Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 9

Neuroethics (2016) 9:15–22

DOI 10.1007/s12152-015-9245-4

ORIGINAL PAPER

Head Transplants, Personal Identity and Neuroethics


Assya Pascalev & Mario Pascalev & James Giordano

Received: 5 September 2015 / Accepted: 2 December 2015 / Published online: 18 December 2015
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Abstract The possibility of a human head transplant embodiment for personal identity. We maintain that
poses unprecedented philosophical and neuroethical embodiment is central to personal identity and a radical
questions. Principal among them are the personal iden- alteration of the body will also radically alter that per-
tity of the resultant individual, her metaphysical and son, making her a different person. Consequently, a
social status: Who will she be and how should the human head transplant will result in an individual partly
Bnew^ person be treated - morally, legally and socially continuous with the head/brain (in terms of connected
- given that she incorporates characteristics of two dis- memories and mental events), and partly continuous
tinct, previously unrelated individuals, and possess both with the body donor (in terms of the inputs and regula-
old and new physical, psychological, and social experi- tory patterns afforded by the structure and functions of
ences that would not have been available without the the nervous system, and the self-image of this new
transplant? We contend that this situation challenges embodiment). We conclude that the resultant person
linguistic conventions and conceptual binaries (Bpart- would be different from both the individual whose head
whole^), and calls into question the major philosophical was transplanted and the one to whose body the Bnew^
approaches to personal identity: animalism and reduc- head is attached.
tionism. We examine these views critically vis-a-vis
head transplantation and conclude that they fail to pro- Keywords Transplantation . Neuroethics . Personal
vide an adequate account of the identity of the resultant identity . Neuroscience . Philosophy . Embodiment .
individual because both neglect the key role of Derek Parfit . Animalism . Reductionism . Metaphysics .
Donor . Recipient . Self . Head transplant . Whole body
transplant . Head-to-body transplant
A. Pascalev (*)
Department of Philosophy, Howard University, 226 A. Locke
Hall, Washington, DC 20009, USA
e-mail: Assya.Pascalev@bio-ethics.net Recent reports of Italian surgeon Sergio Canavero’s
plans to perform a human head transplant by year
M. Pascalev 2017 [1, 2], and the subsequent news that the first
Bulgarian Center for Bioethics, Gorski Putnik 13A, 1421 Sofia,
Bulgaria volunteer for the procedure, Valery Spiridonov, has
e-mail: Mario.Pascalev@bio-ethics.net already stepped forward [3], are fostering a number of
neurobiological, philosophical and neuroethical ques-
J. Giordano tions, issues and challenges. Principal among them are
Pellegrino Center for Clinical Bioethics, Georgetown University,
4000 Reservoir Rd., Bldg D, Rm 238, Washington, DC 20057, the issue of the personal identity of the resultant indi-
USA vidual, and his or her metaphysical and social status:
e-mail: jg353@georgetown.edu Who will he or she be and how should the Bnew^ person
16 Pascalev A. et al.

be treated - morally, legally and socially - given that he differentially factor in the restorative action of these
or she incorporates characteristics of two distinct, pre- fusogens, and Canavero asserts that axonal alignment
viously unrelated individuals, and possess both old and is also not required for union of donor and recipient
new physical, psychological, and social experiences that neural tracts [4]. Grey matter interneuronal networks are
would not have been available without the transplant? posited to remain intact and functional, particularly if
In this paper, we contend that the feasibility of head and when transplanted tissue is post-surgically treated
transplants challenges the extant philosophical ap- with low level electrical stimulation. Canavero opines
proaches to personal identity: animalism and psycho- that the ideal operating setting involves a suite that
logical reductionism. We argue that both approaches fail enables simultaneous conduct of surgeries on both the
to provide an adequate account of the identity of the body-donor (D) and body-recipient (R - the Bhead^).
resultant individual because both misunderstand the role Anesthesiologic, thermal, and hemodynamic support is
of embodiment for personal identity. We maintain that maintained for both D and R, and suppression of neu-
embodiment is central to personal identity and a radical ronal burst activity is to be achieved through loading of
alteration of the body will also radically alter the person, barbiturate or propofol. Mechanical aspects of decapita-
making her a different person. Consequently, a human tion and HEAVEN-GEMINI are described relative to
head transplant will result in an individual partly con- positioning of D and R bodies, incisions, and the actual
tinuous with the head/brain donor (in terms of connected anastomoses (of vascular, meningeal, neural, and mus-
memories and mental events), and partly continuous cle tissues). Following surgery, the HEAVEN-Gemini
with the body donor (in terms of the inputs and regula- patient is to remain sedated in a cervical collar under
tory patterns afforded by the structure and functions of intensive care, with subsequent physiotherapy instituted
the nervous system, and the self-image of this new and sustained as necessary to achieve maximal function-
embodiment). We conclude that the resultant person al recovery. Considerations are afforded for post-
would be a new person different from both the individ- surgical central pain (consequential to improper or in-
ual whose head was transplanted and the one to whose complete fusion of the spinothalamic tracts), treatment
body the Bnew^ head is attached. of which Canavero addresses by reference to his prior
volume on this topic [7]. Absent from the discussion is
mention or address of the complexities and difficulties
The Approaching Feasibility of Head Transplants of treating and managing central pain (which in some
and its Challenges for Neuroethics cases requires neurosurgical intervention).1 According
to Canavero, HEAVEN-GEMINI is seen as viable, and
According to Canavero, the head transplant could be is proposed as a potentially valuable intervention for a
accomplished successfully in a complex neurosurgical young patient with B... a condition... devastating the
procedure, which he has called the head anastomosis body, for instance, progressive muscular dystrophies
venture (HEAVEN). The key to its success is the or... genetic and metabolic disorders of youth... with
GEMINI technique, which entails cooling and cutting no cure at hand^ [4, p. 340].
the spinal cords of the recipient and donor in a way that That Canavero’s proposal represents at least the pos-
would allow for anastomosis, with minimal tissue dam- sibility of an actual attempt at such an endeavor raises
age, and subsequent axonal fusion that is optimized complex philosophical and ethical issues that have here-
through perfusion of inorganic polymers to reduce tofore been only the stuff of wild speculation and sci-
gliosis and facilitate connectivity [4]. Canavero bases ence fiction. However, as the adage informs, yesterday’s
the procedure upon prior work of White et al. [5, 6], with fiction is today’s possibility, and fictional accounts may
the addition of using particular fusogen/sealants that are serve to at least illustrate the way(s) that head transplan-
polyethylene glycol (PEG) derivatives, such as PEG- tation is regarded in both professional and lay commu-
based polyaxomers, triblock copolymers consisting of nities [9]. Importantly, thought experiments, fictional
PEG side-chains surrounding a hydrophobic center, narratives and metaphors [10–12] facilitate ethical
and/or new forms of conjugated chitosan hydrogel. analysis allowing us to anticipate and evaluate the
These are claimed to be non-toxic (at molecular weights neuroethical implications of this procedure and to
greater than 1000), and highly hydrophilic. The diame-
1
ter and/or myelination of axons do not appear to For an overview, see [8].
Head Transplants, Personal Identity and Neuroethics 17

consider, before the fact, its moral permissibility (or regarding the nature of the novel procedure and the
impermissibility) and reach conclusions that could in- resultant donor-recipient relation: Is this a head trans-
form clinical, legal as well as policy discussions. To be plant, or a body transplant? Who is the donor and who
sure, some of the ethical issues of head transplantation the recipient, and are such distinctions merely semantic?
stem from the high risk of the neurosurgical procedure, Derivative questions include if, how, and what ought to
the possibility of rejection, the necessity and burdens of be done to prevent the misuse of the procedure for
protracted, if not life-long medical care, and the frivolous reasons (e.g., cosmetic pursuit of an ideal body
resulting psychological and economic stress(es) in- image), and socio-cultural – if not political – agendas?
curred. Such concerns are well known, and inherent to The precise nature of the relationship between the
organ transplantation, particularly if and when the pro- brain, the cognitive and emotional functions known as
cedure is experimental. While such issues are certainly mind, and the concept of self remains a source of ongo-
crucial, and give rise to important clinical, legal and ing philosophical debates, which, today, have been in-
ethical protocols to minimize risk, optimize outcomes, formed by insights from the neurosciences. The possi-
and ensure that procedures are soundly executed, they bility of a human head transplant lends practical rele-
are not new. However, other, more explicitly vance and urgency to the questions at the heart of such
neuroethical issues arise from the neurobiologic and debate and poses unprecedented challenges to notions of
neuro-cognitive aspects of the transplant. While animal personhood, self and identity. It is plausible to assume
studies have shown the relative viability of the that a successful head transplant would have profound
HEAVEN and GEMINI procedure(s), the cognitive in- impact on the recipient’s life; but what would life in a
tegrative capabilities and experience(s) of the resulting Bnew^ body mean for the recipient’s sense of self?
anastomosis are unknown, given that (1) long-term Would it change who he or she is and who would the
manifestations have not been studied (due to the mor- resulting individual become? As philosopher Bonnie
tality of research subjects to date), and (2) the phenom- Steinbock pointedly asks, Bwould the patient’s life be
enal consciousness of animals remains inaccessible. saved? This is not a medical or scientific question, but a
Canavero acknowledges the possibilities of body image conceptual or metaphysical one^ [13]. Somewhat intu-
and identity issues, and calls for B... psychiatric assess- itively, one might assume that the individual who sur-
ment and treatment... to prevent adverse postoperative vives after the transplantation is the one whose head
emotional reaction... related to... new body image^ [4, p. Breceives^ a body; after all, the head is the repository of
339]. the brain, which is essential to consciousness, thought
Indeed, the proposed procedures raise important phil- and the sense of self.2 Indeed, much of consciousness
osophical and ethical issues, as the principal questions entails embodiment of some sort. But, in a head-to-body
posed by the HEAVEN-GEMINI scenario concern the transplant, it is not necessarily obvious who Breceives^
nature of the self and personal identity: What makes one and who Bgives^, and who Blives^ or Bdies^ considering
who he or she is? What makes one the same person over that the entire body of one individual (the Bdonor^)
time? How is one’s brain related to one’s body, mind, survives its attachment to a part, albeit a central one, of
identity and self? Who is the person who survives the another (the Brecipient’s^ head).
transplantation: the Bowner^ of the head, the Bowner^ of Unlike other types of transplantation in which the
the body, or a qualitatively new person? Is the person recipient’s body becomes the environment for a donor’s
whose head is transplanted to another’s body the same body part, a head transplant involves a much greater
Bperson^ they were before the surgery? Following from degree of inter-dependence between the donated Bpart^
this are the challenges of the metaphysical and social and the receiving Bwhole^. We contend that this situa-
status of the resultant person. Namely, how should the tion challenges both linguistic conventions and such
Bnew^ individual be treated - morally, legally and so-
cially - given that he or she incorporates the physical 2
This view will not be shared by those cultures that believe that
characteristics of two distinct, previously unrelated in- the brain is not the locus of self and consciousness. Notably,
dividuals, and possess both old and new physical, psy- Buddhists deny the existence of the self [14, pp. 120–124] and
Taoists believe that the seat of consciousness is the body: BThe
chological, and social experiences that would not have
ancient Taoist conceived the body as consisting of five orbs - liver,
been available to the Brecipient^ without the transplant? heart, spleen, lungs and kidneys - which were associated with five
Thirdly, head-to-body transplantation raises questions agents, five senses, five psychic centers...^ [15, p. 128]
18 Pascalev A. et al.

conceptual binaries as Bpart-whole^. In essence, we are In contrast, proponents of the biological continuity
now asking whether the body is part of the brain/mind, view also called animalism (i.e., Eric Olson [22] and
or if the head (and brain) is a part to be fitted to the David DeGrazia [23, 24]), maintain that psychological
Bwhole^ of the body. Is an entire body a Bpart^, and is continuity is not essential to the survival of the individ-
the head, given its importance as Bpart^ of the body and ual over time and that one’s identity will be preserved as
its connection to thinking, self and memories, just an- long as one’s body exists. This is possible because we
other Bpart^? are organisms, and thus, what is essential to psycholog-
Rather, we opine that the result of a head transplant is ical continuity and personal identity is physical continu-
a new head-body unit (what we refer to as a Btrans- ity [24]. Consciousness is just another property of the
somatic individual^). This contends against the initial organism. Consequently, DeGrazia speak of human in-
intuition that the surviving person is the individual, stead of personal identity and maintains that one would
whose head was transplanted. To understand properly remain the same individual even if he or she loses
the characteristics of the resultant trans-somatic individ- consciousness permanently e.g., if he or she becomes
ual (or TSI), we must examine the fundamental ques- comatose, vegetative, or even brain-dead: B…if we are
tions of what makes us who we are, what constitutes essentially human animals, and not essentially beings
personhood and identity, and how they relate to one’s with psychological capacities, then… it is not clear—
mental and physical experience. These are philosophical indeed, it is false—that we go out of existence upon
questions that have important ethical, legal and clinical irreversible loss of the capacity for consciousness; rath-
implications. How they are answered will depend on er, we die upon the collapse of organismic functioning^
one’s view of personal identity, i.e., what makes some- [24].
one the same person over time, what makes someone We consider critically each of these views in turn.
that person (e.g., memories, sensory experience, modes
of perceiving and responding), and how we know who
is who. Animalism and Head Transplants

Although animalists are able to explain the relation of


Biological vs. Psychological Continuity the person to his or her body, they also less than fully
account for the personal identity of the head transplant
Scholars have offered competing accounts of personal because here, for the first time, the mental life of an
identity. One proposal is that personal identity consists individual (i.e., the TSI) does not correlate with a single
of the continuity of one’s mental events and psycholog- organism. A head transplant preserves parts of two
ical experiences over time. This psychological continu- distinct organisms, yet no single biological unit survives
ity view has been favored by many Western philoso- the surgery.
phers, including John Locke [16],3 Sydney Shoemaker One reply open to the animalist is to maintain that the
[17, 18], Derek Parfit [19] and Jeff McMahan [20]. individual who survives the head transplant is the donor,
Based upon this view, the person who will continue to whose body is attached to the head despite the fact that
exist after head-transplant surgery is the one whose head the donor would have completely new and unfamiliar
is transplanted onto another’s body, because the capacity mental contents and history. Another reply is to claim
for mental life resides in the surviving brain. This view that the survival of the head/brain is sufficient for the
is also known as mind essentialism, namely, Byou go survival of the entire organism, and thus the resultant
where your mind goes^ [21]. Such a position, however, person is identical to the one whose head survived the
does not fully account for the relation between the surgery. However, such a response would imply that the
person qua psychological states and the biological or- brain/head holds a privileged position in the organism,
ganism. As Steinbock notes, on this view it is literally which is hard to justify without also privileging the
impossible for a person who loses consciousness and functions of the human brain, which are primarily psy-
enters a persistent vegetative state (PVS) to continue to chological and include thinking, self-awareness and
exist as the same individual over time. memory.
Thus, if the animalist is to identify the organism with
3
See particularly Chapter XXVII on BIdentity and Diversity^. the brain, the view would collapse into its opposite, the
Head Transplants, Personal Identity and Neuroethics 19

psychological identity approach. Alternatively, the conclusions of the psychological conception of iden-
animalist could maintain two further, incompatible and tity, particularly the views of Derek Parfit.
logically contradictory views: he or she can claim that,
in the case of a head transplant, both the donor and the
recipient die because their organisms no longer exist as Psychological Continuity and Head Transplants
the units they were before the operation. Or, the
animalist could maintain that both the donor and recip- Parfit was the first to argue that personal identity (un-
ient survive the transplantation as two distinct organ- derstood as numerical identity of a person over time) is
isms, dismembered and stitched together. Neither of not what matters for the survival of the self. In his
these two options is particularly promising and neither seminal book Reasons and Persons [19], he explicitly
answers the question about the personal identity of the discusses brain transplants by way of thought experi-
post-transplant individual; rather, they explain it away at ments intended to support his view on identity. Parfit
the expense of the philosophical plausibility of the bio- rejects animalism in all its forms and also denies that
logical view. personal identity is dependent on any form of substance,
Faced with the limitations of the psychological and be it a physical body or something immaterial.
biological approaches, philosophers from both camps Moreover, Parfit rejects the very notion of a person
have argued that we should separate the thorny question and personal identity understood as Ba deep fact^, Ba
of personal identity from the problem of what matters to Cartesian Pure Ego^, something distinct, unifying, and
the self in survival, claiming that the latter issue (i.e., separate from the various states one is in. Parfit rejects
what matters to the individual) does not necessarily accounts of identity that presuppose the identity of the
require maintaining personal identity over time, regard- person, or that the mental states are had by that person
less of whether the individual is understood as an or- [19, p. 212]. Instead, he starts from the connectedness of
ganism or as psychological unity. For DeGrazia, what memories, intentions, beliefs, desires and other mental
matters to the person whose survival is in question is states. Connectedness for him is a matter of degree. BFor
narrative identity: B... a person’s self-conception, what X and Y to be the same person, there must be over every
she considers most important to who she is, the way she day enough direct psychological connections,^ at least
organizes the story she tells herself about herself^ [24, p. the half that existed on the previous day. [19, p. 206]
8]. DeGrazia links this to concepts of autonomy, authen- Psychological continuity is Bthe holding of overlapping
ticity and self-creation. It seems that one’s narrative chains of strong connectedness.^ A specific memory
identity could be disrupted or even lost not only if one’s can fade over the years, meaning my present memories
memories are disrupted or lost (i.e., due to amnesia or are no longer directly connected to it. (One may not
extended periods of unconsciousness) but also if one remember what he or she wore when attending a
experiences a profound loss, a catastrophic personal Professor Rawl’s lecture in 1996.) Still, other overlap-
event or loss of autonomy, which cannot be reconciled ping chains of memories, originating and fading over
with the meaningful story of one’s life. the last twenty years help that person recall many im-
All these conditions would lead to discontinuity in portant events (including attending the lecture in 1996).
one’s narrative identity, even if the individual con- Parfit Breduces^ the person to a series of psycholog-
tinues to exist as a mental and/or biological unity. ical experiences and relations between them and dubs
When applied to the case of the head transplant, the this view Breductionism^:
concept of narrative identity would require the pres-
ence of mental life and psychological continuity of [W]e are not separately existing entities, apart
experiences. Since these are only possible if a func- from our brains and bodies, and various interrelat-
tioning brain is present, sophisticated animalists (like ed physical and mental events. Our existence just
DeGrazia) would have to concede that, at least as involves the existence of our brains and bodies,
relates to narrative identity, the post-transplant TSI is and the doing of our deeds, and the thinking of our
that person who can tell a coherent story of survival, thoughts, and the occurrence of certain other phys-
i.e., the head. Thus, albeit for different reasons, the ical and mental events. Our identity over time just
conclusions of the narrative identity version of the involves (a) Relation R-psychological connected-
biological approach come very close to the ness and/or psychological continuity-with the
20 Pascalev A. et al.

right kind of cause, (b) that this relation does not philosophical and neuroethical paradoxes, which call
take a 'branching' form holding between one per- into question the plausibility of extant philosophical
son and two different future people [19, p. 217]. approaches to personal identity, and their implications
The ‘branching^ form to which Parfit refers is illus- for the identity of the post-transplant individual. Since
trated by fission – a process in which a single individual accounts of metaphysical and personal identity form the
divides into two or more other distinct individuals, thus basis of ethical analyses and judgments concerning
negating the numerical identity of the original individu- moral agency, responsibility and one’s place in society,
al. Parfit claims that as long as the two individuals who the philosophical difficulties we have identified also
inherit the divided, original brain retain enough of its hinder the analysis of the moral, legal, clinical and social
memories and the organization of these memories, the issues generated from Canavero’s proposed surgery.
original person would have survived the fission as two Clearly, the transplant recipient would face a number
persons. Yet, the original person would no longer be of challenges: from body image and a sense of self-
identical to the resulting persons. This leads Parfit to identity to social relations and legal status due to a
conclude that it is not personal identity that matters to a new (bodily) genetic identity. In the remainder of this
person’s survival, but rather the psychological continu- essay, we offer some preliminary reflections on these
ity of her mental life expressed as connections among issues as a first step toward a comprehensive philosoph-
that person’s mental states, or BRelation R^. Parfit main- ical and neuroethical evaluation of head transplantation.
tains that the only condition that is necessary for surviv- The major challenge for existing philosophical views
al is Relation R, Bpsychological connectedness and or is how to characterize the identity of the resultant indi-
psychological continuity, with the right kind of cause^ vidual. As we have illustrated, the major psychological
[19, p. 215]. He explains that the Bright kind of cause^ and biological stances fail to fully account for, or define
can be Bany kind of cause^ that evokes human psycho- the metaphysical status and personal identity of the
logical continuity through experiences, which bring post-transplant TSI. The problem is rooted in a shared
about mental events such as memories. Parfit’s expres- aspect of both psychological and biological approaches:
sion Bany kind of cause^ allows for the possibility that an assumed opposition between the biological organism
mental events can be the result of different causes and qua body, and the person qua the head/brain/mind.
need not be mediated by any particular physical body, Consequently, the animalists see two bodies under the
e.g., memories can be caused both by personal experi- same brain, and Parfit sees only the person (i.e., the
ences and via technological and medical means. Indeed, head/brain/mind) that received a new body.
today it is both conceivable and technologically possible We maintain that this presents a false dilemma, and
for mental events to be caused by brain manipulations that both approaches are flawed. We claim that the self is
(e.g., deep brain stimulation, transcranial electrical or fundamentally embodied and the mental life of a person
magnetic stimulation), and/or simulated virtual realities. is dependent upon (some form of) the physical body for
According to Parfit’s view, the person who undergoes mental contents, orientation, and as a way of relating to
a whole brain transplant will be identical to the one, who the world. Consequently, the continuity of the self (i.e.,
maintains the necessary Relation R of psychological personal identity) is dependent on the body and on the
continuity, i.e., the one whose functioning brain is pre- external environment. We need not disagree with Parfit
served [25, pp. 9–12). If, however, the surgery causes that Relationship R is what matters for identity. We
the loss of psychological continuity (i.e., due to severe submit, however, that the Bright kind of cause^ is more
memory loss), Parfit would argue that neither of the than just the immediate cause of brain processes, but
pre-transplant persons would survive, even if the trans- instead includes broader and more mediated causes that
plantation is successful and the resultant TSI recovers. involve the functional interactions (if not unity) of brain
and body.
The content of one’s experiences is not independent
of the biological Bmedium^; one’s embodiment struc-
The TSI View and Head Transplants tures the contents and form of one’s experience and
shapes one’s conceptual scheme. As Lakoff and
Thus far, we have shown that the possibility of head/ Johnson note, an individual with a very different bio-
whole body transplantation poses a number of logical structure (i.e. a spherical-shaped body) would
Head Transplants, Personal Identity and Neuroethics 21

experience the world differently and our special catego- previously embodied head/brain), and the former indi-
ries, e.g., up-down, might make little sense to such a vidual to whose body the Bnew^ head would be attached
being [10, p. 57]. While the experiential differences (but who previously sensed/perceived and was affected
between individuals with species-identical human bod- by his prior brain).
ies as in the head transplant case would be smaller in Eric Steinhart also argues for the conclusion that the
comparison, the example of Lakoff and Johnson is survivor of a head transplant would be a new person. In
instructive. We could consider the impact of the bodily our opinion, however, Steinhart arrives at the right con-
experience on the self in a continuum of cases, from the clusion from erroneous premises. Steinhart views per-
extreme to the more feasible: from transplanting a hu- sonal identity as Bthe functional persistence of cellular
man brain to a whale’s body, to Pucetti’s famous sce- and molecular systems^ (the central nervous system, the
nario of transplanting Churchill’s brain to a 6-year old enteric nervous system, the immune system and the
girl’s body [26, p. 60], to Parfit’s example of endocrine system) [27, pp. 1, 6]. Such strong biological
transplanting an identical twin’s head to his sibling’s determinism entails that in the merging of two cellular
body [19, p. 253]. At some point on this continuum, and molecular systems, as involved in the head-to-body
the body would be too different to allow for continuity transplant, neither of the previous persons will survive.
between the memories and experiences of the old body In fact, Steinhart’s view entails that attaching the head
as retained in the mind of the brain and the experiences and one half of the body of one person to a half of the
and sensory impact of the new body. Perhaps a body of another will result in a new person. It seems to
head-to-body transplant between monozygotic twins is us that Steinhart proves too much leading to the conclu-
the closest conceivable case of preserving the continuity sion that not only a head-to-body transplant will also
of the person whose head is transplanted to a new body result in a new person but so will a range of complex
but even such a case will likely fall short of complete thoracic multiple-organ transplants even though the re-
continuity. Therefore, we conclude that a radical alter- cipient’s head, brain and (most of the) body are retained.
ation of the body will also radically alter the surviving The reality of a human head transplant, no matter
person, making him/her a different person. We argue for how remote, prompts further and deeper neuroethical
a dialectical understanding of the resultant person. This inquiry and guidance. Elsewhere, we have posited key
will be a new individual, who is partly continuous with questions conceptual frameworks and responsibilities
the head/brain (especially in terms of memories, psy- that can, and arguably, should be required to assess
chology, life content), and partly continuous with the and direct the technical validity and ethical probity of
body donor, particularly in terms of the inputs and new neuroscientific and neurotechnological advance-
regulatory patterns afforded by the structure and func- ments in medicine [28, 29]; we hold these to be wholly
tions of its nervous system, and the resulting self-image applicable and necessary here. But the surgery proposed
of this (new) embodiment - all of which affect one’s by Canavero also incurs more deeply philosophical and
psychological states. The resultant person would need to neuroethical questions and issues that must be ad-
reconcile the two in the personal and social sense: he or dressed. The HEAVEN-GEMINI procedure evokes pos-
she must deal with questions of family and kinship, sibility for radical transformation of the body-brain re-
history, narrative, and the way(s) that one is socially lationship and the relation of the self to his/her past, and
regarded.4 We posit that this will make the resultant challenges the meaning (and perhaps values) of embodi-
person (viz. TSI) quite different from both the prior ment and social relations, the outcomes of which remain
individual whose head was transplanted (i.e., the uncertain and unfixed. On the one hand, there are good
reasons to leave it to the individual undergoing the
4
transformation to negotiate the parameters of his or her
The questions of family, kinship, and the social and legal stand-
identity, on her own terms and at her own pace. To the
ing of the TSI merit their own in-depth exploration. For instance,
would the children of a post-transplant individual be considered extent that we are social beings, however, the process of
siblings of the pre-transplant body donor, based on their genetic transformation would also include a reciprocal transfor-
makeup? What would be the legal status of a TSI person, if she is mation in the relations of others to the self, including
as we claim a new person? Would he or she be legally continuous
relations with the family and loved ones of the body
with the donor of the body, the donor of the head, neither, or both?
These important questions go beyond the scope of this paper and donor. Perhaps the novelty of this – and other avant garde
need to be addressed separately. techniques and technologies on the proximate horizon of
22 Pascalev A. et al.

possibility – call for new neuroethical principles that build 12. Pascalev Assya. 1996. Images of death and dying in the
intensive care unit. Journal of Medical Humanities 17(4):
upon, and in some cases revise philosophical constructs
219–236.
to adapt to changes in scientific knowledge, capability 13. Steinbok, Bonnie. 2015. How to get a head in life. https://
and the social milieu of the twenty first century world thebioethicsprogram.wordpress.com/2015/03/27/how-to-get-
stage [30, 31]. It can be entertaining to speculate upon the a-head-in-life/. Accessed 12 Dec 2015.
trajectories that brain science and its technologies will 14. Ho D.Y. 1995. Selfhood and identity in Confucianism,
Taoism, Buddhism, and Hinduism: Contrasts with the west.
assume, and instructional to engage ethical thought ex- Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 25(2): 115–139.
periments based upon fictional accounts. But we argue 15. Lind Richard. 2006. The seat of consciousness in ancient
that it is imprudent to be unprepared for those neurosci- literature. Jefferson, North Carolina: McFarland.
entific developments that can, and likely will occur in the 16. Locke John. 1689 [1975]. An essay concerning human under-
standing. P. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
near future [32], and in this light, advance the discourse
17. Shoemaker Sydney. 1970. Persons and their pasts. American
that we have herein initiated. It is the task of neuroethical Philosophical Quarterly 7: 269–285.
analysis to illuminate and question these transformative 18. Shoemaker Sydney. 1963. Self-knowledge and self-identity.
processes and to help to envision possibilities for mean- Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
ingful life within the expanding boundaries of science, 19. Parfit Derek. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
technology and the human condition.
20. McMahan Jeff. 2002. The ethics of killing: Problems at the
margins of life. New York: Oxford University Press.
21. Steinbok Bonnie. 2011. Life Before Birth: The Moral and
References Legal Status of Embryos and Fetuses, 2nd edn. USA:
Oxford University Press.
22. Oslon Eric. 1997b. The human animal: Personal identity
1. Thomson Helen. 2015. First human head transplant could
without psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
happen in two years. New Scientist 225(3010): 10–11.
23. DeGrazia David. 2005. Human identity and bioethics.
2. Watt, Alex. 2015. Head transplants: No longer science fiction
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
but a step closer to reality? European Medical Journal. http://
24. DeGrazia, David. 2011. The definition of death. In The
emjreviews.com/press/head-transplants-no-longer-science-
Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2011 edition), ed.
fiction-but-a-step-closer-to-reality/. Accessed 12 Dec 2015.
Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/
3. Whiteman, Honor. 2015. 30-year-old Russian man volunteers
entries/death-definition/. Accessed 12 Dec 2015.
for world's first human head transplant. Medical News Today.
http://www.medicalnewstoday.com/articles/292306.php. 25. Parfit Derek. 2012. We are not human beings. Philosophy 87:
Accessed 12 Dec 2015. 5–28.
4. Canavero Sergio. 2013. HEAVEN: The head anastomosis 26. Puccetti Roland. 1969. Brain transplantation and personal
venture project outline for the first human head transplantation identity. Analysis 29(3): 65–77.
with spinal linkage (GEMINI). Surgical Neurology 27. Steinhart Eric. 2001. Persons versus brains: Biological intelli-
International 4(1): 335–342. gence in human organisms. Biology and Philosophy 16: 3–27.
5. White R.J., L.R. Wolin, L.C. Massopust Jr., N. Taslitz, and J. 28. Giordano James. 2014. The human prospect(s) of neurosci-
Verdura. 1971. Primate cephalic transplantation: Neurogenic ence and neurotechnology: Domains of influence and the
separation, vascular association. Transplant Proceedings (3): necessity – and questions – of neuroethics. Human Prospect
602–604. 4(1): 1–18.
6. White R.J.. 1999. Head transplants. Scientific American 10: 29. Giordano James. 2015. A preparatory neuroethical approach
24–26. to assessing developments in neurotechnology. AMA Journal
7. Sergio Canavero, and Vincenzo Bonicalzi. 2011. Central pain of Ethics 17(1): 56–61.
syndrome, 2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 30. Lanzilao Elisabetta, John Shook, Roland Benedikter, and
8. Rasche Dirk, Patricia C. Rinaldi, Ronald F. Young, and Volker James Giordano. 2013. Advancing neuroscience on the 21st
M. Tronnier. 2013. Deep brain stimulation for treatment of century world stage: The need for – and proposed structure of
various chronic pain syndromes. Neurosurgical Focus 21(6): – an internationally relevant neuroethics. Ethics in Biology,
1–8. Engineering and Medicine: An International Journal 4(3):
9. Wurzman Rachel, and James Giordano. 2014. Neuroscience 211–229.
fiction as eidola: On the neuroethical role and responsibilities 31. Shook, John, and James Giordano. 2014. A principled, cos-
in representation of neuroscience. American Journal of mopolitan neuroethics: Considerations for international rele-
Bioethics – Neuroscience 5(3): 49. vance. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 9 (1).
10. Lakoff George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live 32. Giordano James, and Roland Benedikter. 2012. An early – and
by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. necessary – flight of the owl of Minerva: neuroscience,
11. Lakoff George, and Mark Johnson. 2000. Philosophy in the neurotechnology, human socio-cultural boundaries, and the
flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western importance of neuroethics. Journal of Evolution and
thought. New York: Basic Books. Technology 22(1): 14–25.
Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without
permission.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi