Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 10

The European Legacy

Toward New Paradigms

ISSN: 1084-8770 (Print) 1470-1316 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cele20

Socrates: Master and Martyr, Maverick and


Mystery

Victor Castellani

To cite this article: Victor Castellani (2014) Socrates: Master and Martyr, Maverick and Mystery,
The European Legacy, 19:3, 359-367, DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2014.898939

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2014.898939

Published online: 23 Apr 2014.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 43

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cele20

Download by: [Gothenburg University Library] Date: 13 October 2017, At: 14:40
The European Legacy, 2014
Vol. 19, No. 3, 359–367, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2014.898939

Review

Socrates: Master and Martyr, Maverick and Mystery


The Cambridge Companion to Socrates. what he did or said when alive is no less ben-
Edited by Donald R. Morrison (Cambridge: eficial to people, or rather it is even more so.’
Cambridge University Press, 2011), xviii + What matters about Socrates is that we never
413 pp. £19.99/$29.99 paper. tire of him or stop wanting to talk to him and
get mad with him” (378).
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

Anyone who knows the least about this


provocative figure is likely aware that he is
VICTOR CASTELLANI the protagonist of many dialogues, direct and
A heroic, seminal “lover of wisdom” who reported by one of the young Athenians who
denied that he possessed the divine knowl- associated with him, though he was not an
edge required for perfect virtue, Socrates of early or close disciple: Plato (d. 348/7 BCE),
Athens needs no basic introduction and has perhaps the greatest prose writer of all classical
needed none for centuries in the West or antiquity. However, we have other evidence
among the educated in Western style. He has about the master from contemporaries, some
often and long been perceived and admired as of whom were Plato’s elders. It begins with a
a martyr who preferred ethical and intellectual tendentious caricature in Aristophanes’ com-
integrity such as he understood it, which pre- edy Clouds (423 BCE, revised a few years
scribed a lethal dose of poison hemlock over later). The playwright gives us a picture,
a pleasant life among rich and powerful however distorted, of an already famous mav-
friends, at Athens or in comfortable exile. On erick thinker and “gadfly” (as he calls himself
the other hand, each new generation will in Plato’s Apology), at a point in his life when
approach—sometimes confront—Socrates the other principal witnesses to it were only
anew. little boys. Since Socrates himself left no writ-
From the very last page of the fifteenth ings, a “Socratic Question/Problem” has
and final article of this well assembled collec- complicated our effort to understand what he
tion, “Socrates in Later Greek Philosophy,” I himself did, thought, and stood for—and
quote the distinguished ancient intellectual against.
historian A. A. Long. After demonstrating The first three articles help us around this
how radically different versions of “Socrates” apparent obstacle. In the very first sentence of
and “Socratic thought” emerged over the “The Life and Death of the Socratic Prob-
centuries after the man’s death in 399 BCE, lem,” Louis-André Dorion of the University
he summarizes: “generations would repeat- of Montréal refers to its “desperately unsolv-
edly interpret Socrates in their own image, able nature” (1). He traces the history of the
elide what did not suit them, or even turn quandary since early in the nineteenth cen-
him into their own antithesis, as the Epicure- tury when Friedrich Schleiermacher raised it.
ans did. Can we do better? Probably not, and Some historians of thought have regarded
that is just as well. For, whatever we make of Plato’s dialogues, at least the supposedly ear-
Socrates, these words from [first-century CE lier ones written close to the master’s death
freedman-philosopher] Epictetus ring true: (when readers would have been able to reject
‘Now that Socrates is dead, the memory of any misrepresentation by Plato), as a sort of

Dept. of Languages and Literature, University of Denver 2040 S. Race St., Denver, CO 80208-2662 USA. Email:
vcastell@du.edu

© 2014 International Society for the Study of European Ideas


360 REVIEW

accurate dramatized biography. Many have eral of them, about whom we have varying
accordingly rejected Plato’s contemporary amounts of information, sometimes only evi-
Xenophon as a clueless lowbrow bystander dence that is itself indirect and dubious. The
who missed almost the entire point of the doyen of these was Antisthenes, a much older
“real” Socrates, cutting him down to his own man, whom Plato opposed with regard to
feeble intellectual level. Without taking Xen- epistemology and the sufficiency of available
ophon’s part, Dorion argues that “everything “knowledge.” The last pages of this chapter
seems to indicate that neither Xenophon nor consider these differences (42–45), but also
Plato set out with the intention of faithfully identify a distinctiveness of attitude that
reporting Socrates’ ideas. Xenophon’s and makes us regret the loss of Antisthenes’ writ-
Plato’s Socratic writings belong to a literary ings. As well we might do, since nothing of
genre—that of the logos sokratikos, which Aris- the latter’s work survives except through testi-
totle explicitly acknowledged and which monia. The younger Aeschines, in contrast,
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

authorizes by its very nature a certain degree wrote seven dialogues about which we know
of fiction and a great freedom of invention as something—only their titles in five instances,
far as the setting and the content are con- rather more in two. Though we lack
cerned” (7); for “it is likely that Socrates rap- extended surviving quotations, those two
idly became a sort of literary character clearly dealt with “erotics” and the impor-
(dramatis persona) endowed with his own exis- tance of love as in Plato’s Symposium. Phaedo
tence and placed at the center of the polemics of Elis, the young man after whom Plato’s
and rivalries that pitted one Socratic against famous death-of-Socrates dialogue is named,
another. Each author of the logoi sokratikoi in wrote at least two himself, while a certain
this way created ‘his own’ Socrates, whom he Euclides of Megara left six. Aristippus of Cy-
contrasted with the competing ‘Socrates’ por- rene, founder of the hedonist “Cyrenaic”
trayed by the other Socratics. Each laid claim movement, seems to have written whatever
to, and quarreled over, the heritage of their he did in other forms, but traced his thinking
bygone master, as well as faithfulness to his to Socrates too. Döring’s chief contention,
memory and to his teachings” (9). Moreover, however, is that “there is strong reason to
sporadic agreement between those two prin- think that no other Socratic brought the
cipal dialogists, Plato and Xenophon, is slight, potential contained in the Socratic dialogue
and where they do agree the latter may have to such fruition and full development as Plato
gotten the matter from the former; moreover, did, with respect to both literary form and
Aristotle, despite his and Plato’s falling out, philosophical breadth and depth” (26).
seems to use only Plato as the source for his Indeed, except for the immediately following
information on Socrates (16). Socrates, there- article, the subsequent contributions to the
fore, must be best categorized as a stimulant Cambridge Companion equate Plato’s “Socra-
rather than a dogmatist—which, for good or tes” with Socrates, albeit ever with the pre-
ill, is what each of the several feuding Socra- caution that Middle and Late dialogues,
tics increasingly did become. however exactly they are to be ordered and
“The Students of Socrates” by Bamberg periodized, reflect Plato’s thinking as it
Professor Emeritus Klaus Döring may be a bit evolved to a point where it no longer
of a misnomer. The man himself claimed to embodies that of Socrates, even when “Socra-
teach nothing and thus to have no students, tes” is an interlocutor.
only friends who listened to and sometimes American scholar David K. O’Connor of
joined in his probing conversations. Who Notre Dame University contributed the third
even perhaps, like Alcibiades in some of Pla- article, “Xenophon and the Enviable Life of
to’s dialogues, rooted for Socrates in his Socrates.” Xenophon’s chief fault is that he
debates with the reputed wise who crossed was not Plato. He was, however, hardly so
their path. On the other hand, each of the intellectually weak as is often supposed.
several persons who also wrote about him, Indeed as a stylist of Attic prose he ranks
often though not always in dialogue or anec- high; a non-Socratic historical work of his
dote form, claimed to be his uniquely faithful would be a chief model for Julius Caesar’s
disciple, ostensibly deriving his method and/ masterful Commentarii on the war in Gaul. “It
or doctrine from Socrates. Döring treats sev- is useful to look at Xenophon to compare
REVIEW 361

him to Plato,” O’Connor writes, “but this concocts an intellectual composite, making
perspective can diminish or distort Xeno- fun of all unconventional and suspect ‘think-
phon’s own achievement. Xenophon is more ers outside the box’ (sc. of conventional reli-
interested in what makes politics and political gion and morality). Socrates’ religious
leaders work, and in improving politics in unorthodoxy and his interrogation of the
ways that politicians can actually find credi- common understanding of morals and values,
ble” (49). Unlike Plato he wished to insulate above all his undeniable energy and cleverness
Socrates from politically catastrophic young in negative elenchus,2 discrediting respectable
aristocrats like Critias and especially Alcibi- persons and positions, made him an easy,
ades who were invidiously associated with available target. Moreover, his was a familiar
him. Xenophon himself was less under the ugly face to the Athenian audience, a joy for
sage’s spell. Two of his anecdotes “show the theatrical mask-maker. He may also have
Xenophon was an affectionate admirer of had a characteristic voice or delivery—not a
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

Socrates but a less docile disciple than Eut- charming speech impediment like that of Alc-
hydemus. He maintained a certain distance ibiades, but one that could he amusingly imi-
from Socrates despite his affection and admi- tated. “Socrates” is, in fact, as pious in the
ration” (71). Nevertheless, just as he found comedy as ever in Plato’s pretrial-trial-impris-
Cyrus the Great to be an ideal ruler, he onment-and-death tetralogy; on the other
judged Socrates to be an ideal private citizen. hand, rejecting the conventional mythology
Both the Persian King and the Athenian sage as he probably did (see below on Chapter 6)
established their eminence by benefaction and and heeding his personal daimonion, he could
patronage, according to Xenophon, by giving well be parodied as a worshipper of Clouds
more than they received from those whom and Vortex who figuratively ‘looked down
the one governed well as king, and whom the on’ conventionally religious common people
other guided by example and exhortation to —as in a hilarious play he does, literally, from
the good life (50–60). Xenophon understands an elevated basket. Indeed his greeting address
this good life, in a secular, non-”philosophi- to the dense protagonist Strepsiades, “o crea-
cal” way. It includes mastery of self and oth- ture-of-a-day,” could well reflect the man’s
ers, self-sufficiency and consequent freedom. insistence that the true Socrates was an immor-
He believes further that pious Socrates, like tal “soul.”3
Xenophon himself, had a “good daimōn” who The fifth article, by Paul Woodruff of
blessed him with happiness by directing the University of Texas at Austin, assesses
sometimes quite mundane activity.1 One sus- Socrates’ relationship to what Woodruff calls
pects, I might add, that the Socrates who “the new learning.” Socrates and his
“invented new divine entities that the nation sometime opponents had several things in
does not recognize” (as the capital indictment common: they challenged people’s tradition-
against him alleged) was more superstitious in bound comprehension of the divine; they
an idiosyncratic way than Plato liked or indi- demanded consistency in characterizing the
cated. gods and their role, if any, in human affairs;
The next trio of articles, Chapters 4–6, they respected the human intellect and con-
place Socrates in the context of what has been science, with consequent hope that humans
called the Greek Intellectual Revolution of may gain by collaboration in the quest for
the fifth century BCE. In “Socrates in Aristo- moral truth; they criticized irrational customs
phanes’ Clouds,” Brown University’s eminent and conventions (nomoi); and they were pas-
scholar of ancient comedy David Konstan sionately dedicated to the art of words.
makes two very important points. First, Woodruff maintains that “Socrates uses his
“comedy has its own licenses” (80), far skill above all for a very serious call to philos-
greater than those likely allowed to the logos ophy, and this use has no parallel in the sur-
sokratikos, for the specific purposes of comedy—to viving works of the new learning” (108);
raise laughs by surprise, by incongruity, and indeed, “his defenders—Xenophon and Plato
especially by exaggeration. Secondly, in what —show him resisting certain innovations [in
intellectual historian Eric Havelock deemed a thought and speech]. But Socrates’ resistance
generic parody of undifferentiated “science,” was evidently far from a defense of tradition.
“philosophy,” and “rhetoric” the comic poet Even as he was shown by his defenders, he
362 REVIEW

was affected by the new learning, like other doubts that any true atheist was to be found:
thinkers of his time, so that his resistance... notorious Diagoras of Melos was reputed to
consisted in developing alternatives to the be one such, and as such was brought to pub-
intellectual fashions of the day that were no lic trial, judicially condemned, and expelled
less revolutionary than the fashions he from Attica. Athenian tragedy’s speculation
opposed” (93–94). Presumably for this very about and sometimes—in Euripides—critique
reason, he could (as Mark McPherran notes of the gods is also unfortunately overlooked
in the next chapter) be grouped—in Clouds here. Socrates is said to have been an avid
for example—with the physicists and sophists theater-goer at the annual Dionysia, and tra-
of his times with whom he shared “a willing- gic poets were the Athenians’ de facto public
ness to question the traditional ideas, a fasci- theologians through most of his lifetime.4
nation with what it is to be human, and a “Socrates and Democratic Athens” by
delight in the effective use of words” (95). Stanford University scholar Josiah Ober
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

The final sentence of the article adds that comes next. He examines, within the setting
“Through Socrates, Plato was no more critic of a recently restored democracy—restored
of, than he was heir to, the new learning” (109; after some of the “beautiful and good” young
my emphasis). friends of the philosopher had instituted a
Chapter 6, “Socratic Religion” follows murderous tyranny—the philosopher’s indict-
neatly upon the preceding piece, surveying ment, trial, and execution. Plato and Xeno-
(1) Socrates’ public conduct, which seems to phon both make the democrats ‘bad guys’ in
have been reverential and unexceptional; (2) the event; but Ober, who devotes ten pages
his reported statements, which could provoke to a mixture of legal and rhetorical aspects of
pious polytheists, as he may be likened to a the case (166–76), asserts that the fundamental
street preacher who “challenged and renewed question is not whether Socrates was “guilty”
the religious conceptions of his time” (112) as charged, but why and how those two liter-
and which evidenced “a religious commit- ary defenders (and perhaps Socrates himself)
ment integral to his philosophical mission” sought to show him “not guilty” not in a trial
(111); and (3) his discoverable positive beliefs. before five hundred Athenian jurors but for
Belief, of course, for anyone but a religious the ages (144). Ober also offers cautious and
fundamentalist can be elusive, even to him- reasonable guesses about what actually hap-
or herself, and is surely so in Socrates’ case. pened, including the poisonous background
(We have already seen that Plato and Xeno- —amnesty or no amnesty—of Socrates’
phon found different levels and kinds of piety widely known friendship with several of the
in the master.) Here Canadian scholar Mark hated Thirty Tyrants of 404–403 BCE and
McPherran of Simon Fraser University con- his outspoken admiration for features of the
siders Socratic critique of scandalous myths. (oligarchic-royal) Spartan constitution. In
Rhetorician-sophists might cynically use these light of Plato’s Apology and Crito Ober also
to exculpate, if hardly to justify, atrocious considers Socrates’s attitude to the laws and
behavior (as Strepsiades’ ‘sophist’icated son civic duty, divided and sometimes conflicted
Pheidippides does toward the end of Clouds). between conventional (including brave mili-
Socrates was more in earnest. McPherran tary service) and provocative (his “stinging”
finds puzzles about him to solve, or try to Delphic missionary efforts).
solve, in half a dozen concerns on a kind of The ensuing four articles, Chapters 8–11,
continuum. They range from his notions of constitute a suite that should interest literary
(1) strict rationality and (2) human ignorance, critics and philosophers alike, the first,
through his (3) conviction of his divine “Socratic Method,” especially the philoso-
mission with (4) an oracular source, to (5) phers, because of its technical approach, and
extra-rational information and (6) the famous “Reconsidering Socratic Irony,” the fourth,
daimonion. A discussion of contemporary both constituencies. In his discussion of the
fifth-century popular religious notions (some dialectical method (Chapter 8) University of
of which Aristophanes also chides in Clouds) Oklahoma’s Hugh H. Benson asks how dis-
vis-à-vis intellectuals’ unsettling agnosticism tinctive Socrates’ method is as demonstrated
and skepticism is on the mark and valuable. It in those “Socratic” dialogues of Plato that he
is, however, surprising how McPherran identifies in a footnote. Conversations there
REVIEW 363

are often quite drama-like. Interrogated inter- think,” on the chance that this may prove
locutors often lose their patience with his per- sustainable as knowledge. “What is at issue
sistence in demanding “doxastic coherence” here is not what people believe, or are con-
through the famous elenchos, where he com- vinced about, but rather whether they know
pares the definitions that a victim proposes anything. Self-examination is an extension of
with that person’s unarticulated beliefs and the examination of others, and vice versa—
behavior. Most of the earlier dialogues end in and it will be self-examination just to the
an “aporetic” impasse, but not in despair. Pro- extent that it is an examination of how one
fessor Benson analyzes how Socrates proceeds stands, oneself, in relation to knowledge.
from an initial (and soon rejected) answer to That, for Socrates, is the absolutely
the ‘What is F-ness?’ question, a refutand that fundamental question” (206; Rowe’s empha-
collides with new premises such as the inter- ses). The early direct dialogue Charmides
locutors next establish. These premises need receives lengthy analysis. Rowe pronounces it
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

not reflect anything that Socrates himself “a paramount example of self-examination”


holds to be secure and true, only what his (209). In fact, the discussion there is ulti-
examinee sincerely believes. The purpose of mately about three things: about the virtue
such frequently embarrassing investigation is “temperance” (sōphrosunē), which Socrates
not only to exhibit another person’s igno- wishes to define; about whether anyone can
rance (as Plato’s Apology suggests), but also to possess it without understanding it; and about
move toward robustly understood wisdom. whether and how one can understand it or at
Benson treats at length and with finesse the least approach an understanding—that is, its
question of how ability to produce a sustain- knowledge.
able definition is related to “knowledge,” “Socratic Ignorance” follows as Chap-
without depending upon the presumably post- ter 10. Knowledge in an impregnable sense
Socratic disembodied Idea-of-F-ness. A prob- eluded the sage, as Johns Hopkins professor
lem with this occurs to Benson: “Evidence Richard Bett observes here, yet not about
of... doxastic incoherence provides no reason physics (pace Aristophanes) but about the
to suppose that some allegedly targeted belief ethical matters that from a certain point in his
is false or that its negation is true. For this we career as a thinker-inquirer Socrates deemed
need evidence that Socrates thinks degree of to be immeasurably more important, the
belief or definiteness of belief carries with it most valuable things for a rational human
some epistemic weight. But no such evidence being to be certain about. Socrates, Betts
is to be found” (193). Nevertheless, “what maintains, was quite sincere in his confes-
the attribution of the priority of definitional sion that he lacked the art/skill/practical sci-
knowledge [for secure comprehension of ence (tekhnē) that he craved. Bett finds that
F-ness] to Socrates indicates is not that he is the philosopher had changing stances with
committed to an implausible view, but that regard to the Priority of Definition ques-
he is committed to a stronger conception of tion. Could and should one who has
knowledge than the ordinary one” (197). His attained one specific virtue among many be
dialogical, elenchic method is “coherent and able to define it before claiming to possess it
distinctive” (198). when one is singled out for consideration
Christopher Rowe, Emeritus Professor of (as “piety” is in Euthyphro and others else-
Greek at Durham, explores Socrates’ “Self- where)? If several virtues are named (as ini-
Examination” in the next article. He, too, tially in Meno) should “virtue” be narrowed
does not distinguish Socrates from Plato’s rep- down, or must one first undertake a
resentation of the master. His chief interest is descriptive-definitional quest for generic
in how Socrates turns the testing inward, “virtue”? Arete¯ as such becomes the object
albeit not to himself as individuated person of question and quest in Meno as in other
with such-and-such characteristics and experi- dialogues, with or without a qualification
ences. Rather it is to his rational soul, the like the “arete¯ politike¯” in Protagoras. No
same as others’ though more self-conscious. “neat and tidy” conclusions can be drawn,
Rowe therefore also discusses how Socrates Bett concludes, whether because Plato chan-
examines others, not necessarily for their ged his view, or because Socrates’ own
deepest convictions, but rather for “what they thinking evolved or simply was inconsistent.
364 REVIEW

Melissa Lane, Professor of Politics at piece of critical philosophy itself, as is the clo-
Princeton, in “Reconsidering Socratic Irony” sely related following chapter, Christopher A.
makes one of the smartest, most appealing Griswold’s “Socrates and Eudaimonia.” What
contributions to this collection. She differen- besides sensual appetite moves a person to
tiates dramatic irony, on the one hand, as choose “the right thing”—and the right thing
deployed in scattered anticipations of Socra- for whom? For oneself? For another individual?
tes’ trial, condemnation, and execution, from For one’s community? For all humankind?
what the Greeks called alazoneia, a false pre- And how is happiness, correctly understood
tense of something. In the case of Socrates (an elusive question in itself), related to right
this would be his profession of knowing nei- moral choice? Socrates’ answers, explicit or
ther (1) the most important things at all, as in more or less clearly implied in the Socratic
Bett’s preceding chapter (and as he himself dialogues, are what these two chapters seek to
declares in Plato’s Apology), nor (2) more, and articulate.
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

better, than his interlocutor. This last would Penner’s Socrates holds that all motivated
include sarcastic flattery of a smug or arrogant action worth judging is deliberate, the result
yet profoundly ignorant “partner” in his of our reasoning from desire of what we
inquiry. Eirōneia, whence we have English believe to be beneficial for us toward its
“irony” and its cognate counterparts in other achievement. Our good, however, is insepa-
modern European languages, has a history in rable from the good of others, or at least can
ancient discourse, which Lane reviews. One never entail harm to them. Ethics is one
cluster of corollary questions is whether, for among the sciences, all sciences are teleologi-
whose amusement (someone’s on the scene, cal, and ethics’ end is “practicable happiness”
or only the reader’s?), and at whose expense (265). It is “a purely factual matter. It is not a
ironists do their sarcastic thing, and whether matter of moral truth, or norms, or values,
the target is aware of mockery, mild or harsh. not a matter of what is intrinsically good as
A further one is whether irony is a sometime such, good in itself, good simpliciter, or any
instrument—with “a dialectical or argumenta- such thing. It is simply what is good for
tive purpose” (243)—or an essential character humans. For Socratic ethics, in total contrast
trait of the person who employs it. Certainly, to most of modern moral philosophy, there
for Socrates “The difficulty is to enlist pride are no further elements of the subject-matter
on the side of <one> entering the dialectic, of ethics involving any of the aforementioned
while avoiding the anger that might militate norms, values, moral principles, intrinsic
against continuing the encounter” (254). goods, or the like. There is just the science of
Critical Epicureans and, in modern times, what is good for humans and of the means to
Nietzsche have found Socrates’ irony arro- that good” (269); and “wisdom is the only
gant, and find fault in it. Lane denies that thing good in itself as a means to happiness”
“‘Socratic irony’ is a central organizing prin- (271). Penner considers and rejects objections
ciple of Socrates as depicted by Plato. ... that such a stance is, on the one hand, merely
There is certainly a rhetoric to Socrates’ con- Selfish Egoism, if we only want what is good
versational interplay, but it need not amount for others because in the long run it is good
to irony. And if there is no basis for a system- for us; or error-prone, on the other, because
atic (as opposed to an occasional and casual) our desires for apparent good often conflict
imputation of Socratic irony, then those tradi- with our progress toward the actual good
tions positing its philosophical significance— when our human wisdom, which Socrates
however one evaluates its purpose, audience, concedes is imperfect, fails us. Nevertheless,
and worth—need to be reconsidered” (256f.). we always really want the really good, as the
The following three articles endeavor to Gorgias and the Republic both argue. Penner
distill a “philosophy” of Socrates, interrogat- also uses the Euthydemus as a key text, but
ing, as several preceding contributors do, adduces as decisive the paradox of Plato’s (as
Plato, with scarcely a glance at Xenophon he believes) Hippias Minor, according to
even for secondary, corroboratory witness. which only the wise person is capable of
“Socratic Ethics and the Socratic Psychology “doing wrong”—because he alone knows
of Action” by University of Wisconsin Emer- what he is doing! In fact, no one can or will
itus Professor Terry Penner is a provocative “do wrong” on purpose, but only by accident
REVIEW 365

or mistake. Penner adds a cogent explanation These matters of private moral virtue
of Socrates’ “policy of almost never asserting clearly impinge upon the topic of Chapter 14,
his views explicitly” (280), and diagnoses the “Socrates’ Political Philosophy,” since, at least
sage’s “ultra-realism” (286). He ends strik- according to the Apology but also from a strik-
ingly with the comment that Socratic ethics ing claim in Gorgias, Socrates was the unique
“is, I think, the one morality-free theory of model citizen. He alone took pains to get his
objective good available to us that contains compatriots to tend their true selves, their
no elements of conventions of the sort souls, although the enterprise won him ene-
Socrates or Plato would have regarded as mies; and he alone practiced true statesman-
unacceptable. The conjecture occurs to me ship because only he was dedicated not to the
that it may be virtually alone among non- material benefit of Athens but to the intellec-
conventionalist theories compatible with the tual-moral improvement of each and every
Descent of Man from the high primates. For I Athenian citizen. The author of this article is
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

doubt that there could be a comparable Charles A. Griswold, Professor of Philosophy


evolution of a non-conventional categorical at Boston University, who gets the last word
imperative” (291). in this Cambridge Companion, since only A. A.
“Happiness” has been a notable topic Long’s article quoted at the outset follows,
before Chapter 13 but becomes the subject of dealing with what Socrates meant to thinkers
the discussion here of its theory-and-practice, in Hellenistic Greece and the Roman Empire.
“eudaimonism,” on the part of Plato’s Socra- Griswold begins with a generalized treatment
tes. Its author Christopher Bobonich, Profes- of the relationship between philosophy and
sor of Philosophy at Stanford University, first politics, more precisely between philosopher
reviews language-historical applications of the and statesman. He notes that Socrates might
Greek words we translate as “happy” and not have been so public a figure as Plato’s
“happiness,” deploying a bit of philology Apology would suggest, given the private set-
before the philosophy. Then he provides a tings—in townhouses, at gymnasia, on walks
thorough discussion of the relationship outside the city walls—of the other dialogues.
between happiness and virtue, which for Soc- The Apology acknowledges the danger to a
rates ultimately coincide (314–24). Virtue, of candid teller of uncomfortable truth; how-
course, is wisdom, upon which all other ever, its author Plato may exaggerate, if he
goods depend—the wisdom to recognize that does not invent, a claim by Socrates himself
what is truly best for Socrates is also truly best that he had a “divine mission” to wise Athens
for all. Bobonich treats much but not all of up (343). Griswold also examines his involve-
the same Platonic evidence as Penner, since ment in public affairs (as distinct from his
the mechanism that effects happiness is at exemplary military career) and finds that he
once rational and psychological. He allows at was not much of an activist, resisting clearly
the outset that there are “gaps” in Socrates’ unconstitutional or criminal actions quietly
thought, which on these matters he extracts rather than vociferously. Such “civic” action
from the probably very early Charmides and as he initiated was not public. Of course, his
Protagoras and from the somewhat later Gorgi- overheard conversations seem sometimes to
as and Meno. He concludes that, although have touched or even been centered upon
rational eudaimonism has important advanta- “political virtue,” but in the earlier dialogues
ges (which he lists on 328), “Socrates does he does not himself define this or allow any-
not provide a detailed account of what is one else’s definition to stand. Furthermore, in
good for human beings” (330). Certainly, I the Apology and its sequel the Crito Plato’s
may add, he never brings an interlocutor in Socrates merely obeys the existing laws, and
earlier dialogues to a confident understanding in the latter, imprisoned on the Attic ‘death
of precisely that. Plato himself, Bobonich row,’ explains his obedience. He does not
concludes, in middle-period dialogues makes criticize them or the democratic government
a better case that virtue is necessary or suffi- that enacted them. “However much he con-
cient for happiness and that all good depends trasted a political ‘ideal’ with the unsatisfac-
upon wisdom, when he defines human nature tory reality of the historical polis, he did not
and links virtue to “knowledge of the Forms” otherwise agitate for the radical reformation
(331). of his polis by, say, proposing measures in the
366 REVIEW

Assembly or organizing reform movements” cusses “Socrates in Later Greek Philosophy.”


(336). Nor is he known to have criticized The Athenian gadfly became a stock charac-
Athens’ imperial wars, in which he personally, ter, exemplary sage to many—though not for
patriotically fought. (Indeed at the beginning Epicureans, who, joined later by some Peri-
of Pericles’ war he served in the besieging patetics,5 blamed him for all that was wrong
force that invested a subject “allied” state, with rival philosophies, whether mistaken
Potidaea, which attempted to withdraw from dogmatism or unwholesome skepticism. Soc-
an involuntary “alliance.”) Implicit, however, rates’ importance depended upon how he was
in the Crito and suggested more clearly in the interpreted, always with simplification, verg-
famous discussion of specious versus true, ing upon misrepresentation, of what he actu-
moralizing statesmanship in Gorgias is the ally was, what he thought, and (however
thought that a good, wise rhe¯tōr—using per- indirectly or by negation) what he taught.
suasive speech, and not teaching it unless by Competing and evolving schools of philoso-
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

example—ought to be able to talk legislators phy seized upon one facet of his thinking or
into right legislation, policy-makers into right another. Increasing skepticism among Aca-
policy. But what those laws and policies demics in the generations after its founder
would be, concretely, “Socrates” in Plato’s Plato, moral cynicism of the Cynics, Stoics’
earlier works does not give a reader to under- determination to situate the rational soul in
stand. Griswold devotes a section to Republic, the cosmos and in relation to the divine—all
where “Socrates” strives to relate the ideal to derived from selective memorialization of a
the actually practicable—the management of mythologized Martyr to Philosophy. Long’s
the soul to management of the state. Wishful article traces the doxographic ramifications,
thinking about crowned philosophers, how- from Socrates’ senior disciple Antisthenes,
ever, or philosophized kings does not amount who evidently attempted to codify Socratic
to a political philosophy. Griswold returns at ethics, onward. As others noted in Chapters
the end to Crito and Socrates’ thoughtful 1–3, Plato and Xenophon preserve clearly
acquiescence in his execution, of which (as contrasted versions of Socrates for us, if only
his friend Crito knew and found embarrass- because their works survive. A century after
ing) all of Athens was aware. In fact, since the Socrates’ death, Plato’s fourth successor as
amnesty of 404 BCE, executions were proba- head of the Academy, Arcesilaus (called ‘the
bly very rare. “Socrates is explicitly attempt- Skeptic’) “pushed the aporetic Socrates to the
ing to define and justify a new human limit” (364). Diogenes the Cynic and Zeno,
possibility—the ‘philosopher’ understood in a founder of the Stoa, who took inspiration
distinctive and innovative way—and the both from Diogenes and (Long adds) from
manner of his death was an inherent part of Plato’s Euthydemus, had much in common.
his enactment of that deeply controversial life. Both stressed the ignorance and consequent
Socratic politics aimed to establish publicly irrational conduct of everyone, beginning
and persuasively, and therefore in deed as well with themselves, although Zeno came to
as in word, that the philosophically examined believe he could attain and impart positive
life is best” (351). Government for him, wisdom. Long devotes a detailed section
therefore, was individual personal, rational (371–74) to a novel interpretation of Socratic
self-government, more valuable than corpo- elenchus centuries later by an important Mid-
real life. dle Stoic of Roman times, Epictetus, who in
As an idea, and a very flexible one, Socra- turn influenced the part-time self-examining
tes never did die. Indeed “Socrates” stalked philosopher Marcus Aurelius. The chapter
the stage in a number of fourth-century come- also takes notice of Platonizing Plutarch,
dies, where, though acknowledged to be very author of On Socrates’ Divine Sign, who falls
smart, he was also somewhat odd in looks and chronologically between those two Stoics. He
in behavior—something like Albert Einstein ends with the contrasting reception of Socra-
in contemporary U.S. popular culture. In tes by a pair of early Christian thinkers,
comedy, of course, his martyrdom was Augustine of Hippo (d. 420 CE), who
ignored. deemed the old Athenian’s daimonion truly a
In our book’s concluding Chapter 15 “demon’s” prompting, in a bad, unholy sense,
California-Berkeley Professor A. A. Long dis- whereas the earlier Justin Martyr (d. ca. 165
REVIEW 367

CE) admired and praised the Athenian as a the thirteenth article in this collection
good person, a Christian precursor whom book examines Socratic eudaimonism,
divine inspiration guided toward a glimpse of though without actual theology.
God’s truth, who rejected the numerous 2. This term of Socratic art is variously trans-
divinities that the Athenians worshipped— literated as elenchos or elenchus. It could also
false gods, true “demons.” be elenkhos. Different contributors to the
There the book ends, but hardly the leg- book under review use different spellings,
acy of Socrates! which I respect here and below. The word
Every chapter-article ends with a list of refers to the verbal testing of a statement
works cited, in several cases with a specific or of a moral or intellectual stance for its
bibliography or suggestions for further read- soundness—what, under Socrates’ verbal
ing. Each therefore is useful in itself for treat- probing, like a suspect tooth under a den-
ment of a sometimes controversial matter. tist’s with her or his little pick, it often
Downloaded by [Gothenburg University Library] at 14:40 13 October 2017

Editor Donald Morrison also provides a topi- lacks. Painfully to the victim!
cal bibliography, which itself acknowledges 3. Greek psuchē, “ghost” or (in religious and/
other more comprehensive bibliographic or philosophical application, “soul,” to
works. Especially valuable is a thirteen-page which certainly Socratic term Aristophanes
Index of Passages—of all the ancient literature alludes explicitly some years later in his
cited anywhere in the collection—inevitably masterpiece The Birds.
lots and lots of Plato, but much and many 4. Aristotle, whose take on tragedy is so
besides. influential, has misled many by his effective
nullification of the profound religious
dimension of the plays and their state-
NOTES cultic setting, part Carnival, part Passion
Week.
1. The Greek word for “happiness,” eudaimo- 5. Aristotle himself, however, took issue with
nia, suggests a fostering daimon/divinity; Plato, not with Socrates.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi