception is indirect — so-
world and withdrawing to a ground of primitive engagement, one lipsism is an unavoidable byproduct of the capacity of selves to
finds au fond an underlying commonalty with the precursors of think and act. The lament that in spite of our social bonds with
those objects to which one formerly was a spectator. This is the others, we live and die alone is a deep philosophical truth trans-
absolute or ultimate ground of things, what Sprigge has called the muted to a common emotion. It is little wonder that the alienation
“deep ground of connectedness”. In the language of physics, it of autonomy is a driving force behind the universal search for in-
conforms to the implicate order of Bohm and Hiley (1993). timacy and contact.

When such relatedness occurs with full absorption and aboli- A second path involves a monism at all phases in the brain
tion of self and a disappearance of concepts and psychic bound- state. On this view, mind and brain are manifestations of a funda-
aries, the knowledge of the true nature of individual mind, as mental process that flows through all reality, an all-in-all of mind
Schiller wrote, is a kind of death from which a return to life and and nature. This path takes a different route to the same relation-
consciousness is possible. Conceivably, the loss of self is equiva- ality as the prior option. The mental state is one with the brain
lent to animal mind at one with its Umwelt, though a deliberate state, which in turn is grounded in natural process. Brain activity
retreat to passivity accompanied by a mode of awareness that is second-hand knowledge filtered through the psyche. There is
can be transported back to consciousness, even if it remains in- little distance between the immediacy of thought and feeling and
effable, might distinguish the oneness of human descent from the subjectivity of the objects that are felt and thought about. The
the minds of lower organisms. The metaphysical relatedness that gap is from mind and its objects to the physical process they ex-
underlies the contrasts, dissociations and analyses of conscious emplify. A reduction of mind to brain is merely a replacement of
thought is a oneness that nullifies individuality, small consolation subjective experience by its objectified contents.
for avoiding solipsism. An escape from solipsism that abandons
consciousness is less a refuge from autonomy than an affirmation If we keep in mind that the identification of the mental state
that consciousness is an iron-clad cage. To lose the self for union with the brain state does not apply just to its vegetative core but
with the extra-psychic is to achieve a cure by eliminating an illness to every phase in transition, i.e. that mental activity is mediated
but in this case the malady is consciousness, and the retreat to an by neocortex as well as by brain stem, a retreat to the core is not
objectless non-self, a state of existence unified with the physical a closer approach to the physical than an absorption with the
surround, is an abdication of personhood. It is the emptiness of a neural correlates of the final object. The only difference is that,
death-like state, or a dreamless sleep, in exchange for an illusion in the former, the dissolution of consciousness results in a loss
that is a shroud of the unreal. In the depths of the unconscious, of knowledge of the encapsulation of psyche. If the mental state
arises in rhythmic oscillators in hypothalamus or upper brain
stem as a complexly individuated portion of natural process, i.e.
a physiological node in the absolute, further individuation would
17
A neutral solipsism, unlike an extreme form, accepts insularity but does not
deny the existence of an extra-psychic reality; indeed, it presumes an external not distance consciousness from nature, but only elaborate a
world as the basis for its illusory representation. consciousness that apprehends the distance it has created. The
188 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 189

correlates of organism that lead from immersion to refinement or is a categorical prime antecedent to its exemplifications, either to
from unconscious integration to conscious autonomy are bound sub-categories or concrete facts, which are categories that actual-
to physical process at every phase. ize objects. We think of ideals as the conscious goals toward which
we are striving. But if ideals play a role in mental life they must be
Like the leaves of a tree, objects in the mind are no less part coordinate with the categorical primes that enfold and generate
of nature than the root. As the root is the origin and source of the their exemplifications. The particulars realize and exhaust the po-
canopy, conscious mind develops out of an unconscious that, like tential subsumed in the universal as approximations to an ideal.
the root, seems embedded in nature while the leaves, like ideas, If we strive for beauty or loyalty, these values generate the striv-
seem to ascend heavenward in abandon. The transition from un- ing, while the acts to which they lead are their exemplifications.
conscious core to conscious surface is not a journey from nature The ideal or universal is not before us beckoning us onward but
to mind, but from unconscious mind to conscious nature. If the behind or within us pressing us forward. Thus, particulars satisfy
onset of the state in the physiological unconscious seems to have ideals but do not achieve them. The relation of ideal or universal
a proximity to non-conscious nature, so too does its conscious to particular or exemplification is that of potential to actual, of
termination in the objects of the world. The mid-segment of the concept to object, or idea to implementation. This way of thinking
process is associated with the conscious self as a unique psychic informs an account of intentionality as the trajectory of an act of
phenomenon that apprehends the sources, outcomes and choic- thought over its temporal extensibility.
es — the posterior unconscious and the anterior world — from a
midway point in this transition. The brain is an organism of extraordinary complexity, a com-
plexity that does not increase to allow for cognitive advance but
The whole-to-part pattern of the process is, for me, reminiscent is generated by a progression to greater articulation combined
of arguments by Whitehead and Santayana (Sprigge, 1974) that with expansion of antecedent form, i.e. the growth of parts out
“the nature of a particular thing consists wholly in the universals of wholes. The adaptation drives the complexity necessary for its
which it exemplifies (and therefore cannot contain intrinsic refer- realization, not the reverse. An increase in complexity without
ence to any other particular things)”. The universal is the back- pattern does not account for novel formations. The challenge of
ground of its exemplifications and conveys into them its essence, an evolutionary materialism is not to reduce the complexity of
i.e. the particulars convey or express the ‘stuff” of the universals mind and behavior to physical cause and effect but to enlarge the
they instantiate, and do not relate to other particulars by way of scope of a process-based materialism as a foundation for increas-
internal relations. Like the arbor of a tree, particulars in the mind ing complexity.
seem to reach out into space from a buried core of connected-
ness; but the transition in process monism from root to leaf, from The thesis of process monism is that mind and brain emanate
core to object, or from generality to individuality, points to differ- from a universal process of evolutionary change. Brain activity
ing manifestations of the physical patterns that underlie material underlying mental events is generated by patterns continuous
entities and psychic phenomena. with those in evolution. The population dynamic of evolution is
replicated in the pattern of individual cognition. In evolutionary
In mapping the microgenetic model of the mind/brain to advance, the mind/brain articulates categories that fit and adapt
cerebral infrastructure, one might suppose that a universal cor- to, and thus are determined or shaped by, a given physical reality.
responds with the potential of a core and a particular with its The concept of evolution is not just a theory; it is a pre-condition of
realization at the cortical surface. If the mental state collapses all theory in physics, biology, cognition and theology. The transi-
without remainder to the brain state, how are we to characterize tion from pre-atomic, to atomic, to molecular and more complex
universals other than as ancestral categories from which sub-cat- unities corresponds with the transition from energy to simple
egories (particulars) of greater specificity emanate? The universal
190 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 191

feelings, tropisms, drives and, eventually, consciousness and in- ity, but all we can know is whether experience fits the subjective
tentionality. The evolutionary pattern is apparent at all stages and ecology in which it occurs; in theory, in the environment or in a
in all spheres of physical and psychic activity. scientific model. We know this by adaptive success, i.e. survival,
not by correspondence.

The gap from psychic representation to physical reality is a zone


of mystery that is the ground of creativity and religious imagina-
7.5. Solipsism and reality tion. Spirit flourishes in the shadow of the real. There will always be
The logic of solipsism contradicts the ordinary belief that exter- incompleteness in scientific truth, since the psychic only approxi-
nal reality is identical with the facts of perception, and that we mates the real. The deepest aesthetic is not the creativity within
interact with objects and others in a mind-independent world. this virtual space but an uncovering of its laws. Whitehead (1933)
The argument that we are locked in a mental chamber, perceiving wrote, “the type of truth required for the final stretch of Beauty is
and acting on our own mental images challenges the ingrained a discovery and not a recapitulation.” This stretch leads from con-
belief that the outside world exists much as we perceive it, that cepts to the reality toward which they are groping. The gap from
it continues to exist during sleep and will continue long after we dream to perception is like that from perception to the real. The
are gone. It is said that one ought not deny in philosophy what limit of what is knowable has dream and the unconscious on one
is affirmed in the heart, but the claims of idealism and the rep- side and noumenal reality on the other. Unconscious precursors
resentational theory of the mind go against the common sense of conscious objects are infused with feeling and imagination, but
presumption of direct perception and a world of real objects. An the real is always one step beyond our reach.
extreme solipsism — not the neutral form — asks us to deny the
Soul and other forms of spirit are not of mind or matter. They
belief that we act on, perceive and engage a world of real physical
may be conceived as products of the imagination or as real enti-
entities. Such beliefs are acts of faith that trace to mechanisms
ties in nature, but in truth they inhabit a nether world between
related to survival, which are then conditioned by early-acquired
the cognitive and the physical. The belief in spirits is not to be
values, dispositions and the inheritance of the drives.
dismissed as superstitious thinking that will fade as scientific data
One should not confuse illusion with delusion. We may be accumulates. The persistence of such beliefs in spite of scientific
deluded in thinking that an illusory world is real, but the illusion advance is a sign that materialism has not absorbed the full im-
of the world is not itself a delusion, only the belief in its reality. In pact of an evolutionary continuity of form. Uncertainty as to the
the dream of an ordinary life we are in the grip of many illusions existence or exact nature of the real is the lure of scientific effort,
that we take as established facts (Vaihinger, 1924; Brown, 2004). but it also adds numinous quality to the cycle of personal exis-
Illusion refers to appearance, or to the non-real or non-physical. It tence.
can also apply to indirect knowledge of the world. Even a perfect
adaptation — because it is pruned to fitness — is not a substitute
for the real but a Rorschach or negative of the entity to which it
refers. Illusion is often contrasted with truth; but a deeper truth 7.6. Other minds
can be missed when truth is conceived as pragmatic or empirical
utility in adaptation (James). One should not think of illusion only The logic and consequence of solipsism imply an inability to know
as distortion, though it may be, or as error or false perception, the external world; they do not exclude the presumption that an
which is also a definition, but as a point of limitation. The truths external world exists. The postulate that only immediate thought
of psychic experience may correspond to those of physical real- and perception are knowable, or the claim that to exist is to be per-
192 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 193

ceived, asserts that only occurrent thought and perception exist the belief in spirits, ghosts, demons and gods, most of which do
and that reality is an idea in the mind (Berkeley). The conclusion not inhabit bodies. If the belief in spirits is an accentuation, exten-
that the observed world is psychic does not strike down indirect sion or precursor of the belief in other minds, a belief in other
knowledge of the physical nor lead to the isolation of self and the minds may not be predicated on the existence of other people.
annihilation of others. A neutral solipsism accepts that knowledge Put differently, we assume a person is required before a mind can
of the physical world is inferential, or rather substitutive, in that be inferred, but the common belief in spirits indicates that it is not
veridical objects or concepts stand for real entities, since objects in necessary to have a body (or any substrate) to infer a mind.
normal perception mirror physical entities. It can be argued that
as the physical is modeled in the psychic, the psychic is modeled Malcolm (1958) wrote that a rigorous solipsism ought to hold
in the physical; i.e. physical entities have psychic or proto-psychic that the thought there is “thinking or pain other than my own is
properties. The psychic veil that obscures a vision of the physical unintelligible”. A solipsism of this type is autistic or psychotic. The
is then the source of a panpsychism in metaphysical speculation. argument that we cannot know the external world does not imply
its non-existence. Indeed, it insures this fact as an explanation of
We assume or are conscious of the fact that mind is present in the sources of individual mind. Thought is trial action. We hypoth-
others. In the perceptions of psychotics, people without a mind esize all sorts of imaginary objects, scenarios, and n-dimensional
are automatons. This implies that automatons are perceived di- spaces, constantly testing the reality of the imperceptible.
rectly, whereas minds are inferred, say by analogy with our own.
The existence of another person is comparable to that of any ob- When psychic experience does not conform to the physical
ject, but the existence of a mind in that person is presumed to be world, survival is in danger. Pain misidentified or mislabeled is as
secondary. An inference is involved in philosophical accounts or dangerous as the misidentification of a snake. As a signal of inter-
uncertain cases such as whether a computer can be said to have a nal or external danger, pain leads to adaptive behavior: external
mind. In everyday life, this is less an inference than an implicit act pain to avoidance and action; internal pain to immobility. Malcolm
of faith that depends not on reason but on “coping mechanisms” wrote that correct and incorrect have no application to inner iden-
that arise in the animal inheritance. The belief in an external tification. It is true that a judgment of the truth of an internal state
world is an example of what Santayana called animal faith. The is not the currency on which the state is decided, but someone
belief in god is an example of human faith. Many acquired beliefs who confuses pain and hunger would not survive unattended.
such as those of religion, depend on primitive modes of thought, Children with congenital insensitivity to pain must be carefully
e.g. animism, that develop on an instinctual basis. watched. The argument (of Malcolm, after Wittgenstein) rests on
an external standard, but the “external standard” is coping and
Innate belief in the existence of the world underlies the belief survival. The only “standard” is successful adaptation when the
in other minds, which depends on or is secondary to the belief in maladaptive has been eliminated.
an external world. First, there is the reality of other people, then
other minds. Animal faith includes the implicit belief that other Wittgenstein’s critique hinges less on the existence, than the
objects exist. Human faith includes the implicit (and explicit) inability to guarantee the correctness of, inner states. Inner states
belief that other minds exist. The belief in other minds probably do not have a character sufficient for assessment until they ex-
develops out of primate social behavior, in which “intentions” ternalize. Is this mere consensus, and if so, is consensus not the
are read off facial expressions and other gestures. Psychologists same problem multiplied? Is it possible that a mental phenom-
claim this inference appears in children around age 5, but my son enon such as pain could be misidentified? In rare brain disorders,
Ilya, at 3, liked to tease other people. Teasing in a child suggests a patients do not recognize pain as painful, or they acknowledge
“theory” of mind. The belief in other minds is probably allied to pain but ignore its noxious quality. This is not misidentification
but a separation of painful feeling (and affective response) from
194 Jason W. Brown

the feeling of pain. Similar responses occur in hypnosis. One can


harbor wrong beliefs about intra-psychic phenomena so long as
one does not act on them. The problem of verification for inner
states is of the same type as for objects. Concepts become objects
in a process of objectification. Coherence shifts to correspondence
as the object moves outward, a difference only in the degree of
externalization.
Chapter 8
Microgenetic Theory of the Unconscious
1. Philosophy, Psychology and
Psychoanalysis

“Consciousness is not a quiescent state, but a process


— a continual becoming-conscious.”
E. von Hartmann (1868)

This chapter discusses the basis for the idea of the Ucs and its
implications for theory of mind, as well as accounts of the Ucs in
philosophical psychology. 18 The chapter also reviews the concept
of the atomic trace, the notion of cathexis and repression, the
searchlight theory, the copy theory of memory and its relation to
current accounts of focal attention. It concludes with the assertion
that the psychoanalytic model and other accounts of the Ucs are
inconsistent with studies in clinical research and case pathology.
Instead, Ucs cognition is characterized by a sequence of catego-
ries (wholes) that partition to instances (parts), which then serve
as wholes for the next wave of whole-part transformation. This
argument is taken up in detail in the ensuing chapter.

After some period of neglect, the topic of Csness is back in


fashion as each discipline — physics, molecular biology, computa-
tional psychology, and so on — offers a theory unique to its field.
While Csness would seem to presuppose an Ucs, as what is not yet
conscious Cs) or its underpinnings, there has been little discussion
of the philosophy of the Ucs, its relation to Csness in human mind
and that of other organisms. Although the philosophical roots of
the concept are early, the first systematic study of the Ucs was the
treatise of Hartmann (1868/1931).

18
The abbreviations in this paper are: Conscious(ness) = Cs(ness), Unconscious
= Ucs
198 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 199

Prior to Freud, the Ucs19 was characterized in fairly general and The discovery of the Ucs is in some ways the transfer to mind of
non-psychic terms, but since the Project, the paper on the Ucs, and the invisible in nature, extending the Platonic tradition that seen
the Interpretation of Dreams, mechanisms such as cathexis and things are temporal, those unseen are eternal, or that an unseen
repression, operations such as the dreamwork, and contents such world of unchanging reality lies behind the flux of conscious phe-
as hallucination and symbolic imagery, have been postulated as nomena. When this unseen, non-temporal world is displaced to
ingredient in Ucs structure. Mechanisms and processes constitute mind from its relation to object-Csness, one has the timelessness
one — physical — level of explanation; Ucs ideas, representations and universality of the physical Ucs. The shift is from a physical
or symbols another. The notion of psychic events in the Ucs is tak- world beyond perception to a psychic world inside its objects. To
en by some as a valid description of actual phenomena; for others, the extent this hidden world is the sphere of spirit, it is transitional
the Ucs is a literary invention of causal relations — originating or from physical nature to mind. The effort to penetrate the physical
intermediate — by which otherwise inexplicable wake and sleep ground of Cs phenomena took a great step in Freud’s chart of Ucs
happenings can be interpreted. Others argue for Ucs “presenta- experience.
tions” on the basis of psychophysical theory.
There is such overwhelming evidence of Ucs cognition inferred
The writer on the Ucs labors under the burden that the topic is, from its Cs products that to deny its occurrence is either a refusal
by definition, outside the scope of Cs thought. Many philosophers to address the origins of Cs thought, or taking the indefensible
since Descartes have believed that while Csness is knowable expe- position that all thought arises in Csness. Every Cs thought has im-
rience, the non-Cs, as in animal mind, is mechanism. Mill wrote mediate precursors that are not prior Cs contents. Apart from the
that Csness involves psycho-physical structure, the Ucs only physi- antecedents of Cs thought, this includes the problem of dream,
cal structure. Searle similarly argues that the Ucs is mere physiol- hypnotic and mystical states, waking and Ucs creativity, creativity
ogy. For some philosophers, the Ucs does not even exist. If the Ucs during dream and/or transitional states21, myth, non-intentional
is timeless, as Hartmann (1868) and Freud claimed, it could not moods or objectless states such as anxiety, unresolved conflict,
exist, for excepting the speculation on timeless or eternal objects drive, motivation, as well as sleepwalking and other dissociative
or ideas, timeless entities are changeless, thus non-existent.20 The states, “slips of the tongue”22, obsessions and compulsions, not
central problems are whether the Ucs consists of neural process to mention the whole “storehouse” of grammar, memory, beliefs
with or without psychic correlates, the nature of such correlates if and values that account for Cs thought, acts, objects and language.
they exist and, if not, an account of phenomena that point to an There are also experimental probes of non-Cs processes, such as
Ucs origin, and the transition from simultaneity to temporal order masking (e.g. Marcel, 1983), tachistoscopic presentation (percept-
as Ucs phases pass to Cs ones. genetic and related studies, e.g. Smith, 1989), priming, learning
during anesthesia, split-brain cases, incidental and procedural
learning, conditioning, habit and skill formation. To dismiss the
Ucs as physiology is a mere negation that sidesteps an account of
the transition to Csness, immediate precursors and evolutionary
19
The Ucs merges into the subconscious and preconscious. These terms have
varied meanings, that include: the ambient fringe of Csness, the subliminal prior
to Csness, the storehouse of memory, etc., an organized self and personality
beneath Csness, and so on (e.g. Munsterberg et al, 1910). Each of these “planes” 21
See Lowes’ (1927) account of Ucs work in the poetry of Coleridge (Koestler,
of cognition can find a place in a theory of becoming. 1964 and other examples).
20
The timelessness of an eternal truth is that it is always true, not that it exists 22
Of note in relation to the ensuing discussion of errors in brain damage, the
timelessly. An entity that becomes timeless as it perishes also becomes non-ex- idea of slips of the tongue developed on Freud’s observation of aphasic errors,
istent. The passage to and from timelessness requires an existent to develop into though he considered the account of aphasic errors irrelevant to the more color-
and out of non-existence. ful interpretations of the slips.
200 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 201

ancestry. However, if the Ucs is known only on becoming Cs, and of inner objects. Though objects independent of the organism are
if every description of the Ucs is an inference on the predecessors feared, devoured or enjoyed, it is unlikely there is awareness of a
of Cs experience, what can be said non-inferentially of a psychic subject-object relation. It is more likely that higher mammals per-
Ucs? The first step, it seems to me, is a decision as to how the Ucs ceive a world much as we do, each with its own object categories,
is to be conceptualized. yet they do not gaze in wonder at the evening sky or, so far as we
know, have aesthetic responses to sunsets and flowers. Except for
What I mean by this is whether there are such things as Ucs play in juveniles, which is instinct-driven trial and error learning,
ideas or representations. The question is not dissimilar from that the expression of subtler emotions, such as grief, is probably an
of animal awareness, in which the matter of psychic experience instinctual reaction, e.g. to separation, that bears a superficial re-
is unresolved. While animals in the same class — dogs, bears, etc. semblance to human experience. Animals do not appear to enjoy
— may show different “personalities” with respect to characteris- objects that are not targets of immediate utility or preparations for
tics such as shyness or aggressiveness and exhibit behavior that is action. Perhaps animal awareness is similar to what Piaget called
purposeful, there is no evidence for the occurrence of inner states the object- and activity-awareness of small children.
resembling those of humans. We assume that the “loyalty” of dogs
or their “grief” on loss of their master, like the “isolation” cry of a A distinction can be made between grades of animal aware-
separated baby monkey is a physical reaction based on instinctual ness up to a certain threshold, but human Csness can have animal
attachments. The inferred mental correlates of such behaviors are awareness as its object. An Ucs that has awareness as a goal but
symptoms of anthropomorphic distress when reason is trumped not Csness as an outcome is impoverished and likely character-
by empathy. The use of tools by animals, the findings of imitation, ized by object-categories that are the aims of drives. The lack of
expectancy, even inference, though perhaps on an evolutionary complexity in categorical structure is confirmed by the stimulus-
continuum with human cognition, do not establish the presence boundness and predictability of behavior, as well as in the patho-
of psychic events no more than the search by a dog for a buried logical data. For example, errors in children with developmental
bone, or a monarch butterfly migrating to the tree of its birth, is language disorders show simplifications that are repeated within
evidence of an intentional state in which the dog or butterfly is Cs a narrow range.
of the bone or the branch it is searching for.
Among the questions that impact on the concept of the Ucs,
In humans, Cs ideation supposes Ucs forerunners that are in- one is continuity or discontinuity in the growth of mind. Selves
ferred to have psychic correlates. Even if Ucs forerunners are as- have knowledge of subjective states of ongoing Csness but in-
sumed to be strictly physiological, the differences and specificities ner experience is inferred by other selves, or in animal behavior.
of states that are causally relevant to Cs outcomes from those that Mentality in animals would seem to be required in the evolution
are not cry out for psychic labels. Thoughts and memories resist of mind from the primitive to the developed, or a progression
explanation in terms of a causal chain from one idea in Csness to from the automatic to the voluntary. If Csness emerges from com-
the next. When Cs idea A leads to Cs idea B, we attribute psychic plexity, is this true for the Ucs? If there is continuity, how far down
correlates to the neural states underlying the sequence, but when does it go and, if not to the foundational constructs, at what point
Cs idea B does not have a definite Cs antecedent, the Ucs physiol- do psychic features appear? Microgenetic theory takes a position
ogy that is evoked merely strips off the psychic and muddies the consistent with that of Ward (1933), who wrote that mental pro-
explanatory step. cess is “a partial segmentation of what is originally continuous
rather than an aggregation of elements at first independent and
In animals, except for sleep and/or dream, there is no obvious distinct… (a) totum objectivum or objective continuum which is
gap between Cs and Ucs experience, so all experience — correctly gradually differentiated”.
or not — is inferred to lack awareness of self, of subjectivity and
202 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 203

8.1. Some philosophical problems in the state. Alternatively, if psyche is non-reducible, mind appears ei-
ther when neural systems evolve to support it or there is a psy-
psychology of the Ucs chic aspect to physical elements at the earliest pre-organic stages.
The idea of the Ucs and its transition to Csness has many philo- Simply put, the sequence from particle to brain is all physical, all
sophical ancestors, notably Leibnitz, who introduced the notion psychic, or the physical possesses proto-psychic features, with
of strength or intensity in the capacity of petites perceptions or Csness appearing at some point in the physical sequence, by a
slumbering ideas to become Cs. The idea of the Ucs is also found gradual or radical emergence.
in the German Idealists, notably Kant. Eduard Von Hartmann
(1868/1931) began his great study of the topic with a citation While pan-psychism is consistent with an evolutionary pro-
from Kant (Anthropology, sec. 5): “To have ideas, and yet not be gression from preliminary to advanced states of Csness, the pre-
conscious of them, — there seems to be a contradiction in that; ponderant opinion is that the precursors of Csness do not extend
for how can we know that we have them, if we are not conscious “all the way down” but that Csness arises at some level of neuro-
of them? Nevertheless, we may become aware indirectly that we nal complexity. This assumes a lack of complexity or order to ac-
have an idea, although we be not directly cognizant of the same”. count for marginal states or degrees of Csness, from sleep, dream,
Hegel believed Csness to be a modified form of Ucs structure with diffuse awareness, distractibility and fatigue to full lucidity. The
psychic experience. He wrote of a “nightlike abyss within which presumption is: (1) that Ucs states inter alia are insufficiently
a world of infinitely numerous images and presentations is pre- complex to generate Csness; (2) and/or that psychic accompani-
served without being in Csness (Mills, 2002).” ments in the transition to Csness dissolve in the transformation
to ensuing phases; (3) and/or that Ucs psychic experience cannot
The philosophy of the Ucs, to the extent there is one, is an be remembered; i.e. as in dream, it is a fugitive experience forgot-
offshoot of a theory of Csness. The problem of a psychic Ucs is ten on its occurrence; and/or (4) Ucs categories do not specify an
secondary to that of psyche generally; how mental phenomena identifiable content. The question for materialism is if Csness is
and Csness arise in relation to brain and evolution. Ucs experi- physiology, like the Ucs, what features of Cs and Ucs physiology
ence supposes mind without Csness, and raises the more general explain the occurrence of psychic phenomena in the former but
question of psychic properties in physical matter, or panpsychism, not the latter?
which entails a world of mind or spirit or proto-psychic proper-
ties in basic entities. If the psychic is not a compounding of the The philosopher of zombie-mind reduces mentation to brain
physical to some threshold where Csness is possible, it must be an process; we behave as if (or have the delusion that) we are Cs.
incipient feature, ab origo. The description of proto-psychic prop- Zombies or robots are not Cs in the usual sense; in a robot, apart
erties in elementary particles is an alternative to all-mind and all- from the distinction of output and material elements, there is no
matter. So is emergentism. But if emergents are genuine novelties difference in Cs and Ucs experience. Indeed, there is no experi-
they defy causal laws, constitute a break in the evolution of the ence, only information, though some would conflate the two.
mental from the physical, rupture physics and mind and provide Zombie-mind is the terminus of a materialism that collapses
an entry point for soul and spirit. mental phenomena to brain as an expedient in physicalist theory.
For microgenesis and process theory, the mental evolves with the
For materialism, the evolution of the brain is physical; mind physical by an expansion of proto-psychic features.
is an insider’s view of an objective description of brain function.
First-person or subjective accounts are untestable, thus incoher- One consequence of a continuity of psychic experience in a
ent from a scientific point of view. An account of the brain events transition from the Ucs to Csness, or a continuum to human mind
involved in an act of cognition exhausts the description of the from lower forms, is panpsychism (Clarke, 2004) with a continu-
ous development of mind over the organic series, arising in the
204 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 205

most elementary “bits” of matter. The possibility of degrees of language the human mind resembles animal awareness, assumes
Csness in plants, insects and animals entails the incorporation of that pre-Cs human awareness and animal awareness are equiva-
proto-psychic features in physical entities that are fundamental lent.
to nature. If Csness evolves out of stages of Ucs experience, and a
transition over Ucs phases is necessary for Csness, the Ucs, or the If animals without human Csness can be said to have psychic
primitive Csness of animals, would provide a forecast of human experience — a dog in pain, a worm on a hook — is this a mode of
Csness. Is the Ucs an active process in the human mind that gen- Cs or Ucs experience? Are Cs and Ucs distinguished by features
erates Csness or an inactive storehouse of automatic procedures? other than wakefulness and verbalization? If one dreams one is in
Is there Ucs assimilation and growth of once-Cs perceptual traces? pain, is this Csness of pain? Is dream a mode of Csness? The same
Is the Ucs a collection of mechanisms for language, perception question arises in humans as in animals, e.g. a person in a vegeta-
and so on, or a mode of cognition antecedent to Cs thought? Is tive state who withdraws and grimaces with painful stimulation.
the Ucs prior to or derived from, i.e. secondary to, Csness, or do How does one determine the occurrence of inner feeling or pain-
Cs and Ucs develop together? Some would have it that the Ucs is Csness, indeed, of any internal content that does not in some way
created by Csness, for what is “in the Ucs” must first pass through manifest itself? The behavioral manifestations suggest the animal
Csness. On this way of thinking, memorial contents in Csness are is in pain, but this cannot be said of a person who is in a vegeta-
copies of Ucs traces deposited in Cs perception. tive state.23 Most neurologists assume the reactions are reflexes
without subjective experience. If one claims a lower organism is
There are more questions than answers in this area and each in pain but not that it is Cs, what is the nature of Ucs or non-Cs
question is the seed of new theory. If animals are not Cs in the hu- pain? If the pain of a dog is a psychic experience, e.g. a feeling, and
man sense, are they, in the human sense, Ucs? Are there similari- the dog is not Cs in the human sense, would one say the psychic
ties between Ucs human mind and waking animal awareness? If experience of pain is Ucs or just not Cs? In the transition from the
contents in the Ucs are derived from Cs experience, and animals deep Ucs of dreamless sleep and coma to acute Csness, are the
are not Cs in the human sense, how would we compare their Ucs Cs and Ucs contingent on each other? Presumably, Cs mind could
to that of humans? If animals have an Ucs or its equivalent, as not exist without the Ucs, but what is the difference between the
is likely if they dream, does it arise, as assumed by the continu- obligatory activity of the Ucs during a state of Csness and Ucs ac-
ity thesis, from the “psychic potential” of instincts and tropisms tivity when Csness is lacking? Are there transitional states from
in lower life forms? For microgenetic theory, the forming object Ucs to Cs mind, such as a pre-Cs phase?
traverses planes of long-term memory and, with forgetting, lapses
into the imagery revived in dream. On this view, a Cs perception
does not deposit Ucs memory but individuates archaic configura-
tions of past experience in becoming an object, i.e. we remember
an object into perception. 8.2. The Ucs and human mind
The problem of pain illustrates a wider problem with theories of
The machine-view of animal awareness entails continuation the Ucs, especially psychoanalysis (see below), in that the account
to human Csness as an extension of brain physiology. If the Ucs of the Ucs is modeled after that of Csness so that Ucs pain or, if
(or automatic) in animals or a waking state of animal awareness
lacks the potential for Csness in the animal, but anticipates hu- 23
Evidence of meaning detection in cases of vegetative states using evoked
man Csness, the arousal or awareness of animal Ucs would be the
potential methods (Kotchoubey, 2005) are comparable to other techniques, such
ground of human Csness. The argument that human Csness is as priming, masking, blindsight, conditioning, split-brain studies, and so on, that
created in the acquisition of language, or conversely, that without access Ucs meaning. If there is Ucs meaning, can there be Ucs pain, and if so,
what would it be like?
206 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 207

one considers this an oxymoron, Ucs thought, memory, etc., are Presumably, the Ucs in an animal without human-like Csness
assumed to be qualitatively identical to what is in Csness except would not have a subterranean character. There would be no un-
that they are Ucs. The inability to describe what may be Ucs pain Cs or sub-Cs in animal awareness, which would be Ucs only in
(idea, image) is evident in certain forms of pathology. There are relation to human Csness. The awareness of animals conceived as
cases of brain lesion in humans in which pain is experienced the equivalent of the human Ucs is an artifice, if the Ucs is defined
but not responded to, such as “pain asymbolia”. This applies to in relation to Csness, though the mental states of animals, e.g.
somatic pain but also loud noises and annoying visual stimuli. primates, may resemble the waking object- and activity-aware-
A person with frontal lobotomy for chronic pain may have pain ness of infants and young children. In higher animals, with brains
that has lost its noxious quality. He says he is in pain but has similar to those of humans, a behavior or an act of cognition must
none of the behavioral criteria associated with a painful state. A involve a traversal of categories. If so, the Ucs of animals is not
similar reaction occurs in hypnotic states. Painless surgery can sheer mechanism, since patterns of category-formation, even if
be performed in people under hypnosis. Patients have told me the categories differ, should not depart markedly from those of
of dreams they had pain that, months later, became Cs signs of human thought.
illness. It is possible to be Cs of pain but not bothered by it. It is
possible to display emotion without having it, and possible to have In man, Csness depends on the separation of subject and ob-
emotion without being able to display it. Assuming that pathology ject, then self and other. The detachment of an independent world
does not cleave apart phenomena that are inextricably bound, leaves a subjective world behind for the psychic accompaniments
if Csness and behavior dissociate, as they do in other situations, of Cs and Ucs thought. An animal without a subject-object distinc-
such as pathological laughing and crying, sham rage, implicit and tion is embedded like a plant in its Umwelt. Insects, fish, reptiles
explicit memory, the dissociation of knowing and doing in frontal and birds are like this. There is little sign of autonomy or subjec-
cases, etc., what does this mean for inferring a state of feeling, or tive boundaries. When this boundary first appears is uncertain.
any inner state, from behavior? The subjective is too rich and the We do not know how to characterize the subject-object relation in
mind too complex for externalist theories. animals, but this distinction is a critical first step in the evolution
of object-Csness. A subject is distinct from the objects of percep-
While it is unsettled as to whether the human Ucs, apart from tion, but a self is Cs of both inner and outer objects.
language, is comparable to that of animals, there are major dif-
ferences between human and animal cognition that may not be
uniquely dependent on language. These include the occurrence
of a now or present moment that creates a theater for the Csness
of inner and outer events, and a past in relation to a memory that 8.3. Psychic “properties” of inorganic entities
can be revived in present Csness, not just implemented in learn- One critique of the continuity thesis is that physical entities do
ing. The immediacy of the knife-edge present of dream may pre- not have properties of the type associated with mental states.
figure the waking now or be a residue of its duration. Humans are Increasing complexity in a physical system does not alone explain
likely the only animals with a Cs present, a self and a remembered Csness. Subjectivity expands in the temporal extensibility of enti-
past. Unlike animals, the human Ucs elaborates a dream self in ties and complexity increases to fill it. Increasing complexity in
relation to images (Brown, 2005; 2008). An Ucs defined in relation brain activity as the basis of Csness is no more than a platitude
to Csness, as what is not Cs, is conceived as a furnace for Cs idea unless the configural properties of processes underlying the com-
and emotion, or its infrastructure and preparatory stage. plexity are clarified. It is often assumed that complexity reaches
a point where novel behaviors emerge, but the concept of emer-
gence, like that of complexity, lacks explanatory power without
208 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 209

an account of the pattern and fine structure of the emergent step. type. The evolution of atom to brain is conceptually similar to the
Still, the notion of emergence is in synch with holism and process transition from physiological trace to Cs memory. In both, parts
theory. How mind arises in a physical brain is not comprehensible (atoms, traces) expand to wholes in which the nature of the whole
if the physical (or mental) is conceived as the sum of its parts. To is not forecast in the parts. Csness does not arise from the contri-
add up the inventory of parts for a car and the plan for its assem- butions in miniature of a multiplicity of static constituents, but
bly might satisfy its description but one does not go for a drive in evolves out of an interior dynamic.
a plan or inventory. The same is true for a brain, which unlike a
car is a coherent whole. Penfield once remarked that alteration The transition from physical matter to brain viewed as a physi-
of function with brain damage is like trying to determine what cal system is, from an evolutionary standpoint, equivalent to the
is missing from a symphony when a violin is removed from the “transition” from brain to Csness. In the former, the progression
string section. Holistic systems are unified, adaptive and self-orga- from the primitive to the complex remains within the physical. In
nizing, not piecemeal constructions. the latter, there is a gap in the passage to (and from) the mental.
This gap can be avoided by positing psychic features at all stages,
A compilation of proto-psychic properties of basic elements in with a compounding of the proto-psychic to a progressively wider
a complex system such as a brain cannot explain human menta- sphere. One proto-psychic feature with the potential to evolve is
tion. Even if a brain vastly multiples the proto-psychic features of energy as the process-ground of feeling, which is the process (be-
single particles or monadic isolates, this might just give more of coming) that lays down the substance (being) of entities in recur-
the same “stuff”. A pile of marbles is still a pile of marbles. Csness rent cycles.
may or may not obligate emergence, but it does require a coher-
ence of organic wholes not predicted by properties of elementary Wholes are created in the coming-together of quanta that rep-
units. Indeed, the very concept of an atomic unit negates growth licate the activity of parts. This is the graded outcome of feeling
and change. Most of what transpires in life and mind — in dream as it expands intrinsic relations within the temporal extensibility
and waking imagery as in happiness and love — is outside the of entities. A qualitative transformation of feeling underlies the
province of logic, so it would be premature to enthrone a logic quantities of physical science. Feeling is the “glue” of unity. At each
of solid entities as the lord of observation when logic itself is stage, unity in a complex system such as a mind/brain can no
opaque to novelty and the elements on which it works may be more be decomposed to elements than predicted from them. The
wrongly decided. A re-combination of atoms is not inconsistent becoming of an element evolves to “societies” as feeling expands
with evolutionary theory but incomplete as an explanation of the the duration of individualities and pushes complexity ever further.
appearance of novel systems, especially when they are more com- A beginning with physics and a science of material entities cannot
plex than the units of which they are composed. One molecule of reach (explain) Csness without an emergent step. However, to be-
H20 is not liquid, nor can liquidity readily be predicted from the gin with Csness and descend to particles retains mind all the way
properties of a molecule. In organic entities, societies of particu- through and recovers the proto-psychic in patterns unimaginable
lars enjoy a unity that cannot be grasped by an accumulation of from a purely physical, i.e. quantitative, point of view.
external bonds.

The “mind dust” theory, in which complex entities are ex-


plained by the multiplication of psychic features in basic ones, is
comparable to the copy theory of memory (see below), in which
Ucs traces are revived into Cs thought. The atoms of mind-dust
and the static traces of copy theory are logical solids of the same
210 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 211

8.4. The psychoanalytic Ucs: preliminary remarks in neurosis and dream interpretation, Wittgenstein thought there
was no “dynamic theory of dreams”. What began as a descrip-
To my mind it is principally Hartmann, in a work widely read in tion, uncovered a correlation and ended in causal explanation.
his day though rarely cited now, to whom we are indebted for a Reasons deduced from neurotic symptoms were inserted as mo-
general theory of the Ucs. Though metaphysical and discursive, tives that instigated the behaviors they were invoked to explain.
the work attempts to establish the biological and neurological cor- But reasons are verbal acts, i.e. Cs outcomes and, like other con-
relates of the Ucs, and postulates a wide range of Ucs modes of tents in Csness, lack causal force (Brown, 1996; 2005). A reason is
thought, such as creativity, intuition, inference, mystical insight, a surrogate, a bit like a translation in this respect, where the space
will, purposefulness and timelessness, or the instantaneity of pro- between languages is an obscurity one seeks to diminish but can
cess, e.g. a “compression into the timeless instant” (p. 272). The never overcome.
emphasis on Ucs instinct, and the importance of sexuality and
shame anticipate the account of repression and the Ucs apparatus In the Ucs, psychoanalysis has found its most congenial home,
by Freud, whose 1915 essay on the Ucs borrows from Hartmann but it is less a workplace of novel ideas than a graveyard of mid-
the notion of Ucs ideas, instincts and emotions. Hartmann also night rumblings with imaginary ghosts doing the work left over
wrote of a second personality in the Ucs that, presaging Freud, from the preceding day. An analytic interpretation can be a spell-
is comparable to Csness in its structure and function. In spite of binding tale, the persuasiveness of which belies its shaky founda-
the criticism of Hartmann’s work, mainly for the wide range of tions in the metapsychology. The affirmation of the interpretation
functions posited in the Ucs, so inclusive that, as Hoffding wrote, by the analysand in collusion with the analyst is taken as “proof” of
“it explains nothing because it explains everything,” the transi- the correctness of the theory and validation of the clinical model
tion from Hartmann to Freud is one from comprehensiveness to (Grunbaum, 1984; after Wittgenstein). Links from psychoanalysis
limitation, from possibility to dogmatism and from richness to to psychology are unconvincing, while attempts to correlate psy-
closure. Bouveresse (1995) remarked that the effect of Freud’s choanalysis with neuroscience, which are meant to rehabilitate
discovery was “to lock us into a predetermined possibility which the scientific credentials of a theory bereft of innovation, remain
now appears to be the only one that merits attention.” tenuous and forced (see Brown and Stremler, 2008).

Psychoanalysis postulates elements in the psyche that inter- To reduce the psyche to brain parts, machine components or
act by way of energy. In the substantialism and determinism of genes transfers mental phenomena to a physical level of descrip-
his doctrine, Freud’s Ucs is a thing or a place filled with psychic tion. For example, the claim that hallucination or dream arises
entities that interact in causal space. MacIntyre (1958) wrote, from — or is associated with — activity in cingulate gyrus, or visual
“the conception of unconscious ideas as non-physical entities is cortex or orbito-frontal region, even if partly true, is trivial without
an odd one, largely because the conception of ideas as entities a qualitative neuropsychology of imagery, an account of the tran-
is odd.” The metapsychology is the indispensable foundation of sition of image to object and the relation of imagery to memory,
the entire theory, in which an idea or drive-representation results agency, feeling, and so on. Though psychoanalysis fancies itself
from the cathexis of memory traces. Freud sought a dynamic al- a science, in the Nibelungenheim of dream interpretation it takes
ternative to the static association model in neurology critiqued in allegory to analogy, analogy to reason, and reason to cause and is
his aphasia book, but instead, he substituted psychic associations more closely allied to mythology than science or psychology.
for anatomical ones and put the dynamic into energy, leaving the
traces on which it operates inert (Brown, 1998). In his commentary, MacIntyre notes that Freud’s Ucs, as a
link from infancy to adult life, is largely a repository of repressed
Perhaps because of the atomism of the trace, its aggregation wish-fulfillments, though wishes (desires, intentions) character-
to ideas and the “push-pull” thinking of repression and defense ize Cs behavior as well. Except for dream or neurosis, the Ucs is
212 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 213

unknowable and comparable to Kant’s noumenal reality. Terms waking interpretation to the one explanation that makes sense,
such as wish, idea and resistance that describe Ucs process are i.e. satisfies the analyst and the client. Interpretation furthers the
derived from a Cs vocabulary. In Freud’s materialism, the shift of coherence of the narrative by filling in missing elements, not by
Cs entities to an Ucs locus fixes them in the physiological matrix extracting causes or motives. Features absent in the dream report
denied to them when Cs. MacIntyre writes, Freud’s unconscious turn up in the interpretation to empty the underlying categories
“is the ghost of the Cartesian consciousness”, though a very solid, from which the dream arises. Like a mysterious painting with
material ghost it is, and with neural underpinnings. blank spaces on the canvas, the analyst adds content to disambig-
uate the meaning. But is there only one interpretation, as Freud
We see the Cs vocabulary in the description of Ucs ideas and thought, or many interpretations that could be adapted to a dream
emotions. What does it mean to have an Ucs idea? Ideas crystal- or analytic situation? The problem is that there is no method to
lize out of thoughts, and thoughts individuate categories that are determine which interpretation, if any, is correct (Farrell. 1964).
even less specific. The prototypical Ucs idea is creative intuition,
but this is hardly a sum of smaller ideas bundled together waiting Take a brief actual recurring dream described to me by a wom-
to be unpacked. How can one discern an Ucs wish (or desire) until an that began at age 10. In the dream, she tries to grab a needle
its ends are known? A wish is intentional. Is the Ucs intentional? that is floating over a yellow river. She is anxious and confused.
The Ucs may drive to an end, but the object of the wish is not Could the needle represent the straight path in life and the river
in sight when Ucs process is active. To construe Ucs process as a one that is winding and uncertain? Could the needle represent
wish implants the object of the wish before it is decided. The drive the present or now, and could the river represent continuity or
that is antecedent to desire shapes and configures the wish in eternity? Might the contrast lie in the fixed and immutable op-
specifying an aim. Ucs motivation presumes a goal that becomes posed to the fluid and changing? Is there reference to a choice
clear as the act materializes. between staying home, e.g. the needle as sewing, and leaving
home, e.g. the river as travel. Perhaps she had been sewing some
Dreams are conceived as “night memories” rather than pre- time before, or received a knitted sweater, or thought of a boat,
terminal phases in thought and perception. Ucs repression selects or looked at a picture with a river in the background. Pötzl (1960)
ideas for the dreamwork to fashion into symbolic representations described instances in which unnoticed fragments of daytime
of unfulfilled wishes. In microgenetic theory, every act is a memo- perception recurred in dream imagery. The juxtaposition of the
ry sculpted to an object, the dream content actualizing categories two main images is not a conflict between psychic entities. River
that are the bearers of Ucs process. The antecedent pre-object and needle do not stand for opposing objects, but are at most,
or word-category is not identical to its outcome but undergoes incidental precipitates at a phase of uncertainty or irresolution.
individuation to a waking object. The reasons given for neurotic If every mental event has a meaning, as Freud thought, and as
behavior seem compelling because everyday language with its well may be the case, there are any number of possible meanings,
sexual preoccupation is employed to convert a puzzling act or each as convincing as the next.
thought into its Ucs precursors. But, even the most convincing
interpretation blocks a true understanding of the Ucs on its own Other interpretations — banal, extravagant, mythic — are pos-
terms. sible, as is the deflating possibility that the dream has no interpre-
tation, or that, for various reasons, the vivid imagery of the dream
Freud considered the interpretation to be a translation of the cries out for meaning and interpretation when there is none. If
language of the dream into waking speech. But the ground of both I imagine the face of a friend, what is the “meaning”? Is it the
dream and waking language remains covert in the translation feeling for or about him, his absence, an old encounter, a passing
process. The strategy is to go from one language to the other, en- disposition, a preceding thought? When I imagine my friend I do
larging the dream report with implicit content and restricting the
214 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 215

not ask why I am thinking of him but rather, what is it that I am that strings together the saga of a life? Are these the critical events
thinking about when he is imagined. To apply this to dream, the that shape character, or are they given as reasons why the person
needle and river are markers of categories, possibly one category, turned out a certain way, as a kind of negotiation of interpretation
or an incipient thought. We feel there must be a hidden meaning, with causal explanation? When and why are any mental events
and we may be disappointed not to discern one, but this might to be resuscitated as causes? Is there justification for treating rea-
point to the incompleteness of the picture, and the impact of sons as causes? Is there a well-reasoned theory in psychoanalysis,
meaning-selection at a pre-object phase that leaves the dreamer or for that matter in philosophy, on psychic causation (see Brown,
asking what the dream was about? 1996)?24

Let us take a psychoanalytic approach, and assume the inter- In waking life, we sense that the meaning of an idea is its refer-
pretation to be the proximity of male and female symbols at a ence or context, not usually why the idea came to mind. Awake,
stage of sexual awakening. The grabbing, the anxiety and urinary one does not so much wonder where an idea came from but what
color are signs of desire, fear and disgust. Let us also assume that it signifies, its utility and where it will lead. Waking Csness presses
the symbols of needle and river are figurative images in which to the future. In dream, there is context, but no reference or futu-
disparate objects are fused by predicative relations instead of a lit- rity. Desire (fear, etc.) is for the immediate image or its surrogate,
eral visualization (discussion in Brown, 2006). Needle could have not for an absent or future object. The “aboutness” of intentional-
actualized from a category of instruments or clothing, or it could ity is less pronounced and the referential meaning in the world
have replaced another image related in shape or function, such as turns back on itself to the genesis of the image. Awake, we feel
a body part (eye, phallus) or weapon (dagger). Does a verbal trans- a perceptual object comes into contact with meaning as a sec-
lation of the dream contribute something to the visual picture that ondary event. There is a link from mind to object, or the reverse.
would not be satisfied by adding another picture? A clock would In dream, the image is extra-personal but still intra-psychic. On
complete one narrative, a boy another. Suppose the dream were waking, the events of the dream are felt to be the objects of still
to be reported by an adult with a sexual neurosis. What does it deeper thought. The meaning of the dream seems to reside in
add to the understanding? By what method is the neurosis linked inaccessible layers of Ucs thought, of which the image is a sym-
to the dream? The interpretation rounds out a story and satisfies bolic transcript. The retrospective search for underlying sources,
the need for closure. The analytic interpretation is an engrossing reasons or causes of the dream replaces the prospective attitude
tale that captures the imagination, like all good stories, whether to waking objects, which appear independent of mind, though
true or fictitious. The question is whether it has psychological va- still mental images adapted to the world and “detached” from the
lidity, i.e. accurately represents psychic process. psyche. In the waking state, a mental image precedes the external
object that is its referential aim. In the dream, with no external
Suppose the girl, when young, witnessed the primal scene, object, the image is the final phase, so we ask what precedes it
or has memories or fantasies of sexual abuse. Is this enough to and the response is, the motive, the wish or the need.
explain the dream or the neurosis? Is neurosis the cause or the
reason for the dream, i.e. do neurosis and dream inhabit the same
psychic complex or is one the cause of the other? What of girls
who have similar experiences, even siblings, without such dreams 24
If Cs thought begins with Ucs process, reasons cannot be the causes of acts or
and without, or with different, neuroses? A similar outcome might images. It is common to confuse these in ordinary language, e.g. I reported him
to the police because he stole my money. The sequence seems to justify the rea-
occur with abandonment, jealousy, parental excessiveness or
son as a cause, but another person might respond in a different way, e.g. by not
indifference. Is the fantasy or experience of early childhood just reporting or attacking the thief. The response depends on the sources of an act in
another — albeit traumatic — event in the experiential narrative values, beliefs and character rather than on preceding events that are reasons in
the sense of interpretation or explanation.
216 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 217

8.5. An alternative to repression ties. When a sculptor chips away at marble to reveal a figure, we
do not think the unrealized is a repressed entity. The partitions
I want to make the stronger claim that the concept of repression reflect implicit or Ucs choices at every phase, not the conflict be-
makes a mechanism out of normal properties in the derivation tween the distinct ideas of Cs indecision.
of the mental state, which include inhibitory constraints at each
phase in the whole-part transition, the effects of intense emotions Psychoanalysis asks why particular ideas or feelings develop
bound to conceptual form, and the potential of early categories. and others do not and argues that certain of them, say the painful
Freud happened on an intermediate phase of image-selection ones, are repressed. But this just points to a phase early in the ac-
as the focus of “psychic conflict”, but selection pressure in mi- tualization of meaning-relations and affective intensity. The same
crogeny, like that in evolution, occurs at all phases. Ucs material constraints on form, i.e. sculpting, parcellation, pruning, account
is not suppressed or de-innervated in repression or resistance. for the selection of one item instead of others. The unrealized
There is no decathexis or inhibition of ideas or experiences, which does not rise up in protest but remains unborn, though active in
are postulated as a kind of mortar to fill in the cracks in theory. the potential for forthcoming states. There may be tension among
Psychoanalysis is a work of great complexity, but the complexity configural possibilities at the core of each category, but possibili-
is less in the process of mind than its interpretation. ties are not entities or psychic contents. In sum, the individuation
of parts from wholes is not a competition among psychic objects
The truth is simpler. Ideas, acts and memories, develop or fail or mechanisms but a cascade of whole-part shifts in the micro-
to develop according to the constraints of sensation, habit and the temporal structure of the mind/brain state. In this process, the
immediate inner and outer context. The object (act, idea, etc.) that virtual becomes real, the category becomes an instance, figures
survives the transition and ideas that recur in a series of mental develop out of grounds and potential becomes actual, all by way
states, in Cs or Ucs thought, reflect the dominant trends at dif- of constraints on the recurrent specification of form.
ferent segments in the actualization. At each segment, categories
give rise to instances that become categories for the next transi- The transition from possibility to fact in the passage to Csness
tion. The continuous parsing of wholes-to-parts is the “vehicle” of does not entail a defense against unwanted ideas. Some ideas that
process. One can think of parsing as inhibition or elimination, or a are “repressed”, i.e. fail to reach Csness, are related to juvenile or
veto on instances that fail to materialize. Repression is Ucs veto. Cs syncretic modes of thought. Their elicitation is specific to that
“veto”, as Libet (1999) described in action-development, is Csness mode. Because of the depth they can influence the derivation
of the Cs segment of implicit veto, i.e. constraint, as alternate pos- process, but they may well be skeletal in the personality, unable
sibilities are sacrificed for the one path that develops. to individuate. It is a truism that much of what we have forgotten
of early childhood is what we have become or, conversely, that of
Repression is one instance of the constraints that occur over the which we are Cs tends to be in a more superficial relation to the
entire transition. The difference from other phases is that repres- personality. Emotionally-charged configurations bound to catego-
sion involves constraints on a phase associated with a primitive ries of experiential memory and linked to Ucs drive are not fully
mentality that is transitional to rational thought. A relaxation at derived to individuated feelings. Like the proverbial camel through
this phase allows images and symbolic forms to appear in dream, the eye of a needle, the failure to become Cs may owe to an in-
reverie and creative thinking, while an application of constraints tensity of emotion that impedes individuation to a partial affect.
gives behaviors that can imply selective repression or resistance. Strong emotions linked to inchoate ideas are trapped in the Ucs.
However, constraints on developing configurations occur at all The totality of the drive-representation develops to the particulari-
phases. When a phoneme or word actualizes a phonological or ties of idea and feeling having left behind their antecedents. The
lexical category, we do not say other speech sounds or words are powerful feeling of meaningfulness of dream does not signify the
repressed, only the potential to develop those alternate possibili-
218 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 219

dream has a meaning. We feel the dream has meaning because it 8.6. Csness as a searchlight
is irrational though familiar in some ways and not incoherent, or
because it lacks outer reference, is affect-laden, incomplete, and We owe to Freud not just one but several theories of the Ucs,
most importantly, actualizes at a phase of meaning-relations. though each account recognizes the fundamental operations of
condensation and displacement, which relate to metaphoric ex-
Since experimental data on brain and Ucs process tend to be tension and predicate-driven fusions of disparate topics. Freud’s
fitted to psychoanalytic theory rather than the latter modified to Ucs is timeless, though its plurality is inconsistent with the unity
adapt to the data, an understanding of the Ucs does not entail that timelessness obligates, since occurrences that are simultane-
minor adjustments to psychoanalysis but major revisions of the ous should be ingredient in the same temporal point or undif-
entire edifice, beginning with the core concepts of repression, ferentiated in a non-temporal occasion. Probably, timelessness is
conflict and resistance that are the linchpins of theory and the simultaneity or lack of serial order rather than non-temporality.
pillars of clinical practice. Conflict reifies the selectional process There is an elaboration of an internal reality, more like a parallel
through which figural contents individuate. Anxiety is a symp- universe than segments in the continuity of inner and outer, and
tom of irresolution, easily demonstrated for affect-neutral mate- there is a lack of contradiction or negation, which is consistent
rial, e.g. the Zeigarnik effect on incomplete tasks, percept-genetic with a potential for multiplicity prior to specification and actual-
studies (Smith et al, 1989), as well as configurations that are af- ity. Freud thought the lack of the negative in dream could be a
fectively-charged. The conflict is not between opposing mental sign of conceptual ambivalence or the unification of discrepant
objects but alternate developments that are virtual in the potential meanings. This also occurs in myth, in schizophrenic thinking
of the field. These are not definite paths but possibilities in the and in primitive mentation. The simultaneity of potential leads to
specification process. Ucs ideas are virtual. There is no conflict a definiteness of aim, finally through choice to actuality. Every act
between virtual possibilities and unrealized potential. Conflict is or object is an Ucs “decision” that arises through phases of incipi-
the analyst’s interpretation of the normal pruning of non-adaptive ent struggle. The elimination of alternatives for the survival of one
possibilities prior to the elicitation of the most adaptive or least instead of innumerable others re-enacts an evolutionary drama in
hurtful resolution. The conflict is between what reason dictates the adaptation of redundancy to necessity. The general character
and need demands. This is a matter of sculpting the personal to of Ucs ideation in dream and pathology and the more detailed
the exigent. If Cs actualization is aided by therapy, it is probably account in the metapsychology (Brown, 1998; 2000) resonate in
not due to the addition of context, or to insight, but to suggestibil- all of Freud’s later papers.
ity. In general, modes of therapy are forms of cueing, facilitation
or empathic fusion, i.e. identification with the other, not the lifting Among Freud’s more interesting if fruitless ideas is that of a
of repression or a breaking through of resistance.25 Cs searchlight. Searchlight theory rests on the assumption that Cs
and Ucs contents differ only in the degree of attention directed to
them, a premise that survives in the copy theory of memory (be-
low) and the idea of retrieval from a store. In this theory, the Ucs
trace is neither relocated to Csness nor undergoes a development.
The trace becomes Cs when attention is directed to it. This was
Freud’s later view, which differed from that of the metapsychol-
ogy, in which there was transfer from Ucs to Cs compartments.
Still, he maintained that transfer was a form of retrieval, not trans-
25
Consistent with the microgenetic interpretation, it may be that just “discharg-
ing” Ucs process, e.g. as in creative writing, has a therapeutic effect independent formation. The searchlight brings the trace to varying degrees
of the content that is verbalized. To empty a creative thought even in abstract
material gives concrete form to categories that are barely felt or intuited.
220 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 221

of Cs attention.26 The theory gains simplicity in maintaining the Rapaport, 1951), which failed to survive the scrutiny of the priests
trace as a static entity, eliminating the transition or relocation to of orthodoxy.
Csness, and in the idea that energy (libido, cathexis, attention) is
decisive. However, collapsing “retrieval” into a searchlight inters The cathectic charge attributed to libidinal drive is responsible
the complexity of revival in a single mechanism and introduces for trace arousal, its withdrawal for de-activation or repression. In
an ad hoc device no less in need of explanation than the process the metapsychology, trace-cathexis was Ucs, with the drive-rep-
it purports to explain. resentation becoming Cs by virtue of the intensity of the charge.
Now, the arousal is divided between compartments. Cathexis is
In searchlight theory, the transition to Csness is a gradual il- detached from the trace and aligned with Cs attention. How the
lumination or increasing intensity of the trace, not a passage of searchlight locates the trace or the trace attracts cathexis is un-
Ucs content through successive phases or modes of cognition. certain, though in fairness the inability to explain or even address
The dream is not an obligatory phase of primitive mentation, but this point, a major failing in the metapsychology, has not yet been
a distortion of an uncorrupted trace. While the attributes of Ucs resolved. Ideas and emotions are still conceived as distinct psycho-
cognition differ, in my view, from those of Cs thought, they were logical and/or neural phenomena, with no theory on how their
described largely in terms of Cs experience, beginning with traces association comes about. This differs from microgenetic theory, in
and an affect-pool. Traces are either permanently Ucs and not which drive-categories are constructs of affect-laden concepts, i.e.
subject to the searchlight or actively subdued and waiting for ac- conceptual-feelings. These constructs undergo further individua-
tivation (de-repression). Wittgenstein and others contended that tion to feelings that appear non-conceptual, and concepts that ap-
the Ucs grammar differs from that of Csness. Freud also noted pear affect-free, though every feeling or emotion has a conceptual
that the language of dream differs from that of wakefulness, for framework and every concept has an affective tonality.
example, in the absence of negation, or the symbolism and fusion
of disparate concepts. The unique language of the Ucs in neurosis If one dispenses with the Ucs, non-Cs brain process would be
and dream may lie in the narrative of recall. However, in psycho- irrelevant to Csness, though few would argue that the Ucs por-
analytic theory, dream is not a manifestation of the Ucs but its tion of the mind/brain state can be eliminated and the Cs por-
distortion due to repression. The actual Ucs and its “grammar” are tion remain intact, i.e. that Csness has a specific mechanism that
modeled after Csness and can be reconstructed by decoding the operates independent of other brain activity. If Csness is not an
dream to access the Ucs directly. autonomous system with a unique apparatus but rests on Ucs
process, Cs experience must develop on events ingredient in its
The concept of Cs cathexis of Ucs traces assigns a derivative micro-temporal structure. If this much is granted, a Cs searchlight
of libido to Csness in what seems a radical departure from drive would require, at the minimum, some degree of motivation or
theory. The theory goes beyond the metapsychology, shifting the interest to explain the choice of a target. One also must consider
primary mechanisms of activation to Cs derivatives. The notion the largely Ucs presuppositions, core beliefs and values that guide
of a static trace contrasts with a transformative process through the activation of the trace. It then follows that an act of thought
which memorial contents are derived into acts, percepts and begins with an Ucs bias, predisposition or motivation that chan-
thoughts. A qualitative transformation from Ucs to Csness in- nels the Cs searchlight, which then retro-activates the Ucs trace to
formed a more scientific branch of psychoanalysis (Schilder, 1951; a focus of attention.

Given that the Ucs is outside awareness, it is unclear how Cs


attention could select, much less locate or even think of, and then
26
Searle (1991), for example, not only accepts the searchlight but adds an
adjustable dimmer for altered states! His account of the Ucs admits only those activate, an Ucs trace. If motivation or interest corresponds with
mental states that are potentially Cs. the bias to an action or an object of thought, assigning motivation
222 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 223

to the Ucs, where it largely belongs, displaces the antecedents of so on? When the searchlight activates the trace does it activate
the searchlight back to Ucs cognition. Whether interest arises in all these components? The process corresponding to repression
Cs or Ucs process leaves undecided why one idea develops instead filters products of the Ucs, but do Cs perceptions retreat to be-
of another. In the metapsychology, the activation of the trace only come the underpinnings of Cs ideas? Even if the difficulties can
postulates a source of energy. It does not address why one trace be sorted out, the bi-directionality of trace-reception, storage and
and not another is aroused, or whether the trace specifies or is arousal, i.e. a trace that is first Cs, then Ucs, then Cs again, is a
specified by the drive, i.e. whether the selectivity is in the drive rather untidy picture.
or the trace. This is the question of how drive energy locates and
innervates an appropriate trace. The argument is circular, i.e. the If the searchlight is under Cs control it is voluntary; if not, it
activation of a trace is proportional to its quanta of energy, while is part of the Ucs, and there is no advance in theory. If an idea
the greater the energy the more active the trace. in Csness was previously Ucs, its ”becoming-Cs” could occur by
several routes: by the causal propagation of Cs ideas, which re-
Any theory of attention should apply equally to inner and quires that a Cs idea evokes an Ucs trace into Csnes; by deliberate
outer objects. The older terms for this are intero- and extero-cep- thought or attention, in which an act of volition locates and high-
tion, where interoception refers to the perception of inner objects, lights an Ucs idea; or by the microgenetic route of a progression to
comparable to the perception of outer ones. This is distinguished increasing definiteness.
from thinking about such objects, which is introspection. The
notion that we deliberately attend to images and ideas in Csness Attention to an object or memory by way of a searchlight is an-
is extended in searchlight theory to Ucs traces or ideas. The Cs other way of describing a state of focal perception. The difference,
locus of the attentional mechanism is a derivative of the largely and it is considerable, is that attention directed to a Cs object is
Ucs apparatus that was formerly the explanation of the transition now directed to an Ucs trace. Is the focal attention to an object in
from perception to trace, and from trace to thought and recollec- the world or an image in the mind the same as that which focuses
tion. Apart from the psychological difficulties with a “top-down” on Ucs ideas? Is the Cs searchlight identical with focal attention?
cathexis, there are anatomical problems as well. It is probable It is likely that a state of attention retraces a common path for
that Cs experience depends to a great extent on neocortical re- all objects. Attention to an external object should be the same
gions, and that memory depends on limbic regions. This gives as that to an image; there is no reason to postulate an additional
the problem that a neocortical searchlight arouses a limbic trace system for Ucs traces. The problem is that attention to an image
that remains in the older system even as it is engaged by the more or object involves successive points on the same trajectory, while
recent one. The transition from limbic to neocortical formation is to dip into, explore and find an Ucs trace reverses the direction of
the forward direction of microgenesis; the process generates and actualization.
replaces states of Csness, it does not requires Cs instigation.

The absence of a shift in location or qualitative transition as


the trace becomes Cs is also inconsistent with the argument that
every Ucs trace was previously Cs, as well as with the stages of 8.7. Arousal and attention
memory through which traces are assumed to pass in forgetting We have the intuition that an exertion of will brings a mental ob-
and retrieval. Is a perceptual trace deposited in systems or net- ject into a sustained focus and that this is a fully Cs activity. An act
works that register shape, size, color, movement, depth, mean- of will, the choice of an image, and the ability to concentrate on it,
ing? Is the trace distributed over all the components entrained in are felt as Cs prerogatives. If one is asked, why did you say (think,
its perception, including long and short term stores, buffers and remember) such and such an idea, the person might respond, “I
224 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 225

wanted to”, but if then asked, why did you want to, there is no continue to the mental image, then the external object. On this
good response other than to repeat the previous answer or admit view, attention has an Ucs onset, and merely describes phases of
an inclination, and what is an inclination other than an Ucs bias? the coming-into-Csness of the trace. If this is the case, focal atten-
It can be argued that the term disposition covers our ignorance of tion (searchlight theory) postulates an unnecessary mechanism
the mind/brain divide, but we simply have no way at present of for the recurrence, in each mental state, of the progression to a
characterizing initial phases of bias, belief or value that underlie definite object, i.e. the successive analysis of wholes. The drive to
the core self, nor can we describe in more precise neural or cogni- individuation is simply the pattern of the transition. The direction
tive terms the intermediate phases, e.g. lexical or object-concepts. of mental process toward Csness is obligated by a large volume of
The mind/brain problem applies not just to the instigation of the observation and not refuted by a single datum. It is necessitated
mental state but at every point in its development. Nonetheless, by the temporal lag in perception, by phases in the generation
there is ample evidence that preparatory stages anticipate Cs acts. of voluntary acts, and by the Ucs precursors of words, acts and
The widely-cited studies on the readiness potential are one dem- objects.
onstration. A simpler observation is that a voluntary movement
such as lifting the finger develops at the cyclical peaks of normal With one exception (see below), a Cs mechanism of attention
resting “tremor”. This indicates that Ucs rhythms or oscillators (searchlight) has, to my knowledge, not been described with re-
underlie voluntary action, as in the respiratory timing that frames spect to temporal order. In the arousal of traces or the transition
an utterance. to Csness the trace assumes temporal order in relation to other
mental contents and ongoing experience. An Ucs storehouse of
Moreover, the capacity for willed attention can be perturbed by static traces would be non-temporal. What else could a trace be
brain disorder, which may lead to increased attention to ideation- but the potential strengths of the innumerable synapses that give
al or motor details, e.g. perseveration, or to obsessional thinking, rise to the configurations from which memories are derived? The
where there is an exaggerated preoccupation with a behavior or storehouse of potential memories may be stacked in episodic se-
an idea. This heightened focus of attention in pathology raises the quence, but not all memories are episodic, while the stacking is a
question of how truly voluntary an act of attention is, i.e. whether simultaneous virtual array of potential recollections that are not
Cs attention is the result of Cs decision or Ucs bias. Does a persis- in play until the episode materializes. The temporality of memory
tence of attention reflect the maintenance of a set or the recur- is achieved on activation as the trace takes on Cs time-order not
rence of similar sets over a series of states? Is the appearance of present in the store.
sustained or excessive attention to an idea the result of voluntary
or involuntary fixation on the idea or are similar mental states iter- This problem was alluded to in a celebrated paper by Karl
ated so that the idea is continuously renewed? More importantly, Lashley (1951) who postulated a scanning device for temporal or-
in the standard theory of perception, which begins with input to der as thoughts develop out of co-temporal Ucs or Pre-Cs phases.
(visual) cortex that is assembled to an object, the individual does Lashley cited the undifferentiated precursors of thought, i.e. the
not know what an object is and, by implication, whether to look initial sign of a thought or utterance, in the “determining tenden-
at it, until after it is consciously perceived. On this view, which the cy” of the Wurzburg school. He discussed at some length clinical
microgenetic account rejects, attention follows perception, it does observations by Pick (1913; Brown, 1972), as well as instances of
not guide it. temporal order in the Cs realization of co-temporal phases, e.g.
anticipation in language production, holistic effects in translation,
Ordinarily, we assume that focal attention resolves in Csness errors in aphasia and Spoonerisms, to which, inter alia, he could
out of a diffuse or ambient field. In microgenetic theory, atten- have added pronominal reference, co-articulation and other such
tion is postulated to begin with categorical primitives in the Ucs, phenomena. The concept of a scanner adds a mechanism to bol-
226 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 227

ster the inadequacy of existing theory but contributes little to its that Ucs representations are theoretical objects isomorphic to, i.e.
advance. Moreover, a scanning device is no less in need of expla- copies of, something else and defines at least three classes of Ucs
nation than the serial order it attempts to explain (chapter 2). “stimulus representations”: stored episodic memories, linguistic
knowledge and habituated stimulus representations.

The copy theory is implicit in retrieval, in which a memory bit


or informational unit is looked up and revived by Cs attention.
8.8. The copy theory of the trace The concept is employed with little dissent even if it is riddled
The twin of the searchlight is the copy theory of memory, first dis- with problems: e.g. how agency retrieves the trace; how agency
cussed by Berkeley, and Reid. Contemporary psychology, which knows what trace to retrieve if it is Ucs; what accounts for success
is modeled on the design of a computer, implies the retrieval of or failure in retrieval; how a naked trace is associated with context
informational bits stored in a bank that recombine in thought. If and feeling; how retrieval accounts for the “physical” relations
Ucs traces are stored percepts, and Cs memories are illuminated of short-term memory, the semantic or conceptual relations of
copies, there is no obligation to explain retrieval, i.e. the trace just long-term memory, the pathology of memory, the creative or pro-
becomes Cs. The difference between the original perception, ductive aspect of memory and its boundary with thought. Copy
which is of photographic quality, and the memory of that percep- theory cannot account for studies of implicit or subliminal cogni-
tion, reflects the imprecision of memory and the degrading of tion. It tends to avoid study of subjective phases in recall and the
the trace. False or inaccurate memories are deflections of a more relation of perception to memory, in that trace-Csness is a matter
or less automatic retrieval. The simplest way to characterize Ucs of quantity (of activation), not qualitative transition.28
memory is that it is identical to, or a degraded version of, what
Trace theory is part of a package of ideas, in which percep-
was once in Csness. Most writers have agreed with Freud that
tions are autonomous units, like the traces they leave behind, that
traces are stored perceptions, and that alteration over time points
sense data are assembled to objects and that recognition is post-
to a degrading, not a re-working. For example, Ellis (1995) argued
perceptual. The traces of cortical sensation are rapidly lost; those
that since Ucs processes are mostly derived from Cs ones, there is
of short-term memory fade, while the long-term trace persists.
little difference between them.27 On this view, Cs and Ucs traces
But if the long-term trace preserves conceptual features in the
are identical, the only problem being how the trace comes into
perception, i.e. the gist rather than the detail, how does Ucs gist
Csness. The copy theory dominates contemporary psychology,
translate to a specific item in Csness?
but conditions such as false memory, confabulation and amnesic
disorders have chipped away at the model. In microgenetic theory, the trace consists of all of the phases
activated in its elicitation. The actualization of a memory leads
In its regress, what was once Cs, like learning a piece on the
from past to present, from phases that are “memory-like” to
piano, becomes less Cs and more automatic. Ucs phenomena that
phases that are “perception-like”, with stages in memory — long-
at one time were Cs are postulated to be mediated in the Ucs by
term, short-term, iconic — traversed, in that order, and uncovered
automatic mechanisms or “processors”. Baars (1988), in a compu-
in forgetting or incomplete revival. There is no transfer from
tational approach, notes the extraordinary range of Ucs processes
short- to long-term stores; indeed, there is no store. Rather, these
underlying language, action, memory and perception. He argues

27
There are processes that support the generation of Csness, but no such thing 28
Freud was conflicted, as was his theory, on the relation of process and sub-
as a Cs process. One grasps the stabilities that process creates; ideas, images, stance, or quality and quantity. He went half-way to a fully processual theory,
words. Process and representation refer to the transitive and substantive aspect retaining the static traces of association psychology and adding energy as the
of the Ucs. The question is whether there is a “substantive” or “contentive” Ucs. dynamic factor (Brown, 1998).
228 Jason W. Brown

transitional phases are uncovered in an order that is the reverse of


their entrainment in the original perception. In the development
of memory from long-term through short-term and iconic stages
to perception, the endogenous substrate of memory is sculpted to
an external object.

In sum, the pre-suppositions, biases, tendencies, dispositions,


beliefs and values that underlie Cs acts, general knowledge and
personal memory, specific knowledge such as that of a grammar,
perceptual and motor skills including pre-perceptual processes
and preparatory stages in action, reflect the configural patterns of
myriad neurons or networks that become active in the occurrent
state. A mental state or act of cognition consists of spontaneous
arisings over the decaying structure of just-prior states that adapt
to the inner and outer conditions at the moment. The context and
knowledge that are trimmed away as entities materialize are not
abandoned residues but the context of the occurrent state, and a
foundation for the next. Phases left behind participate in the final
content constitute the subjective portion of the state and form a
ground for its renewal. Context in an epoch is a co-temporal po-
tential incremented in the completion of an act. Phases of experi-
ential memory and meaning are initial segments, those of objects,
images and words are later segments, but all phases concur in
the now of the final object. A mind/brain state enfolds the transi-
tion or sequence of configurations, as each partition save the last
serves as a whole for a further derivation. The memory trace is
the diachronic matrix of the complete set of phases that gives the
final actuality.
Chapter 9
Microgenetic Theory of the Unconscious
2. Categories and the Unconscious

9.1. Dream
In humans, the understanding of Ucs cognition has historically
depended heavily on the interpretation of dream, which provides
a compelling story of the meaning-relations that “connect” or ex-
plain what are otherwise fragmentary and puzzling events. The
dream can be taken as a representation of experience in the past,
a commentary on the day’s events or a portent of the future, but
in each instance it creates a parallel universe that is symbolically
linked to the Cs life. The Freudian key to unlocking this symbolism,
though controversial, opens the way to an explanation of what is
inchoate or inexplicable in Cs thought. The dream is traditionally
conceived as a distorted representation, or working-out, of situa-
tions in everyday life, but it can also actualize a mode of cognition
that prefigures Csness.

The space and time of dream sample preliminary cognition,


just as waking hallucination. Space is foreshortened, volumetric,
lacking in depth, curved, fluid and “palpable”. The space of hal-
lucination is extra-personal but still image-like and not indepen-
dent of the viewer. The passive self of dream is fixed in a present,
without a past or a future and lacking in duration. The self is car-
ried along on the edge of change, as the before passes into the
after in a subjective time experience that is intermediate between
physical succession and a present or now that is the axis of a con-
sciousness of past and future. We assume a dream recounted on
waking is an accurate rendition of the dream while asleep, but
dream content may undergo rapid change in the transition to
Csness. In REM studies, dreams seem to unfold over time, but
many psychoanalysts believe they occur in milliseconds (Trupp,
2006). Freud recognized this possibility, and wrote “how can one
picture to oneself the psychical condition during sleep? Do all the
dream thoughts (subsequently elicited by analysis) actually exist
232 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 233

together, or after one another, or do they constitute different con- both standpoints, as a focal disorder of thought or perception and
temporaneous streams finally coalescing (Die Traumdeutung, p. in relation to the personality.
205; cited in Munsterberg et al, 1910)?” If the Ucs is non-temporal,
dream events would be simultaneous and achieve temporal order The need to interpret dreams is an expression of the natural
on awakening. The serial order of the events in the dream, thus pressure toward meaning in all experience. The brain is an engine
its narrative, is retrofitted to a simultaneous efflux of imagery of meaning-creation. It is difficult to accept that some dreams,
(see below). The celebrated dream of Maury discussed by Freud however outré or banal, do not have a coherent meaning, like
(SE IV:26-27, V:495-497) is an instance in which such an account some delusions in this respect. The delusion that there are rob-
seems plausible (discussion in Brown, 1991; 2002).29 bers under the bed is a concrete representation of anxiety, con-
ditioned perhaps by the insecurities of modern life. The delusion
Along these lines, some physiologists maintain that dreams are one is Jesus Christ can be interpreted in terms of religiosity and
the conscious interpretation of random neuronal firings in brain- megalomania, but it can as well represent a paralogical syllogism
stem (Hobson, 1988). This position recalls the argument that the in which the fusion is based on a partial resemblance (see discus-
symptoms of brain damage are guesses or the sparks that fly out sion below).
of a damaged machine. On this view, the Cs self attempts to make
sense of otherwise meaningless images. However, the dream is a The pressure to interpret the dream can lead some to think the
symptom of preliminary thought or perception that engages the narrative of the dream is itself an interpretation, i.e. that the dream
personality, which is where we look for its meaning. In contrast, is a symbolic representation of one’s needs, fears, etc., thus an
the symptoms of brain damage are interpreted in relation to the interpretation of experience in the vocabulary of Ucs thought. The
“instrumentalities”30 of language, action, perception or thought. A Cs self attempts to describe the experiences to which the dream
symptom such as a waking hallucination or speech error tends to refers. This supposes that the dream is a revision of Ucs content
be interpreted as a disruption without meaning in the life of the that is more or less realistic. The symbolism is the window into
individual, whereas hallucination in dream and, since Kraepelin, this content before it submits to the dreamwork. On this view,
speech errors are presumed to relate to past or present experi- Ucs content is a copy of content in Csness that has been derailed
ence. A delusion is intermediate between the pathological symp- on its way to expression. The dream is not transformed to Csness
tom with its delimited interpretation and the dream as a natural but distorts traces that in Cs states are retrieved without corrup-
phenomenon relating to one’s life. A delusion is abnormal but tion. Simply put, the Ucs memories to which distortion is applied
often without demonstrable pathology, so it is approached from are identical to those in Csness.31 Once the distortion is lifted by
dream interpretation, the film between Cs and Ucs memory dis-
solves (see below).
29
Maury described an extended dream sequence that eventuated in the
dreamer being escorted to a guillotine with the beheading coinciding with a An alternative way of thinking about the Ucs is that dream rep-
headboard falling on his neck. There are many descriptions in which events resents the incomplete actualization of a thought or perception,
around a sleeping person are incorporated in the dream, e.g. responding to oth- and that “dreamwork mechanisms” are the normal operations
ers in sleep-speech, transforming an alarm clock to a church bell, etc. The latter that come into play at pre-logical or syncretic phases in any act of
change suggests a recasting or revision of the dream or its invention on waking.
More problematic are those artists who have imagined works in dream or tran-
thought. These “mechanisms” are prominent in dream because
sitional states, e.g. Coleridge in poetry, Stevenson in literature, Wagner in music, the realization of the thought or perception is incomplete. The
Kekule in scientific experiments (see Koestler, 1964). Some personal experiences
are described in Brown (2005).
31
Consistent with Freud’s theory of Csness as a searchlight (discussion above)
30
Kurt Goldstein’s term to distinguish the more superficial symptoms of brain that alights on traces and brings them into Csness, i.e. that Cs and Ucs memory
damage from thought disorders in psychopathology. traces are identical.
234 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 235

incompleteness is not a partial satisfaction that is lacking in ele- ing, and that the ordering occurs after the whole is perceived. As
ments. Dream approximates the goal of Csness but is attenuated discrete events are recalled, duration is parsed by temporal order
in its actualization. On this view, the dream is not a perturbation to create a narrative that gives the dream progression. Most likely,
or recombination of traces but a phase in the transformation from the Cs self generates, facilitates or provides a framework for the
the deep Ucs to waking thought and perception. The degree of event-order.
distortion in dream or waking hallucination, or in the fantasy of
the dream narrative, reflects the “psychological distance” of the The creation of a narrative for dream images recalls interpreta-
content to the waking endstage and the sensory constraints that tions — fabrications, confabulations — in various neurological dis-
drive the content to a veridical perception. Whether a dream is orders, such as amnestic states and alterations of the body-image,
mundane or bizarre, whether one takes a trip to the market or is as well as cases with section of the corpus callosum who are asked
eaten alive by goats, depends on the attitudes, dispositions and to account for situations of conflict. For example, if a snowy scene
trends in thought that impact on the developing process, and the is presented to the right hemisphere of a split-brain patient, and a
degree of objectification or level of reality the image achieves (see: chicken claw to the left, and the patient is asked to choose an ob-
Fig. 6.1., chapter 6). ject with left or right hand, the left hand may choose a shovel, the
right, a rooster. Asked to explain this behavior, the patient might
say he chose the shovel to clean out the chicken coop (Gazzaniga,
2005). The patient elaborates a narrative to account for unrelated
acts.
9.2. The becoming-Cs of a dream
This behavior is not limited to pathology. A normal person
A dream becomes a Cs thought when the dreamer awakens and
given a random set of words or images and asked to make sense
then infers, retroactively, that the memory of the dream corre-
of them can easily do this. It is a common exercise in memory
sponds to its Ucs version. The argument here is that awakening
training to give a patient a set of unrelated pictures or words, such
brings dream events into existence. The sequence of the narrative
as chair, fish, clown and baseball, and ask him to create a context,
is realized in Csness as the content assumes a serial order. While
such as “a clown with a baseball sat on a chair looking at a fish”. It
the unfolding of dream events on Cs recollection is strongly felt to
is not far-fetched to suppose that if the waking self is conscious of
represent the actual sequence during sleep, it is likely that events
five or six dream images, mundane or bizarre, it would be natural
in the dream are simultaneous or nearly so and aligned in the
to order the images in such a way as to form a story that explains
most plausible sequence on recall. The absence of duration for
them. The mind strives for meaning and closure. The argument
dream events and for the dream self is consistent with their simul-
is that the dream images that actualize on waking under the pres-
taneous occurrence. Perhaps this is also an explanation for the
sure for meaning combine in a story that seems reasonable or
fluidity and melting of dream images that would not be clearly
fulfils or conveys a meaning or points to one. On this view, the
demarcated in a contracted duration.
temporal order not apparent in the dream on awakening is elabo-
Usually, when we awake, we first apprehend the dream as rated in or by the Cs self out of the thickness of the memory or
a whole. Then, we recount to ourselves or others the history of thought that is the dream experience.
events in the dream. The initial Csness of the dream takes in all or
A second point is that a content or event that is attributed to Ucs
most of the events for which recall is possible, though missing de-
cognition — a dream, a language error, a pathological image — can
tails may be filled in later. Once we grasp the whole of the dream,
be understood as referring to a category of thought, language or
we struggle to revive the main events even as they slip away. It
perception out of which the image materializes. The category, not
does seem that the dream is apprehended all at once on awaken-
its incidental content, the image, is the key to a description of the
236 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 237

Ucs. If one focuses only on the image, the Ucs seems populated Specifically, Ucs events are recurrent transitions of configured
by a variety of symbols, representations, mechanisms, agencies, phases that, in dream, terminate prematurely or, in waking cogni-
faculties, not a succession of categories that individuate as they tion, continue to a Cs actuality. Except for symptom formation,
actualize, on waking from sleep, or in lesion-effects. there is no direct access to Ucs cognition, but special methods
allow us to infer covert phases of concept, feeling and meaning.
It is hypothesized that categories traversed in the succession of Such phases are not easily transposed to the dreamwork, since
states congeal, or are suspended, in the simultaneity of the dream, experimental methods that rely on differential speed and accu-
or the state on waking. The fact that categories are often conceived racy tend to show the contribution of the phase to final cognition,
as timeless may add to their collective simultaneity. This means not actual contents referable to the phase. The dream image is
that the categories that underlie the dream images, not the im- an instance, a singularity, from which a variety of mechanisms
ages themselves, are the true bearers of the process and the textual are inferred, while experimental studies use instances to sample
underpinnings of what becomes Cs. Pathological symptoms (see categories. An example follows.
below) show that an image samples a category that could deposit
any one of a number of possible items. This may be the case in Semantic priming33 demonstrates Ucs effects of lexical catego-
dream as well. ries on word recognition. Activating the category facilitates the
elicitation of member items. The Ucs category is preferentially
activated by words related in meaning or sharing properties with
the preceding item. The individual is not Cs that semantic prim-
ing occurs. Global aphasics show enhanced priming but give no
9.3. Probing the Ucs evidence they comprehend the stimulus words. How does the
Conventional methods of exploring Cs or Ucs brain function, in experimental technique of priming relate to dream? In dream,
which regions of the brain are connected by fibre pathways, are word-images are related in novel ways to other words or situa-
for the most part based on the synaptic model (Cajal, 1954), i.e. tions. The dream engages the same phase, e.g. lexical-semantics,
firings of single neurons or bundles of neurons in columns or but instead of showing the influence of common properties on
brain regions. Distributed systems or networks are imagined as rapid activation, the common properties blend words from dispa-
compilations of linked atomic units. Alternative methods to inves- rate categories to evoke the word spontaneously.
tigate field or wave effects, fractal, chaos or oscillatory systems, or
population dynamics, are neither widely employed nor fully devel- For example, in a dream I offered a room in a German hotel
oped. Most imaging studies localize functions rather than display to my American editor of a German company (Springer-Verlag),
mental or neural process. Older studies of mica gel or aluminum whose surname was Zimmar. I recall saying something like,
foil in neocortex, or cortical under-cuttings, appeared to refute “Would you like ein Zimmer, Mr. Zimmar?”, and on waking was
the concept of cortical fields, and dissuaded many from research amused at the play of words. The pun on Zimmer/Zimmar com-
in this area, even to the point of eliminating Gestalt psychology.32 bines disparate categories — room, person — that have the same
The microgenetic postulate of a wave-like transition over distrib- property (name). The pun derives from the explicit recognition
uted evolutionary growth planes has not yet been submitted to of this relation. The cross-language effect and the German pub-
experimental test. lisher may be relevant. I would argue that the same phase that

33
In brief, subjects are required to make decisions as to word or non-word
when preceded by a related or non-related item that is flashed too quickly to be
32
Wertheimer attributed the demise of the Gestalt to the “piecemeal thinking” recognized. Other methods include masking and metacontrast. The relation of
of the Americans. the technique to microgenesis (perceptgenesis) is described in Smith et al, (1989)
238 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 239

is entrained in priming is elicited in the dream. Semantic prim- Fig. 9.1. Top: In dream or schizophrenia, a word like “throne”
ing activates words in the same class or that belong to multiple might individuate the category of furniture based on properties
categories, e.g. the word shovel might prime the words snow shared with other members. Or, the category might be evoked
and rake. The shared attributes may link separate categories of by items from another category, e.g. parents. Here, the overlap of
which the prime is a member. In dream, shared attributes result attributes determines the replacement. Thus, ruler might serve as
in the fusion of words or objects across different classes, as in this a bridge across the disparate categories of furniture and parents,
example, where the word Zimmar as a surname, and the word or “father” might be the link to “king”, or the image of a throne.
Zimmer as a common noun, underlie the association of person
and room. Were I to simply dream of entering a room in a German Bottom: Shared properties are the basis of resemblance and
hotel, a relation to my editor would be implicit. The room might, category membership. Asked to name a chair, an aphasic might
on analysis, be found to symbolize the editor, but this interpreta- say “table”. Either word — chair or table — could individuate the
tion would depend on a knowledge of my prior experience, not a category as both share properties of the class. The lesion causes
play of word-categories of (hotel) room, German (book, publisher, retardation in process at a phase of word specification where chair
room) and so on (see: Fig. 9.1.). and table are covalent. If the patient says, “chair”, though correct,
the word tends not to have the precision of reference of normal
subjects. It is more holophrastic, like the “daddy” of a child for all
men, or doggy for animals. Functional or experiential properties
can determine errors, as when a patient says “sit” for chair. The
patient with paraphasic errors, e.g. “table” for chair, is often un-
aware that naming is erroneous (see text below et seq.).

The phase transition that explains such phenomena has the


character of a whole-part relation governed by intrinsic regulari-
ties. Whether a thought takes the form of logic or paralogic de-
pends on what segment of the individuation dominates the final
actuality. When preliminary whole/part relations involve subject
and predicate there is paralogic. When they concern objects and
properties, there is dream symbolism, animism or creative think-
ing. An example of paralogic is given below34 (see Fig. 9.1.). Dream
symbols exhibit this relation (von Domarus, 1944) when different
objects (wholes) are identified through an overlap in properties
(parts), e.g., a penis visualized as a knife owing to the shared attri-
butes of shape, penetration, etc. It is possible that the word knife
could prime the word penis, but in dream one image replaces the

34
The syllogism, Jesus Christ had a beard/I have a beard/I am Jesus Christ, or
I am a virgin/Mary is a virgin/ I am the Virgin Mary, are such examples. This
relates to animistic fusions, such as: Akiba is swift/tigers are swift/Akiba is (has
the living spirit of) a tiger (Lévy-Bruhl, 1935/1983).
240 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 241

other based on common attributes. The image represents a cat- are given meanings instead of being perceived as random or
egory (whole) and the exchange of categories depends on shared probabilistic indicates how difficult it is for most people to accept
properties (parts). At a phase of logical relations, shared parts that the greater number of life’s events are contingent rather than
underlie similarity, not sameness. The whole/part relations that meaningful. The tendency to project meaning on to impersonal
guide the developing pattern have a different expression accord- events is nearly irresistible, because all objects individuate out of
ing to the changing “substrate” on which they operate. A central meaning-laden phases in the mind. The material world may have
thesis of microgenetic theory is that a single process is iterated at meaning for us but it is not, or does not appear to be, intrinsically
multiple phases rather than multiple processes acting at different meaningful. The intuition that perceptual objects realize inchoate
loci. meanings in the mind of the observer motivates a search for mean-
ing in the world, in the Ucs, or in a transposition of personal mean-
Most thinking is relational and not easily forced into a logi- ing to nature, spirit or deity.
cal framework. The statement, John is virtuous (handsome, etc.)
is neither true nor false, but related to context, perspective and What is the relation of the subjectivity of dream to the “objec-
circumstance. The transition from whole to part gives the ap- tivity” of other life events that do not necessarily possess meaning
pearance of operations that conform to modes of logic, but the but manifest it in the endogenous trends of the visual and verbal
shift from Ucs to Cs thought involves increasing discrimination, imagination? Dreams express the mind of the dreamer. After all,
partition and specificity of reference, and a diminished emphasis what else could they express? But do events in dream have in-
on predication that is not reducible to a change from primitive to trinsic meaning? Do they conform to a meaning or arise out of
rational logic, as in the analysis of myth (Lévi-Strauss, 1962/1966). interpretation? If I spend a day in the park and then dream of
One can describe some aspects of Ucs thought in terms of logic bears, the dream can be explained by the revival of the category
(e.g. Blanco, see Rayner, 1995), e.g. the account of the paralogical of forest, of which a wooded park might be an instance, along
syllogism, but this does not imply that thought is driven by the with the animals that live in a forest. This is a banal occurrence,
logic. The logic reflects the dominant patterns, trends or regulari- since a walk in the park could as well evoke the image of a bear
ties extracted from the thought content, not rules that determine in Cs thought. Other events are explained by metaphoric exten-
what that content will be. Studies in logic reveal a tendency for sion. A bear calls up a pet cat in the category of animals, which
dichotomies, which arise from the fact that the mind is oblivious in turn calls up events relating to that animal, e.g., people who
to process or transition, thus more sensitive to oppositions than have come in contact with the pet, loss, death, and so on. As in
continuities, with the result that polarities become artificial sta- the Zimmer example, the word “bear” may call up the homonym,
bilities that anchor the continua. “bare”, which then arouses other contexts, memories, desires.
The propagation of images is driven by trends in thought, and the
The “logic” of the dream and recurrent patterns of symbolism experience and personality of the dreamer, as well as by general
imply intrinsic lawfulness or regularity. The feeling of lawfulness categories, such as childhood, sexuality and death which, though
and an intuition of the transition from meaning to form impel a universal experiences, are not necessarily universal symbols or
search for meaning in dream events. In waking life we do not ask archetypes. Dreams in psychoanalysis are the currency of clinical
if every event has a meaning. We accept the contingencies of life, insight and treatment, though not every dream affords a penetrat-
accidents, illness, and so on, without having to assign each event a ing interpretation. Analysis fills in a narrative by adding to its co-
meaning. Of course, there are people who say that someone who herence in a way that resonates with needs in the subjective life
suffers a misfortune got what he deserved, or that evil is eventu- as well as in the world.
ally punished, if not in this life, the next, or that natural disasters,
earthquakes, tsunamis, are god’s will. The fact that such events
242 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 243

The degree of distortion in dream points to the phase in mi- retroactive interpretation. Why should a set of random images be
crogenetic process that is accentuated. It is likely that the more felt to have a lack of closure in Cs interpretation? These observa-
bizarre the symbolism, the more archaic the phase, while lucid tions imply that one should avoid over-interpreting a given image,
dreams are close to waking cognition. The individual has a run- or treating it too literally, since it reveals the category that is the
ning Csness of the dream. This might suggest that dreams have true conveyer of meaning, in addition to the narrative supplied by
psychic attributes rather than taking them on in Cs thought. In the subject. The dreamer can take what he wants from the imag-
lucid dreams, the self appears not to be fully passive, and may ery, but its import is what it points to, or derives from, namely the
achieve the detachment, even the agency, of the waking self that categorical structure of an individual mind.
spans a succession of images. In daydreams and reveries, there is
also a flow of images, at times coherent, at other times not. The Such an account of dream does not, of course, retain the Ucs
proximity of these states to an empirical or Cs self may explain the agencies and distorted traces of psychoanalysis, nor does it make
actualization of the categories. That is, the lucidity corresponds too much of the significance of a specific image. Dream is not a
with a Cs self that accounts for the occurrence of images instead recombination of affectively-charged (cathected) memory traces
of categories. Indeed, a flow of categories would give no content (drive-representations). The interpretation of the dream tells us
to the dream, and a self without objects would disappear. more about the dreamer than the content that is interpreted. For
microgenetic theory there is no uncorrupted trace, no store and
The dream is a mode of Csness conditioned by early phases no retrieval. The “trace” is the full transition over neural configu-
in space, time, language, perception and self, organized accord- rations or psychic categories that participate in its actualization.
ing to metaphoric and other pre-rational relations. Phases buried The personality determines, and is determined by, this categori-
in waking mentation that come to the fore in primitive thought, cal structure. Every act, object and thought passes through an
psychosis and the creative imagination are continuous with Cs infrastructure that begins with the core self, leads through dream
thought, as the Ucs category transports the forming object to a cognition, to rational thought. The entire process of transition is
final actuality. The importance of dream to theory of mind is that the trace.
the relations exhibited in the dream content, not the content it-
self, like the symptoms of brain injury, are clues to the categorical
precursors of waking objects. On this theory, dream images retain
their importance as representatives of categories of thought that ex-
press personal meaning. However, the meaning is interpreted along 9.4. Dream recall
the lines of primitive cognition and whole/part relations at succes- Parenthetically, the account of dream as a narrative that articu-
sive points in the trajectory of a thought, regardless of the narrative lates the simultaneous apprehension of the dream content in the
achieved on waking. Dream is a mode of cognition that prefigures temporal order of waking cognition, is similar to descriptions of
Cs thought. The narrative has meaning for the dreamer, but the the creative process, in which a work is sensed or imaged as a
categories behind the narrative are of greater significance for whole prior to being worked out in detail (Chapters 2 and 12). This
theory of mind. process applies not only to the rare event of having the whole of
a symphony or literary work in the mind at once, but to the more
The idea that Csness interprets images that actualize on waking common experience of an inchoate thought as a totality that, over
does not entail that images are random, since psychic categories time, is realized, serially, in composition. As in the progression
are prioritized thoughts. The attempt to prolong a pleasant dream from the whole of the dream to the events in its recall, or from Ucs
that is interrupted by an awakening, or any incomplete dream, to Cs thought, the category is depleted in the art work as potential
indicates that dream is not a set of random images combined in a achieves existence in actual fact.
244 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 245

The paralogical, animistic, mythic, magical or supernatural symbolism, did not occur in the dream, so it is not the dream, but
character of dream is typical of subsurface cognition. The promi- sleep that relates, if it does, to consolidation, with the dream aris-
nence of long-term memory and rapid forgetting imply cognitive ing for reasons other than memory storage or assimilation. This is
“depth”. The forgetting may be related to state-specificity. It may not to say dream is unnecessary, but to raise a question as to its
also be impelled by the memorial quality of the events to be re- role in the “consolidation” of memory. If the dream, as some ar-
membered, since actual experience is ordinarily more durable gue, consists of the least-noticed fragments of the day, one might
than reflection. But the principle explanation of dream-forgetting predict such fragments would be the best-recalled. The memory
is the realization of sequential order on waking. In this respect, of events early in life more likely reflects the elaboration of early
there is a similarity with iconic memory, which is the immediate, phases in long-term and experiential memory that were implicit
Ucs, ephemeral apprehension of the whole of a presentation. In in the waking experience to which the symbolism of the dream
iconic memory, experimental probes indicate a capacity well be- refers (Brown, 1988; 1996).
yond that implied by the recall of constituent items. The effort to
specify the contents corresponds with, and perhaps is responsible The process of dreaming is embedded in every waking
for, the loss of the memorial whole. This suggests one account of thought. Dream is endogenous infrastructure liberated from the
the forgetting of dream, namely, that the attempt to revive and se- constraints of sense data. The gaining of reality in the transition to
rially order the contents partly explains their loss. The “all at once” wakefulness is occasioned by sensory limitations on pre-percep-
of an iconic gestalt is fractionated to a serial order of episodes with tual phases. A dream hallucination, like hallucination in the wak-
only those images revived that serve the narrative, while the shift ing state, is an incomplete object (Brown, 1988). The gradations
from simultaneity to succession alone entails loss of elements. of visual imagery from the near-veridical (eidetic) to the fantastic
retrace the development of an object outward to the world. A simi-
Presumably, the more rational or commonplace the dream, lar phenomenon occurs in verbal imagery. Errors in sleep-talking
the less the disparity between depth and surface and the more (Arkin and Brown, 1971), in REM and NREM sleep, are like those
likely it is recalled though bizarre dreams may leave such an in aphasia, in that they expose early phases in language produc-
impression they are never forgotten. If so, this suggests that the tion (see below).
dream state itself figures more importantly in recall than the con-
tent. Specifically, the microgenetic characteristics of the dream
state, independent of the contents, determine the potential for Cs
realization. In addition, the frequent occurrence of events that di-
rectly or symbolically point to the remote past argues that dream 9.5. Ucs imagery and the unremembered dream
is not a mere re-working or consolidation of the previous day’s This interpretation suggests an account of Ucs phases while they
occurrences. Were the dream to consolidate the memories of the are Ucs, i.e. before they actualize as dream or as symptoms of pa-
preceding day, it would take the length of the day for all percep- thology. In this account, the Ucs consists of phase-transitions like
tions to be consolidated, though the simultaneous nature of the those of waking cognition, in which neural configurations that
dream does open the possibility that a multiplicity of events can correspond with categories of incipient thoughts arise, perish and
be compressed in a minimal thickness of subjective time. recur. In dreams that are not recalled, the categories are abstract
potentials not embodied in actual contents. What is the role of, or
If one awakens a dreamer after each of the six or more dreams need for, imagery without a self as witness? It is likely that the self
in a night, one could, in principle, record events pertaining to the of dream, which makes a brief appearance on waking, arises as
preceding day, and find that most of the day’s events have not an intra-psychic segment necessitated by its extra-personal exten-
been dreamt of, or that, even in the most liberal interpretation of sion in the image. Dream images or events may be apprehended
246 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 247

by a self that is vivid or in the background. Usually, such events are experienced and described. What is it like to experience a mental
“perceived” as actual happenings in the world, but the self is felt category independent of its constituent items?
to flow with the dream, changing with the changing content. Such
observations imply that the self, like its images, is also a category We all have the experience of searching for a word with some
in the process of image-formation, a necessary category if the im- idea of its category. If I am trying to remember the word vicuna,
ages arise from it, as postulated in waking imagery and perception. I can have a more or less vivid picture of the animal. Here, the
Put differently, the dream self is necessitated by the subject-object visual image actualizes in place of the verbal one. If I could neither
divide as images develop to an extra-personal locus. picture the animal, nor its size or shape, what kind of experience
would this be like? In Ucs thought that never achieves Csness, a
In the waking state, thought is more likely preceded by cat- transition of categories might leave a unique trace according to
egories than specific contents or Ucs representations. If I say the the kinds of categories that are generated, e.g. animals, vacations,
word “chair”, or see a chair, one supposes a background lexical haunted houses, etc. However, it is unlikely that the imprint of
category or object-concept out of which the word or object is this transition on thought would have the same effect for dreams
specified. The difference between dream and wakefulness is that, that are recalled as for those not remembered, for the latter do not
in dream, there is premature specification of the categories. If the have the same quality of existence. A ghost takes on greater reality
specification results on waking, the status of an unseen image or as an image than as a category of spirits.
Ucs phase in waking thought would be comparable to that of an
unrecollected dream. Though a sequence of categories is likely, Only a fraction of life is lived in actuality. A good part is spent
its demonstration may not be possible. Thus, it is conceivable that in non-productive sleep and in dreams that are not remembered.
the ordinary view of dream is correct, that categories decant into What is the fate of such dreams? The short story by Garcia Marquez,
visual or verbal images prior to becoming Cs (see below). The con- “Eyes of a blue dog”, ends with a woman’s accusation, “You’re the
cordance of laughter, crying, orgasm or sleep talking with later-re- only man who doesn’t remember anything of what he’s dreamed
called dream events suggests psychic correlates, as the occasional when he wakes up.” Is he any the worse for this? Is this a blessing
description of animals grasping at what appear to be imaginary or a curse? How does he differ from someone — Jung is the great
objects suggests hallucinatory, i.e. dream-like, experience in ani- example — who remembers his dreams, analyzes and talks about
mals without human Csness, thus phenomenal experience in the them?
aware, but non-Cs, organism.
Suppose a person awakens from a nightmare that leaves him
With some exceptions, the weight of evidence supports a shaking for days. There is often a powerful effect on a person of a
transition of categories without definite psychic correlates, unless terrifying dream. This is especially true for the classical nightmare
something happens to collapse the category to an image. For ex- (Jones, 1949) with paralysis and suffocation. But if the person
ample, the headboard in the dream of Maury provided the sense sleeps through the dream without awakening, there seems to be
data to actualize an image of a guillotine. A similar effect occurs a negligible effect on subsequent thought. It may be that a night
when one dreams of church bells and awakens to the ring of an of troublesome but unremembered dream accounts for being
alarm clock. Such categories do not need labels, e.g. things that out of sorts the following day, but to my knowledge, this has not
strike your neck or morning noises. Though we speak of catego- been demonstrated, perhaps not even investigated. How could it
ries such as food or furniture, it is not clear how a mental category be without waking the person to determine if the dreams were
is to be characterized. The progressive zeroing-in on the lexical upsetting? What is the difference between sleeping through a bad
concept arrives at a phase — the word — where the content can be dream and waking to it? The “night terrors” of children do not ap-
pear to leave lasting effects unless the child wakes up. Waking trig-
gers the panic. What does it mean to sleep through a nightmare?
248 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 249

“Ucs terror” is terrifying but only in relation to Csness. A person tom (below) in that it specifies a semantic category into a distinct
can be more frightened by the not-known than the known. The item.
objects of anxiety are unresolved. Panic attacks often arise for
reasons of which the person is unaware. This does not show the The difference in sleep talking or other motor reactions in REM
existence of Ucs content in Cs thought; rather, the emphasis on or NREM sleep would seem moot now that evidence has accrued
an Ucs segment of thought that has not fully resolved. In effect, for a two-way dissociation of REM and dream. The more interest-
it points to the tension within or across categories rather than an ing, if unanswerable, question is, what does it mean for a person
elicitation of definite Ucs content. to sleep through a nightmare or any dream? In what sense does
(did) it exist? What is the impact, if any, on subsequent waking
We see people who are agitated in sleep. We hear them cry thought and behavior? Something exists for us directly when we
out; we say they are having a restless sleep or unsettling dream. are Cs of it; indirectly, because of effects that can be felt, measured
If we wake them, they may describe a frightening dream. Once I or experienced in other ways. Do unrecollected dreams that are
was awakened from sleep when I was heard gasping for breath, never Cs and without demonstrable effects, even if others witness
and on being awakened, I recounted, trembling, that a giant clam outward manifestations, exist for that person as experience, i.e.
had my leg in its grip and I was drowning. Of course, the possibil- other than as brain activity, and if so, how can that mode of exis-
ity exists that, as in the Maury dream, a narrative was invented tence be described? If waking gives dream its character, content
on waking to explain the difficulty in breathing, which may have and affect, the lack of recollection of a dream, or any event that is
had a very different cause. I have also laughed in sleep and, when not experienced, known, demonstrated or derived, lends uncer-
awakened, have not necessarily related a funny experience. tainty to its existence.
Similar anecdotes with variable concordance are reported in
Arkin (1981). There is the poet who dreamt what seemed of earth-
shaking import. She awoke and wrote it down, then returned to
sleep and, in the morning, read what she had written, which as
I recall was: hogamus, higamus, men are polygamous, higamus, 9.6. Dream and memory
hogamus, women monogamous. One could also ask why waking experience tends to be remem-
bered and dream interpreted? Waking images affect or constitute
Sleep-talking studies are not conclusive on the concordance one’s life; dream images have meanings to the dreamer and may
of verbalization with dream content, which differs with REM and have some slight relevance to one’s life but they are not constitu-
NREM dreams (Arkin, 1981). At least half the time, there is con- tive or ingredient. One says, my life consisted of such and such ex-
cordance, whether literal, symbolic or interpretive, but one could periences, but dreams are usually not among them.35 Perceptual
maintain that sleep speech actualizes categories of verbal imagery objects arouse categories in their voyage to external space, but the
that, on being awakened, determine the corresponding categories constraints on this transit are strong, and it is mainly reflection,
of visualization. My wife talks in her sleep and when asked, on when the self withdraws to an introspective mode that revives
waking, about her dream, she usually reports either not dream- those categories out of which the object developed. If dream con-
ing or a thought unrelated to the speech content. If vocalization sists of categories that incidentally become images, the categories
in sleep shows unpredictable concordance with dream it may be or context will prevail over the image. This partly promotes the
because content is unsettled, i.e. indefinite (or categorical), at the search for meaning. Were dream to consist of a clear sequence of
moment of vocalization. If there is concordance, it may be driven
by the vocalization. Verbalizing in sleep is like an aphasic symp-
Jung (1961) is an extreme case, where his own dreams served as data for
35

much of his theory.


250 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 251

images, their experiential quality, even if apprehended as personal 9.7. Forgetting in dream and amnesia
or hallucinatory, would have a greater impact.
An unrecollected dream resembles a period of retrograde amne-
We know that a primary feature of many dreams is novelty. sia after head injury, in which the amnesia for recent events is like
Yet in spite of its inventiveness, a dream is felt to be a kind of that for the events of a dream. There may be an awareness of the
memory, and the dream report is felt to be a memory (recall) of a amnesic interval as an unfilled duration, as one has an awareness
memory (dream). The dream itself is not of an actual experience, of the interval of a sleep.37 When I awake during the night, before
while its recall is an immediate memory of a slightly less-immedi- looking at the clock, I often try to guess what time it is, and find my
ate memory, or thought, according to its novelty. The feeling of estimates are usually close. If I try to guess the duration of sleep
realness and actuality of a dream is an element in recall, or the to that point, the estimates are also fairly accurate. Many people
dream may be felt to be a thought or recollection. The memorial also have the experience of waking just before the alarm clock
quality derives from the subjectivity and uncoupling from direct goes off. The feeling of duration probably does not depend on the
sensation. The distinction of memory and thought reflects the sense of too much or too little sleep. If estimates of sleep interval
productive or reproductive character, i.e. the extent to which the are accurate, this would differ from a period of amnesia, which
dream brings forth new content. The distinction of dream-recall is markedly under-estimated, e.g. three months of post-traumatic
and waking perception is less sharp when one realizes that even amnesia is estimated as three weeks. One possible explanation for
waking experience has a memorial quality. the under-estimation is the inability to recall events in the interval,
thus punctuate and so “stretch out” duration. “Unfilled” durations
The explanation of this phenomenon probably lies in the dif- are felt as shorter. This should apply as well to uninterrupted sleep.
ference between the dream self and the Cs self in relation to the If what passes in continuous sleep is non-psychic, its felt duration
present moment. The Cs present is a span over physical passage should follow the pattern of amnesia, namely, a marked collapse
within which successive events are perceived. In contrast, the to a briefer period. Conversely, if estimates of sleep duration are
dream present is a knife-edge of change, without past or future. accurate, it would argue for Ucs psychic experience.
When we recall a dream, we sense that the feeling of duration is
not possible in the dream, only on its waking articulation.36 The Another resemblance of sleep and post-traumatic amnesia
self, swept along by the dream events, is itself an image along with concerns some aspects of the quality of recall. When confabula-
others in the dream. In all likelihood, the self is an image depos- tory amnesics are given emotionally-laden stories to remember,
ited as an intra-psychic category out of which the dream image the content is transformed according to the “laws of the dream-
develops. On waking, a Cs self spans the apparent progression work” (Betlheim and Hartmann, 1951), e.g., a rape is recalled as
of the dream-events, an overview of which is not possible for the a woman perishing in a fire. There is also amnesia for the period
dream self, which does not reflect on past events, nor have them just prior to losing Csness, in concussion and in sleep. Are dreams
available in the present of the dream. There is usually no feeling of
agency for ongoing events, no prediction, no anticipation and no 37
Many years ago, using a Zeigarnik technique of incomplete (interrupted)
expectancy. This is not surprising if the dream self, like the wak- tasks on falling asleep and questioning the subject in the morning, I attempted to
ing self, occurs as an early category in a simultaneous state determine whether “sleeping on a problem” helps in its solution. The results of a
pilot study were unclear, but the problem deserves to be revisited, for a positive
result would indicate that thought occurs during a night when a subject does not
awake. The demonstration of learning during anesthesia is suggestive in this re-
gard, but this does not show spontaneous cognition, only that verbal material can
36
Even in waking experience the sense of past duration depends on the recall be introduced and saved in some sense during a non-Cs state, perhaps analogous
of events during the interval. In amnesics, the estimation of duration is markedly in some ways to hypnotic trance. Learning occurs in all organisms irrespective of
contracted. Csness.
252 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 253

that do not rise to Csness similar to memories that sink beneath 9.8. The symptom as a clue to Ucs cognition
it? That is, are dreams that are not recalled like events that were
once Cs but have since been forgotten? Such events can be ac- One of Freud’s more important insights was the recognition that
cessed, if at all, by a retreat into subjectivity, by re-dreaming the psychopathological symptoms are not additions but uncoverings.
same dream, or a progression over successive nights in a dream Microgenetic theory extends this principle to the symptoms of fo-
narrative. This was described by William James, who also won- cal brain damage. A symptom such as a word-substitution, e.g.
dered if he was getting mixed up in other people’s dreams. Access saying table when asked to name a chair, or an error of the object-
may be aided by hypnosis or other forms of regression. Aural phe- concept, e.g. confusing a fork with a cup, or a derailment of action,
nomena just prior to seizures that are not recalled can be revived or a phenomenon such as hallucination or delusion, represents
by stimulating the epileptogenic area in the brain. Most of us have a momentary incompleteness and/or derailment in the normal
moments of uncertainty as to whether a past event was a “real” process of language or percept formation. Instead of a full trans-
experience or a dream. There are (rare) patients with brain injury formation leading to an object adapted to the external situation,
who say they do not know if they are awake or dreaming (Luria, phases that bear the maximal brunt of pathology either actualize
1972). Uncertainty as to the actual and the memorial are sweetly directly, say in hallucination, or as nested substitutions, as in ag-
recorded in the ode of Keats: nosia, that are carried through to the terminal phase. Recognition
and recall of errors are less adept than successful performances.
Was it a vision or a waking dream? To a varying degree, the different forms of normal and pathologi-
cal imagery are embryonic perceptions.
Fled is that music — do I wake or sleep?
The relevance of the symptom to a theory of the Ucs is two-fold:
There are instances in which a nightmare announces the im- (1) As images that are meaningful to the dreamer are arbitrary
minent recall of amnesic events in the interval prior to an accident. members of categories, symptoms are similarly arbitrary, but
A patient of mine with a retrograde amnesia did not recall being they do reveal phases that are otherwise opaque to observation by
in an accident in which his fiancé was killed, nor did he show an the self or others. The invisible process displayed in a symptom
affective reaction when he was repeatedly told what happened. illuminates the phase to which it refers. Symptoms are signposts
As recall improved, he developed nightmares for some days prior of categories in brain process when injury deposits a member
to the return of sufficient recall to ask what occurred in the ac- item. The same reasoning applies to dream. Withdrawal to ear-
cident, at which point, when told, he was overcome with grief. The lier segments in object-formation deposits images as markers of
nightmares, however, were not directly about the accident; they categories. (2) the interpretation of the symptom in relation to its
reflected the anxiety that forecasted the recall. That dreams revive ambient context reinforces the concept of dream as a “collection”
forgotten material or affective tonalities that cannot otherwise be of categories. Dream arises in closer proximity to experiential
derived to Csness raises questions as to how Cs and Ucs “experi- memories. Focal symptoms tend to be superficial and delimited,
ence” is to be understood; specifically, if what is inaccessible to yet one could readily string them together in a narrative related to
Csness and indiscernible in its effects counts as personal experi- the personality. The symptom has value as a counterweight to the
ence (see below). everyday notion that dream images are the subjective equivalent
of objects, i.e. components of “real” episodes. The ordinary view
is powerful and its vocabulary ingrained. The idea of categories
that undergo specification seems at odds with commonsense. But
this interpretation gains strength on a closer look at the process of
symptom-formation.
254 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 255

9.9. The symptom in imagery, perception and studies, image and object are usually attributed to different sys-
tems with overlapping mechanisms.
language
A symptom of brain damage, such as an abnormal image or In contrast, the microgenetic claim is that hallucination devel-
wrong word, arises when an object or lexical category actualizes ops over the same substrate as perception; objects are externalized
prematurely. Symptoms refer to normal but earlier phases in images, images are attenuated objects. Early studies demonstrat-
mental process, when the phase (category of language, percep- ing the identity of the substrate for image and object39 have been
tion, etc.) is disrupted. Categories that are normally transformed ignored, partly because of disinterest in historical research, but
leave symptoms as markers of the upstream disruption. The also because the research was mostly descriptive. When images
whole-part relation, i.e. the context-to-item or category-to-mem- are conceived as phases in perception, an account of the charac-
ber transition, actualizes an exemplar that might otherwise serve teristics of the phase from which the image arises is possible.
as a potential for ensuing phases. The theory of a symptom as Damage to perceptual cortex does not “release” an image but ex-
an exposed category is a theory of mind, not just an argument poses it before it objectifies. Epileptic irritation arouses pre-object,
about neurological patients. The origin of symptoms as signatures e.g. hallucinatory, phases in a developing modality.40 The psychol-
of phases in relation to the phase-sequence is also a description ogy is tied to a dynamic neurology, with the image an instance in
of the mind/brain state, thus a description of an act of thought. a category exposed in its transition. Novelty is continuous, and
The various contents that actualize in this transition — feelings, lies in the potential of the category, and its transformation over
thoughts, words, images — are outcomes of Ucs process that come phases when sensory constraints are relaxed. In sum, the argu-
into Cs relief.38 Some examples may help illustrate this idea. ment is that Ucs or sub-surface phases are categories, not images,
the image arising when the category discharges or is disrupted.

Consider imagery and hallucination. The fundamental miscon- The lifting of sensory constraints in dream, in pathology, or in
ception that has plagued neuropsychology for over a century is sensory deprivation, reinforces the sense of a fully endogenous
that sensory data, after input to visual cortex, are assembled to development. According to the locus of the disruption, the result
objects that are mapped to memory images for recognition. The can range from a fantastic hallucination to an eidetic image of pic-
images are stored in secondary visual areas, adjacent to primary torial quality that is nearly veridical. Hallucination tends to arise at
cortex or in regions of the temporal lobe. Apart from its pernicious early formative phases of personal memory and feeling. At a phase
effect on all aspects of neuropsychology, as well as epistemology, closer to the world, a disruption gives illusion. The difference is
the assembly/store/retrieval model entails that hallucination oc- not that hallucination is a mental image and illusion a distortion
curs when the center or storehouse of images is activated or dis- of a physical object, but the elicitation of an image at successive
inhibited, or when damage to visual and auditory areas “releases” points in the object-formation. Whether there is hallucination or
memory-image centers, or when seizure activity evokes halluci- illusion is determined by the proximity of the disruption to early
nation by exciting the centers. In this theory, an image is a dis- or late cognition. Hallucination is early and psychic, and usually
inhibited memory. There is no account of novelty. The psychology
is tied to the neurology of association, i.e. damage to areas and
pathway interruption. In spite of their resemblance on research 39
Lhermitte (1951), Morel (1936), De Morsier (1938), Ey (1973), inter alia
(Brown, 1988).
38
Introspection occurs when a self that is Cs of images is embedded in a Csness
of objects. This represents a coming-to-the-fore of earlier phases in a full object- 40
Horowitz and Adams (1970) argue that images on temporal lobe stimulation
development. The symptom is not a ceiling on this development, except when are not discrete elements but arise in the context of a dream-like state induced
the object world is lost. Then one has dream or psychosis. by the excitation.
256 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 257

appears as an intrusion into private space; illusion is late, “physi- the error — is conveyed into the final phase of the object-develop-
cal” and usually appears as a distortion of “public” space. ment, that of featural detail. The agnosia involves the selection
of an object in an array of objects in the same category, i.e. the
Organic and drug-induced hallucinations may unfold in a wrong exemplar in the category. The counterpart of the symptom
dream-like progression yet the patient does not seek meaning in aphasia is a wrong word arising in the same lexical category as
as he does for dream. Perhaps this is because waking hallucina- the target.
tions seem arbitrary and, unlike dreams, are sustained in Csness.
They may be frightening or entertaining, bizarre or conventional, In the second type of agnosia, usually with occipito-parietal le-
familiar or unrecognizable, but they do not usually evoke a psy- sions, a fork may be called a chisel or screwdriver. Here, the prob-
chological interpretation, except for verbal hallucinations in lem is the perception of form, not meaning. This variety involves
schizophrenia, where the persecutory nature can be analyzed the specification of (the category of) object shape, size, etc., after
in terms, say, of the sources of paranoid delusion. The Ucs origin meaning has been established. The difficulty selecting the object
of dreams, their compression in a brief duration and need for in an array of perceptually similar objects is independent of the
serialization, motivate the need for interpretation. The ordering object-concept. Again, the problem, now in the domain of form, is
of dream images into a narrative is already an interpretation, so in eliciting the part, i.e. the figural detail, from a background whole,
that the ordering, more than the images, promotes a further drive or gestalt, or in giving evidence the whole is perceived when the
to meaning-analysis. The temporal order of the Cs experience of perception of the parts appears to be defective. This type of agno-
scenic hallucination tends to mitigate the need for interpretation. sia is important in showing that the whole is not constructed from
Organic hallucinations are often distorted snapshots, less like the the parts but is antecedent to them. We see the preservation of the
symbolic images of dreams. whole in the presence of object-meaning even though the object
does not appear to be adequately perceived. This is demonstrated
If hallucination is the productive or phenomenal aspect of by having the patient select the category of the object, or a con-
pathology in the perceptual system, agnosia is the negative or de- ceptually-related object, on a forced choice test.41
ficiency aspect. Agnosia, a term thought to be first used by Freud,
involves the object perception, not the image, but the image is the This “dissociation” can also be seen in ordinary behavior. One
subjective side of a perceptual defect, and the types of agnosia are of my patients could not copy a triangle or count a small number
similar to those of pathological imagery. Defective phases that are of lines or dots on a paper, or discriminate simple shapes, but he
exposed in hallucination and illusion are buried in agnosia. The was able to take the elevator to the hospital cafeteria, order and
two major forms of agnosia — disorders of concept (meaning) and pay for a meal, and find his way back to the ward, walking with
discrimination (form) — can be distinguished on testing. In the confidence, not groping like a blind man.42 The involvement of ob-
conceptual variety, usually with bilateral mesial temporal lesions, ject form or featural detail with preservation of the object-concept
the patient sees a fork and calls it a cup. The object is misidenti- or meaning, and the reverse, points to a two-way or double dis-
fied but can be copied, and named correctly by touch. The error sociation. While this dissociation has suggested to psychologists
is limited to the modality: visual, auditory, tactual. The accurate the existence of separate centers for the different functions, it is
perception of the fork, inferred from the ability to copy it, owes
to the sensory constraints, i.e. sculpting, on subsequent phases in 41
The patient is given only two choices, e.g. two object drawings or pictures,
object-development, while the conceptual derailment that arises and is “forced” to choose one, even though he may say that he cannot make out
at an antecedent phase is sustained into the endpoint. The patient what he has been shown. A score better than chance suggests an access to the
object-concept or its realization prior to the analysis into features at a Cs end-
sees a fork, copies it and names it by touch, but still calls it a cup, point.
because the conceptual substitution — the category sampled in
42
I have observed the same behavior in cases of “total” cortical blindness.
258 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 259

compatible with a continuum from meaning to form, as predicted forthcoming phase. One moment there is normal perception, the
by microgenetic theory. This is because focal lesions do not de- next, hallucination. One moment an object is misidentified, the
stroy function; they expose the process mediated by the damaged next, identified correctly. The symptom depends on the segment
area. in the microgeny where, at that moment, the pathology has maxi-
mum impact. Such observations imply a series of categories, not a
There are agnosic syndromes with comparable disturbances destruction of psychic entities or lack of access to them. The symp-
of recognition and discrimination for faces, routes, etc. An impor- tom links pathological to normal behavior, uncovering processes
tant point is that the distinction of meaning and form in agnosia ordinarily hidden from self and observer. Because the exposed
parallels that in the sphere of imagery, e.g. hallucination (meaning) process is Ucs, the person often has limited or no insight to the
and illusion (form). Agnosic errors of form are the objective cor- error. Indeed, “error awareness” and self-correction are generally
relates of illusion. Those of meaning are the objective correlates signs of more superficial involvement.
of hallucination. The progression is from the core constructs of
value, belief and personal meaning to word or object concept, The findings are more compelling in disorders of language,
then to form and featural detail (Fig. 9.2.). A disruption is an un- i.e. aphasia. The patient who names a chair a “table” samples
covering, not an interruption. The phase uncovered goes through the background category, i.e. furniture, out of which both words
normal subsequent processing. These disorders illustrate the fact arise (Fig. 9.1. bottom). He can usually point correctly to a chair
that each phase in the cascade of whole/part relations has the when asked to do so, though some patients can neither name the
potential for a multiplicity of contents, themselves categories for object nor, when asked to point to it, understand its name. Most
another wave of partition. naming errors are within category: red for blue, coat for shirt, arm
for hand, and so on. There can also be errors of experiential or
functional relations, e.g. glove for hand, tomato for red, bullfight
for guitar. Familiarity, word-frequency and concreteness play a
role as well as contrast and metaphor, e.g. black evoking white,
night, death. Category errors tend to reflect “typicality” effects43,
e.g. table is more commonly substituted for chair than lamp. The
“distance” of error from target is a sign of conceptual depth. This
is not greater inclusiveness but qualitative change, initially a shift
from abstract to experiential relations. In general, the more ab-
stract the relations, the more superficial the disruption; the less
abstract the relations, the more dream-like or delusional the sub-
stitution. Such errors occasionally occur in aphasia, but are often
seen in schizophrenia.

Fig. 9.2. The derivation goes from meaning to form — self to In confabulation and delusion, derailment is inter-sentential,
world — in perception, imagery and language. Imagery reveals the i.e., involves context at the level of the concept or phrase. In apha-
phase directly in errors. Such errors in aphasia and agnosia occur sia, substitution is intra-sentential, limited to the word or word-
spontaneously but can also be elicited on testing. concept. In the derivation of an utterance, the transition is from

Errors of imagery and perception actualize categories of Ucs 43


The core or prototypical item in a category, e.g. canary for bird, is a more
process, sampling context that would ordinarily morph into the common substitution, though there is a class of patients that tend to use less
familiar words, e.g. ostrich for bird, spectacles for glasses.
260 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 261

affective, personal and experiential relations to lexical category, In dream, experiential properties form novel categories within
then the elicitation of a “word frame”, then a similar — wide to which otherwise unrelated items are identified; or, one item re-
narrow — process of phoneme selection in the realization of the places another through the implicit mediation of the attribute.
syllables of the word. As in the relation of hallucination to agnosia, Thus, coffee might be the basis of a fusion of mug and Brazil. An
errors in language often parallel difficulty in the assignment of unpleasant experience in Brazil might lead to a dream of coffee
category membership. For example, words like fireplace, window or a mug. A “coffee date” might result in a dream of Brazil. The
and piano may be grouped with chair and table in the category of fusion of dream imagery and language is comparable to that of
furniture (Grober, Kellar, Perecman and Brown, 1980). The more schizophrenics. A schizophrenic patient gave his name as “foot-
elastic the boundaries the less specificity there is in word-use. This ball”, possibly because he felt he had been “kicked around” in his
corresponds in word production, to sampling errors in naming, life. The word was not used as a pun or a Cs metaphor, but as if it
where denotation is less precise. were his given name. The priority of the attribute or predicate is
prominent in paralogic. The prominence of predication44 indicates
Just as organic hallucinations can be related to schizophrenic that object-properties are laid down before the object is realized,
hallucinations, and both to normal perception, errors in aphasia can i.e. the predicate develops before the noun or object. Predicative
be related to language errors in dream and schizophrenia as well as relations are the context out of which objects arise. The genuine
to phases in normal language (Figs. 9.1.). The comparison rests on dynamic of predication is antecedent to the artificial demarcation
the understanding of whole/part relations. In abstract thought, a of objects. Similarly, the attributes of a noun are the dynamic out
property is a part of the whole. In the paralogic of schizophrenia of which it develops. They constitute a potential for other nouns.
or dream, the part (property) becomes a whole in relation to other Once a noun appears it is static, “thing-like”; its contextual under-
wholes. The part-as-whole enlists other categories in relation to it, pinnings can only be recaptured in a descent to earlier phases in
which then function as parts, e.g. when a schizophrenic woman noun generation.
thinks she is the Virgin Mary based on the shared property of vir-
ginity. The predication that underlies category membership be- In sum, an iterated specification of wholes (categories, con-
comes a category to which items in other categories are wedded. texts) into parts (properties, items), from earlier (past, intra-psy-
In the above example, virginity no longer modifies a woman, but chic) to later (present, extra-personal) phases, characterizes the
is a category to which they belong, or more precisely are iden- transitional series that constitutes the mind/brain state. Each
tified. The same fusion occurs in primitive thought (and in the phase in this transition is a category that “contains” innumerable
metaphor of creative imagery), for example when ferocity serves virtual members. Each category is itself in transition, individuat-
to unite a tiger with an individual. ing parts or sub-categories that continue the transformational
sequence. Normally, the succession of categories, or whole-part
In aphasia, when experiential properties determine word er- transformations, is an Ucs process that leads to a Cs endpoint. The
rors they tend to be within the word category. Substitutions such Cs endpoint incorporates the self and inner and outer segments.
as “sit” for chair or “eat” for table are not unusual. The charac- Pathology exposes phases in this transition. The particular form
teristic or defining properties of the objects commonly occur in of the pathology determines the phase that is disrupted and the
substitution, or circumlocution, in word-finding difficulty, in nor- symptom that follows. The symptom is an instance in the category
mal states of distraction, fatigue, and so on, e.g. “you drink coffee that happens to actualize when the phase is disrupted.
from it”, when a person cannot find the word “mug”. A normal
individual or aphasic is generally aware of the search and effort,
since knowledge of the properties of the object implies that the
noun and abstract reasoning are to some extent available. 44
Vygotsky (1962) wrote that inner speech was largely predicative since the
topic is known to the speaker.
262 Jason W. Brown

Thus, the symptom exposes the category behind it, of which


it is a potential outcome. The key to understanding the Ucs is the
succession of category-shifts. This is also the basis for an inter-
pretation of dream imagery in relation to pathological symptoms.
Microgenetic theory provides a coherent account of alterations in
perception and language in brain-damaged cases, schizophrenia
and normal dream, alterations that do not point to deviant brain
function, but illustrate the process that underlies the mind/brain
state. In this, the theory of the symptom — in language, percep-
tion, dream — is a theory of the mind.
Chapter 10
Psychology of Intentionality

10.1. Intention and intentionality


Intentionality (intentional) is a description of the directionality of
relations between phases in an act of thought or, more specifi-
cally, between the self and some internal or external content in
consciousness. Intention has a different meaning, and refers to a
feeling of agency that is specific to action or volition. Intention has
both a conscious (explicit) and unconscious (implicit) reference,
while intentionality is tied to states of consciousness. Except when
the unconscious reference for intention is marked implicit or Ucs,
the term will mean conscious intention, or intent. The conscious
perception of an object or the desire for an object is intentional,
but we do not ordinarily think that we have an intention to per-
ceive an object. An intention may cause an object to be perceived
in averting the eyes to the intended target, but consciousness of
the object is usually held to be passive or receptive, i.e. object per-
ception is intentional but not intended. The idea of perception as
active or productive (e.g. Bergson, 1944ed) has gained little trac-
tion over the years, but it would permit one to think of an external
object as the outcome of an intention.

The intention implicit in a perception is recaptured in its sub-


jective antecedents when we move back one step to the prefigur-
ing concepts, images or feelings. When consciousness is directed
to its internal antecedents, the self becomes conscious of the in-
tention or volitional feeling and choice that underlie the passivity
of object-perception. A thought-image can be altered in the imagi-
nation. We have the feeling of a voluntary effect on the image, as
well as choice in the image type. Under certain conditions, such as
expectancy and hallucination, the image can externalize, but then
it is apprehended as independent of the observer. The interpreta-
tion of such phenomena is that the volitional feeling (intention)
in a thought image becomes passive to an hallucinatory image
and is finally lost in perception when the image detaches as an
external object.
266 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 267

One might say the desire for (fear of, etc.) an object causes in such a way as to cause the act to occur. However, the intrinsic
the person to act on it, but a more accurate depiction is that the change that results in each content, i.e., the process of its becom-
intentionality of the mental state, which includes the feeling of ing, or actualization, passes from unconscious to conscious phas-
desire (fear), incorporates a direction toward or away from the es. Contents in consciousness are outcomes of the unconscious
target object. Desire, like fear, is not a definitive preliminary to processes leading to them, not starting points for novel occurrenc-
action. A desire that immediately captures an object or a fear that es. Physiological studies support this account in showing that the
escapes one is more like a drive. Desire has the object in thought. consciousness of an intention follows its onset (Libet, 1999). The
The desire for an object, like the fear of it, leads to an implicit or interpretation of this phenomenon (Brown, 1991) is that a concept
explicit phase of choice. Fear may lead to uncertainty or paralysis. discharges first into an idea (of the desired object), later into an
The desire for another person may not rise to the level of action action (to obtain it). In spite of the common sense notion that a
because of shyness, timidity or other circumstances. Satisfaction conscious idea leads to action, here is no causal bridge from idea
may be avoided to prolong desire. A delicious yet painful longing to act. Rather, a single concept serially actualizes or exhausts its
for an unobtainable other is a theme of romantic poetry. Desire potential (Fig. 10.1), first into the conscious idea, desire (or inten-
marks off an intentional state but does not signal an impulse to tion), then into the action.
act. It anticipates a decision as to whether or not to act, which then
may lead to the intention to satisfy the desire. A desire to visit the
Grand Canyon is not a desire to obtain, possess or even perceive
an object, e.g. a vista, but to have the experience of that perception.
It is an experiential and intentional state the goal of which is for
the individual to be in another experiential and intentional state.

The intention in intentionality would seem to cause or instigate


the action. To say, I intend to lift my arm, or that I have the idea
to lift my arm, and then lift the arm, assumes a causal link from
the intention to the action. However, the association of intention
and action merely points to separate and not necessarily consecu- Fig 10.1. Successive overlapping mental states. In the initial
tive, acts of cognition. In one mental state, the self is conscious of state, a concept delivers an idea (perception, image, etc.). In the
the intention, or the conceptual feeling directed to action. In the ensuing state, which may occur immediately or after a delay,
other, an action occurs, but this does not indicate the intention the same concept delivers another act, object or mental content.
causes the action no more than it assigns causal efficacy to any When a conscious idea (or intention) is followed by an action, the
preceding state of thought or memory. One can say the intention succession is interpreted as a causal sequence when, in fact, both
is superseded by the action, but the initial state can be followed by contents arise out of the same ground of conceptual feeling.
many intervening states that are unrelated or tangential to the ac-
tion, or the action may not occur. Intention occurs with and with- In perception, intentionality is a state of consciousness of an
out an action, and with an action, it can be immediate or delayed. object with or without an overt intention. Every act of thought
This is true for the intentional aspect of certain visual images, less begins with some orientation. The orientation, bias, disposition,
so for imagery in other modalities. presupposition, etc. develops to interest, desire or intention. Any
content can suffice as an object of interest. An object provokes
The succession of intention and action, or idea and act, implies interest by arousing unconscious constructs in the mind that are
a psychic cause for the action, or that the mind (self) wants to act predisposed to attend to it. In this sense, interest finds its object.
268 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 269

Put differently, for an object to arouse interest is for the pre-object vested in a more preliminary phase, closer to the self, to will and
to tap an existing bias or valuation. The will may find objects it desire. The desire to act is the experience of an intention that has
seeks, and then we say the object stimulated the search, but all transitioned from an implicit to an explicit phase. Intentionality is
along, intention, implicit in the percept, guides and chooses ob- closer to the object toward which the mental state is directed, or to
jects on the path to the one it is seeking, which then surfaces as a a content that itself points to an object. The desire for an object is
feeling that the object is an incentive for the action. the experience of intentionality. The direction of intentionality is
aimed at the content the state is about. One could say that inten-
For example, as I revise this paper, I am on a train to Warsaw. I tion is most obviously is based in will or feeling and the direction
can see the compartment, fully scrutinize the passengers, gaze at to action, and largely hidden in perception, while intentionality
the snowy landscape or peruse the manuscript. Does each object is based in the direction to an object-content or its direction to
continuously register in my cortex to be constructed into a three- something else. This hidden intention in object-formation makes
dimensional shape and color, then recognized and assigned a the direction of intentionality explicit, turning agency into per-
value? Were this the case, I would be passively drawn to whatever ceptual aboutness, or aboutness into agency and preparedness.
comes into my visual field since I do not even know what I wish Intention can be conscious or unconscious. The intentional is
to see until after I consciously perceive it. Do I choose to perceive always conscious. The difference between conscious and uncon-
an object in this array to the neglect of others, say focusing on scious intention is like that between volition and purposefulness,
the manuscript oblivious to all else? Interest not only drives but or the deliberative and the automatic, or choice and impulse.
generates my perceptions, as each momentary object actualizes
out of (with) unconscious value.

Intention in object perception comes to the fore in delibera-


tion when preparatory phases in the object-development actual- 10.2. Consciousness and intentionality
ize as endpoints. A car is approaching; we step out of its path.
What has not been demonstrated is the uniqueness of inten-
The sighting seems the natural stimulus of the avoidance. The
tionality or its dissociation from consciousness. Historically, the
conscious content, the car, is presumed to trigger a bodily (axial)
intentional has designated what a mental state is about, while
reaction of escape, and the surface content is presumed to arouse
consciousness has designated what it feels like to be in that state
an archaic motor reaction. I would say the external object incites
(Kriegel, 2003), a distinction of conscious object and inner feeling
action through a system common to both action and perception.
that splits content from its antecedents (see below). The differ-
The core of the forming percept activates the core of the act, and
ence reflects a focus on interior process that is inaccessible, or
both develop into awareness, consciousness and/or behavior. If
on a superficial content that is conceived as independent of its
we are some distance from the car, we decide whether to wait
precursors.
until it passes or quickly cross the road. In one instance, the ac-
tion is immediate, in another there is a delay. In the latter state, Consciousness is always consciousness-of-something, and
we are aware of the deliberative, decisional or intentional phase the “of-something” is its intentional quality. Consciousness of an
in perception and action that is rapidly traversed in the former object or a goal implies the presence of a self, a state of interest,
state. Here too we see unconscious or implicit intention pass into and an object that is the object of this interest. This object is what
conscious or explicit intention. the intentional state is about, while the orientation to the object is
its aboutness. Intention is like an accentuation of the perceptual
While intentionality does not obligate a conscious intention,
line of the intentional as it veers to action. Object-awareness is not
having a conscious intention presumes an intentional state into
passive enjoyment, but readiness for action. Readiness is prepara-
which an implicit intention develops. The feeling of intention is
270 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 271

tion for purposefulness in behavior. Probably, intentionality de- Pascal was said to get rid of a toothache by concentrating on a
velops out of implicit intention in the same way that conscious mathematical problem. Is this a shift in the object of attention or
agency arises out of the purposefulness of awareness. Specifically, the intentional state? The problem of diffuse and focal attention in
the purposefulness of awareness leads in action to the agency of both awareness and in consciousness is a doorway into psychol-
consciousness, and in perception to the intentional relation to ob- ogy that philosophy must cross for intentionality to be more than
jects. Explicit intention is consciousness of goal-orientation that a mode of literary discourse.
discharges implicit intention into action. When implicit intention
becomes explicit choice, action is attenuated and its antecedent The question, what is intentionality for, is like the question,
concepts come to the fore. Options buried in potential are ac- what does intention do? To the extent the directedness of the
centuated. This heightening of the preliminary is the ground of intentional is like a scanner or focus on a content, it has an ac-
introspection. tive or agentive character. To the extent the agency of intention is
applied to objects or images, it merges with the intentional. The
Intention develops in the context of action and spreads to per- question, is the aboutness of the intentional a volitional direc-
ception or other mental phenomena. The first step in the appear- tion, is like the question, does intention have causal power? This
ance of conscious intention is a delay in action, say, in the child’s comes of shifting a set of intrinsic relations that are ingredient in
hesitation before reaching. This delay, when filled by thought, a state to a set of external relations among seemingly arbitrary
reveals the intentionality of interest or value that is the source of components. Intentionality implies a self, a vector and an object
aboutness. Hesitation that points to uncertainty is the kernel of to which the vector is directed, all of which inhere in the mental
possibility, of goals and paths not imminent in consciousness. A state. These phases evolve one out of the other; they do not occur
conscious intention has absent objects in the imagination. Trial independently. The state is not divisible into a self, an object and
action is a form of mental play that unites intention with delibera- a direction. Without the object, there is no self. Without a self,
tion. More fundamentally, intentionality derives from abstracting there is no consciousness of the object. The becoming of the state
the purposefulness of action and turning its end into an object is not arrested when the self crystallizes, for the self exists in the
of interest. The outcome of a purposeful act, or the aim of the demarcation from ensuing phases. A self does not occur without
act, objectifies as the goal toward which the conscious intention a tacit predication. The “I” is always “I am (think, want, etc.)”. The
is directed. “I” does not exist without a verb or relation. The relation estab-
lishes the “I” as a figural contrast in relation to something else,
Aboutness or directionality must be differentiated from focal minimally to the ambient field in which it develops.
attention. The difference between anxiety and fear is a differ-
ence of generalized/diffuse and focal/individuated attention. Every entity has a direction of becoming over the temporal
Consciousness is always of-something irrespective of what the extensibility of its minimal existence. In organic systems, the be-
something is. However, focal attention in states of awareness must coming of the organism is uni-directional. In basic or elementary
differ in some way from focal attention in conscious states. It may physical entities, the becoming may be reversible or isotropic. The
be that the gazelle seen by a lion is the same gazelle seen by a con- becoming or directionality of the mental state is fundamental to
scious person, but the person sees it in a different way. As soon its existence, its being. The Würzburg school of psychology dis-
as one is conscious of attending to an object, the subject-object cerned a vague feeling of directedness (Bewüsstheit) before the
relation becomes explicit and the self acquires a volitional atti- appearance of a content. The direction is the forward surge of the
tude. The becoming-conscious of what is singled out in awareness state and its aim to actualization. This feeling can be felt before the
accompanies a feeling of deliberate perception. This volitional state terminates, as a presentiment, a tendency or a disposition.
quality in focal attention may well be the essence of intentionality.
272 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 273

This feeling of direction without an object is discussed in mystical 10.3. The scope of the subjective
writings and is common in creative discovery.
The idea of intentionality, especially of psychic causation, the dis-
Generally, the mental state is said to be intentional when the tinction of primary and secondary qualities, inner and outer, and
self is conscious of an object (content), and purposeful when there the relation of sense phenomena to objects divides consciousness
is object-awareness without consciousness. Explicit intention is into components beginning with the self and its acts/objects. This
intentional consciousness in relation to action. Implicit intention division is reinforced by the common belief that the objects we
is purposefulness in awareness. The former is built on and pre- perceive are mind-independent, and that acts are implemented
sumes the latter. The latter precedes the former and can occur by, and thus distinct from, the psyche. The variety of possible ob-
in its absence. Both states, awareness and consciousness, have an jects includes “pure sensory” qualities (colors, sounds), feelings,
object as subjective aim but only consciousness has a self and a intra-psychic objects (beliefs, desires), extra-psychic objects (trees),
mental (intrapsychic) object. According to this way of thinking, and phenomena that have psychic qualities but are extra-personal
all conscious states are intentional and all intentional states are (rainbows, illusions). The intentional is most assuredly grounded
conscious, regardless of whether or not the content is intentional, in the direction to the extra-psychic, which is the satisfaction of the
though an intention can be conscious or unconscious. subjective aim of the state, or its intentional goal. The distinction
of the self “inside” the mind and the action or object “outside” it
Once the logical implications of the concept of intentionality is central to Brentano’s (1874/1973) argument that intentionality
are exhausted, and the properties of intentional objects are fully gives existence to physical phenomena, i.e. qualia, that otherwise
mined for their complexities, the fundamental problem that re- are presentations with no real existence (see Chisholm, 1952;
mains, which led to the description of intentionality in the first McAlister 1982 ). Intentional existence is a halfway house between
place, is how mental states can be about something, a problem still real existence and the imagination. But do we want to say that
untouched by the many arguments that swirl around it. Analyses such entities exist only as objects of attention? A color and a tree
of the conditions and varieties of aboutness swamp the few pa- are both objects of attention, or intentionality, and are both brain
pers on its psychological basis. One gets mired in distinctions and events. What insures the reality or existence of one object over
ignores the relation. It is as if one set out to explain gravity by another?
elaborating and analyzing all instances of the phenomena with-
out ever explaining it. The fact of aboutness is that it is essential An external object or phenomenon such as a “sensory qual-
to consciousness, without which conscious states would not oc- ity” is not about anything and is not intrinsically intentional, in
cur, since consciousness is the relation of self to inner and outer contrast to certain mental phenomena, e.g. beliefs, desires, which
objects. The agentive feeling in consciousness is a combination seem to refer beyond themselves. Since sensory qualia are not
of this relation with the anisotropy of actualization. This gives the directed to something, they take on existence through an invest-
direction or aboutness that is the justification for the “problem” of ment of intentionality, whereas beliefs are intrinsically inten-
intentionality. tional in pointing to something else, or so the argument goes.
The distinction depends, in part, on the contrast of primary and
secondary qualities, i.e., secondary qualities lack real existence as
psychic additions to physical nature. It can be asked, what is the
critical difference in perception between seeing an object and see-
ing its color, or seeing the colored after-image of the object? What
are the grounds for dividing objects into those with sensory quali-
ties only and those with sensory plus mental qualities? Sensory
274 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 275

impressions are mediated by cortical and sub-cortical areas; they anxiety becomes fear and takes on an object, the present mental
impinge on pre-perceptual regions in the brain and, because they object is now fear, not anxiety. The content actualizes as or near
are pre-perceptual, are inaccessible to consciousness. Objects come the outcome of the mental state; the self is close to its onset, the
to us whole. We are not conscious of their constituents, their “as- world its endpoint. Aboutness is the direction from self to object,
sembly” or their actualization. Sensory qualities such as color or or the relation between polarities in a transition from the activa-
pain are private modalities of perception that, it is assumed take tion of the state to its terminus.
on spatial properties through visualization. For example, in the
sighted, the localization of sound is parasitic on, and disrupted by The difference between anxiety and fear may correspond to a
alterations of, visual space. difference in perception and behavior but there is little impact on
consciousness. If consciousness does change as the object clari-
In addition to qualities, we are conscious of contents that are, fies, what is the difference? The resolution of the field would seem
in themselves, considered non-intentional, such as moods. A inconsequential, for the self is conscious of being anxious in the
mood does not have an object, even if it is what the mental state same way that it is conscious of being fearful. That a state such
is about. The self is conscious of being anxious or depressed. The as anxiety is non-intentional until the person knows what he is
feeling of pain or anxiety is what a state of anxiety or pain is about. anxious about, at which point the state becomes intentional, is
If the self wonders why it is anxious or depressed, is wonder over the slender thread on which intentional theory rests. What is the
a non-intentional content intentional? Take the shift from anxiety value of this concept? Brentano appears to have believed that in-
to fear. In one state, anxiety is the content of consciousness; in tentionality and consciousness-of were identical, though he raised
the other it is fear, along with the object of the fear. The differ- the issue of the intentional quality of unconscious ideas. If con-
ence is the degree to which the aim specifies, or the delimitation sciousness is always consciousness-of something, and conscious-
of a generalized state of conceptual feeling as an object resolves ness that is not consciousness-of is awareness, intentionality is a
within a category. The world is a necessary backdrop for a self superfluous concept.
and its objects, whether incipient or formed, whether directed to
inner or outer events. When the affective state is anxiety, the self is If intentionality is about something, what is the class of states
related to the content of mind as a whole. When the affective state that are not exactly moods in which the self is leaning to some-
is fear, the feared object is specified. Yet in both instances, one thing that is not yet clear? As fear differentiates out of anxiety, or
could equally say that the true object of the state of intentionality a morbid depression resolves to one in which a cause or reason
is not anxiety or fear but to be rid of them and replace them with is identified, so one searches for a memory or a word that is not
a state of tranquility. forthcoming. A writer holds a pen waiting for a thought to come.
What object is the state about? If one tries without success to recall
As long as there is a self, there is consciousness, even of vacan- something, is the state intentional? What of an expectation that
cy or meditation on emptiness, or absent-mindedly gazing at the does not yet have an object? Is the not-yet one is waiting for still an
sea. Even a person in a state of mystical absorption in god or the object of consciousness? A state of dynamic tension, perhaps like
absolute is conscious of, and exhilarated by, the oneness of the ob- that described by Zeigarnik (Kurt Lewin, 1948), is sufficient for an
ject (Hughes, 1937). Intentionality is not the direction to an object intentional content.
beyond the immediate content, for the future is an idea within the
present that is a target of attention. Content actualizes the future
as its own intrinsic aim. Implication and reference are not addi-
tions to content but remain part of the total state. Aboutness is
still within-ness, ingredient, not extrinsic or supplemental. When
276 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 277

10.4. Process and content metaphor or symbolism. Intentional content is a kind of outer
representation of the self along with an echo of agency pointing
The discussion has exposed the fundamental difference between to objects in the future, in short, a starting point of thought with
a theory based on mental content as opposed to one of process reference to external objects. The surface of the state is the floor of
generating the content, or between a descriptive and a genetic the philosophical imagination. One reminisces on a vacation last
psychology. This descriptive approach follows the experience of year to Barcelona and a set of experiences recurs in memory as a
everyday life, in which interest is fixed on thoughts, memories, source of pleasure or disappointment. One plans a vacation next
ideas, hopes, struggles and fears. Most fields of psychology and phi- year to Madrid, because it is inexpensive or sunny, for a profes-
losophy begin and end with the analysis of content. For Brentano sional opportunity, an invitation, interest in bullfights or to see
and others, philosophy is essentially descriptive psychology, the the Bosch triptychs at the Prado. The plan or the reminiscence
mind revisiting its own thought. Clinical psychology also begins — the forward or backward glance — is, for substance theory, part
with content and works backwards to cause, postulating needs, of a network of associations that accounts for its occurrence while
attitudes, motivations, early experience, as determining events in for process theory, these contents are endpoints in consciousness
the occurrent state. The prior sequence gives a cursory explana- that severally exhaust the series of overlapping source concepts.
tion of the present but is not deeply genetic; it merely aligns sur-
face contents in a series that makes plausible the occurrent state. A phenomenon such as a belief is a typical intentional object.
The inter-connectedness of the contents of conscious thought and But an explicit or conscious belief is the realization — outcome, fi-
perception, both past and present, produces a narrative that feels nal content — of an unconscious or implicit belief, value or dispo-
explanatory. sition in the core self. The conscious belief is the terminal content
of an unconscious presupposition. The intentional relation lies
Cognitive psychology, which for the most part is also descrip- in the trajectory from the presupposition to the conscious belief,
tive, with its modularity and animosity to evolutionary gradualism, not from the content of the conscious belief to what the belief is
introduces quantitative methods that are largely antithetical to a about. The belief is the outcome of the mental state. Its content
genetic interpretation. The temporal is secondary to the spatial; may be true or false, rational or irrational, but to make the con-
substance and quantity replace process and quality. The origin of tent of the belief the intentional object of the state rather than the
the content is reduced to the spatial interaction of rules on con- belief itself displaces the aboutness of the self/object relation to
stituent elements, e.g. representations, propositions, strategies, relations within the content of what the belief is about, effectively
etc. The philosophy of intentionality and its correlates in cognitive removing the content from its psychological antecedents.
science are a mode of descriptive psychology in which the imme-
diate object is primary, while its formative history is collapsed to a Similarly, a desire is the individuation and outcome of a drive,
reconstitution of its assumed constituents. The dissociation from and a sufficient object of consciousness. The desire may be for an
genetic process gives content as an externalized solid indepen- apple or an orange, but the intentional process is the desire for the
dent of its source. The content takes on a life that is independent object, not the analysis of the object for which one has the desire.
of the mind, and consciousness is left with little to do other than Indeed, a person might prefer to remain in a state of desire, which
feel what it is like to be in a particular mental state. is then the goal of the state. Others may wish for happiness or
success without a particular object or plan to achieve it. The fact
Contents are the settled endpoints of an unconscious creative that belief and desire point to a pending object in the same way
process opaque to thought that is reconstructed from the felt con- that a reminiscence points to a memory image, is irrelevant to the
nectivity between endpoints. Logical solids interact by causal links intentionality of the state, for it is the state that is intentional, not
that can be direct, as when an idea leads to action or to another its content.
idea, or indirect, as when the association of ideas is mediated by
278 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 279

On this account, the intentionality of the content is not what duration. For substance theory, the mental state does not incorpo-
makes the state intentional; a conscious state is intentional no rate a direction to content; rather the intentionality of the content
matter what its content. The direction to an object is the subjec- describes the state. This content, which is argued to be the basis
tive aim to actuality. This actuality can be intra- or extra-psychic, of an intentional state is, in fact, the object toward which the state
diffuse or focal, means or end. What matters is the transition from is directed. Turning the content into the state is an example of
unconscious to conscious, from self to content, not the nature of what Wittgenstein, in a slightly different context, referred to as the
the content. Every conscious state is about something. The some- conjurer’s trick of arguing mental states and events before their
thing the state is about is its momentary content. This content nature is decided.
does not lead to something else but gives way to, or is replaced
by, other contents. The trajectory of the state, the course of its actu- Wittgenstein (1969ed) seemed to have an uncertain under-
alization, gives the state its intentional quality, regardless of what standing of the mental state in relation to its content. On the one
content actualizes. hand, he wrote (38) that in mathematics, “one has to keep on
reminding one’s self of the unimportance of the ‘inner process’
While the aboutness of the intentional is a relation to content, or ‘state’ and ask, ‘why should it be important?” Yet even math-
a shift from the relation-to-the-thing, to the thing-the-relation-is- ematic propositions depend, as do other propositions, on a co-
about, displaces the temporal dynamic of becoming to the spa- herent system of conscious and unconscious knowledge. On the
tial immediacy of being. Even in reminiscence, the progression other hand, he says (42) that to think different states correspond
from past to present is treated as subordinate, for a memory is to the words ‘believe’ and ‘know’ is like believing different people
interpreted as a present object to which thought is directed. As correspond to the word ‘I’ and the name ‘Ludwig’. But believing
in memory, so in belief, a statement is a product to which belief and knowing are different concepts, and different concepts are,
gives rise. But the outward reference of a proposition or belief, strictly speaking, different states, while different states can have
the intentionality in the statement, shifts a completed subjective more or less the same referent. One cannot go from identity of
aim to an incomplete intentional content. The objectification of referent to identity of state. Methuselah and ‘the oldest man who
process that severs intentional content from mind even gives rise ever lived’ involve very different concepts, thus states, though the
to arguments over whether non-cognitive entities “represent” or referent is the same. One is merely a name, the other, a relational
point to something, perhaps not surprising in that physical enti- concept. Wittgenstein (410) acknowledged that “our knowledge
ties, having been imported to the mind to fill it with causal units, forms an enormous system. And, only within this system has a
are then exported back to the world as atomic entities carrying particular act the value we give it”. What is this system other than
intentionality with them as a psychic residue. the context (transition) through which a particular act develops?
The transition is the mental state, while value is not given but
Intentionality would be an innocuous topic for psychological arises with the act itself. The point is, contents do not decide the
study if its description were restricted to parsing beliefs and de- state; the state determines the contents.
sires instead of driving an account of mental states. For process
theory, the solids of spatial content are replaced by temporal Still, in the sleight of hand that excises a proposition from its
phases that deposit evanescent actualities. A brain state is that antecedents to analyze it in relation to its consequents, the distal
configuration of neuronal activity generating a mental state. A phase in a process of form-creation becomes the product of an
mental state is a virtual duration that corresponds with an epoch assembly line, encapsulated, detached and examined as an inde-
of brain activity. The epoch is the minimal duration necessary pendent entity. This is like dissecting a leaf from a tree to analyze
for the state to actualize. The mental state enfolds embedded or it as a distinct object, when the leaf only exists in relation to the
transformed and actual (deposited) events or contents within its whole of its organic process. Without a tree, a leaf is a dead object.
280 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 281

The spray of a fountain is inseparable from the stream beneath in other brains or in the same person at different times. The same
it. In the mental state, phases leading to the distal portion do brain areas (cells) are activated by different stimuli, tasks and re-
not evaporate when the final content is achieved but inhere as sponse measures. Surgical removal of the active brain area would
constituents. Recognition, meaning and experiential relations are probably not affect performance on the task eliciting the activa-
sub-surface phases without which perceptual objects do not ex- tion, while the brain area active on the task will not, were it to
ist. Imagine a fluid as an aggregate of discrete molecules, or such be otherwise activated, reproduce that functional state. A brain
molecules as the building blocks of a system in flux, like a river area associated with a task can be stimulated with or without the
reconstructed from bricks. occurrence of the mental content which, on a given task, caused
that area to be active, and the area can be ablated and the perfor-
The impact on theory of mind of externalizing mental content mance left unaffected. What, then, has been demonstrated?
spills into studies of brain activity underlying mental phenomena,
in conceiving units of thought, e.g. a proposition or perception, or Substance theory builds on the atomicity and locality of par-
elements in their assembly, as isolates in a formative sequence. ticulars. The modularity of psychic elements is presumed to cor-
The mental content is not, as in process theory, a momentary respond with discrete brain areas, with brain process and func-
emphasis in a field of intrinsic relations, but is an artificial solid in tion assigned to their connectivity. The philosopher Mario Bunge
external relation to other solids, none of which can be reduced to referred to this way of thinking as the Lego theory of the mind.
the dynamic of brain activity. The common technique of subtrac- With mental contents divorced from their psychic antecedents,
tion in studies of brain metabolism or the elimination of contex- analysis tends to a formal (linguistic, logical) explication that is
tual variables in psychological performance treats psychic process only compatible with a static neuroscience. Process theory cannot
as a combination of logical solids that can be added or subtracted. yet account for specific contents within a category, e.g. an apple
The demonstration of different patterns of metabolic activation or banana, but has the potential to give the sequence of phases
for widely divergent phenomena, such as vision or language, still underlying the derivation of categories, which in principle can be
does not allow one to go from brain region or activation pattern to mapped to dynamic neuroscience. In brief, for substance theory,
a specific visual or linguistic experience. being is the source of becoming. For process theory, becoming is
the source of being. In truth, an epoch of being consists of phases
Instead of accepting inconsistent findings as a critique, varia- of becoming that, on completion, deposit being in each recur-
tion is taken as evidence that function is multi-componential, so rence.
that every activation is part of an aggregated system or network.
Such findings are common in most psychological domains. The
non-repeatability and questionable methodology are not indict-
ments of brain correlation, but of what is being correlated to what
and the theory behind the correlative techniques. Thus, the per- 10.5. Existence and intentionality
ception of a fruit (banana, apple, orange) may activate a different A curious aspect of the writing on intentionality, and a sign of its
part of the brain — even a single cell on unit recording — than the importance to philosophy, is the relation of intentionality to exis-
perception of a person, as may the thought of fruit trees, orange tence (McAllister, 1982). It can be said that an intentional object
juice or breakfast, or the names or pictures of fruits, though when exists intentionally, i.e. has intentional but not real existence, or
the relevant brain areas (cells) are active one could not say the that it exists from the standpoint of the intentional, but not that
person is thinking of fruit, much less anything else. The areas of otherwise it is non-existent in the sense one thinks an imaginary
active metabolism depend on subtle differences in stimuli, timing object, e.g. a centaur, is non-existent. These concerns were central
and experimental technique. The findings may not be duplicated to Brentano’s distinction of real and imaginary, as of physical and
282 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 283

mental phenomena, and more recently, that of intrinsic and de- a judgment than a feeling to which intentionality is secondarily
rived intentionality. Physical phenomena include sensory qualia related. This is evident in the observation that the very concept
but also, for some writers, images and objects, while mental phe- of intentionality weakens as objects depart from the intuitively
nomena include these physical entities with intentional reference. “real”. Hallucination, imagery and dreams are not non-controver-
Thinking of an object, real or imaginary, turns a physical existent sially intentional. The intentionality of “unconscious ideas” and
(or non-existent) into an intentionally existing phenomenon. The covert motivations is uncertain. Moods and attitudes are in ques-
perception of a physical tree becomes a mental phenomenon tion. A slight change in content can transform a non-intentional
when consciousness is directed to it, incorporating the entity into state to an intentional one, e.g. when fear and hope emerge from
an act of thought. anxiety or elation.

Brentano wrote of intentional inexistence, by which he meant If an object takes on existence when it is invested with inten-
existence by virtue of being an intentional object. The difference tional interest, there would be a transition from non-existence to
between an object in perception and the same object as intentional existence or from physical to mental existence, according to the
would seem to correspond with the distinction between an object degree of object resolution. It seems odd to say that a mood is a
of awareness and an object of consciousness. We tend to assume physical state while its object is mental, especially given the stages
that an object of consciousness is identical to one in immediate in the individuation of the object as the mood resolves, or intensi-
perception, or that the addition of consciousness to perception fies, e.g. when anxiety passes to fear, then to panic or terror, as a
does not alter the object, e.g. the gazelle spotted by a lion and the frightening situation clarifies. Why is one stage in this transition
gazelle in human perception. If consciousness creates or accom- physical and another mental when the self is conscious of every
panies a difference in the perceptual object, it is probably small, stage?
though not to say insignificant, in comparison with the shift from
awareness to consciousness, for example, in the volitional quality It seems natural to think, with Aristotle, that such things as
of focal attention. Being conscious that we look at a gazelle, we centaurs exist only as objects of thought. It would then also be
think we choose to look at it. The feeling of intention in perception true that propositions and concepts exist as thoughts. A propo-
is the initial phase of deliberation. The degree to which conscious- sition has an existence like that of the idea of a centaur regard-
ness affects the object depends on the degree to which the object less of whether it is true or false, or refers to something real or
saturates the field of attention, as in love, or the more it gives way imaginary. The thought or statement, “snow is red” exists even if
to reflection. The more an object is contemplated, the more in- red snow does not. The object referred to exists or does not exist,
ward and thought-like it becomes until it is eventually replaced by but its existence is a different existence than that of the idea that
thought. The particular drowns in the whole or, put differently, the refers to it. But if percepts are derived from concepts, and if both
conceptual root of the object is progressively unearthed until the are objects and realizations of thought, what is the difference in
object finally disappears. existence? The object, red snow, might exist in some conceivable
universe. Would we say snow is red if we perceived it with red-
The separation of the physical and the mental hinges partly on tinged glasses? How can we determine snow is white other than
the account of reality and existence. It may be that, to introspec- be consensus? If we rely on our perceptions, such as the percep-
tion, the real is derivative on existence, but psychologically, we tion of a tree, for a judgment of existence, how can we affirm that
tend to think that unreal phenomena do not “really” exist and that illusions do not exist? Illusory and non-illusory objects are equally
those internal and external phenomena that seem real, such as objects of perception.
feelings and trees, indubitably do exist, though trees differ in be-
ing substantially real. Moreover, the real, unlike existence, is less All psychic and perceptual phenomena develop through
endogenous brain process. What object develops depends on
284 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 285

physical constraints on the process. Without constraints, there to experience and the deep unconscious is physiology, there is a
are hallucinations. With them, there are objects (or illusions). The continuum through animal mind to the lowest life forms. Merely
corollary to this is that perceptions are hallucinations that are placing an intentional spotlight on an object does not do the nec-
adapted to the physical world. The concept of a centaur does not essary work. This is still apart from the actual nature of existence.
become an external perception because there are no sensory con-
straints or physical manifestations to drive belief and imagination Concepts have existence independent of their exemplifications
to perception, nor is there certain knowledge that centaurs exist, as concrete particulars, at which point their existence becomes
or have existed, as external objects. The concept of a centaur is more or less “real”. One would say a tree in perception is real, or
that of an imaginary or mythological beast that entails the shared that red snow is not real, based on knowledge of trees and snow
knowledge that no one has ever seen one and that it is an ana- and the feeling of realness in the object, i.e. that it is not a ho-
tomical impossibility. Yet one may never have seen an okapi or the logram or hallucination. This way of thinking is compatible with
Gobi desert but know they exist. If the knowledge of the existence transitional cases such as illusions, in which the feeling of realness
of a thing, even something that is inferred and has never been depends on the object-experience. An endogenous illusion such
perceived, is vital to the existence of the thing, what part does as seeing insects on the wall in the delirium tremens of alcohol
perception play in this determination? The existence of scientific withdrawal has a feeling of reality (and fear) that does not occur
facts can be hypothesized, but we would not say an entity exists with external illusions, such as the Müller-Lyer or bent-stick-in-wa-
until it is verified by experiment, if not perception. The difference ter. Yet even here the boundaries are often vague.
between no-longer-existing objects, like dinosaurs, or ones that
Most people would deny the Loch Ness monster exists or they
take on existence when they are discovered, like coelacanths, is
would be uncertain. Those who believe it exists may have so strong
of peripheral importance to the concept of existence, when exis-
a belief they “see” it swimming in the lake. Visions of god and
tence is conceived in relation to brain and experience.
angels occur in those with an intense belief. The psychotic hears
Whitehead wrote that apart from experience there is nothing, and at times sees the objects of his beliefs. A strong belief can give
bare nothing. James, Bradley and many others held similar views. rise to a perception. We have all had the experience of imagining
But what is experience? If psychic events have brain existence, the distant sounds of a train or the illusory chimes of a far off
where is the line between the intentional existence of an object church bell and some of us have even seen a mirage. The fact that
and its conscious or unconscious field or, in Whitehead’s termi- there is a “real” train and church, but not an oasis, is irrelevant to
nology, prehensions? In what sense does a “stored”, unconscious the auditory or visual image. In each, an affectively-charged idea,
or forgotten memory exist, or automated skills, passive vocabulary driven by need or expectation, externalizes as a perception with-
or the knowledge of a grammar as opposed to these capacities out the sensory constraints that are ordinarily necessary for this
when employed or “activated”? When I perceive a tree, does its ex- transition.
istence include the tacit memory and knowledge of all other trees
Each moment, various individualities appear, some real, some
in my experience, or the concept through which this or any tree
illusory, some fictitious, some factual, but each participates in a
is named and/or recognized? If a pain has intentional existence,
common process of specification. The generation of objects in the
what about the processes giving the pain, its obscuration of other
transition from mind to world is a micro-evolutionary adaptation
perceptions, the response to the pain and its effect on a person’s
in which unfit exemplars are ordinarily eliminated before they
life? Does everything in the auditory, visual, tactile, etc. field have
become actual. As in evolution or ontogeny, maladaptive objects
psychic existence? Is experience the totality of what is in the mind
do occur, either to be marginalized or eliminated. To ask what is
at a given moment, the life history of that experience, or only an
the nature of the unrealized world that is pruned in every act of
object of momentary interest? If consciousness is not essential
thought so the actual world can come into existence is to inquire
286 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 287

into the range of possibilities latent in untapped potential. We the perception of my breath on a winter day an object? If so, what
have an intuition of what is possible as the sum of our acts and of my breath at other times when it is not perceptible?
thoughts, even our dreams, but we also know what is not possible
given the knowledge of human activities, our own and others, and In psychosis or other brain disorders, the “rock-bottom” belief
their limitations. in the reality of perception breaks down. Self, body and world exist
for the person but they are no longer securely real. There are rare
If one can say unreal objects — external (rainbows) or intra- brain disorders in which a person believes he is no longer alive.
psychic (dreams) — exist as experiences that correspond to brain Who, then, is this non-existent person who claims to be dead?
events, one can say the same for all perceived objects such as Like non-existence, death is impossible to fully contemplate, not
trees, though trees are felt to be real in a way that dreams and the least because the very existence of the thinker contaminates
rainbows are not. Why are trees felt to be “more real” than dreams the thought of nothingness. The opposite of existence is non-ex-
or rainbows? A tree is perceived by several modalities each con- istence; the opposite of real is unreal or illusory. Since existence
firming the other, a concordance that also makes the dream, dur- and reality are linked concepts, grades of existence and degrees of
ing the dream seem real, while rainbows are purely visual. The reality are transitional, up to the point where entities vanish and
image of a tree externalizes in an adaptation to the environment thoughts can no longer follow them.
as thought is delimited by sensation. Trees persist, while dreams
and rainbows come and go, even if the tree also changes, more Realness in perception, as in dream, develops on the inability
or less slowly. A rainbow occurs with effects in the atmosphere in to disconfirm its authenticity. An object, the reality of which is un-
relation to the position of an observer, but the shape, size, color, challenged, is accepted as real. To question reality or, especially,
etc., of a tree also depend on light, distance and perspective. A to feel an object as unreal is already to lose one’s grip. Illusion and
tree is judged to be a solid existent independent of perception. reality are relational phenomena. Delusion and hallucination are
A rainbow is a transient mental phenomenon that does not have not distortions of the real that can be summarily dismissed in a
objective existence. So too for a dream, though many believe the description of what the real is, for it is a short step from the feel-
dream has a reality in the mental life, as a meaning, a forecast or a ing that a perception is real to one, as in vertigo, of an uncertain
symbolic representation. The tree is real. The rainbow and dream reality. For the observer, things are more or less real depending
are illusory. on some standard of reality. For most, this standard is the habitual
world of perception; for others, it is the abstract world of phys-
Illusion is not distinguished from reality by mind-dependence ics; for still others, it is a noumenal world that is impenetrable to
but is recognized and felt in the comparison to other perceptions knowledge.
and to a base of knowledge. The rainbow is seen one moment,
from one point of view, then disappears, so its perception can be The distinction of illusion and reality is less problematic when
compared to preceding and succeeding mental states. Knowledge perceptions are all conceived as brain images, with the brain the
brought to bear on object-judgment is immediate in perception, proximate physical reality that is the unknowable ground of object-
not prior to it. The object is perceived in the limitation of its prefig- appearances. The reality of perception is then secondary to the
uring concepts. This is most clear in primitive thought when a tree feeling that one object seems more real than another. Ordinarily,
is a totem or a rainbow is a sign from god. Thunder, clouds and concrete reality is the image through which physical reality is in-
fog are transitional cases. To what object does thunder refer when ferred. We see the tree and infer the physical entity on the other
lightning occurred moments earlier? Clouds and fog are coales- side of the perception. But again we come back to rainbows, bent
cences or densities of moisture? What sort of objects are these? Is sticks, vertigo, and duck/rabbit figures. If all internal and external
images are phases in object-formation, the distinction of inner
and outer, physical and mental, qualia, objects and thoughts, will
288 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 289

be settled by the locus and context of the image in a single process physical though, on reflection, the latter is clearly inferred from
of object-formation. the phenomenal.

One would not want to deny that physical entities have exis-
tence other than as objects of thought. The fact that we cannot
experience superstrings makes them hypothetical, not non-exis-
tent. We know there is a difference between hypothetical objects
that cannot (or never) be experienced and witches or goblins,
but it is difficult to say what this difference is other than agree-
ment among observers. If everyone believes that witches exist
and only a handful believes that superstrings exist, an intelligent
and impartial observer would turn to the coherence of the belief
with other facts. But the circularity is precisely the problem. The
accumulation of facts out of beliefs reinforces the discovery (cre-
ation) of new fact, and fact is what most people accept as real or
existing. Beliefs become facts that are supported by coherence
Fig. 10.2. All direct knowledge is in the mental state. Phases
with other facts, which themselves are the products of beliefs. A
that correspond to the generation of the perception are inferred to
phenomenon that is more than belief but not yet fact, such as a
have their correlates in the physical brain state. Perception adapts
superstring, does not half-exist. Does a fact exist until it is refuted,
to the physical world but its proximate correlate is the brain state.
at which point it ceases to exist?
Physical stages are outside the mental state, as are early Ucs phas-
es in the mental state. Locke wrote that everything real is individual. Most philoso-
phers have agreed that individuality is what exists and is real.
Externality and verifiability are common to objects and many
This supposes that individuality is independent of mind or that
illusions. Externality, privacy and non-verifiability occur in hal-
individualities once discovered are facts distinct from the mind
lucination and endogenous illusions, e.g. delirium tremens,
that discovers them. But, within experience, individuality is an
metamorphopsias (Brown, 1988). Privacy and non-verifiability
achievement. There is an invisible filament from potential to
characterize dreams and many concepts. The consensus of those
actual, whether the temporal extensibility of physical entities or
who see rainbows or sticks-bent-in-water does not lead them to
the mind as a medium in which particulars are realized. For a
suppose they have objective existence. The externality of halluci-
particular to exist, it must recur, and in the recurrence, particulars
nation does not initially lead an individual to believe the image is
individuate as they traverse layers in becoming. The existence of
real, or that it exists like other objects. Brain activity is the existent
any individuality is the minimal duration over which it becomes
to which these diverse phenomena refer. Next to brain activity, the
what it is, and the being it becomes over that duration. The poten-
sensation that guides the object-formation is its proximate physi-
tial of a particle is that process prior to the completion of one cycle
cal existent. The physical reality of brain events, inferred from
of existence. In mind, potential is a phase in the mental state prior
phenomenal experience, is closer to experience than the physi-
to, but inherent in, its diverse particularities.
cal correlates of the perceived object, i.e. the physical tree as the
source of its perception (Fig. 10.2). In everyday life we think the Consider entities that cannot be experienced and objects not
objects before us are real physical entities, not veils that obscure a in immediate perception. A footprint in the sand exists; it is an
hidden physical realm. We have no intuition of a mediating brain object no less than the sand or sea into which it vanishes. The
process. The phenomenal is immediate and identified with the recognition of a footprint does not imply a different process than
290 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 291

the recognition of the sea. The pattern of the footprint, the pattern Such an account of existence is continuous with an account
of sand and sea around the footprint, the name for these objects, of physical nature. A perspective is merely a particular momen-
are all secondary to their existence. Sand and sea are objects we tary existence, but theory derived from study of the mental state,
recognize. A depression in the sand that resembles a footprint ex- i.e. from an intra-psychic or subjective point of view, can be pre-
ists as does the actual footprint, differing only in the cause of its sumed to apply to entities inaccessible to human cognition. To
occurrence. If we refer to the former as a footprint, we are in error infer a physical tree from its mental image is no less a stretch than
— we should say, it has the shape of a footprint — but this does not to infer, from concepts, any other physical entity. This is a logical
alter or eliminate the existence of the perceived shape as a mental extension of microgenetic theory. However, from the limitations
event. The point is, naming a thing individuates an object-concept of a human framework, the nature of existence is closely tied to a
and a lexical-semantic field, but reference is not existence. The theory of appearance and reality. To hold that perceptual events
difference between the configuration of the sand and that of the such as trees exist, while others such as rainbows do not, or that
footprint is one of scale and duration. There is also the space of ob- true propositions have greater reality or existence than fictitious
ject-contrast. A footprint may be defined by the absence of sand in objects like unicorns, is to conflate existence and reality, or con-
the space it occupies. In this sense, it is like a shadow, which is an fuse physical and mental existence, or existence as a brain event
absence of light within a certain contour. Is absence something? with existence as a mental phenomenon. A tree as an (external)
Is the fact that I am here but not there part of where I am? Can a image generated by the brain is assumed to exist independent
tree be defined by everything it is not? If the via negativa cannot of the observer. Yet the tree is an image, no matter how real and
describe the color green, how can it describe a tree? Yet, in some independent it seems. One has only to close one eye, then the
sense, all things can be defined by what they are and are not. A other, and see the tree jump from side to side to realize that the
featherless biped satisfies one, rather impoverished, description perceived tree is an image extracted from monocular disparity.
of man. There are those who believe, not without reason, that be-
cause a privative does not invoke a fictitious limitation, it can be a If brain activity is common to all human experience and if
higher order of description. apart from experience in the widest sense there is bare nothing
or non-existence, one image does not differ from another with
All objects are points of view. A point of view is not a lens float- respect to existence, only with respect to realness. The occurrence
ing in space but an act of thought supported by myriad uncon- of trees and rainbows can be verified by others, yet we say the
scious and biological processes. It does little injury to the idea rainbow does not really exist, or that it exists as an illusion, or in
of existence to embrace all phenomena in a wider ground of physical relation to perception, while the tree is independent of
existence including contents in the imagination, shapes, noises, an observer. The duration of existence enters this judgment, since
odors, pains, hallucinations, concepts and dreams. Whatever one a tree that vanishes in a second, without an explosion or some
perceives or thinks about, any object of thought, as well as the other explanation, might be judged as illusory or unreal and thus
covert process through which it develops, and the unconscious non-existent. To say an object exists independent of perception, or
background it evokes, exist as patterns of brain activity, as do all that external objects have greater existence than thoughts, is not
the physical constituents — cells, molecules, etc. — ingredient in to say that some objects are more real, or that real objects have
those patterns. The pattern of existence of every atom in the brain more existence than unreal ones, but to say that some objects are
is similar to the pattern of activity through which the brain-state more conceptual than others.
exists, which in turn has affinities with the pattern of the mental-
state as a psychic manifestation of brain activity. The theory of existents is foundational to physical entities,
including the brain. The difficulties occur with psychic existence
and the distinction of the illusory and the real, concept and fact,
292 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 293

and so on. The mental state is a psychic object that corresponds theory. The objective refers to the externalized or objectified por-
with a physical existent, i.e. the brain state. its actualization and tion of the mental state, while the subjective refers to the internal
that of its constituents. The psychic correlates of the state, inter- or psychic portion. In the specification of a subjective aim, the
nal, external, conscious, unconscious, etc. distribute into real, unextended segment is transported to one that has extension in a
unreal, intentional, illusory, fact etc. But taking a mental state as continuous wave. Mind and world, inner and outer, are phases in
a complete occasion of human experience, whatever occurs in a single process of objectification.
the state exists in a derived mode of existence (dream, concept,
object), whether or not that mode satisfies a judgment and feeling Given the controversy on the nature and significance of qualia
of reality. and their relation to intentional states (e.g. Tye, 2000), it is useful
to examine concepts prior to a materialism in which “sensory”
A complete theory of such phenomena is a theory of change qualia have become the last refuge of the subjective. Brentano
in nature, in which some events are transient, others glacial. The bundled external objects with internal qualia as physical or non-
rate of change reflects the frequency of the repeatability of the intentional entities that took on intentional existence when they
event. Persistence is continuous recurrence. An object that exists became momentary targets of thought. The approach rightly ex-
for a second differs from one that lasts for years in that the latter tended the problem of qualia to external objects as elements in a
recurs with inconspicuous change. Such an entity does not have common field, even as it placed physical elements in opposition
“more existence”, for each moment all things perish. The longer to the intentional. But what fundamental difference between the
a thing exists, the greater the number of recurrences. Existence perception of pain and the perception of an external object could
is becoming into being over the minimal temporal extensibility bring about a radical alteration of a theory of the physical and the
for an entity to become what it is. Being is created in a process mental if these phenomena merely refer to different modalities
of momentary becoming. The thread of becoming in mind is a of perception?
complex exemplification of the arising of entities in nature. Every
entity, from a sub-atomic particle to a fully developed brain, is a The first-person “what-is-it-like” experience is a fragile entreaty
momentary discrimination of the deep underlying unity of nature. that justifies much theory of mind. More generally, the inacces-
This pruning of the irrelevant as a world individuates in the mind sibility to others of putative sensory experiences or uncorrupted
resonates with the metaphysical principle of “limitation” through “raw feels” can readily be extended beyond interior phenomena
which individualities arise out of the Absolute or universal being to the entire spectrum of personal experience. The tendency to
(e.g. Hawkins, 1954). define qualia as inwardly experienced sensorial phenomena is an
unnecessary retreat since qualia include outwardly experienced
phenomena in the perceptible world. Apparent differences in
the mental and physical reflect the degree of spatial realization
or objectification for a given modality. To limit qualia to sensorial
10.6. Qualia and space experience gives a spurious division of the subjective into psychic
The fictitious division of mind into a physical and a mental por- and physical portions. There is no consciousness of sensation,
tion infects the concept of the intentional. The physical is wholly only what are imagined to be sensorial or sensory-like experi-
outside mind, though mind objectifies objects that appear to be ences. Sensorial consciousness is an intra-psychic perception, like
non-mental. Apart from sensory qualia, the contrast between a mental image in one modality.
extended and unextended objects that, for Brentano as for oth-
Moreover, “sensory” data such as color, after-images and pain
ers, was central in the distinction of the physical and mental is a
are not apprehended in a pure state but as part of a spatial field.
continuum from the subjective to the objective in microgenetic
The fracture lines of pathology reveal the contextual bases of
294 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 295

such phenomena. In frontal lobotomy, pain may be felt without its presumed universality in sentient organisms. Pain is a primi-
its affective or signaling qualities. The patient admits to having tive psychic experience in an incipient spatial field in contrast to
pain and states that the pain is painful, but is not bothered by it. perceptions that develop out of body space into visual objects.
There is no sign of a painful experience. What sort of pain is this?
Perhaps there is a relation to relaxation or meditative treatments As there is no pure pain, there is no pure color experience.
of pain, or post-hypnotic suggestion, in which, one might say, the Color and form are inseparable. The contours of objects are carved
pain is not attended to or does not enter consciousness. In pain out by differences in color or hue. In hallucinogenic experience,
“agnosia” or “asymbolia” with parietal lesions, the meaning or sig- colors melt into the viscosity of “empty” space as object bound-
nificance of felt pain is lost, not only somatic pain but shrill sound aries dissolve. Early in the recovery of cortical blindness there is
and light. The contrast of pain and pleasure is asymmetric in that a diffuse color experience, usually a red field (erythopsia) with
pleasure is complex while pain, especially physical pain, is fairly little or no depth perception, rather like the visual gray of the eyes
straightforward. We may not agree on our pleasures but we do closed (Katz, 1935). One does not regain the redness (greenness,
understand the quality of pain. Yet the pathological cases make us etc.) of a tomato without the tomato. Color assumes or defines
ask, what is a pain without its noxious quality? Pain is not a simple shape with a return of form perception. The “flight of colors” in
sensation but a conceptual, affective experience. the after-image shows spatial extension in the increase in size in
relation to “projection” surface (Emmert’s law). The character of
The occurrence of pain without a painful experience recalls ar- the after-image is similar to pathological illusion in being closer
guments of Rosenthal (1993) that the intentional focus on a state to the geometry of visual space. The after image lacks object
of pain gives the painful feeling. One can be distracted and notice constancies, which would suggest a lack of transit through earlier
a mitigation of pain. But patients who have had a lobotomy are still segments in object-formation. The features of the after-image are
conscious of pain or can be reminded of it, so it would seem that those of an image arising at the apex of the visualization process,
what is decisive is an indifference to pain, or a loss or suppression the aim of which is an external, i.e. “physical”, object.
of affect, or a lack of access of the affect to consciousness rather
than an intentional focus that makes unconscious pain painful. In infants, visual space tends to be limited to the perimeter of
It is tempting to explain such instances by saying that an unfelt limb action. This is also the space of the congenitally blind. The
pain is like an ambient perception in awareness without access intra-psychic space of pain does not develop to an extra-personal
to conscious mind. However, animals certainly feel pain without field. This is because pain is mediated by sub-cortical structures,
states of human-like consciousness or intentionality. but also because it is tied to the body. There are cases (autotop-
agnosia) where body parts are referred to external locations. The
Pain is considered a pure sensation, i.e. perception, but exclud- parts are presumably seen but not felt by the self. I am not familiar
ing “emotional pain”, there is spatial extension in its body loca- with cases where pain is externalized, though the tortured expres-
tion. A pain may be focal or diffuse, deep or superficial, strongly sions of hypnagogic faces and autoscopy suggest that at least the
or weakly localized, but it is never “unattached”. One knows, in appearance of pain can objectify. Of course, objectification is one
general, where the pain is located. The transition from the inte- way of getting rid of the pain. The axial space of the deep body is
rior of the body to its surface accompanies a shift from a more the initial stage in the derivation of all later modes of space per-
primitive non-specific pain to one that is more acute and local- ception. Visual space begins with a construct of bodily space that
ized. The primitive quality of pain is consistent with its distribu- is also the field of pain but, unlike pain, it undergoes an outward
tion in a more archaic stratum of body-space, as well as the light development. The body space of pain, the kinesthetic space of the
myelination of “pain fibres”, the largely sub-cortical representa- congenitally blind, the object-space of visual perception, are suc-
tion, the association with aggressive and defensive reactions and cessive levels of space realization. The progression from archaic
296 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 297

to recent, or somatic to external, is a continuous transformation. process, similar to that of idea and act. Searle’s “conditions of
This fact is overlooked, as early and late segments solidify into satisfaction” refer to the fit of belief to world as the “truth” or ve-
opposing mental and physical polarities. ridicality of an object-perception. This permits a judgment of the
truth in correspondence, e.g., of concept to fact, in which mind
Theories of the world heavily depend on the visual modality. maps to a physical entity. Obviously a “correspondence” of mind
Epistemology is the field of inquiry that seeks to account for the to world is important for survival and the empirical grounds of
extensive character of visual space in relation to interior mind. concepts. But correspondence implies a match, not a transition,
Patterns of pathological breakdown reveal the external world of and finesses the intermediate phases in becoming through which
visual perception to be the most superficial layer in a multi-tiered the world actualizes, a move assumed to avoid skepticism and
process of space-formation. This process begins with a two-di- solipsism to which phenomenalism leads by creating an artificial
mensional space of the body in upper brainstem and transitions gap out of what are early and late segments in a single process, a
to external objects through a fluid, extra-personal but still viewer- gap the intentional has been invented to fill.
centered space of dream. The object space of ordinary perception
has to be renewed and revived each moment in the imagination A critical issue for direct perception is that if objects are directly
as sensation guides the forming pre-object to adapt to the imme- known, what is the status of the concepts that prefigure them?
diate surround. Without sensation, the mind would not achieve a The object tree has a greater sense of reality than the concept uni-
veridical representation of the world and we would live in a private corn, though the concept can be said to be real and exist even if
sphere of imagery and pre-rational thought, like that of dream. its referent is imaginary. Conversely, if we deny direct perception
for external objects, what are we to make of the felt immediacy of
concepts and other conscious contents? If there is direct knowl-
edge of the concepts that give rise to objects, what is the implica-
tion for object knowledge? Are objects phenomenal and concepts
10.7. Direct and indirect knowledge real, or the reverse? Are both real, neither? The thread that binds
Pols (1993) writes, with equivocation, “that our hold on the real, the contents of mind together, concepts, images, objects, proposi-
if it is to be effective, must in some cases be direct”, implying that tions, etc. is the underlying activity of which they are manifesta-
direct knowledge of the real is possible for some things, which tions.
then can serve as a basis for the knowledge of other things that
cannot be directly known. Searle (1983) speaks more forcefully In the path from concept to object, sensation delimits the
and for much of philosophy, when he accepts direct perception, potential of the concept to individuate particulars. The delimita-
and proclaims he is a naïve realist. Like Pols, he offers no argu- tion gives objects as inverse mirrors, Rorschachs, of the physical
ments for this position, which is apparently justified by its utility world. The derived nature of the external owes to a shaping effect
and, one has to assume, as an attempt to eliminate psychology outside the mind of the perceiver. Every “sensorial” experience
from philosophy. Whitehead is more honest about the psychologi- is a perceptual endpoint. The shaping effect of sensation and the
cal issues, noting that the temporal lag in perception alone refutes intrinsic constraints of habit determine how a concept develops in
direct perception. He maintained that the duration separating a a given act of thought. Object and concept are phenomenal, but in
perceptual object from its inferred physical datum reveals a com- a different way. The phenomenal character of objects is the rela-
ponent of memory in every perception. tion to a model of the physical world. The phenomenal character
of concepts comes of their need for the concrete particulars that
The commitment to direct perception goes directly from con- make thought real or empirical.
scious belief to conscious object, circumventing the antecedent
298 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 299

10.8. Purposefulness: dream and wakefulness mediate forms. The limited intentionality and pre-agentive feeling
in dream expose the vulnerability of certain arguments on the
Purposefulness without intention occurs in awareness without a relation of intentionality to consciousness.
conscious self, possibly in “altered states”, such as hypnotic trance
or sleepwalking. The externalist treats action as physical output The agency that accompanies some forms of thought imagery
that has left the agent and is part of the material world, in the is key to understanding the agency that accompanies voluntary
same way that sensation is conceived as physical input that can be action. One can say that the aim to a definiteness not fully speci-
seized as an intentional content. Perception, action and content fied in a concept or image is comparable to the agency in thought-
are all split from the invisible process behind them. From this (ex- imagery that aligns intention for a thought image with that for an
ternal) perspective, and on an empirical basis, consciousness and overt action. The sense of volition for certain images and concepts
awareness — the intentional and the purposeful — cannot be read- refers to phases in thought-development in common with the
ily distinguished. We apprehend this difference in our own mind, intention for a given action. Intention is intentionality with a fo-
as when we reach without thinking for a cup of coffee as opposed cus on action rather than objects. When the dynamic of action
to a conscious decision, but the inability to confidently ascertain stabilizes as a content, intention becomes intentional. When in-
in another person the presence or absence of a self engaged in a terest condenses into action, the intentional becomes intention.
particular action is no excuse to conflate the two states. The child Intention is buried in the intentional like an action that is attenu-
who, for verisimilitude and lack of knowledge, takes a mechani- ated in its aim. This attenuation is the aboutness of intentionality
cal crocodile as a real one is not so distant from the philosopher at a phase prior to action when goals, not acts, are targets. This is
who, for the same reasons, or through indolence or weakness of also the phase of choice or decision in action.
thought, claims identity in a mere surface resemblance.
In sum, intentionality signifies a consciousness-of (about)
In dream, is the thought or feeling of action without the possi- something that is descriptive of consciousness but is not a unique
bility of acting sufficient for purposefulness? One can dream one state of mind. The question is moot, which came first, intentional-
is acting with an intention to act, but dreaming of an intention ity or consciousness, or which depends on the other. The trace of
and having an intention are subtly different experiences. The thin the intentional in the actualization of every physical and organic
line that separates the passive intention of dream from the active entity is the aim to definiteness in its becoming-into-being. If con-
volition of agency is a point in the passage of internal to external sciousness is always about something, intentionality disappears
mind. One does not have true agency until commitment follows in the general problem of consciousness. A consciousness that is
into action. The antecedent feeling of choice, in concepts or in not about something is awareness. Aboutness excludes contents
images, leads in two directions: to agency, when it passes to the without distinct objects. Intentionality narrows consciousness to
feeling of activity for action; and to detachment, when it passes to the self-object relation; consciousness expands this relation to
the feeling of receptiveness for objects. include, inter alia, the present, identity, remembrance and the
mediating phases through which contents actualize.
Is the aboutness of a dream image sufficient for the state to
qualify as intentional? Dream as “wish fulfillment” can be con-
strued as intentional. The self of the dream “sees” the object (im-
age) it desires (fears, etc.) or its symbolic representation. The self
of dream lacks agency, its objects have limited spatial extension
and its beliefs and wishes are obscured by distortions. But still,
the dream is an intentional mode of consciousness, transitional
between belief and object, in which the actualization is for inter-
Chapter 11
Subjectivity and Truth

“The task of philosophy is


to recover the totality obscured by the selection”.

Whitehead (PR 15)

11.1. Introduction
The interpretation of mental content in philosophy differs from
that in process thought, particularly microgenesis, where the
theory of the mental state is fundamental. In microgenesis, the
direction of development and iteration of the mental state is from
the core self to conscious mental content and external objects.
Ideas, images, objects and feelings are individuations of the self
that perish as momentary endpoints in a single act of thought or
perception. Mental contents expose phases in the actualization.
They do not lead to future acts but are replaced by ensuing ones.
The relation of image to object, or of proposition to fact, is that of
an intermediate to a distal phase in the same state, with interme-
diate and distal phases emanating from an antecedent phase of
self. A fact is an outcome of conceptual-feeling, a mental object.
Contents in the mental state are not themselves states. A proposi-
tion or image is not a mental state. The mental (mind/brain) state
is the full process of actualization from core to content, from self
to object. In clinical studies, symptoms are transiently exposed
segments in mental process. The study of symptoms permits a
reconstruction of the mental state that can serve as an anchor for
speculation in neuroscience and psychology (see: Fig. 7.1.).

Externalism is outside the mental state, thus non-psychological.


The primary relation is from a developed mental content, such as
a proposition, to an objective fact. There is no mental thread from
self to proposition, nor from proposition to fact, or if there is, it is
conceived as inconsequential. The psychic antecedents of surface
contents have no bearing on their interpretation. A proposition
302 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 303

is distinct from its formative history, perceptions are “out there” nalism conforms to common sense, as in the idea of mind as a
in the world and reality is independent of thought. The truth of storehouse of feelings, memories and ideas, or the world as a col-
a proposition turns on the adequacy of the relation of mental to lection of objects in causal interaction. The assembly model of
world events, but the mental events have already, in many instanc- perception and the copy theory of memory are derived from this
es, assumed the properties of external solids. Externalism uproots way of thinking. The burden on process theory is to demonstrate
mental content from the psyche, displaces it to an abstract theater the fiction of common sense beliefs when applied to the mind/
in external space, and finally re-inserts it into mind as a functional brain, i.e. how such beliefs deceive us into thinking the mind is
component. In the case of propositions, they are severed from organized as a mirror of the world it displays. This burden is com-
mind, examined as to their truth-value, then transferred back into mon to substance theory when mental objects, which are phases
mind as instrumental in action. Externalism fabricates a theory of in actualization, such as the self, are deemed illusory. If one holds
mind from the exposed objects of ordinary experience, whether that an object-like self that persists over time is an illusion — one
logical solids such as propositions, or the constituents of concepts of the most powerful we have — an account is needed of how it
and perceptions, which are presumed ingredient in the objects comes about, though it is probable that a thoughtful account of
into which they are assembled. this problem would undermine the ordinary view of external ob-
jects. If the self is a category, so too are its derivations. If the self
These differences between process and substance stem from is an illusion, so are the mental and external objects to which it
such foundational issues as: (1) how do objects, as segments of gives rise.
events, precipitate in the mind (images, ideas) and in the world
(objects), i.e., how are objects or mental contents carved out of Not all distinctions are important, but importance can be given
flux, (2) why do we perceive objects, not the change that lays them to any distinction. Once a distinction is made, it sheds its attach-
down, including the transition from the self to its objects, and (3) ment to the ground from which it separated, and objectifies as
how, in substance theory, does change occur across the sharp an element or building block in the thought behind it. Organic
edges of object demarcations? wholes once divided are recombined as aggregates. Hume wrote
that things distinguished are as separate as if there were no man-
Microgenetic theory requires an intuitive leap beyond direct ex- ner of connection between them. A distinction justifies and prop-
perience. We see objects that change, not the change that deposits agates arguments on its behalf. With increasing definiteness and
them. Objects are everywhere, motion is seamless, and change multiplication, inessential partitions obscure the deeper reality of
is invisible. The concepts of atomic or irreducible substance, antecedent wholeness. Artificial entities take on life in an artificial
instantaneous time and external relations, postulate change in world, a parallel psychology or sphere of philosophical discourse.
the causal connectivity from one perceptual or logical solid to A computational model of the mind is the most obvious fiction,
another. In process thought, objects arise in the replacement of the main rationale for which, its presumed heuristic value, has a
epochs. Change is in the transition from potential to actual. The negative impact on direct study of the mind/brain.
philosophy of becoming posits qualities; quantities, in contrast,
are the currency of a philosophy of being. The accounts depend All internal and external objects are contrasts that achieve
on competing theories of time and space. Are they irreconcilable, specificity at each phase in their derivation. Most of these phases
or can a substance ontology of being and external change be re- are transitional and the contents are virtual; others are final and
solved with an event-ontology of becoming and intrinsic change? definite. All contents individuate out of neural configurations that
have the potential to specify a number of alternative paths. The
Process theory appeals to its adherents for its subjectivism and phase-transition is a series of whole-to-part shifts. At each phase,
tendency to idealism, while substance theory enlists support for the configuration is a matrix of possibilities. The succession of
its realism and objectivity. This is also a way of saying that exter-
304 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 305

whole-part shifts exemplifies a fundamental law of the mind/brain There is a strong tendency, in the privacy and subjectivity of
that characterizes the transition from one phase to the next. The knowledge, for pragmatism and microgenesis to lead to Idealism.
transition can also be described as a shift from potential to actual, The adaptive nature of truth-seeking implies the primacy of an in-
but this is more aptly characterized as the trajectory of the entire dividual perspective. The externalist links pragmatism to the opin-
process. This tendency to ever-greater individuation or analysis ion of a solitary thinker, rather than one who adjusts thought to an
is the natural direction of thought, which leads ever further from external standard. However, matching inner to outer or adjusting
the unity out of which partitions develop. In process theory, the personal truth to an external judgment is preconditioned on the
individuation of objects in the mind/brain state illustrates the law- existence of an external truth to which individual truth appeals,
fulness of mental process. In substance theory, this lawfulness is as well as the absolute or irrevocable nature of a truth that results
replaced by entities in ad hoc relations dictated not by psychologi- from, or points to, a consensual judgment. External validation is
cal necessity but by gaps in philosophical argumentation. the sum of individual judgments each of which is adaptive. Even
if consensus is closer to “the truth”, it is still provisional. To step
outside all individual minds and compare an individual concept
with god’s perspective would entail a correspondence between
individual or collective mind and mind-independent reality. It as-
11.2. Microgenesis and pragmatism sumes access to the absolute reality of a physical world that is
William James (1912) was close to the microgenetic concept of the inaccessible to individual mind, which in any case would infect
mind/brain state in writing that: it with subjectivity. Put otherwise, if mind could know the physi-
cal world directly, that world would be altered in the very act of
“whenever certain intermediaries are given, such that, as they knowing it.
develop towards their terminus, there is experience from point to
point of one direction followed, and finally of one process fulfilled, From an adaptive standpoint, individual truth is matched to
the result is that their starting point thereby becomes a knower and the external by continuous revision. This occurs not by correspon-
their terminus an object meant or known”. dence but the success in fitness and adjustment to the considered
views of others. Except for states such as dream or hallucination,
In the description of overlapping pulses of consciousness he the world of perception is the only world we can perceive. Sensory
was also close to the microgenetic account of recurrence. The data coming from the world prevent alternative, often maladap-
analogy would have been greater had he included the sculpting tive, possibilities. Thoughts and propositions that are realized in
of phases by intrinsic habit and extrinsic sensations that shape the acts and statements are shaped to the world by reaction and con-
whole-part or context-item shifts to adapt personal need to condi- versation, in response to outer conditions and the behaviors of
tions in the world. Put differently, the sensory environment con- others. These influences are not resolutely “out there”; they affect
strains the mind/brain state to eliminate maladaptive form. In art individual mind by sculpting cognition to conditions to which it
or poetry, truth rests on symbol, metaphor or allusion. This mode must adapt for the organism to survive and flourish.
of truth-seeking has an affinity with the microgenetic account of
intermediate phases in fact-creation. Shaping is incomplete; the The pragmatic or microgenetic theory of truth holds for ob-
greater subjectivity and interioricity of early cognition come to the servers up to the limit of evidence and a consensus beyond which,
fore. In ordinary thinking, the content of a thought is achieved at it is supposed, an absolute truth, outside consciousness and inde-
the conclusion of the mental act. The object of the thought and pendent of human thought, is waiting to be discovered. Individual
the agreement of thought with object, are outcomes of the state or consensual truth may resemble final truth, but unable to know
not evident at its inception. the latter, it is a best approximation to the conditions to which
306 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 307

it is applied. The locked-in mental world of a solitary mind, or a a similar revision, carving out ideas to reach a consensus that a
comparison to an external but unknowable physical world, im- majority of like-minded thinkers endorse. Truth is a matter of
plies Idealism at one extreme and/or an absolute reality at the dispelling error to make room for fact. False beliefs are aides in
other. Idealism does not obligate an absence of the external, but coping, resilient, often magnets for reinforcement. The belief in
rather, a world that can only be known through a model, even if it god grows out of affective need, instilled values, early education,
is shaped so exactly that mind perceives its own product as “the life-experience, the search for meaning, other phenomena, largely
real thing”. inexplicable, together with the complexity, obscurity and lack of
signification of the everyday, as well as in reaction to scientific
In microgenesis, every mind/brain state, every thought, per- fact, which seems empty of personal value. A powerful emotional
cept or action, begins with implicit (unconscious) beliefs. When we experience, or one instilled by trauma or “brainwashing”, can in-
perceive an object, the implicit belief inter alia is that an external duce conviction in false belief. False beliefs such as the Capgras
world exists. When we have a thought or image, the implicit belief delusion (see below) or the beliefs of a primitive mentality are
is a self that is thinking. An unconscious belief is the progenitor unshakeable. For example, Lévy-Bruhl (1975) described a tribe,
and guide to thought or action. The core self is derived from im- the Bororo that cannot be convinced by arguments that another
plicit belief and then specified to the conscious or empirical self, tribe, the Trumai, do not pass the night under water.
ideas, feelings and objects. A belief is not isolable from the self
that believes. Such fixed beliefs have adaptive value in serving to explicate
unknown realms of psychic or natural experience into which
Belief is neither true nor false. It is the agreement of belief with observation and objectivity have not yet ventured. A false belief
“reality” that determines truth. In having an internal and external that a person can outrun a tiger — or is imbued with tiger-spirit
segment, value is similar to belief. A perceived object selected by — might help him to escape, while a rational acceptance that the
interest (Perry, 1926) is midway between implicit and explicit val- belief is untrue entails waiting to be devoured. One acts according
ue. The internal aspect of value is desire; the external aspect is ob- to conviction regardless of its truth. To believe is not the same as
ject worth. Beliefs and values are unconscious determinants that to know. One says, I believe there is a god, not I know there is a
can become conscious in thought or imagery, but the conscious god. One can say, I do not know but I believe. True knowledge is
belief is not a replica of that in the unconscious; it is an endpoint the unacknowledged subtext of thought, but belief is its engine.
in a transition to consciousness in which proximal categories are
linked to distal ones by symbolic, metaphoric, experiential and In a false belief or delusion such as the Capgras syndrome, a
affective relations. spouse, close friend or relative is misidentified.45 This disorder is
“modularized” by cognitivists who, ignoring the context and full
description of the disorder, maintain that it points to an isolated
belief system. But a false belief is not an island of mentation. Such
cases often have other reduplications, e.g. their home, altered feel-
11.3. Conviction and belief ing in the double, e.g. a seducer, age regression, e.g. the double
Errors are acts that do not adapt to the external and are correctible may be younger, and the belief is not resistant to manipulation
in ensuing revisions. An external standpoint is implied from by the examiner. Even psychotic delusions can be altered by sug-
the revision of an internal one. If error is thought to undermine gestion. In conversion hysteria, correcting one false belief, e.g. a
pragmatism, trial-and-error resurrects it. The account of truth is limb paralysis, may lead to another even worse, e.g. blindness.
weakened if the standard or standpoint outside the individual is
absolute and independent of all thinkers. Each thinker undergoes
45
See my description of a Capgras case (Franklin, Brown and Freedman, 1982).
308 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 309

The claim of modularity follows from the divisibility or logical of truth and much to deny it, exert a powerful effect on reason.
substantiality of encapsulated psychic phenomena, which are Unlike conviction, certainty does not tolerate an incompatibility
postulated as autonomous so as to conform abnormal psychol- of belief. When conviction conflicts with fact or other beliefs, true
ogy to philosophy and to models of normal cognition, when such or false, or when, from an objective standpoint, one belief con-
perturbations should be the data from which a robust philosophy tradicts another, the opposing beliefs retain their force through
could be extracted. shared attributes or conjoined properties that override incompat-
ibilities. A shared property or predicate leads to the identification
Russell distinguished the psychological question, what makes of disparate topics instead of a resemblance of topics in respect of
us hold a belief is true, from the philosophical question, what is it that property.
for a belief to be true. What makes us hold a belief is true can be
construed as the capacity to distinguish true and false belief. This What gives a belief conviction is not whether it is right or true,
reflects the structure of a belief and the reasons why we believe since conviction is often stronger for beliefs that are evidently
it to be true. Action is driven by conviction, certainty is hesitant. false or untestable. The strength of conviction accompanies a re-
I can be certain that pastrami will give me indigestion or that a sistance to falsification. Conviction replaces the need for choice
certain movie will cause a headache, yet I eat the pastrami and see and decision. It is closer to drive, desire and the core self, often
the film. Someone who believes a house is haunted will probably bound up with the self-concept, rooted in unconscious bias and
not enter it. Superstition and magical belief are manifestations of the seeds of action. Truth for the psyche is the adaptation of need
a preliminary phase of syncretic thinking in normal people. The to circumstance. The transition from deeper, more personal
conviction in false belief, in myth, delusion and primitive mental- concepts and feelings to rational ones depends on the degree to
ity, are not distortions of the normal but markers of the paralogi- which the sensory environment shapes the emerging thought, i.e.
cal thinking that underlies rational thought. the strength of endogenous concepts versus adaptive pressures.
These pressures carry the concept to the external world, to greater
Conviction leads to action, certainty tends to be provisional. impersonality and concessions to others. The dominant focus of
Certainty implies knowledge supported by reason with openness an act of thought determines whether a belief is fixed and de-
to refutation, and has an impersonality that conviction rejects. lusional, scientific and provisional, or a philosophical truth that
One can be certain of a thing, but then realize that you were mis- depends on the agreement of generic propositions with timeless
taken. Conviction does not depend on proof or demonstration, objects. What it is for a belief to be true engages less the bases of
but on values that underlie belief and the coherence with other truth-demonstration than the conditions on which truth is decid-
beliefs and past experience. Moore wrote of rock-bottom beliefs ed. Ultimately, this depends on the agreement of belief with fact,
such as this is my hand, yet amputees with phantoms have a hard though facts depend on other beliefs so there must be coherence
time believing, with the eyes closed, that the hand is not there. within belief systems for any given belief to be decided as true.
Patients with autotopagnosia with a lesion in the parietal lobe and
intact limbs may locate their hand on the wall! Pathological case For psychology, it is less how my belief relates to the exter-
study reminds us of the vulnerability of so-called rock bottom be- nal situation and more how it relates to what I know and feel.
liefs based on certain knowledge, of the self, of the existence of Conviction seizes on facts that satisfy innate, early-acquired, un-
the world, even that one is alive. conscious or implicit beliefs. The implicit beliefs that guide con-
viction are saturated with feeling and deep in individual character
What makes a person hold a belief is true involves factors oth- and personality, while the explicit beliefs that guide abstract or
er than its truth. Strong conviction is absolute in its truth; it may rational thought are surface articulations of these constructs in
coincide with truth but does not require it. A belief in heaven and which feeling and valuation have been decanted. The certainty
hell, angels and devils, obsessions and delusions, with no evidence
310 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 311

one will defend is not the conviction one will die for. Though applicable to the very large and very small, to mind and world,
conviction in a false belief is occasionally given up when reason experience and thought, then the provisional truths of psychology
prevails, rarely does conviction — as opposed to certainty — follow are a continuous working-toward them.
on rational deliberation.
In logic, the direction from idea to reality prevails over that
We should recall that in most instances, expediency is the from thinker to thought, though to begin with reality, which is
mother of truth. The context behind a fact is too vast for the whole the tendency in analytic and empirical thinking, as in common
truth to be taken into account. To say, this is a cup of tea, supposes sense, and move inward to thought, is the reverse of the direc-
one comprehends the language and has an intact perceptual sys- tion of thought itself. The reality that shapes thought is the reality
tem, that one knows what tea is and can distinguish it from other thought creates. The former is that of physical sensation applied
liquids, that one knows a cup and can distinguish it from a bowl, to thought as a limit, the latter, a mental picture (or sound, touch)
saucer and other such items, that one comprehends the other that results from an iterated trimming of endogenous form. To
(object, person) in relation to the self, and can access an object- common sense, a picture of the world is the starting point of
concept out of wider spheres of self and world knowledge. thought, not its outcome, but for internalism (or microgenesis),
intra- and extra-personal contents are outcomes. The content that
externalism maps to reality and the reality to which that content
corresponds are phases in a single mind/brain state. The irony is
that truth in externalism depends on a correspondence between
11.4. Adaptation and correspondence two false beliefs: the reification of mental content and the reality
Utility is an adjustment of inner to outer, or the fitness of concept and autonomy of its objectifications.
to fact, which is the adaptation of mind to an inferred external
world. Truth is conformity to an external situation. Trivially, this Along these lines, the externalist concept of the aboutness of
implies that truth is what works in a given circumstance. The lo- intentionality as a direction to a mental or external object can be
cality of utility is in tension with the generality of its application, seen as a relation of penultimate to final phases in a mind/brain
for a conditional or provisional truth in pragmatism, or in science, state. Introspective content is intermediate in the actualization,
even if it has a relative ubiquity of application, is not perceived as not a terminal addition. The forward direction and the analysis or
eternally true. The question is whether pragmatism is an inad- individuation over phases narrows intra-psychic potential to extra-
equate theory for philosophy, or whether philosophy must adjust psychic definiteness. A relative suspension of sensory constraint
its truth-claims to psychological reality. allows thought to deposit at pre-terminal phases, e.g. imagination,
fantasy, reverie. With loss of constraint, in dream, hallucination
The correspondence of content with reality and the adaptation of and psychosis, thought moves outward (or the world recedes).
content to reality are linked ideas. The ideal of philosophical truth The transition is from felt experience to observation, from gestalt
is an agreement (adaptation) of mind and nature that is univer- to figure, from generality to precision. In this progression, the
sally and forever true. Psychological truth approaches philosophi- mind achieves conformity to an experiential niche that is a negative
cal truth when an adaptation holds on repeated occasions. The image of the real.
difference is the imperfection of truth-finding in psychology (and
science) and the absoluteness of truth-knowing in philosophy. Given the opposition of internal and external perspectives,
The scientific concept of truth as provisional contrasts with the neither of which are decisive, one perspective ought not to prevail
philosophical concept of a truth as pure, final and irrefutable. If at the other’s expense, since a metaphysic probably owes more
there are such timeless truths — logical, mathematical — invariant, to the unconscious presuppositions of the thinker than the logic
behind them (Collingwood, 1940). Moreover, either approach is
312 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 313

incomplete without the other. From an internal standpoint, the A thought can be a vague idea, a specific idea of an object, or
relation of self to content gives truth limited by personal need. the object the idea is about.46 Thinking of a horse, the idea is immi-
From an external standpoint, with the self left behind and distal nent in the perception, even if a horse suddenly comes into view
phases sliced off, truth is the correspondence of earlier to later in without thinking about it. The horse is recognized as it is seen. It
a single state. Comprehensiveness demands the incorporation of is judged to be beautiful or ordinary, approachable or dangerous.
all phases in the state, and a sincere effort to deal with feeling in Concepts and feelings are activated with the initial perception. The
decision-making and object-value and, more generally, the affec- object (horse) individuates meanings and feelings that are part of
tive tonality of supposedly affect-free concepts. its structure. In ordinary perception, concepts relinquished in a
transition to the object, endure in the perception as identification,
It is worth noting a similarity in the relation of idea and object import and affective charge. The idea or concept of a horse, and
to that of recall and a standard in memory. In the former, corre- the horse, objectify successive phases — from intra- to extra-psy-
spondence is across distal phases in consciousness. In the latter, chic — in a common process.
it is from an unconscious phase to a conscious one. If a concept
arrives at truth when it matches an object, does a memory arrive A statement, such as “that is a horse”, or the depiction of a horse
at precision when experience matches recall? In one instance, in a drawing, points to an object beyond the words or marks. Signs
a conscious mental content is compared with a physical reality that stand for or point to objects are said to have a derived inten-
on the other side of perception. In the other, a conscious mental tionality from the meanings behind them. In that an objectified
content is compared with the physical reality of the unconscious. content — word, drawing — designates an object, it is presumed to
In truth-seeking, thought, memory and the objects before us all be intentional. On this view, the mental content is interpreted as
realize the potential behind them striving for completeness. intentional rather than the trajectory from the self to that content.
But drawing a horse, a unicorn or the Guernica is the outcome
of a series of mental states. The object depicted in the drawing
— real, imaginary or an art-work — develops out of an idea. It is
not a further object to which the drawing refers, since the referent,
11.5. Process, content and truth present or not, is also derived from the mental state. The horse in
An external object requires a subject as observer but an internal or the fields that is named or called, or rendered in a drawing, is an
psychic object requires a self. All mental contents are conscious. extra-personal image that has developed out of an object-concept.
The rest is non-conscious process, whether intra- or extra-psychic. The fact that phases in qualitative transformation take on greater
The becoming of a conscious object is the dynamic through which substantiality in their outward development makes us think that
the mental state takes on existence, i.e. phases that generate the we copy a real horse, not a picture of a real horse in the external
subjectivity of an object (or entity). For internalism, truth depends space of mind, in which a drawing and a horse individuate a com-
on the realization of veridical objects, as well as coherence at mon ground.
each phase in fact-creation. Externalism assumes self-sufficiency,
stability and persistence. The concordance of thought to fact, or
logical to perceptual objects, has one (logical) foot in the psyche,
the other (perceptual) foot in the physical world. The description 46
Object and content are here used interchangeably. From a psychological
from outside treats some psychic contents, e.g. propositions, as standpoint, the distinction is arbitrary. The real divide is between the object (con-
objective, others not, e.g. hallucinations. Diachronic process goes tent) and the process that actualizes the object. The content of an object, e.g. a
from unconscious to conscious, past to present, potential to ac- horse depicted in a painting, the painting, the actual horse, its tail or a tear in the
tual; synchronics goes from one conscious actuality to another. canvas, merely reflects the immediate focus of attention, which is the content of
the momentary consciousness.
314 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 315

For externalism, the mind produces or discovers facts that are act of spilling coffee becomes non-intentional when the coffee
mind-independent. For microgenesis (and pragmatism), facts are is discovered to be tea, though the spilling can still be an act of
creations, irreducible values as Dewey put it. Since perceptual agency. Here, the act of truth-reconciliation is appended to a prior
objects are products of the mind, the internalist tends to infer a act, which substitutes for belief a true fact that relates to world
physical ground, an absolute reality that is independent of ob- knowledge. If true knowledge can retroactively negate or call into
servation and beyond human experience. The absolute and the question the intentional quality of a prior act, would this not apply
eternal are palliatives for incessant loss in a theory of flux. This even if the agent were unaware of the contents of the cup? The act
tendency is less pronounced in externalism where permanence is of thought in which others know the cup contains tea is devoid
endemic and the distinction of object and entity is blurred. of psychological import, though the knowledge, if available to the
agent, can become part of subsequent intentions.

If the outcome of an action — spilling coffee instead of tea


— has retroactive force in altering intentionality, at what point is
11.6. Intentionality the outcome fixed? Take a hypochondriac who believes he has
A good example of snatching mental contents from the mind as cancer. If one were to falsify the belief that might not alleviate the
philosophical objects is found in the literature on intentionality, hypochondria nor alter conviction. The doctors are wrong, or have
in which propositional contents are detached, analyzed and re- over-looked the correct diagnosis. Suppose he develops cancer
inserted in the mental state as adjudicative in choice and action. some years later. How does this rebound on the intentionality of
Intentional objects lifted from the psyche and re-introduced as his prior thoughts or acts? If a person gives money to help some-
determinative in judgment require a construal of truth as deter- one but the money winds up, instrumentally, in the hands of an
mining the intentionality of the act it subtends. The procedure is assassin, at what point does the later outcome cease to influence
confused because two mental acts are postulated, that of thinking the intentionality of the original act? An intentionality hostage
about something, which is the act of believing or having a thought, to truth requires many qualifications. Most statements are not
and that of believing the thought is true. An act of speculative clearly or immediately true and what is true of a statement at one
thought as to the truth of the belief is postulated to supplement a time may differ at another.
genuine act of agency, i.e. believing, desiring, intending, etc.47
Mistaken attributions do not influence the psychological qual-
Confusions arise when the object of a thought is interpreted ity of action. An act based on true knowledge is identical to one
in terms of its content, especially its propositional content, and based on error, since the knowledge guiding the act is the same
the glide from the content to the impact of truth-attributions on in both cases. If I believe I can reach an apple in a tree but fail in
action. This is sharply drawn in the writings of Davidson (1980) my attempt, how does the error in belief affect the act? Were I to
on intentionality, where it is claimed that intentionality requires truly believe I could not reach the apple, I would not reach for
background rationality or, put differently, intentionality can only it, and there would be no act of reaching to which a judgment
be ascribed to rational acts that are based on the truth of state- of intentionality would be applied. This raises the problem that
ments about them. Davidson’s example is a person who spills a a judgment of intentionality in such an instance based on a true
cup of tea thinking it is coffee. The claim is that the intentional proposition would, if known and accepted beforehand, result in a
failure to act, so there would be no act based on false belief, save
inaction, to which the truth determination applies.
47
See the critique by Sprigge (Putnam, 1997) who, along the lines of this argu-
ment, postulates one act of conceiving a state of affairs that includes belief in its Assuming that the quality of an action is independent of
actuality. whether the knowledge accompanying the action is true or false,
316 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 317

it is obvious that most individuals have incomplete knowledge of as an agent, while others decide whether or not the act is inten-
the true nature of their objects, whether they believe a ticket will tional? This implies that the judgment of the intentionality of an
win the lottery or that to marry your true love brings lasting hap- act is another act in the mind of the actor, or an act in the mind of
piness. If an act does not differ if the agent believes it is based on an observer. But these external and ancillary acts are open-ended
true knowledge that turns out not to be the case, as in the usual regressions that can also be submitted to a judgment of their in-
example of Polonius, or a husband who kills his wife believing, tentionality, i.e. the statement that a proposition is true or false is
falsely, she is unfaithful, what is the utility of arguments from the itself a true or false statement. This implies that the determination
standpoint of truth attributions? of intentionality is not by means of a secondary act appended to
the primary one, but can only be decided within the act itself and
To replace the psychology of actions with judgments of the by the actor, though it can be inferred by an observer.
truth of propositions about them presumes a degree of certainty
as to the truth. If the cup contains tea instead of coffee, what sort Another consequence of the dual-act argument is that it sup-
of tea, how strong, how hot? Tea is a super-ordinate category. How poses the opposite condition, namely, that a person can either
much has to be known about the object for the action to be inten- mistakenly believe his act is intentional, or unknowingly act in-
tional? Must one know or say, I am spilling a three-quarter cup of tentionally. Such examples show the difficulties that accrue when
mild, luke-warm Darjeeling? If the individual believes he is spill- the intrinsic nature of the act, i.e. the correlated mental state, is
ing a liquid without knowing the type, or merely inverting a cup replaced by descriptions based on the truth of statements about
without knowing the contents, how does his knowledge impact it. The displacement from privileged access transforms a direct
on the intentionality of his actions? If an error in the identifica- account of action — voluntary, agentive, intentional, involuntary,
tion of an object vitiates intentionality, what degree of precision automatic, or other acts of thought and perception — to a decision
is required to restore it? If the act of spilling coffee or tea does not on the truth of statements about the content of an actor’s mind.
differ according to the truth of the actor’s beliefs, how can the More precisely, the description of an action is removed to a shared
knowledge of an observer influence its intentionality? This takes field of propositions distinct from the intrinsic states they purport
intentionality outside the agent, and turns the psychology of the to describe. The cure for this distortion is for the intentional to be
intentional into a discourse on linguistic or semantic attributions? transported from the truth of an external committee to a subjec-
Is this what Brentano had in mind? Is the intentional fundamental tive aim in the mind of an individual.
to conscious thought or is it a meta-theory about the words used
to describe it? It seems obvious that a content in the mind such as a proposi-
tion, or in the world such as a chair, manifests an unseen internal
If the intentionality of an act is determined by the truth of a process of composition or formation. This process, the momentary
belief or if intentionality depends on the beliefs of others as to the pre-history of the content, is conceived as physical with respect to
aim or content of the action, how and by whom is the intentional the chair in its mechanical or atomic structure, and physiological
to be decided? If another person’s knowledge of an action can or psychic with respect to the mind, in brain activity or a com-
decide whether or not an act is intentional, what aspect of the bination of memorial and perceptual features. A strictly physical
intentionality of an act is determined by factors outside it? The theory entails that an object is the sum of the parts from which
external perspective entails a consensus as to the content of the it is constructed and into which it decomposes, for example the
actor’s mind even if the act is identical across conflicting judg- way a chair or sentence is physically put together. On this view,
ments. Absent the truth-judgments of others, is it possible for a assembly does not count in what an object is. The process that
person to act intentionally in isolation, or to know whether or not generates an object or statement is like the manufacture of a car,
his acts are intentional? Is it not odd to maintain that one acts which is conceived as independent of the order in which it was as-
318 Jason W. Brown

sembled. From the internal standpoint, the world and its objects
are wholes. From an external standpoint, objects are aggregates.
Externalism liberates mental events from their antecedents, crops
them into objects, and transfers them to a world of substance, cre-
ating entities at the forward edge of causal efficacy.

There is one world, not a choice between an immaterial psyche


and a mindless nature, but a nature that is compatible with psy-
chology. A theory of becoming is the key to the unification of in-
ternal and external perspectives. If becoming in mind and nature
does not deposit entities but constitutes them, to demarcate the
actual as content and neglect the antecedent as assembly is like
describing the flow of a river with bricks. The tendency to extend
mechanism to the psyche and not expand the psyche to the ex-
ternal leads to a machine theory of organism. This tendency is
reinforced by the rupture of a graduated aim to definiteness by
the uncoupling of late phases from early ones, or subtracting the
early ones from their outcomes, when all phases participate in the
epoch of every object or idea.

Finally, substantialism is related to instantaneity. If instants are


discrete, so are substances. Whitehead (PR 20) asked, “how can
concrete fact exhibit entities abstract from itself and yet partici-
pated in by its own nature”. I take this to mean, how does nature
enter (participate in) entities that are abstractions of the mind?
The reply is that modeling is an adaptation to nature in which flux
is anchored by abstractions of time and space, i.e. epochs of pro-
cess create objects from overlapping durations. The specification
of fact from initial generality is exposed in the suppression of the
irrelevant. The context sampled at successive phases in the men-
tal state, with the impact of nature at every phase, is one aspect of
the totality to which Whitehead referred.
Chapter 12
The Inward Path: Mysticism and Creativity

“I may not hope from outward forms to win


The passion and the life whose fountains are within”
Coleridge

12.1. Introduction
At least since Plato, madness has been associated with inspiration
in the artist and poet, while descriptions of delusion, paranoia,
dissociation, hallucinations and other symptoms of psychotic
thought are common in mystics (e.g. Leuba, 1925). 48 The occur-
rence of such pathologies in celebrated mystics such as Suso or St.
Theresa, and to a marked degree in sects such as yoga, together
with an extraordinary sensitivity, have led some to dismiss the
mystic as a lunatic and his or her visionary truths as delusional.
Here, we are not concerned with the truth of art or ultimate reality,
nor with the turn of mind that may be a pre-requisite, or accom-
paniment, of its attainment, but rather with the mental process of
truth-seeking in modes of thought independent of any judgment
on their outcome.49

The study of the Ucs has revealed a succession of categories


prior to the actualization of the final category into an image or
object (Brown, 1997; 2005; 2007). The retreat into the deep sub-
jective is, thus, a withdrawal to the categories before the arousal
of language, behind the visible and the palpable. This withdrawal

48
In this chapter, “artist” refers to all those who work in a creative way, in dif-
ferent forms of art but also in science, mathematics, philosophy and other fields.
When the artist is distinguished from the scientist, this will become clear in the
text.
49
It has been argued that mental disturbance is more pronounced in the
“would-be” mystic than the true one, Plotinus, Eckhart, Blake, Augustine,
Boehme, but even a cursory reading of the lives of the mystics raises objections
to this claim.
322 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 323

is the path to mystical insight and to what Goethe called the pool for a trance-like state that may last but a few moments and recur
of the creative Ucs. Certainly, the lives of the mystics are not so briefly, once a day, a week, a year, or never again. The parables of
dissimilar from those of many artists, and the creative experience Buddhist sutras emphasize the life of self-denial that is necessary
has features in common with mysticism. While the libertarian for enlightenment and liberation. Absorption in nature, or one-
spirit of some artists may seem in contrast to the asceticism of the ness in god’s love, is often the life goal. The artist also undertakes
mystic, social norms are defied in both by an unconventional, at a period of preparation and learning, a stage of incubation, before
times outrageous personality. In spite of the tendency for exag- the work congeals. At times, a state of inspiration that can reach
geration, the mystic would seem a more extreme manifestation of near-mystical rapture may herald the process of composition,
the same trends in many artists, where the romantic ideal of the though the Eureka or Aha experience, well described by Koestler
genius tends to overshadow personalities of equal ability but less (1964), is probably over-rated. In the daily routine of writing or
flamboyant careers. composing, each line or measure is intuition objectified. The
artist’s craft requires discipline if something original and of value
For the mystic and for many artists, ultimate reality is personal: is to see the light; occasionally, the work is preceded by an intense
the inward turn, the common occurrence of eccentricity or mad- transformative insight. The whole that emerges at such a moment
ness, of intoxication with drugs or alcohol, a variable degree of must recur, less vividly, if the insight is to quietly guide the elici-
self-denial for the pursuit of the calling, the concentration and tation of the parts, but at any given moment, only the parts are
the passivity, the “flash of insight”50, the certainty, authenticity present in Csness. Bosanquet wrote that in drawing a figure, the
and intimacy of the experience, its deeply personal nature and artist’s thought is concentrated at the tip of the pen, though once
uniqueness to the individual, and the passivity and the surrender we see the finished design we imagine the whole work was there
that is necessary in art and mystical experience. in the beginning guiding the artist’s hand.
The austerities of the mystic — starvation, flagellation, thorns, The artist’s insight, when it occurs, has the character of holism
and so on — are a more extreme expression of similar trends in (Mehta, 1963), simultaneity, and lack of multiplicity that resemble
the artist, in the need for alienation and isolation, or ruthless dedi- the mystic’s big Idea (Bennett, 1923; Stace, 1961). In the mystic,
cation, even a pact made with god or the self to limit distraction surrender is to the Other. Artistic wholeness is not apprehended
and enhance concentration and devotion (Gardner, 1993). Many as immersion in otherness — god, nature — but rather as a deeper
mystics, especially those with prophetic visions or an accentuated sounding of the self in relation to an intuition that is the object
passivity, have counted themselves instruments through which of inspiration. In the mystic, god is that intuition or object. The
god communicates but this can also occur in creative individu- experience is of the multi- or pan-modal categories of the core
als. Schopenhauer believed his principal work was dictated by the self; diffuse, without distinct content, prior to the partition of the
Holy Ghost. If one compares the mystical and artistic genius, the modalities of perception and the different spheres of cognition.51
similarities can be pronounced. In some individuals, the experi- The artist’s descent is less profound. There is Csness of concepts.
ence is identical. Blake wrote the poem “Milton” from immediate Intuition is in relation to the empirical self and a segment of its
dictation in a state of mystical ecstasy. partition, such as music, literature or painting. The feeling is
closer to desire, “located” in the self and its conceptual content.
There are also important differences. While mystical experi-
For the mystic, the core has an intensity that is drive-like, filling
ence has been reported as sudden and unexpected, more com-
the subject and its categorical primitives. Desire entails division
monly the mystic goes through a period of prolonged preparation

50
St. Augustine wrote, “and thus with the flash of one trembling glance it ar- 51
Microgenetic theory holds that perceptual modalities are not recombined but
rived at That Which Is (Conf. vii. 23). individuate from a multi-modal or synaesthetic core.
324 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 325

or partiality, not wholeness, and is consequent to drive-based feel- While mystic and artist have differing feelings of volition ac-
ings of love in union. cording to the degree of passivity and surrender, both feel as vehi-
cles or channels for spiritual inspiration.52 The process of creative
The combination of an empirical self that is Cs of a profound work is a fragile mystery to the artist, who feels relief, elation and
concept and its truth and authority tend to give the artist a sense gratitude when a work begins to emerge from the shadows onto
that he is a conduit for the influx of spirit, even a messianic feeling a blank canvas or an empty page. Dante expressed the feeling of
with a responsibility to implement the work and seek publicity for many artists when he wrote that, “art is the grandchild of God”.
his efforts. Historically, the allusion to the muse is a metaphor for Freud commented that, “whoever works as an artist certainly feels
the mystery and receptivity of creation. The notion of a muse is as a father to his works”. A musical work, historical treatise, math-
an assignment to a lesser god of the spiritual power of the “divine ematical proof, visualized all at once in the mind, is not a religious
Presence” from which everything emanates, including the power experience, though it can inspire the awe and humility that are es-
of the muse, who operates in a limited sphere of His influence. sential to religious feeling. But the artist, unlike the mystic, pours
Inevitably, the (usually male) artist and the female muse, and (in his religious feeling, or reverence, into the work, not into himself.
the Christian transition, the) often female mystic enthralled with Once complete, the work is detached, independent, like a child
a masculine god, lend a sexual flavor to creation in art and inter- with its own life in the world, while the inspiration — conception
penetration of god and soul in union. — with which it began, having been replaced and satisfied over
multiple implementations, is a near-forgotten memory. For the
The recovery from mystical exultation may accompany an ac-
mystic, however, the event, not having been discharged over time,
count of the experience so far as it is possible, but the experience
remains incandescent, real, transcendent and deeply personal.
is an end in itself. The withdrawal is solely for the purpose of mys-
tical experience. Even the service to others that often precedes The creative is not the experience of inspiration but the concept
union is for the merit of the mystic as a potential recipient of god’s that inspires and the work that follows, to which method and skill
love. In religion, the offering precedes and justifies the Idea; in art are subsidiary. In the mystic, method is necessary to achieve the
it is the reverse. The artist is driven to share the Idea with others. Idea, but lacking skill, nothing comes of it except personal exulta-
This process is codified in the Talmud, which advises one not to tion. The austerities that beckon the mystic to unity contrast with
seek god but to study so that, one day, perhaps, if you are fortu- the unity of the Idea that deposits the manifold of an artwork. So,
nate, god will find you. then, does the soul’s union with god achieve a kind of immortality
for the mystic that, for the artist, comes only with the greatness of
The testimony of a mystical experience is itself a tacit and soli-
his works. One could say that mystical union exemplifies potenti-
tary “artwork”. One could say the mystic is the artist and union is
ality, while the potential manifest in the Idea of the artist has value
the artwork. Everything goes into the creation of the mystic as an
only in actuality.
outcome of personal effort, and all this effort is for an audience
of One. Few are interested to hear the story of the artist’s inspira- The artist with an overarching vision (potential) may use vari-
tion; it is the artwork, not the Idea that precedes it, that holds our ous means over many occasions to revive and so empty (actual-
interest. A recounting of a Eureka experience is like listening to a ize) it. For composition, the Idea must be reinstated, implicitly
person’s dreams, which hold small appeal except for the dreamer and without the intensity of its first appearance. The potential is
and his analyst. However, the ancient belief that a descent into
dream reveals hidden truths in the temporal world mirrors the
52
Artistic and mystical trance probably also incorporate aspects of the feeling of
belief that a descent into the mystical reveals hidden truths in the
the sublime, which can be attributed to the presence of a sense of the “here-now”
timeless world. against all space-time, or a point of space in relation to infinity and a moment of
time in relation to eternity (Brown, 2000).
326 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 327

mined for content and at some point, when it is exhausted of its metaphor and fluid imagination — taps early phases in subjectiv-
fertility, the work is complete, or at least should be. The greater the ity that prefigure the objects of ordinary Csness. The series of pre-
scope of the creative Idea, the more it is profound, personal and paratory actions leading to union requires the severance of bonds
universal. The more delimited the Idea, even if strikingly original, to the outside world, monastic existence, isolation and subjective
as in scientific creativity53, the less personal and the closer to the retreat. The mystical ascent to heavenly planes of thought and el-
world of objects. Artistic vision, tied to the material, and replete evated Csness in the exaltation of god-union begins with personal
with potential, insinuates the totality or the contour of a forthcom- needs and self-sacrifice, and follows an ingoing path. The profun-
ing work if not the detail of its parts. The artist apprehends an im- dity of the descent, the self-denial needed for union, the frequent
age of the entire work, but does not drown in its totality. He retains failure at explication, the sustained and energetic passivity, make
sufficient detachment to serially revive, convey and recapture the the experience inherently solipsistic.
intuited unity of the whole.
Every foray into oneness is an inward search54. The god of
Mystical vision actualizes the fullness of its potentiality in a union, the absolute, the real, the Buddha-nature, is not found “out
concrete reality in which the self is immersed. The totality of the there” in the world of nature or god’s creation but in the mind of
category is an all-inclusiveness in which ultimate love and god- the seeker, in a pre-verbal field of inchoate thought and primitive
feeling pervade the subject in an objectless state. The passivity of emotion. William James suggested that the threshold of Csness
immersion and the loss of self are signs of a regression to levels be- might be lowered to admit what is usually pre-Cs. Meister Eckhart
neath word and image, antecedent to the individuation of content (1958ed) described a shift from the temporal order of the world
from the core self. The world dissolves and only pure subjectivity to pure subjective duration. Eckhart in Christian mysticism, and
is left. The lack of content, the unitary or undivided nature of the Coomeraswamy in yoga (1993) described an expansion of the per-
state, the relinquishing of the empirical self, attest to its general- sonal now to the infinite now of god. Nature-mystics contemplate
ized, ineffable and domain-free character. In place of Csness of the Absolute, or ultimate reality of nature, with a focus on a single
god there is objectless awareness suffused with spirit. The depic- object, but even in this method the retreat is from plurality to a
tion of mystical vision as a direction without an object recalls stud- single object, then to its sources in the inner life.
ies by the Wurzburg school of psychology that posited just such
an early phase in the development of a thought (Bewusstheit). The
state also recalls accounts in mystical Judaism of creation, when
a not-yet something that is a mere “not-nothing” takes on a direc-
tion that anticipates the birth of the world. 12.2. Creative and mystical thinking
The principle differences between creative and mystical thinking
The characteristics of mystical states have been recounted in are the depth and, thus, the selectivity of content, and the accen-
endless and fascinating detail by many writers, accounts that, tuation on facets of the mental life as opposed to its whole, i.e. the
like those of creative personalities, usually do not stray far from work of art versus pure experience. Ancillary features of religios-
the stereotype. Yet even with the more conventional mind of the ity or personality motivate the sphere of value, the ambition, the
creative scientist, which differs in that novelty is incremental and goal and single-mindedness of the search, the relaxation and re-
value impersonal, there has been little or no speculation on the ceptivity and, consequently, the depth of self-exploration. Artistic
psychic process underlying creative thinking. For the artist — for
all creative individuals — the descent to Ucs mind — to imagery,
54
For example, a turning point in the life of the mystic, Mme. Guyon, occurred
when a monk told her to “seek God in your own heart and you will find Him
53
See discussion in the Creativity Research Journal 7 (3,4) 1994. there” (Leuba, p.75).
328 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 329

training in composition, literature, dance, etc., leads to skill in creasing definiteness, and thus originality, as the content resolves.
technique, perhaps in theory as well, while religious training leads One sees at first dimly. Then, one becomes blind to the habitual.
to knowledge of scripture and practice. In both there is extreme Finally, eyes refreshed, one sees again as if for the first time.
dedication. For the artist, work is religion, cult; for the mystic, the
longing for perfection is an aesthetic lived in the flesh. Mystical The artist is still bound to the temporal world of objects while
and creative experience depends on access to early cognition in the mystic has left that world for the timeless realm of god or na-
both artistic and religious domains. The truth of art or experience ture. This is a symptom of inwardness as engagement devolves
is an aesthetic of authenticity. The religious individual with skill to antecedent oneness with the other. Oneness is not the com-
in writing (Plotinus, Kierkegaard) or painting (Blake), or the poet ing-together of god and mystic but the reaching-down to the
with mystical sensitivity (Tennyson), uncovers the creative at the foundations of thought before the surfacing of individuality. The I
depths of the mystical, while mystical feeling in an artist, even a and the Thou (Buber, 1958ed) do not embrace each other as in an
scientist (Kepler, Newton), is often ingredient in great discovery. encounter but issue from a common source, like waters flowing
The scientist without a touch of the mystical exchanges wonder from the same spring.
for curiosity, while the mystic without an aesthetic has little but
If we presume a descent in creative and mystical thought
the memory of a waking dream left over from loving union.
through planes of Ucs process, what is important for this idea are:
In sum, mystical experience resembles artistic insight but at a (1) the activity of developing acts, and the passivity of developing
more profound level of the mind, uncoupled from topic or concept, objects; (2) the elaboration of object space out of a personal space
minus the skill needed for articulation. The greater depth of the for- of imagery; (3) the growth of feeling out of core beliefs and values;
mer accounts for the prominence of the core rather than empirical and most critically, (4) the assumption that unrealized or non-ac-
self, the loss of the subject/object boundary (oneness), the intra- tualized phases of the Ucs are not concrete images but categories
personal locus and the greater passivity, absorption and surrender. of thought and perception.
The severity of preparation for mystical union corresponds, in art,
with the dedication to learning and the acquisition of technique.
The preparation is assiduous, the greater when the aim is to be-
come rather than to possess the Idea. The first duty of god’s bride is 12.3. Active and passive
acquiescence. To be worthy is to be selfless. Self-denial is a mode
of active passivity that is the primary condition of submission. In “The road up and the road down are the same”
Buddhism, as in most religions, self-denial is central. Heraclitus
In creative and mystical withdrawal there is passivity to an imag-
In contrast, the artist does not pursue the same path of self-
ined other — muse, spirit or god — who may have authority over
denial. The passive and receptive qualities of inspiration and com-
the self. The feeling of passivity is decisive as to whether agency
position are realized only in the creative state. Mystical union is
is felt as internal, belonging to the self, or external, transferred
not creative; it has no content to divulge other than what it is. The
to the other. The greater the self’s feeling of agency, the less the
totality of union overwhelms all particularities in its subsequent
power attributed to muse, spirit or god. The self must evapo-
revelation. To describe, to discuss, to illustrate is to delimit. The
rate if the mind is to be inundated. Agency and receptiveness
category of mystical experience stands behind a manifold of pos-
are generated within the mental event; they are not applied to
sible concepts, one of which prevails in creative vision. The vision
events from outside. The study of pathological cases affirms that
engages a sphere of content, at first explicit, say a figural, math-
agency depends on and develops with the occurrent state, and
ematic or musical “problem”, but out of receptiveness comes in-
that the object-development is of equal importance to the feeling
330 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 331

of agency and its locus as the action process. One could say the process, and the concentration on an object, are active processes
action discharge gives the feeling that an action is self-initiated55, that become passive in visionary thinking with the appearance of
whereas the object-development gives the knowledge that the ac- images or hallucinations (see below). Receptivity and openness
tion has occurred. There is a need to disambiguate these subtle transform to agency when a mystic receives instructions from an
differences. Perhaps willed movement should be restricted to the angel or hears the voice of god. The volitional quality of the imagi-
feeling of innervation, agency for the sense of free-will, and voli- nary voice is normally a property of the self, i.e. inner speech, and
tion for Csness of action, including choice and decision. In states the relation of self to image or object. Yet, in normal states, there
of palsy, there is still a feeling of effort and will, but this is altered can be a shift in the locus of agency from the self to the image. On
in sensory denervation. Without effort and the aid of vision, one falling asleep, a verbal image occasionally seems to become the
cannot move a limb that is not felt. But action is not necessary for voice of another person. When sensory constraints are relaxed
volition. When action is in abeyance the self still can evoke and or in full dependency on the endogenous, the path outward to
“manipulate” a mental image, contemplate a past event, arouse the world for everyday objects occurs for intrinsic images as well,
an idea or imagine a plan for the future. and like objects, imagined others appear to “contain” their own
impulsivity or volition. When a verbal image objectifies, the voice
The inner bond of the mental event with action and percep- is no longer felt to be in the person’s mind; it seems to come from
tion or with the active and passive attitude changes each moment outside. This is pronounced in schizophrenic command halluci-
with the changing event. Though we sense that we can choose to nations. The phenomenon is not limited to verbal imagery. In a
act or not, a failure of action is not a sign that agency is wanting; phantom limb, the feeling that one controls an amputated limb
agency, willing, volition, are in choosing and implementing, not in may change to a state in which the limb itself feels active. The
the choice that is made. This feeling differs on separate occasions limb seems to “have a mind of its own” independent of the self.
for what appear to be similar acts. One moment I am willfully en- Similar phenomena occur with stimulation of the motor cortex.
gaged in writing, with each stroke an energetic motion. The next In the “alien hand” syndrome, a person may actually be choked
moment, my mind is vacant; there is no impulse or will to write by his own hand.
and the pen rests helpless in my hand. This difference as much a
function of mood as of conceptual urgency, points to the “deep Such phenomena, and a host of others (Brown, 1988), show
structure” of the act. Activity colored by mood can give apathy that the active and the passive are not opposing tendencies but
and akrasia or, conversely, manic self-confidence. The relevance parallel attitudes.56 In man, the feeling of volition depends, mini-
of mood might suggest that active and passive “roles” are addi- mally, on an active feeling in movement that is generated by the
tions to events, not intrinsic to them, but I believe this shows that action discharge. In contrast, the passivity of the object-develop-
moods arise at and condition pre-object phases in the micro-tem- ment is completed when the image objectifies and is no longer
poral process through which events arise. part of the person’s mind. The many forms of imagery, dreams,
memory and thought images, hallucinations and illusions, eidetic
The relation of an image to passive and active undergoes a and after-images, are markers of successive phases in the object-
change in mystical descent. The meditation that initiates the development, and each mode of imagery has a different feeling
of activity or passivity. The proximity of the image to the world
or core self is one factor in volitional feeling. In the final phase of
55
The James-Wundt debate on the feeling of innervation concerned the contri-
bution of action to the distinction of active and passive movement. Without sen-
sory recurrence, i.e. action-perception through collaterals of its discharge, there is 56
Some have argued that the tension between the active and the passive in
not only loss of the feeling of activity but the limb may be felt as not belonging to cognition traces back to the biology of approach and avoidance in unicellular
the individual or organism. A rat will chew its dennervated paw, as a person bites organisms (Schneirla, 1965), which evolves to grasping and withdrawal, extro-
an anaesthetized lip. and introversion, and even aggressive and dependent personality types.
332 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 333

image-development, agency is replaced by passivity. This culmi- tion of self and desire, the purposefulness of animals becomes
nates in the detachment of the image and the feeling of being an the volition of humans. The object of desire that can be imagined
onlooker to the products of one’s own imagination. as an idea for reflection is an image for the self’s enjoyment. We
are spectators for our visual images, including dreams. The active
In the mystic, the complexity of the active and passive ap- quality of inner speech gives volitional feeling to language-based
pears in the mix of pursuit and surrender. The mystic is an active thought (Brown, 2004). The imagery of verbal thought, when bi-
seeker who pursues detachment with vigor and determination. ased to action, gives volitional feeling; when biased to perception,
In the artist, it occurs in the balance of confidence and receptive- it seems to arise spontaneously. Generally, we are passive to what
ness. Mystical union requires resolute commitment and absolute surfaces in Csness even if we feel that our thoughts are purpose-
submission. The union that is actively sought-after is realized in fully generated.
self-abandon. The paradox is that the final passivity necessary for
absorption entails a suspension of the impulse that drove the mys- Eckermann said of Goethe, genius does not struggle to reach
tic to seek union in the first place. Reminiscent of the remark of the heights, genius soars. In ordinary mind as well, thinking does
how much it cost the government of India to keep Gandhi living in not give thought; thought comes. And thought comes best in mo-
poverty, a healthy dose of arrogance is required to surrender the ments of inactivity and quiet repose when the antecedents of acts
self to the Other. The combination of determination with supplica- and objects come to the fore. The passivity in the relation of self
tion, of the quest for perfection with the admission of inadequacy, to thought, or observer to observed, is an active product of the
of detachment from others with the hope of communion, of the process through which objects develop. It is essential for objects
audacity in the search for god-union with the relinquishment to be shared and independent, and for the illusion that the objects
of any vestige of autonomy, is not for the timid or faint-hearted. we perceive are in the world, not in the mind. Agency is partly
Absorption in god begins with self-absorption, requiring a self to a by-product of choice and decision, and partly, a result of mo-
which all worldly relations are subordinate. A strong will is essen- tor discharge. This is essential if the individual is to feel that his
tial to dedicate a life in service, since dedication is a means to an limbs are not prosthetic appendages. Were agency for images like
end — that of union — to which self-denial is preliminary. One passivity for objects, i.e. if actions fully objectified, we would feel
could say with some justification that devotion and humility in the like automata; actions would arise like objects, independent of an
mystic are mere camouflage for so consuming an ambition that actor. Were the passivity of objects to invade the action-formation,
the individual actually believes he or she will achieve a personal we would feel that perceptions were the outcome of mental activ-
audience with god. Hugel (1921) wrote that mystics have a “great ity, i.e. that we think up our perceptions. Such phenomena are
self-engrossment of a downright selfish kind”, in which all things common in psychotic states.
are grouped around a “self-adoring Ego.” Such narcissism, which
is not unknown among the artistic class, is neither unique nor es-
sential to the creative personality.

Many writers have claimed that the brain is designed for action 12.4. Unity and union
and that knowledge is incipient or preparatory action. However, The initial phase in the “ascending series” to god-union described
the inner life is populated mainly by perceptual images. The delay by writers such as St. Theresa, Bishop de Sales and Mme Guyon,
in action that is essential to thought is not filled by more action begins with meditation. Leuba (1925; p 169) notes the similarity
but by visual and verbal imagery. The mental correlates of action to the Buddhist and Islamic traditions. He writes that “the funda-
are largely perceptual (Brown, 1996). Activity arising in the out- mental psychological condition of Union is passivity”, to which
ward flow of action transports the self to a goal. With the evolu- meditation and the ascetic life are subsidiary. Meditation leads to
334 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 335

passivity by “arresting the activity of the mind”. The inward turn elimination of the time order realized in words and objects un-
is a step back from the world, a retreat from acts and objects that covers deeper phases of simultaneity and syncretic meaning, the
relinquishes agency and replaces objects by images. Instead of an “thoughts too deep for tears” and boundless emotions; undivided,
active self in relation to the world, the self is a passive observer inarticulate, generalized, ineffable. The opposition of the self to
of its own bodily and mental content. After meditation comes its images, concepts and feelings dissolves, and with this there is
contemplation; this is not active thought, but attention to one ob- a dissolution of self-consciousness. Bishop Hedly wrote that he
ject as a means of further emptying and so opening the mind for who is conscious while he is praying has not yet arrived at perfect
spontaneous imagery. Passivity is achieved in concentrating the imagery (Butler, 1922).
mind on one object, or repeating a word or phrase, such as a man-
tra. Howley (1920) gave a clear description of the shift in attention In the sphere of emotion, affect that in waking was distributed
from a discursive «wandering» over elements to «a fixation on more or less evenly over all perceptual objects, is now concen-
one element which it draws from the storehouse of memory, and trated into one object of contemplation. When this object is then
concentrates intelligence and will on this one point», so reducing relinquished, affect suffuses inner space and grows more intense
the conscious field to a minimum. The aim of the negative path as individuality recedes to its core, as if one traveled upstream to
of elimination is, as Spinoza put it, «to reach a bare One unen- the source of a great river from one of its many tributaries. The
cumbered by attributes, which are limitations.» In Sufism, where outcome of this descent is surrender in union with god or im-
inwardness and spirituality prevail over the externality of law, the mersion in the absolute of nature. The state is that of a powerful
repetition of a word or phrase from the Qu’ran — sika — leads emotion, usually described as all-encompassing love. The mystic
to a forgetting of self and relations to the world. This can also be is consumed by god, the Other, as lover, great companion or fellow
achieved in repetitive motion, such as whirling. A homogeneous sufferer. According to Poullain (1912), the very center of Christian
state of emptiness ensues as selfless mind is absorbed in a sea of mysticism is the other as an immediate and vivid apprehension
unity. of “divine Presence”. Not to diminish the import of the union or
its significance for the mystic but to align it with other modes of
Accounts of the mystical path emphasize other methods in thought and behavior, one could suppose that mystical ecstasy is
the course of achieving union, many of which have taken on the an experience akin to fully internalized sexual ecstasy that dis-
status of formal doctrine, even if there is considerable variation charges a mode of pre-object mentality prior to the division of self
in the path of each individual. Before the final oneness there are and other.
often visions and hallucinations. This is a kind of twilight Csness
with erosion of autonomy but not to the point where the self is Apart from the sexual histories of the mystics, which have
obliterated. The withdrawal from objects to precursor images cre- been lucidly interpreted by Leuba (1925), and discussed by many
ates a “dreamy” state not unlike that of hypnagogy, epileptic aura writers, including psychoanalysts, the mystical experience can be
or hypnotic trance. The outer world has all but vanished, replaced interpreted in relation to ordinary sexual excitement. Love would
by something resembling a “lucid” dream. The agentive self that then be a derivative of sexual drive, and the extremes of asceti-
initiated the adventure has given way to the passive self of dream cism a form of masochism. Some saints, especially women, report
as an observer of its own imagery. sexual dreams of being kissed and bedded by, or married to, god.
In the passage of consciousness from interest in another person
In contemplation, reason, thought and imagery are replaced to desire for that person, to the coupling with a partner who is still
by ardent feeling, and by the “simple gaze on divine truth” of St. external, the ever-greater proximity and absorption leads to a melt-
Thomas. There is an arrest of inner speech and thought. Ordinarily, ing of the physical boundaries of flesh and the psychic boundar-
objects and words parse meanings and increment time. The ies of feeling. The dissolution of the self and the inter-penetration
336 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 337

with the other accompany a retreat from asymmetric and deliber- forms of mystical union (discussion in Forman, 1998). The reli-
ate limb movements to automatic and symmetrical axial motility. gious and cultural background may determine the conditions that
Focal voluntary actions are replaced by rhythmic impulses. The are pursued for descent, while the part-categories of culture and
transition is from adaptation to the world to the archaic and en- personal interest naturally guide the less profound descent in cre-
dogenous. The confluence of drives that are suppressed, deviant ative insight and the still more superficial objects of science. The
or inner-directed — repressed sexuality, hunger in starvation, fear phases of descent (Fig. 12.1.) occur in all human minds.
in acquiescence, anger in self-directed austerities and mortifica-
tion — coalesce in solitary rapture. The sublimation of the outer-
directed drives, the loss of their objects and the muted expression
of their natural realization result in a wholly subjective discharge.
Mystical union is fully intra-personal. The outer world has disap-
peared. Motility is suppressed. A similar phenomenon occurs in
REM-state dreams, where there is also paralysis. In ecstasy when
visions and revelations occur, the individual is incapable of vol-
untary movement, unable to come out of trance at will (Poullain,
1912).

The allusion to sexuality in union particularly in the religious


mystic, integrates some aspects of the uncanny to what is familiar
and comprehensible. Mystical union is not an other-worldly expe-
rience beyond human understanding. To claim the phenomenon Fig. 12.1. The mystic withdraws to Ucs categories that are the
is god-inspired removes it from philosophical or psychological dis- initial phase in the mental state. In art, there is incomplete with-
course. The parallel trend in the concept of creativity, i.e. that of drawal to the phase of conceptual feeling that partitions the core.
the genius is inspired, implies an influx from outside or a state of Objects that are revived are penetrated with feeling as value. The
supernatural possession that uncouples the creative process from scientist also retraces this process, but lives closer to the object-
what is known of mental experience. Smith (2006 and elsewhere) world. Each mental state is a recurrent transition from core to em-
has described attributes of creativity in relation to experimental pirical self to external world.
studies of personality development, especially the import of pre-
perceptual stages in driving surface cognition, phases of affect
and meaning, and the micro-temporal transition from “depth” to
“surface”. Sexuality plays an important role in the ability to probe 12.5. Theocentric and nature mystics
otherwise hidden or submerged levels. The allusion by students
of mysticism of the importance of sexual feeling is of uncertain The mysticism of god-union is most often described in the Christian
import but it does align the phenomenon with percept-genetic or literature, but accounts resemble those of the Asian mystic who
micro-genetic phases in thought and perception. seeks communion with nature. In the latter, oneness is with the
ultimately real or ground of existence, an absolute that is «super-
Along these lines, to claim that mysticism is a construction of sensual and super-rational». If the One of union is personal it is
social, linguistic and religious traditions does a disservice to the god, if impersonal, the absolute. In the former, god is creator, in
universality of the experience, the commonality of its precursors, the latter the universe is emanation (see Hughes, 1937). For Mercer
the descent into self and the pattern of expression found in all (1913), the term god should be reserved for the phenomenal as-
338 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 339

pect of the absolute. The central idea in nature mysticism is that 12.6. Creativity in art and science
mind and nature are manifestations of the absolute. In both forms
of mysticism, the unio mystica is achieved by a descent through
the personal Ucs as the particulars of Cs experience are abdicated “One-eyed science deficient in its vision of depth”
for a dream of holistic unity. Whitehead
The idea that mystical experience is an extreme of normal cogni-
Mystical thought has a tendency to monism, but it would be tion and an outcome of phyletic trends brings the phenomenon
inaccurate to portray the process as a replication of the same into relation with evolutionary process on the one hand and ar-
“stuff” of matter in increasingly complex systems. All knowledge tistic and scientific creation on the other. Microgenetic theoery
and experience rest on the process through which mental phe- assumes a qualitative change within the mental state in its transi-
nomena are derived, a process that in my view can be traced tion to actuality. For this reason, the differences between ordinary,
back to elementary physical entities. What is continuous is the creative and mystical thinking are as important as the similarities.
expansion, inside-out, of the internal relations, subjective aim and These differences have several explanations: (1) a disparity in seg-
directionality of process within the temporal extensibility of physi- ment or phase, i.e. relative depth of origination; (2) the extent to
cal entities. The pantheist sees the continuum in psychic terms; which concepts are partitioned, i.e. the unity or multiplicity of
the materialist sees it as physical top to bottom. Hughes argues, vision and composition; (3) the prominence or extraction of feel-
citing Plotinus and Augustine, that pantheism is not essential to ing, i.e. intensity, generalization and locality; and (4) the degree of
religious mysticism. objectification, i.e. the phase of concepts, or of objects.
The possibility of love-union with god does not imply that each Mysticism and creativity are grounded in personal feeling. In
of us has godly attributes or is a particular in the mind of god, but the former, feeling is the goal or end to which the state is directed.
that individuality can be immersed in the totality of the divine. The intensity of feeling arises in the proximity to core drives and
The transition from the human psyche and its material basis to a the non-specificity of conceptual primitives, and the temporal
fusion (infusion) with the spirit of god is less a spiritual becoming compression of the manifold of possibility in unrealized poten-
of the person or a recession to a spiritual core than openness to tiality. In the latter, feeling follows the separation of the manifold
god’s love. The notion that we are ideas in god’s mind, or that our into specific occasions that generate a multiplicity of inter-lock-
souls are ingredient in universal spirit, are concepts discussed in ing parts. Science and philosophy are impersonal; they attempt
other formats, but they do not appear to inform the process of to drive feeling out. The certainty of mystical truth and the unique
mystical retreat. This is because the god-union does not uncover vision of the artist depend on their intra-psychic locus. The mystic
an underlying oneness, but achieves unity by allowing god to en- leaves the world the artist returns to. In both, value deposits at
ter one’s being. This contrasts with the nature mystic, for whom a subjective phases in personal experience, or in concepts rather
common process would seem to be necessitated by the continu- than external objects, but the final objects of art and science aris-
um of psychic individuality with the physical absolute. Individual ing out of conceptual feeling are not dead products of thought;
mind is a distal manifestation of the ultimate data of reality. they radiate the intrinsic value that accompanied them into the
Nature and mind may not be composed of the same constituents, world.
but they are emanations of the underlying ground of existence. Of
the various explanations of the continuum, increasing complexity The more personal a belief, the greater is the conviction in its
with emergent features, in spite of its inadequacy, is perhaps the truth, no matter how implausible it may be. Strong and unshake-
one that is most widely accepted. able beliefs are akin to delusions in their resistance to argument
and indifference to verification. Indeed, how could one authen-
340 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 341

ticate a reported union with god or nature? The objects of art There is a transition in every act of cognition from the phase
and science conform to the concepts behind them. To speak of of intuition or the pre-verbal categories that discharge in mystical
deep or shallow concepts is to judge their scope, originality and experience to a conceptual richness of greater specificity, i.e. an
explanatory power. The inwardness of mystical union contrasts artwork or domain of scientific inquiry. This phase leads to the
with the open-ended dialectic of extra-personal science. Most sci- objectified concepts of art, e.g. a poem, painting or performance.
entific “facts” are provisional, and the more impersonal, the more In art, concepts are rendered in a form that can be judged for
provisional, at least in principle. There is no complete objectivity, depth and quality. In science, concepts lead to findings that can
even in the most solid fact; this is evident in the ferocity of sci- be tested and confirmed. Art and science submit their objects for
entific and philosophical debate. Objectivity does not require an extra-personal judgments. The mystic is indifferent to the judg-
external perspective, which can never be fully achieved; rather, ment of others. The artist may act with indifference or disdain and
there is an accentuation of the distal or objectified segment of the reject the opinions of others, but his work will still be judged, while
mental state and a de-emphasis on its subjective portion. The self the scientist’s trade depends on such judgments. The continuity
imaginatively inhabits the objects it perceives, or imagines that it, from the personal to the impersonal reflects the relative depth or
the self, is one of those objects. One has this experience on occa- degree of inwardness that dominates each mental state.
sion in gazing at the body when it seems alien or dissociated, or
just another object in the world. The objectivity of science is less In mysticism, the self uncovers the ground of its existence or
a perspective from outside, than the subtraction of the personal fuses with the Other. The mystic has limited interest in the truths
in observation. The object is no longer the exclusive product of of extra-personal science. Perhaps he believes the scientist is
an individual imagination. For the scientist, shared objects have deluded by appearances that have little relevance to the direct
precedence over individual observers. This is the outcome of an experience of deity or nature. However, a profound truth about
observation of a reliable, eternal world in relation to the fragile, nature must cohere with a truth about the mind; one cannot ig-
perishable self, and translates in epistemic theory to the belief nore the source of one’s objects. One who begins with the objects
that objects are the starting points of concepts. of physics will not reach the mind, But if one starts with mental
phenomena, it may be possible to trace their devolution to basic
For those who believe the path to truth lies outside the mind, entities. If so, a continuous thread runs from mind to physical na-
the intra-personal truths of the mystic are suspect or fraudulent. ture. Nature mystics know this truth, but their insight is without
In contrast, those of the artist are closer to the object world. The content — blind concepts, as Kant put it — leaving nothing to be
ideal is not intra-personal but directed to others. The truth-value decided on. Mystical experience is adrift from the wider commu-
in art is more in the sphere of feeling and symbolism than rea- nity of knowledge. The mystic does not just renounce the world;
son. The artist wishes to transfer to the observer his insights and he is alienated from the illusory objects left behind in his descent.
emotions. Such insights may qualify as truths in that they reveal, In fact, he demolishes those objects without putting forth new
by implementing them, concepts that cannot otherwise be sub- ones to replace them.
mitted to scientific test. Most philosophers would grant that art
reveals truths about the human condition, even if they cannot be In sum, for artist and aesthete, for scientist, philosopher or oth-
formulated as propositions that can be falsified. It was for this rea- ers who work in a creative way, intuition may arise from a concept
son that Goethe titled his autobiography Poetry and Truth. In con- on a universal scale or one of more narrow interest. Concepts of
trast, science puts its questions in the form of propositions that are the widest scope are fundamental categories that spill into in-
true or false. The locus of scientific thought shifts from the mind creasingly more definite spheres of value. The immense joy of
of the individual to a world of communal objects, validation and god-union that is recaptured in descent is an early, unrecognized
consensus. phase in an ordinary act of cognition. This phase partitions to sci-
342 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 343

entific or artistic concepts that still have a high grade of intrinsic ition feels right but cannot be articulated. Ineffability is a psycho-
feeling. Feeling is diminished as it distributes to concepts that logical fact, not a limitation of language. It conveys the experience
point outward to the world. The exocentric locus of scientific con- of potential before it actualizes in words. The lack of words, which
cepts delimits feeling to a concentration on one object or field. is a way of characterizing ineffability, is a failure of the partition
This is the phase of contemplation in the mystic. In the scientist, it of the immediacy of wholeness, which is experienced without
can become a center of inestimable value. The mystic abandons being apportioned, without being incremented into moments by
objects for emptiness; the scientist retains them and fills them thoughts, acts and objects.
with value. The dedicated scientist who spends a lifetime studying
a liver cell, a ganglion in the brain, a physical particle or a piece of William James understood the intensity of conceptual feeling
viral nucleic acid, has enlarged that concept to a universe of value underlying rational thought when he wrote that philosophy is
that claims a devotion that, as in mysticism, is comparable to the more a matter of passionate vision than logic, the logic coming
feeling of love. afterwards to justify the vision. First we have the idea and then we
look for support in the authority of research, tradition and opin-
For the nature mystic, the absolute has certain of the non-mor- ion. The inward descent of the mystic is replicated partially by the
al, impersonal and ideal qualities of the philosopher’s god, such artist. But unlike the former, the artist excavates concepts that, for
as timelessness, permanence and indivisibility. Process thought the mystic, are mere way-stations in a deeper pursuit. The phase
is inconsistent with permanence and wavers on the existence of of conceptual feeling that is the starting point of art-creation for
timeless objects. For this reason, more powerful arguments are the mystic is still too much part of the world. In Buddhism, the
needed to support the belief in a rock-bottom ground of substan- Arhat seeks to rid himself of feeling, e.g. desire. In the final stages
tial nature. In theocentric and nature mysticism, objects vanish in of enlightenment, he must eliminate concepts. This amounts to
a mist of ultimacy. Scientific knowledge retains those objects that an elimination of mind, for so long as mind exists, a state of non-
mysticism discards. The generative concepts behind those ob- conceptuality would seem to be impossible. The state of “pure”
jects, which are the primary instruments in the origins of theory, or objectless Csness is not a mode of awareness, as in animal
are reclaimed when feeling is eliminated in the quest for inter-per- mind, where external objects are conserved, but an immersion,
sonal assent. The elimination of emotion from scientific research or feeling of oneness, in the categorical prime that deposits the
is presumed to result in affect-free concepts. However, feeling is as core self.
fundamental to organic systems as energy is to matter, so much
so that a metaphysics of feeling may well be prior to one of energy The outward progression in art divides a unity of conceptual-
in physical matter. Elsewhere (Brown, 2005) I have speculated that feeling into constructs with little feeling-tone, or feelings that seem
feeling arises in the becoming (change) or temporal extensibility non-conceptual. Put differently, conceptual feeling can go in the
that generates an object or concept, while being is the duration or direction of feeling, in which the conceptual aspect is diminished,
category created by the becoming. or in the direction of concepts, in which feeling is subdued. This
gives the false impression of an opposition of concept and feeling,
Art, like mystical experience, achieves truth in perceptual im- or historically, of reason and appetite. But intense feeling still real-
mediacy. In creative thought, study and deliberation precede in- izes a category (fear, love and so on), while abstract concepts retain
sight. There is a period of gestation, as conception gradually devel- an affective tone in their value to the individual. It is the feeling or
ops, followed by the labor of execution and revision. The aesthete value in the concept that selects it for analysis. The greater the
studies an artwork for a while before understanding catches up partition, the more object-centered or external the concept, the
with “gut reaction”. As in mystical knowledge, we apprehend that closer the creative act is to science than to art, which even when it
a work of art is profound, but we cannot always say why. The intu-
344 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience 345

is displaced to a world of objects remains, in its conceptual integ- psychology. For Miller (1996) scientific theories begin with meta-
rity, very much a subjective experience. phoric constructs. These constructs result in literal descriptions
that approximate concepts of physical reality. He writes, “all our
To put the discussion in a more fully microgenetic context, the utterances about the world are metaphorical”. Science is a sub-set
drives, the base categories and the Ucs or core self are ingredient of such occurrences. One phenomenon is described in terms of
in a plane of cognition that discharges internally in mystical states. another or a surrogate is employed to achieve insight into novel
This phase gives rise to the empirical or Cs self and its conceptual fact. Koestler (1964) described creativity as a sudden convergence
feelings. The partition evokes a subjective aim that will become of two strands of thought that result in a new way of thinking. This
the intentional agent of ideas, acts and objects. At an early, intra- idea has been further developed by Rothenberg (1996). The con-
personal phase of this partition, concepts of particular value arise vergence of different lines of thought is another way of describing
out of core beliefs, ingrained skills and experiential memories, e.g. metaphor as a synthesis of contrasts, or the generation of novelty
mathematical, musical or artistic. These concepts are penetrated from discord. While Rothenberg dismisses the importance of re-
by intense feeling. The intensity can be described as a flood of gression, the ability to tap preliminary or Ucs phases of pre-logical
emotion or gasp of amazement that saturates a still inchoate con- whole-part relations, such as metaphor, is central in the creative
cept. The intuition is gradually worked out as the concept devel- act.
ops into objects (parts). The whole of the insight gives rise to the
particulars that exemplify it. The feeling-tone that was intense in What distinguishes creative from ordinary thinking is richness
the original concept tends to dissipate as it distributes into ideas of metaphoric thinking and greater access to those phases in mind
in the mind or objects in the world. where metaphor is active, as well as the ability to develop meta-
phors of striking originality. From a psychological standpoint, what
When the individual is centered at a distal or objective phase is important about metaphor and related phenomena, such as me-
in the implementation of the concept, say in fine-tuning a compo- tonymy and synecdoche, is that they are instances of whole-part
sition or revising a manuscript, the creative power of the insight, relations through which topics overlap due to shared predicates,
though active, is weakened in the partiality of its material. We now when the part implies the whole, or when certain attributes of an
speak of skill or technique, the 99% perspiration of Edison’s fa- object serve to propagate novel constructs. An example in poetry
mous remark. Conrad wrote in a touching way of the uncertainty might be a “dark” mood that becomes “night falling”. Einstein’s fly
and struggle in the choice of every word. Original ideas develop on a train is an example in scientific discourse. Religion is replete
in the context of experience and interest when the conceptual with metaphors and symbols. With respect to religious mysticism,
mind resists objectification. Whether an idea is interesting, novel an example is god as father, lover or bridegroom. If metaphor is
or deeply original, whether it is revived in art or science, even if ubiquitous in language, it is because whole-part relations are fun-
it remains pre-conscious in a psychotic personality, concepts of damental in mind and nature. The natural tendency of thought is
innovation and power can only arise at a phase prior to objec- to analysis, or the derivation of parts from antecedent wholes. The
tification. This is because concepts are not assembled from Cs creative step reverses this trend by a move inward to the wholes.
elements but precede those elements and give rise to them in a The focus is now on the concept, context or background behind
sequence of recurrences. the particulars. This opens the way to a novelty generated by the
multiple relations of unrealized parts. Put differently, the incom-
One characteristic of creative thought is the exploitation of
plete analysis permits the arousal of unexpected parts that are
early phases in perceptual imagery. Much has been written of the
tacitly subsumed within wholes that have not yet individuated.
Ucs sources of creativity, but few “mechanisms” have been pro-
posed. Perhaps the most important of these is metaphor, which
has been widely discussed in cognitive science as well as neuro-
References

Ajuriaguerra, J.de, Strejilevitch, M. and Tissot, R. (1963) “À propos de


quelques conduites devant le mirroir de sujets atteints de syndromes
démentiels du grand âge”. Neuropsychologia. 1:59-73.
Arkin, A. and Brown, J.W. (1971) “Aphasic speech, schizophrenic speech,
sleep speech and sleeptalking”. Association for the Psychophysiological
Study of Sleep, Bruges.
Arkin, A., & Brown, J. W. (1971). “Resemblances between NREM
associated sleep speech, drowsy speech, and aphasic and schizophrenic
speech”. Association for the Psychophysiological Study of Sleep, 253, First
International Congress, Bruges, Belgium June 19–23.
Baars, B. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Baars, B., Ramsey, T. and Laureys, S. (2003) “Brain, conscious
experience and the observing self”. Trends in Neuroscience 28:671-675.
Baddeley, A. (1986). Working memory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bender, M. & Krieger, H. (1951). “Visual Function in Perimetrically Blind
Fields”. Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 55, 72-99.
Bennett, C. (1923) A Philosophical Study of Mysticism: An Essay. Yale
University Press, New York.
Bentaleb, L., Beauregard, M., Liddle, P., & Stip, E. (2003). “Cerebral
activity association with auditory verbal hallucinations: A functional
magnetic resonance imaging case study”. Journal of Psychiatry and
Neuroscience, 28, 217–218.
Bergson, H. (1896/1959) Matter and Memory (English translation),
Doubleday, New York.
Bergson, H. (1923) Durée et simultaneité 2nd. Ed., Félix Alcan, Paris.
Bergson, H. (1944ed) Creative Evolution. English translation by Arthur
Mitchell, Modern Student Library, New York.
Bergson, H. (1988) Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience.
Felix Alcan, Paris.
Berkeley, G. (1784/1963) A New Theory of Vision. Dent, London.
Betlheim, S. and Hartmann, H. (1951) “On parapraxes in the Korsakow
psychosis”. In: D. Rapaport (Ed) Organization and Pathology of Thought.
Columbia University Press, New York, 288-310.
348 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations
References
of Conscious Experience 349

Bohm, (1980) Wholeness and the Implicate Order. Routledge and Kegan Freud’s Project for a Scientific Psychology. Annals of the N.Y. Acad, Sci.
Paul, London 843:91-106.
Bohm, D. and Hiley, B. (1993) The Undivided Universe. Routledge, Brown, J. W. (1999). “Neuropsychology of the self-concept”. Journal of
London. Nervous and Mental Disease, 187,131-141.
Borges, J. (1960/1970) “Epilogue”, p. 93, Dreamtigers, Dutton, NY. Brown, J.W. (1999a) “Microgenesis and Buddhism: the concept of
Bouveresse, J. (1995) Wittgenstein Reads Freud: The Myth of the momentariness”, Philosophy East and West. 49:261-277.
Unconscious. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Brown, J. W. (2000) Mind and Nature: Essays on Time and Subjectivity.
Brentano, F. (1874/1973) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Whurr, London.
Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. Brown, J. W. (2001) “Microgenetic theory: reflections and prospects”,
Brown, J.W. (1990) “Psychology of time awareness”. Brain and Language, Neuropsychoanalysis, 3: 61-74.
14:144-164. Brown, J. W. (2003) “Value in mind and nature”. In: F. Riffert and M.
Brown, J. W. (1972) Aphasia, Apraxia and Agnosia. Thomas, Springfield. Weber (Eds) Searching for New Contrasts. Peter Lang, Frankfurt.

Brown, J. W. (1975). “The problem of repetition”. Cortex, 11, 37–52. Brown, J.W. (2003a) review of: Changeux, J.-P. and Ricoeur, P., What
makes us think? Princeton.
Brown, J. W. (1977). Mind, Brain and Consciousness. New York: Academic
Press. Brown, J. W. (2004). “A Microgenetic Approach to Time and Memory in
Neuropsychology”. Acta Neuropsychologica, 2(1), 1-12.
Brown, J.W. (1978) “Lateralization: a brain model”. Brain and Language,
5:258-261. Brown, J. W. (2004a). “The Illusory and the Real”, Mind and Matter, 2,
37-60.
Brown, J. W. (1982). “Hierarchy and evolution in neurolinguistics”. In
M. Arbib, D. Caplan, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Neural models of language Brown, J.W. (2004b) “Word concept, verbal hallucination and inner
processes. New York: Academic Press. speech in neuropsychology”. Acta Neuropsychologica 2:237-251.

Brown, J. W. (1983). “Microstructure of perception”. Cognition and Brain Brown, J.W. (2005) Process and the Authentic Life: Toward a Psychology
Theory, 6, 145–184. of Value. Ontos-Verlag, Heusenstamm.

Brown, J. W. (1986). “Cingulate Gyrus and Supplementary Motor Brown, J. W. (2005a). “Genetic Psychology and Process Philosophy”.
Correlates of Vocalization in Man”. In J. Newman (Ed.): The Physiological Process Studies, 34, 33-44.
Control of Mammalian Vocalization. Plenum, New York, 227-244. Brown, J.W. (2008a) “Consciousness: Some Microgenetic Principles”.
Brown, J.W. (1988) Life of the Mind. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Erlbaum. p. 239-268, In : Riffert, F. and Sander, H.-J. (Eds) Researching with
Whitehead: System and Adventure. Alber Verlag, Munich.
Brown, J. W. (1991) Self and Process. Springer-Verlag, New York.
Reprinted as The Self-Embodying Mind, Station Hill Press, New York, Brown, J.W. (2008b) “The Inward Path: Mysticism and Creativity”.
2002. Creativity Research Journal: 20:1-11.

Brown, J.W. (1994) “Morphogenesis and mental process”. Development Brown, J. and Jaffe, J. (1975) “Hypothesis on cerebral dominance”.
and psycho-pathology 6:551-563. Neuropsychologia 13:107-110.

Brown, J.W. (1996) Time, Will and Mental Process. Plenum, New York. Brown, J. W., Leader, B., & Blum, C. (1983). “Hemiplegic writing in severe
aphasia”. Brain and Language, 19, 204–215.
Brown, J. W. (1997) “Process and creation”. In: A. Andersson and N-E.
Sahlin (Eds) The Complexity of Creativity, Kluwer, Dordrecht. Brown, J.W. and Pachalska, M. (2003) “The nature of the symptom and
its relevance for neuropsychology”. Acta Neuropsychologica 1:1-11.
Brown, J.W. (1998) “Foundations of cognitive metaphysics”. Process
Studies 27:79-92. Brown, J.W. and Stremler, E. (2008) review of: Biology of Freedom:
Neural Plasticity, Experience, and the Unconscious, by Ansermet, F. and
Brown, J. W. (1998a) “Psychoanalysis and process theory”. In: R. Bilder Magistretti, P. (2007) Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease.
and F. LeFever (Eds) Neuroscience of the Mind on the Centennial of
350 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations
References
of Conscious Experience 351

Brown, R., & McNeill, D. (1966). “The ‘‘tip of the tongue’’ phenomenon”. Deacon, T.W. (1992). “Cortical connections of the inferior arcuate sulcus
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 5, 325–337. cortex in the macaque brain”. Brain Research, 573(1): 8-26.
Bruce, D. (1994) “Lashley and the problem of serial order”. American Dewey, J. (1925) Experience and Nature. Open Court, Chicago, p. 262.
Psychologist, 49 :93-103. Domarus, E. von (1944) “The specific laws of logic in schizophrenia. In: J.
Buber, M. (1958ed) I and Thou, Scribner’s and Sons, New York. Kasanin” (Ed) Language and Thought in Schizophrenia: Collected Papers,
Burckhardt, G. (1891). “Uber Rindenexcisionen als Beitrag zur p. 104-114, University of California Press, Berkeley.
operativen Therapie der Psychosen”. Allgemeine Psychiatrie, 57, Ebbeson, S. (1984) “Evolution and ontogeny of neural circuits”.
463–548. Behavioral Brain Sciences 7:321-366.
Butler, Dom (1922/1966ed) Western Mysticism. Harpers, New York. Eccles, J. (1970) Facing Reality.
Cajal, R. (1954) “Neuron Theory or Reticular Theory”. Consejo Superior Eckhart, M. (1958ed) Treatises and Sermons of Meister Eckhart. J. Clark
de Investigaciones Cientificas, Madrid and J. Skinner (Eds) Harper and Brothers, New York.
Cambridge Companion to William James. Cambridge University Press. Edelman, G. (1987) Neural Darwinism, Basic Books, New York.
Capek, M. (1976) The Concepts of Space and Time. Reidel, Dordrecht. Eggert, G. (1977). Wernicke’s works on aphasia. The Hague: Mouton.
Caramazza, A. and Zurif, E. (1978) (Eds) Language Acquisition and Ellis, R. (1995) Questioning Consciousness. John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Language Breakdown. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore. Ey, H. (1973) Les Hallucinations, Mason et Cie, Paris.
Changeux J-P. (1985) Neuronal Man. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Farrrell, B. (1964) “The criteria for a psychoanalytic interpretation. In:
Chisholm, R. (1952) “Intentionality and the theory of signs”. Gustafson”, D. (Ed) Essays in Philosophical Psychology. Macmillan,
Philosophical Studies, III, 4:56-63. London.
Clarke, D. (2004) Panpsychism. SUNY Press, Albany. Flavell, J., Green, F., Flavell, E., & Grossman, J. (1997). “The development
Cobb, J. & Sherburne, D. (1973). “Regional Inclusion and Psychological of children’s knowledge about inner speech”. Child Development, 68,
Physiology”. Process Studies, 3 (1), 27-40. 39–47.

Cobb, J. (2008) Whitehead Word Book. P&F Press. Fodor, J. (1981) Representations. MIT Press, Cambridge.

Coghill, G. (1964) Anatomy and the Problem of Behavior. New York: Forman, R. (1998, Ed) Innate Capacity. Oxford University Press, New
Hafner. York.

Collingwood, R. (1924). Speculum Mentis. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Foster, J. (1994) “In defense of phenomenalistic idealism”. Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research. 54:509-529.
Collingwood, R. (1940) An Essay on Metaphysics. Oxford, Clarendon
Press. Franklin, G., Brown, J.W. and Freedman, M. (1982) “Capgras syndrome a
deux”. Lancet 2:222.
Coomeraswandy, A. (1993) Time and Eternity. Munshiram Manoharlal,
New Delhi. Freud, S. (1957). Papers on Metapsychology. Standard Edition XIV.
London: Hogarth Press.
Critchley, M. (1955). “Verbal symbols in thought”. Journal of Neurological
Science, 1, 274–290. Gardner, H. (1993) Creating Minds. Basic Books, New York.

Davidson, D. (1980) Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University Gazzaniga, M. (2005) The Ethical Brain. Dana Press, New York, p. 136.
Press. Gill, M. (Ed.1967) The Collected Papers of David Rapaport. Basic Books,
De Bleser, R., & Marshall, J. (2005). “Egon Weigl and the concept of inner New York.
speech”. Cortex, 41, 249–257. Goldstein, K. (1948) Language and Language Disturbances. Grune &
De Morsier, G. (1938) “Les hallucinations”. Rev. Oto-Neuro-Ophtalmol. Stratton, New York.
16:244-352.
352 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations
References
of Conscious Experience 353

Gould S. (1982) Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Howley, J. (1920) Psychology and Mystical Experience. Kegan Paul,
Harvard University Press. London.
Griffen, D. (Ed.,1989) Archetypal Process. Northwestern University Press, Hugel, F. von (1921) Essays and Addresses on the Philosophy of Religion.
Evanston, p. 21. Dent & Sons, London.
Grober, E., Kellar, L., Perecman, E. and Brown, J.W. (1980) “Lexical Hughes, T. (1937) The Philosophical Basis of Mysticism. T & T Clark,
knowledge in anterior and posterior aphasics”. Brain and Language Edinburgh.
10:313-330. Husserl, E. (1905/1964) The Phenomenology of Internal Time-
Grunbaum, E. (1984) The Foundations of Psychoanalysis. University of Consciousness, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
California Press, Berkeley. Inouye, T., & Shimizu, A. (1970). “The electromyographic study of verbal
Guyau, J.-M. (1988ed) Guyau and the Idea of Time. English translation by hallucination”. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 151, 415–422.
J. Michon. Amsterdam, North Holland. Ishibashi, T., Hori, H., Endo, K., & Sato, T. (1964). “Hallucinations
Hartmann, E. von (1868/1931) Philosophy of the Unconscious, Vol 1-3. produced by electrical stimulation of the temporal lobes in
London, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co. schizophrenic patients”. Tohuko Journal of Experimental Medicine, 82,
Hawkins, D. (1954) Being and Becoming: An Essay Towards a Critical 124–139.
Metaphysic. Sheed and Ward, London. Jakobson, R. (1968) Child language, aphasia and phonological universals.
Hecaen, H., & Angelergues, R. (1965). Pathologie du langage. Paris: Mouton, The Hague.
Larousse. James (1912) Essays in Radical Empiricism, Longmans, Green & Co., New
Hecaen, H., & Ropaert, R. (1959). “Hallucinations auditives au cours York. P. 57-58. in Sprigge, p. 138.
de syndromes neurologiques”. Annales Medico-Psychologiques, 117, James, W. (1890) Principles of Psychology. Henry Holt & Co., New York.
257–306. Jones, E. (1949) On the Nightmare. Hogarth Press, London.
Henderson, V. (1992). “Early concepts of conduction aphasia”. In S. Jung (1961) Memories, Dreams, Reflections. Random House, New York.
Kohn (Ed.), Conduction aphasia. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates Inc. Jung, C. (1928). Contributions to Analytic Psychology. New York:
Harcourt, Brace & Co.
Hobson, A. (1988) The Dreaming Brain. Basic Books, New York
Kant, I. (2008ed) Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, section 5.
Hoff, H. and Pötzl, O. (1936/1988) “Anatomical findings in a case of time Louden, R. and Kuehn, M. (Eds) Cambridge University Press.
acceleration”. In: Brown, J.W. (Ed) Agnosia and Apraxia: Selected Papers
of Liepmann, Lange, and Pötzl. Engl. Translation, p. 231-250, Erlbaum, Katz, D. (1935) The World of Color. Kegan Paul, London.
New Jersey. Kinsbourne M. (2000) “Consciousness in action: antecedents and
Hoff, H., & Silberman, M. (1933). “Anderungen der akustischen origins”. Mind and Language, 15, 545-555.
Wahrnehmingswelt bein Temporallappenlasionen”. Zeitschifft gesamte Kinsbourne, M. (2000). “Inner speech and the inner life”. Brain and
Neurologie und Psychiatrie, 144, 657–664. Language, 71, 120–123.
Hoffman R. (1987) “Computer simulations of neural information Klüver, H. (1933). “The eidetic type”. Association for Research in Nervous
processing and the schizophrenia-mania dichotomy”. Archives of and Mental Disease, 14, 150–168.
General Psychiatry, 44, 178-188. Koestler, A. (1964) The Act of Creation, Macmillan, New York.
Horowitz, M. and Adams, J. (1970) “Hallucinations on brain stimulation”. Köhler, W. (1923) “Zur Theorie des Sukzesivvergleiches und der
In: W. Kemp (Ed) Origin and mechanism of hallucination. Plenum, New Zeitfehler”. Psychol. Forschung 4:115-175.
York.
Kotchouboy, B. (2005) “Apallic syndrome is not apallic: is vegetative
Houghton, G. and Hartley, T. (1995) “Parallel models of serial behavior: state vegetative?” Neuropsychological Rehabilitation. 15:333-356.
Lashley revisited”. Psyche 2 (25).
354 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations
References
of Conscious Experience 355

Kriegel, U. (2003) “Is intentionality dependent upon consciousness?” MacIntyre, A. (1958) The Unconscious. Routledge and Kegan Paul,
Philosophical Studies 116:271-307. London.
Lagache, D. (1934). Les hallucinations verbales et la parole. Paris: Felix Malcolm, N. (1959) Dreaming. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
Alcan. Marcel, A. (1983) “Conscious and unconscious perception”, Cognitive
Lange, J. (1936) Agnosien und Apraxien. Handb. der Neurol. Bumke, O Psychology, 15:197-237.
and Foerster, O. (Eds) Springer, Berlin. McAlister, L. (1982) The Development of Franz Brentano’s Ethics, Rodopi,
Lashley, K. (1951) “The problem of serial order in behavior”. L. Jeffress Amsterdam.
(Ed) Hixon Symposium, Cerebral Mechanisms in Behavior. New York, McCulloch, W. (1965) Embodiments of Mind. MIT Press, Cambridge.
Wiley.
McGuire, P., Silbersweig, D., & Frith, C. (1996). “Functional anatomy of
Lecours, A. (1975) “Myelinogenetic correlates of the development of verbal self-monitoring”. Brain, 119, 907–917.
speech and language”. In: E. Lenneberg (Ed) Foundations of Language
Development. 1:121, Academic Press, New York. McNeilage, P., Studdert-Kennedy, M. and Lindblom, B. (1987) “Primate
handedness reconsidered”. Behavioral Brain Sciences 10: 247-303.
Leuba, J. (1925) The Psychology of Religious Mysticism. Kegan Paul,
London. McTaggart, J. (1916) Studies in Hegelian Cosmology. Cambridge
University Press.
Levine, D., Calvanio, R., & Popovics, A. (1982). “Language in the absence
of inner speech”. Neuropsychologia, 20, 391–409. McTaggart, J. (1927) The Nature of Existence. Cambridge University Press.

Lévi-Strauss, C. (1962/1966) The Savage Mind. University of Chicago McTaggart, J. M. (1934/1968). Philosophical Studies. New York: Books for
Press, Chicago. Libraries Press.

Levitan, D, (2006) This is your Brain on Music. Penguin, New York. Mehta, V. (1963) The Fly and the Fly Bottle, Weidenfield and Nicholson,
London.
Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1935/1983) Primitive Mentality. University of Queensland
Press, St. Lucia. Mercer, J. (1913) Nature Mysticism. George Allen, London.

Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1949/1975) The Notebooks on Primitive Mentality. Miller, A. (1996) “Metaphors in creative scientific thought”. Creativity
Blackwell, Oxford. Research Journal. 9:113-130.

Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1985/1926). How Natives Think. Princeton University Mills, J. (2002) The Unconscious Abyss, SUNY Press, Albany.
Press. Morel, F. (1936) “Des bruits d’oreille, des bourdonnements, des
Lewin, K. (1948) Resolving Social Conflicts. Harper & Brothers, New York. hallucinations auditives elementaires, communes et verbales”.
Encéphale 31: 81-95
Lhermitte, J. (1951) Les Hallucinations. Doin & Cie, Paris.
Munsterberg, H., Ribot, T., Janet, P., Jastrow, J., Hart, B. and Prince, M.
Libet, B., (1999) In: Libet, B., Freeman, A. and Sutherland, K. Eds (1999) (1910) Subconscious Phenomena. Gorham Press, Boston.
The Volitional Brain. Towards a Neuroscience of Free Will. Exeter, UK:
Imprint Academic. Pachalska M., Brown, J.W. and, Bruce Duncan MacQueen (2009)
“Microgenetic theory of consciousness.” In H. Pashler et al (Eds)
Lowes, F. (1927) The Road to Xanadu: A Study in the Ways of the Encyclopedia of the Mind.
Imagination. Houghton Mifflin, New York.
Pachalska M., MacQueen B.D. (2010) “The Microgenetic Revolution
Luria, A. R. (1961). The role of speech in the regulation of normal and in Contemporary Neuropsychology and Neurolinguistics” In Weber
abnormal behavior. New York: Liveright. M., Weekes A. (eds.), Whiteheadian Approaches to Consciousness in
Luria, A.R. (1966) Higher Cortical Functions in Man. Basic Books, New Psychology, Neuropsychiatry and Philosophy of Mind, New York: SUNY
York. Press, 164-185.
Luria, A.R. (1972) The Man with a Shattered World. Basic Books, New
York
356 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations
References
of Conscious Experience 357

Pachalska, M. and Weber, M. (2008) Neuropsychology and Philosophy Rosenthal, D. (1993) “Thinking that one thinks”. In: M. Davies and G.
of Mind in Process : Essays in Honor of Jason W. Brown. Ontos Verlag, Humphrey (Eds) Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays.
Frankfurt. Basil Blackwell.
Perry, R. B. (1926) General Theory of Value. Longmans, Green. New York. Ross, P. (1983). “Phonological processing during silent reading in
Piaget, J. (1955) The Language and Thought of the Child. World aphasic patients”. Brain and Language, 19, 191–203.
Publishing, Cleveland. Rothenberg, A. (1996) “The Janusian process in scientific creativity”.
Piaget, J. (1969) The Mechanisms of Perception. Routledge and Kegan Creativity Research Journal 9:207-231.
Paul, London. Russell, B. (1921) The Analysis of Mind. George Allen & Unwin, London.
Pick, A. (1913) Die agrammatischen Sprachstörungen, Berlin. Santayana, G. (1923) Skepticism and Animal Faith. Scribner’s, New York.
Pick, A. (1931/1973) Aphasia. Engl. Transl edited by J.W. Brown, Thomas, Schelling, (1800/1978) System of Transcendental Idealism. Translated by
Springfield. P. Heath, University of Virginia Press, Charlottesville.
Pols, E. (1993) “The metaphor for a foundation for knowledge”. In: Schiffman, H. (1976) Sensation and Perception. Wiley & Sons, New York.
Bogaard, P. and Treash, G. (Eds) Metaphor as Foundation. SUNY Press, Schilder, P. (1951) “On the development of thoughts”. In: D. Rapaport
Albany. P. 200-223. (Ed) Organization and Pathology of Thought. Columbia University Press,
Pöppel, E. (1988) “Time perception”. In: Encyclopedia of Neuroscience, New York.
vol. 2, Birkhauser, Boston. Schilder, P. (1936) “Psychopathology of time”. Journal of Nervous and
Pötzl, O., Allers, R. and Teler, J. (1960) “Preconscious Stimulation in Mental Disease. 83: 530-546.
Dreams, Associations, and Images”. C. Fisher (Ed) Psychological Issues, Schilder, P. (1950) The Image and Appearance of the Human Body.
II (3) #7, International Universities Press, New York. International Universities Press, New York.
Poullain, S. (1912) The Graces of Interior Prayer. Schneirla, T. (1965) “Aspects of stimulation and organization in
Putnam, R. (1997) The Cambridge Companion to William James. approach/withdrawal processes underlying vertebrate behavioral
Cambridge University Press. development”. In: D. Lehrman et al (Eds) Advances in the Study of
Pribram, K. (1991). Brain and Perception: Holonomy and Structure in Behavior. Academic Press, New York.
Figural Processing. New Jersey: Erlbaum. Searle, J. (1980) “Minds, brains and programs”. Behavioral and Brain
Rakic P. (1992) Developmental origin of cortical diversity. Schmitt lecture. Sciences 3:417-424.
New York: Rockefeller University. Searle, J. (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Rapaport, D. (1951, ed) Organization and Pathology of Thought. Searle, J. (1991) The Rediscovery of the Mind. Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
Columbia University Press, New York. Semmes J. (1968) “Hemispheric specialization: a possible clue to
Rayner, E. (1995) Unconscious Logic: An Introduction to Matte Blanco’s mechanism”. Neuropsychologia, 6, 11-26.
Bi-Logic and its Uses. Brunner-Routledge, Hove. Serres, (1860) cited in Gould, S. (1977) Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Belknap
Rees, M. (2000) Just Six Numbers. Basic Books, New York. Press, Harvard University.
Rescher, N. (2006) “Causal necessitation and free will”. Process Studies Shergill, S., Bullmore, E., Brammer, M., Williams, S., Murray, R., &
35:193-206. McGuire, P. (2001). “A functional study of auditory verbal imagery”.
Revonsuo, A. (2005). In: Feinberg, T. and Keenan, J. (Editors) The Lost Psychological Medicine, 31, 241–25.
Self, Oxford (see review in: Brown, J. W. (2005) Journal of Nervous and Smith, G. (2001) The Process Approach to Personality, Plenum Press,
Mental Disease). New York.
Richards, W. (1973) “Time reproductions by H.M”. Acta Psychologica. Smith, G. (2006) The creative personality: in search of a theory.
37:279-282.
358 Jason W. Brown Neuropsychological Foundations
References
of Conscious Experience 359

Smith, G., Johnson, G. and Almgren, P-E. (1989) “MCT - The Meta- Werner, H. (1957) “The concept of development from a comparative
Contrast Technique”. PsykologiForlaget AB, Stockholm. and organismic point of view”. In: Harris, D. (Ed) The Concept of
Sprigge, T. (1974) Santayana: An Examination of his Philosophy. Development. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Wernicke, C. (1874) Die aphasische Symptomenkomplex. Cohn &
Sprigge, T. (1983). The Vindication of Absolute Idealism. Edinburgh: Weigart, Breslau.
Edinburgh University Press. Whitehead, A. (1978ed) Process and Reality. Edited by D.R. Griffin and
Sprigge, T. (1997) “James, aboutness and his British critics”. In : R. D.W. Sherburne. Free Press.
Putnam (Ed) The Cambridge Companion to William James, Cambridge Whitehead, A. N. (1920) The Concept of Nature. Cambridge University
University Press. 125-144. Press.
Stace, W. (1961) Mysticism and Philosophy. Macmillan, London. Whitehead, A. N. (1933) Adventure of Ideas. Cambridge University Press,
Stcherbatsky, T. (1930/1992). Buddhist Logic, Vol. 1, Motilal Banarsidass, p. 343.
Delhi Whitrow, G. (1972). What is Time? London: Thames and Hudson.
Teuber, H.-L. (1956) “Perception”. In: J. Field (Ed) Handbook of Whurr, R., & Lorch, M. (1991). “The rehabilitation of writing after stroke”.
Physiology, Section I, Neurophysiology (Vol. III) American Physiological Aphasiology, 5, 411–418.
Society, Washington, D.C. Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations.
Tye, M. (2000) Consciousness, Color and Content. MIT Press, Cambridge. Wittgenstein, L. (1969ed) On Certainty, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
Vaihinger, H. (1924/1965) The Philosophy of “As-If”. English translation
by C. K. Ogden. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
Verstichel, P., Bourak, C., Font, V., & Crochet, G. (1997). “Langage
intérieur après lésion cérébrale gauche”. Revue de Neuropsychologie, 7,
281–311.
Vogely, K., & Fink, G. (2003). “Neural correlates of the first-person
perspective”. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7, 38–42.
Vygotsky, L. (1962). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wall P. (1988) “Recruitment of ineffective synapses after injury”. In: S.
Waxman (ed.) Functional recovery in Neurological Disease. New York:
Raven Press.
Wallack, F. (1980) The Epochal Nature of Process in Whitehead’s
Metaphysics. SUNY, Albany.
Ward, J. (1933) Psychological Principles. Cambridge University Press,
p. 76.
Weigl, E. (1964). “The experimental deblocking of aphasic verbal
deficits: A method of investigation of processes of cerebral dynamics”.
Voprosy Psikhologii, 149–159.
Weiszaecker, V. von (1939.1958) Le cycle de la structure. French
translation of Der Gestaltkreis, Desclée De Brouwer, Bruges. Original
publisher, Thieme, Stuttgart.
Werner, H. (1945) Comparative Psychology of Mental Development. Follet,
Chicago.
Also published by
les Éditions Chromatika

Alfred North Whitehead, Les Principes de la connaissance naturelle


[1919/1925]. Traduction de Henri Vaillant, relue par Sylviane Schwer,
2007. (978-2-930517-00-1 ; 296 p. ; 30 €)

Philippe Devaux, La Cosmologie de Whitehead. Tome I, L’Épistémologie


whiteheadienne, Édité par Thibaut Donck et Michel Weber,
Préface de Paul Gochet, 2007. (978-2-930517-01-8 ; 351 p. ; 35 €)

Michel Weber, L’Épreuve de la philosophie. Essai sur les fondements


de la praxis philosophique, 2008 (978-2-930517-02-5 ; 146 p. ; 15 €)

Michel Weber, Éduquer (à) l’anarchie. Essai sur les conséquences


de la praxis philosophique, 2008 (978-2-930517-03-2 ; 239 p. ; 20 €)

Alfred North Whitehead, La Religion en gestation [1926]. Traduction


et présentation de Henri Vaillant, relue par Vincent Berne. Préface
de Bertrand Saint-Sernin, 2008. (978-2-930517-04-9 ; 99 p. ; 12 €)

Jean-Claude Dumoncel et Michel Weber, Whitehead ou


Le Cosmos torrentiel. Introductions à Procès et réalité, 2010.
(978-2-930517-05-6 ; 191 p. ; 19 €)

John B. Cobb, Jr., Lexique whiteheadien. Les catégories de Procès et réalité


[2008]. Traduction de Henri Vaillant, relue par Emeline Deroo, éditée et
préfacée par Michel Weber, 2010. (978-2-930517-06-3 ; 205 p. ; 21 €)
1 6 + &+
38
'
'0& 1

/14 + /
5%

84
† 0#

//:

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi