Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 68

War and Glory: The Myth of Spartan Militarism

By
Joshua Payne Trosch

Dr. William Bubelis, Thesis Advisor

A Thesis presented to
the Department of Classics,
Washington University in St. Louis
in partial fulfillment of the requirement of the degree of
Bachelor of Arts with Honors

March 26, 2015


Μολὼν λαβέ

2
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Introduction 4

Chapter One Thucydides Book One: Analyzing Military Enthusiasm 14


in the Vote for War

Chapter Two Herodotus Book Seven: Reconsidering Military Deference 28


at Thermopylae

Chapter Three Sparta’s Institutions: Why Sparta Went to War 44

Chapter Four Spartan Character: Sparta as an Inherently Fearful Polis 56

Conclusion 61

Bibliography 65

3
Introduction

The city-state of classical Sparta has played a pivotal role in shaping our

understanding of the Greek world. Located in the fertile watershed of the southern

Peloponnese, Sparta emerged as a regional hegemony, contributing significantly to the

political dynamic of the period. Its greatest contribution, however, is said to be its

participation in the famous military conflicts of the classical period.1 Sparta, after all, was

a military society, so defined by the laws set forth by its mythical lawgiver Lycurgus

some time in the eighth century BCE.2 Its institutions were designed to make the Spartan

phalanx an impenetrable wall of spears and shields. Behind these spears and shields stood

fearless Spartan men, each willing and ready to die selflessly for the perpetuity of Sparta,

each a paradigm of the principles and attitudes embodied by Lycurgus’ laws.3 It is

precisely this understanding of Sparta, this notion of a definitively military society in

which every Spartan man, woman, and child lived and died for the welfare of mother-

Sparta, which I aim to challenge. To this end, I will focus on a narrow facet of this

understanding, calling its historicity into question.

1
A significant portion of the surviving literature on Sparta in the classical period addresses its
role in either the Persian Wars or the Peloponnesian War in Herodotus’ Histories and Thucydides
History of the Peloponnesian War respectively. In these wars, Sparta was either a notable
military leader or a major player. See Cartledge, Sparta and Lakonia, 174.
2
Kennel, Spartans: A New History, 38-9. While the extent to which Lycurgus was a real person is
dubious, if he did exist it is likely he instituted his constitution at some point in or around the
eighth century, during which Sparta experienced a period of conquest and consolidation that
Kennel marks as the end of “legendary” Spartan history.
3
This is a general concept that, while noted in various forms in several sources, cannot be traced
to any one contemporary or ancient source. For contemporary evidence of this concept see
Section I of the Introduction.

4
In this thesis I challenge the notion that when Sparta decided upon war, this

decision was definitively militaristic. I understand this concept of militarism as an

“exaltation of military virtues and ideals.”4 These virtues and ideals may reasonably

include courage or bravery, preparedness, respect for one’s superiors, and honor to name

just a few. As such, I will narrow in on two primary consequences of this definition.

First, militarism presupposes a marked enthusiasm for war. This is to say that the

glorification of military virtues and ideals manifests as a love for or delight in the

inherent virtues of war and battle, such as bravery, an honorable death, or the joy of

combat. Second, this understanding of militarism presupposes deference to military

authority. In other words, the exaltation of military virtues and ideals, notably respect for

one’s superiors, incites one to concede or defer to the authority of military figures or

institutions. If the reasons Sparta provided for going to war resounded either with a sense

in which they delighted in the prospect of war or with a sense in which war was

undertaken because of military demands, then those reasons should be considered

characteristically militaristic.

I I start by identifying the reason why this thesis is being written. This

identification highlights both the way in which Sparta is perceived today as well as the

repercussions this skewed perception has for our understanding of Spartan society.

The problem this thesis faces is an understanding of Spartan society that depicts

Spartan decisions for war as definitively militaristic. Contemporary allusions to Sparta,

ranging from sports franchises to popular culture, betray this understanding. Michigan

State University, the seventh largest university in the United States, has the Spartan as its

4
Merriam-Webster Dictionary Online, s.v. “militarism,” accessed April 15, 2015,
http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/militarism.

5
athletic mascot. This choice of mascot is by no means arbitrary; the most prominent and

well-known sculpture on campus, called “The Spartan,” is of a tall, muscular man with

his hoplite helmet in hand. Fearless, he looks off with a stern expression into the distance.

The Spartan is ever ready and looking forward to the battle ahead. In this way, this piece

embodies the virtues of militarism with which Sparta is associated.

As comically inaccurate as it is, Frank Miller’s 1998 Graphic Novel 300 and Zack

Snyder’s 2006 film of the same name are highly indicative of the type of decision-making

that defines the myth of Spartan militarism. 5 In the 2006 film 300, there are numerous

instances indicative of this type of behavior from which one can choose, but perhaps the

most well known occurs roughly fifteen minutes into the film. King Leonidas, displeased

with a Persian emissary’s demand that Sparta pay tribute to Xerxes, kicks the emissary

down a bottomless pit in the center of Sparta herself. The king, still sweating from a

wrestling match that ended not a minute prior, warns the messenger that “Spartans have a

reputation to consider,” and forty-five seconds later he exclaims loudly, “this is Sparta!”

and proceeds to draw his sword and kick the messenger down the pit while Spartan

bystanders join in to liquidate the rest of the emissary’s party.6 One is left with the image

of a warrior king ever prepared for battle, short tempered, and fearless in the face of a

threat. King Leonidas does what Spartan reputation demands: he violently decides upon

war. 7

5
By and large the image it gives of Spartan society is a dramatic idealization. See Cartledge,
"Another View,” n.p. Also Ephraim, "Sparta? No. This is madness," n.p.
6
Miller, 300 #1. n.p.
7
One might suspect that this action is what is most indicative of militaristic behavior in the scene
in question, but Herodotus suggests that both the Athenians and the Spartans really did cast
Darius’ heralds into a pit. Therefore, while possibly interpreted as evidence for militarism, it may
in fact have been politically motivated-a way to match their Athenian rivals. See Purvis,
Landmark Herodotus, 539.

6
This understanding is tremendously problematic because it has repercussions both

for how we generally think about Sparta and for how we read about Sparta. Intuitively,

we should want to approximate historical truth in the study of classical history.

Moreover, this false conception instills a one-dimensional understanding of classical

Sparta, one that depicts Spartans as war-crazed. Therefore, failure to recognize the

dynamic nature of Spartan society, given the pivotal role Sparta played in the ancient

world, has implications for how we understand the classical period and the phenomenon

of the polis.

This conception of militarism acts as a distorting lens through which we read

staple authors, notably Herodotus and Thucydides, forcing us to wrongly transplant

militarism into their work. When reading Thucydides, for instance, many are quick to

claim that at times he is “buying into” a false-conception about Spartans.8 A closer

analysis of the text in accordance with considerations of historical circumstances,

however, reveals that this is not the case. We should not, therefore, think that

Thucydides intends to propagate the aforementioned false-conception. While there are,

no doubt, authors to whom this false conception can be attributed, Herodotus and

Thucydides perhaps should not be counted among them.

II The scholarly field concerned with debunking inaccurate understandings about

Sparta in general is known as the Spartan Mirage. While the Spartan Mirage is a

relatively young field of study and has only just taken off in the past two decades or so, it

contains a wealth of original research. This research has been largely successful in

8
Luraghi, "Thucydides and Spartan Power," 186-89. Luraghi suggests in his treatment on
political dynamics in Thucydides that while a superficial analysis suggests Thucydides was
“under the spell of the Spartan Mirage,” an in-depth analysis shows that he made a conscious
effort to avoid such false conceptions.

7
eroding the skewed understandings that have persisted for nearly two and a half

millennia.

Generally speaking, the Spartan Mirage is the notion that our understanding of

Spartan society is distorted. Upon its inception the Spartan Mirage alluded to a much

more specific historical concern. First posited by Francois Ollier in the 1930’s, the

Spartan Mirage (‘le mirage spartiate’) is a claim about how Greco-Roman Antiquity

idealized Sparta.9 Ollier’s concern was mainly that the authors of antiquity had offered a

largely inaccurate account of Spartan history, one that depicted Sparta as a purely

military society, with little consideration paid to other no less significant features of the

Spartan world. Ollier’s work focused on the extent to which these ancient authors

idealized Sparta as a sort of military utopia. These original Laconophiles include Plato,

Xenophon and Plutarch, figures of antiquity whose writings point to a marked

approbation for Sparta.10 The goal of the Spartan Mirage, then, was to call into question

the validity of the ancient sources, reasonably calling into question other classical sources

such as Aristotle, Herodotus, and Thucydides, from whom we similarly draw many of our

conclusions about Spartan society.11

Though the Spartan Mirage suffered a slight setback in the mid-twentieth century

with the rise of Nazism and the self-identification to the Spartan model made by the

Third Reich, it evolved in the later half of the twentieth century into a more general

9
Ollier, Le mirage spartiate, n.p.
10
Cartledge, "Introduction, ” 2. Both Plato, in his Laws, and Plutarch, in Parallel Lives, are
largely considered to be inspirations for this idealization.
11
Aristotle’s blatant dislike for Spartan society is by no means a new theme. Therefore, while one
cannot claim that he idealizes Sparta, he remains a source of information on Spartan society. For
a brief treatment of Aristotle’s criticism of Spartan institutions prior to the inception of the
Spartan Mirage see Sihler, "Aristotle's Criticisms of the Spartan Government," 439-43.

8
critique of both positive and negative idealizations of classical Sparta.12 This resurgence

was coupled both by the emergence of archaeological evidence that supported aspects of

the Spartan Mirage as well Elizabeth Rawson’s invaluable work on how distorted

understandings about Sparta have evolved over time.13 Therefore, what follows delves

into more recent work within the Spartan Mirage and its relevance to the question of

militarism.

Generally speaking, the specific branch of the Spartan Mirage with which this

thesis is concerned is associated with the inception of the International Sparta Seminar, a

series of annual conferences and publications started by Stephen Hodkinson and Anton

Powell that attempts to sift through the historical validity of the aforementioned positive

and negative idealizations. Of particular note to my research are the volumes, Sparta:

Comparative Approaches (2009), Sparta and War (2006), Spartan Society (2004), the

unaffiliated but related Property and Wealth in Classical Sparta (2009) by Hodkinson,

and The Shadow of Sparta (1994) edited by both Hodkinson and Powell. Each of these

volumes includes a collection of essays that address the historical validity of the ancient

textual or archeological sources as they relate to the titular question. Also worth noting

are Geoffrey de Ste. Croix and Paul Cartledge, the invaluable work of whom engages in

similar criticisms of false-conception of Spartan society. I maintain, however, that the

treatment within this thesis subscribes to the approach held by Hodkinson and Powell

more so than Ste. Croix or Cartledge, as the latter two argue in favor of retaining certain

perspectives on Spartan society that the former associate with a distorted understanding.14

12
Hodkinson, “Was Classical Sparta a Military Society?” 115-29.
13
Rawson, The Spartan Tradition, n.p. Rawson’s treatment of Spartan perception over time is an
invaluable source for understanding how dynamic and varied these understandings really were.
14
Hodkinson, introduction, xvi.

9
Hodkinson offers a roughly similar treatment to my own in Was Classical Sparta

a Military Society? (2006). While he touches on many of the same questions of textual

interpretation, he is largely concerned with the extent to which the various facets of

Spartan society were designed or modeled around a general military purpose. That is to

say, he analyzes the extent to which certain institutions or practices were indicative of a

state that was concerned almost exclusively with its military institutions. Therefore, all

other facets of Spartan society ought to exist for the benefit of these institutions. He

concludes ultimately that they did not. That being said, Hodkinson’s account does not

narrow in specifically on the nature of Sparta’s decisions to go to war, so while his

treatment is tremendously helpful, it acts only as a starting point from which I try to

address the problem of analyzing the militaristic nature of Sparta’s war decisions.15

I propose a two-pronged approach to solving the aforementioned problem. The

first horn of this approach is an in-depth textual analysis of the works of Herodotus and

Thucydides, notably those sections that address the decision to go to war, with the goal of

highlighting the extent to which the decision was militaristic.16 Because there are no

primary sources that survive from Sparta written by Spartans (save for a paltry number of

inscriptions), any account of the historical circumstances will rely primarily upon the

works of Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, Plato, and Aristotle, supplemented by the

16
An earlier version of this thesis included an analysis of the extent to which this is the case in
Xenophon’s Anabasis. It was ultimately removed because I felt that pointing to decisions in the
Anabasis that were not indicative of militarism would not contribute to the notion that we
wrongly impose this false conception upon ancient sources. Xenophon is rightly thought to be an
originator of this false conception in some capacity, so any treatment of this kind would not carry
much weight.

10
later work of Plutarch. The goal then is to draw sufficient evidence from both these

sources in favor of the notion that Spartans did not go to war for war’s sake.

The second horn of this approach involves an in-depth account of what reasons Sparta did

actually provide, if not militaristic ones, for going to war. Furthermore, it turns to what

reasons do we have to think that militarism, in itself, was fundamentally incompatible

with Spartan character.

A comprehensive analytical treatment of every decision to go to war found in

Herodotus or Thucydides would go well beyond the scope of this essay. Therefore, this

thesis will focus upon what I maintain to be those decisions that are typically perceived to

be highly indicative of militarism. For Thucydides, this decision is found in the Spartan

vote in Book One of the History of the Peloponnesian War, wherein the Spartans vote on

whether or not to enter into war with Athens. I am choosing this scene because of the

considerable amount of literature that has been devoted towards breaking down how

Thucydides means for his reader to understand Spartan character; there is a sense in

which Thucydides tries to speak to Spartan character in this particular scene.17 I will,

therefore, attempt to construct an analysis of the text that demonstrates the extent to

which this depiction of Spartan character is not in line with militarism.

For Herodotus, this decision is found in the choice to remain at Thermopylae in

Book Seven of the Histories. I am making this decision not by virtue of the quantity of

scholarly treatment, though significant, but because of the general legend that surrounds

this scene. The story of the last stand at Thermopylae is possibly one of the most well

known military last stands of all time. Its treatment in popular culture is immense,

17
Tigerstedt, The Legend of Sparta, 128-129. Hodkinson, “Was Classical Sparta a Military
Society?” 119.

11
having been subject to numerous books, films, poems, etc.18 Therefore, the argument that

it is not, after all, indicative of militarism, will have greater weight than other lesser

known scenes.

III This thesis is divided into four chapters. The goal of this brief section is to

explain what each Chapter entails.

The purpose of Chapters One and Two is to offer an in-depth textual analysis of

the works of Herodotus and Thucydides respectively, notably those sections that address

the decision to go to war, with the goal of highlighting the extent to which militarism is

not present. Therefore, in Chapter Two I look at the extent to which Thucydides, in the

Spartan vote in Book I, believes the Spartan decision was militaristic with reference to

Spartan enthusiasm for war. It argues that the vote to go to war was formatted in such a

way as to sway the outcome. Furthermore, there is no reason to think that the apparent

militarism the scene demonstrates is, according to Thucydides, a unique Spartan feature.

In Chapter Two I look at the extent to which Herodotus characterizes the Spartan

decision to remain at Thermopylae as militaristic in reference to deference to war. It

argues that the Spartans did not remain at Thermopylae out of a sense of military

deference, but out of a sense of moral obligation. We have no reason to think that

Herodotus believed this sense of obligation was uniquely Sparta. And finally, the

reasoning underlying the decision to remain is unrelated to militarism.

The purpose of Chapter Three is to offer an in-depth account of what reasons

Sparta did actually provide, if not militaristic ones, for going to war. Therefore, Chapter

Three approaches this account at the institutional level, analyzing the extent to which the

18
I could not even attempt to create an exhaustive list of examples. A quick Internet search of
“Thermopylae” reveals the extent to which this is the case.

12
institutions of Spartan society, outside its military institutions, were indicative of

militarism. It argues that an analysis of the roles and workings of Sparta’s institutions

reveals that their behavior was far from militaristic. Rather, when they decided to go to

war they did so out of their own varied political, economic, or religious interests, not out

of an exaltation of military virtues or ideals. One might argue that Sparta’s institutions

are not indicative of larger social militarism, which is why Chapter Four offers a brief

treatment on the extent to which Spartan character was incompatible with militarism; it

should not be considered the case that the Spartan populace exalted military virtue.

Therefore, the reader should take away the following notion: Classical Sparta was

not a monolith. It was, like many other poleis, a highly dynamic society, one comprised

of men and women with very much the same worries, ambitions, and fears as one might

expect to find elsewhere. Generally speaking, when Sparta decided upon war it did not

do so militaristically, giving us no reason to think that Spartans were in any hurry to

sacrifice their lives for war and the glory it might offer. By engaging the narrow question

of militarism, I hope to contribute to a discipline that has fundamentally altered the way

we understand classical Sparta today.

13
Thucydides Book One: Analyzing Sparta’s Military Enthusiasm in the Vote
for War

In Book One of his history of the Peloponnesian War, Thucydides depicts a scene

during which Sparta formally declares war against the growing Athenian superpower

(1.79-87). The staple features of this scene are the speeches given by Archidamus, a

Spartan King, and Sthenelaidas, an Ephor, respectively. Thucydides holds that before

these speeches were given the Spartans had decided, after hearing from both the

Corinthians and Athenians, upon war against Athens. At the same time, however,

Thucydides alludes to the possibility that in the instant war was declared Sthenelaidas

intentionally skewed the voting process through means of a non-anonymous, standing

vote. In other words, Thucydides points to a certain degree of hesitation and political

conflict in the decision made amongst the Spartans. It may be worthwhile, then, to

further analyze Thucydides' illustration of Spartan military enthusiasm in light of his

decision to highlight this specific instance. To this end, this chapter aims to answer the

following questions: How does Thucydides define what is and is not considered a facet of

Spartan military ideology at certain key moments? And, why does Thucydides pick this

specific scene to go about doing so?

I A vital moment for the sake of defining Thucydides' perception of Spartan

military ideology is that in which Sthenelaidas calls for a standing rather than oral vote

14
amongst the Spartans and the decision to go to war is subsequently pronounced.

Militarism assumes that Spartans are accordingly eager for any and all military

opportunities, delighting in the prospect of engaging in battle. At the same time, the way

in which Sthenelaidas goes about procuring the Spartan vote for war might suggest an

alternative interpretation of Sparta’s military ideology. Therefore, Thucydides challenges

the notion that the Spartans are enthusiastic for war, pointing to the appearance of

military enthusiasm in this particular moment as a consequence of deception, not

militarism.

The notion that the Spartans are enthusiastic for war stems in part from Spartan

traditions associated with song and libation. One such poem recorded by Tyrtaeus reads,

For 'tis a fair thing for a good man to fall and die fighting in the van for his
native land... let us fight with a will for this land, and die for our children and
never spare our lives. (Lycurg, Leocr. 107, 1-2, 9-10) 19

This passage suggests that the Spartans consider death in battle, amongst all other

alternatives, to be the most glorious passing a Spartan might achieve – the military, ideal

way to die. Certainly, then, when faced with the option of going to war, according to this

passage, a Spartan would be compelled to pursue it for glory's sake, choosing to fight

rather than to spare his own life in peace. On those traditions emerging from the Spartan

constitution itself, Xenophon points to the penalties associated with cowardice. He holds

that the constitution was framed in such a way that those who cower from war are held in

disgrace, socially ostracized from their fellow Spartans.20 One might conclude, then, that

19
Edmonds, Elegy and Iambus, Lycurg. 1-2, 9-10.
20
Dillon and Garland, Documents, 6.15, 9.1-6. Ostracism is not to be taken literally, as it refers to
an exclusion from Spartan institutions such as the messes, political office, and at times citizenship
(e.g. the battle of Sphakteria - 13.11 Thucy. 4.27-28.5, 38.5-39.9.)

15
the Spartans who, when faced with possible disgrace should their unwillingness to go to

war become apparent, voted for war following Sthenelaidas' call for an standing vote did

so out of this fear of social ostracism. Upon being forced to stand, to make his vote

public, no man would, in accordance with this reasoning, vote against war.21 Also,

Xenophon was an Athenian. Therefore, one might assume that Thucydides, also an

Athenian and a contemporary of Xenophon, understood this cultural perception, this

virtue of Spartan courage. This does not imply, however, that he believed it was a

definitive and practiced part of Spartan military ideology overall. What follows, then,

addresses another possible facet of Spartan military ideology, deceit.

A number of authors, among them Aristophanes and Xenophon, allude to this

notion of Spartan deceitfulness in their own writings. In Peace, Aristophanes depicts the

Spartans as tricksters, frequently comparing them to sly foxes and wolves. Furthermore,

this is not traditionally viewed, he holds, as one of the Spartans' better qualities. He

alludes to a number of characters in Acharnians, Peace, and Lysistrata who are depicted

as deceitful, and all of whom act as hindrances to the protagonist. Furthermore, these

characters are considered warlike; the choruses of old men found in Lysistrata, for

example, illustrate this implicit, associative relationship between deceit and warlike

behavior.22 This allusion might suggest that where there is deceit involved, it is usually

used for the purpose of inciting military action. Xenophon alludes to those practices in

the agoge that taught Spartan boys to be deceitful. This notion of deceit goes hand in

hand with preparing boys to be more "warlike."23 This notion, consequently, becomes

21
While the final vote for war was not unanimous, Thucydides notes that it was a decided
majority (1.87)
22
Harvey, "Lacomica,” 38-39.
23
Dillon and Garland, Documents, 6.49, 2.1-8.

16
cemented in these young boys' minds, implying that they are defined as such in their later

years in service to Sparta both as soldiers and state leaders. Therefore, deceit was not

necessarily perceived by the Spartans to be an evil. Rather, it was a Spartan privilege to

be admired by virtue of their freedom to do so as granted by their constitution.24 The

two aforementioned authors, however, were Athenian. Therefore, Thucydides likely

adopted this notion of deceit, and, as will be discussed shortly, applied it accordingly.

Having now established the role deceit might play in Spartan military ideology, this paper

turns to analyzing how Thucydides characterizes the ideology behind this moment.

Thucydides points to this deceitfulness in his depiction as the single possible facet

of Spartan military ideology behind Sthenelaidas' decision to skew the vote and influence

the subsequent decision. Within the narrative itself, Thucydides states that Sthenelaidas

claimed he could not distinguish whether the oral vote was overall for war, and as such,

he required each voter to literally rise and move to a certain spot that was designated for

or against it. His thinking, however, was quite different:

ἀλλὰ βουλόμενος αὐτοὺς φανερῶς ἀποδεικνυμένους τὴν γνώμην


ἐς τὸ πολεμεῖν μᾶλλον ὁρμῆσαι.

wanting to make the Spartans declare themselves openly and urge them on more
effectively to war. (1.87.2) 25

Thucydides' notion of deceit, itself not too dissimilar from those articulated earlier, holds

that Spartans often think one thing and say or do another. Sthenelaidas is doing exactly

that, thinking that a standing vote will incite this false eagerness and saying, essentially,

24
Harvey, "Lacomica," 285. Plutarch points to the alleged slogan, "no word goes beyond those
doors" (Lyk.12). Also, "When someone accused a Spartan of lying, he replied: 'that's right. We
are free men..." (Plut. Mor. 234f).
25
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 131.

17
that he hasn't the best ear.26 I stipulated earlier that a fear of social ostracism might have

prompted the voters to vote yes; Sthenelaidas was counting on this fear. If this is the case

then it suggests that the Spartans were not initially set upon war, as Sthenelaidas felt the

need to deceive them, to make their votes public, in order to incite this eagerness. This

next section, then, addresses the question of whether or not this notion of military

enthusiasm is displayed by either of the two speakers in question.

II This paper moves now to the speeches of Archidamus and Sthenelaidas

respectively. Thucydides asserts that immediately following the speech given by the

Athenian emissary, the Spartans had already decided upon war:

καὶ τῶν μὲν πλεόνων ἐπὶ τὸ αὐτὸ αἱ γνῶμαι ἔφερον, ἀδικεῖν τε τοὺς
Ἀθηναίους ἤδη καὶ πολεμητέα εἶναι ἐν τάχει.27

The opinions of the majority all led to the same conclusion; the Athenians were
open aggressors, and war must be declared at once. (1.79.2)28

He offers no evidence, however, to support this claim; there is nothing resembling an

early vote, and if there was he chose to exclude it. Therefore, it is possible that he

included this stipulation for the sake of setting up the aforementioned speeches in an

attempt to further demonstrate how an eagerness for battle was innately anti-Spartan.

Thucydides' depiction of Archidamus points to a picture of Spartan military

ideology built upon a degree of calculated reasoning. It should be noted that Archidamus

was not entirely against the prospect of war with Athens, only against the rashness with

26
Bradford, "The duplicitous Spartan," 71.
27
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 130.
28
Crawley, The Peloponnesian War, 1.79.2.

18
which the Spartans wanted to proceed. He argues, rather, that the Spartans should

exhaust possible diplomatic solutions before declaring war:

ἀλλὰ ὅπλα μὲν μήπω κινεῖν,πέμπειν δὲ καὶ αἰτιᾶσθαι.

But do not take up arms yet. Let us first send and complain to them. (1.82.1)29

The reasons Archidamus might argue as such are twofold. First, he asserts (1.84.1) that

the Spartans must exercise βράδυ (‘slowness’) when considering such an issue.30 The

Spartan sense of discipline that emerges by virtue of their military training fosters this

notion; a slow, calculated approach towards war is, or should be considered, inherently

Spartan.31 At the same time, however, he urges the Spartans to prepare for war

nonetheless:

κάν τούτῳ καὶ τὰ ἡμέτερ᾽ αὐτῶν ἐξαρτύεσθαι.

we should make our own preparations. (182.1)32

This preparation does not refer, however, to mobilization, but rather, to fundraising, as

Sparta lacked the financial means by which, according to Archidamus, they might

successfully challenge the Athenian superpower. It is worth noting that military

preparation should be considered a staple military virtue. Therefore, if we are to think

that Archidamus’ proposal is indicative of Spartan military ideology, then we might think

29
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 127.
30
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 128.
31
Wassermann, "The Speeches of King Archidamus,” 195-196. This approach may, however,
have run counter to Spartan military success, as it led to missed military opportunities (1.8.96, 5).
32
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 127 Hornblower points out that
Archidamus' assertion that the Spartan finances were inadequate at the time is historically
accurate (Greek World, 101, 127).

19
that this is a sign of militarism. If that is the case, however, then it only supports the

notion that the decision to go to war was not militaristic, as the Spartan vote is ultimately

against Archidamus. That being said, I talked earlier about how the nature of the

standing vote might have skewed the results, leading the Spartans to a decision that they

otherwise would not have made - in this case, to decide upon war while unprepared.

Could it be said, therefore, that the Spartans, generally speaking, exalt military

preparedness? That the Spartans were not prepared for war with Athens might suggest

that they did not exalt this military virtue. It is not as though the Athenian superpower

simply appeared one day, but rather it had grown slowly over time. Therefore, that

Sparta did not adequately equip itself in light of the emergence of the Athenian

hegemony might speak against military preparedness as a facet of Spartan military

ideology.

The second reason, then, as to why Archidamus argues for an alternative solution

is that he is aware of the eagerness for battle inherent in the young Spartans, a feature

distinct from what Thucydides considers to be definitively Spartan, and proposes a

diplomatic solution with the possibility in mind that should no peace be possible it would

still allow the Spartans time to adequately prepare for the inevitable confrontation.33

What follows is Thucydides' case that Sthenelaidas' speech, itself arguing for immediate

military response, is not in line with Spartan military ideology.

Sthenelaidas' speech, then, unlike that of Archidamus, appeals to the Spartans'

emotions rather than their reason. While his speech is primarily a response to that given

by the Athenians, it does respond to Archidamus' to a point, addressing the

aforementioned notion of slowness, or delay:


33
Wassermann, "The Speeches of King Archidamus in Thucydides," 195

20
οὐδὲ μελλήσομεν τιμωρεῖν: οἱ δ᾽ οὐκέτι μέλλουσι κακῶς πάσχειν.

we will not... put off [lit. 'delay'] helping them, for they cannot put off their
troubles. (1.86.2) 34

He turns the question of slowness away from declaring war against Athens to aiding their

allies, making the question more about prompt allied support than open war against

Athens. As such, he appeals to the audiences' sympathy; he essentially urges them to

help those who cannot help themselves. His careful choice of words, “ἀγαθοί “(1.86.3)

and “ἀξίως “(1.86.5), further moralizes his case, in which case their repetition serves that

end.35 His goal, one may infer, was to reignite whatever moral indignations were

apparent prior to Archidamus' speech, hoping to invigorate the Spartans with a sense of

military eagerness that was otherwise dissipated by Archidamus' traditional Spartan

approach. Why exactly Sthenelaidas sought to challenge Archidamus and traditional

Spartan military ideology, however, will come up in the following section of this paper.

The question remains, however, as to why Thucydides believes one speaker

represents what is typically considered in line with a Spartan military ideology and

another does not. One might argue that there is, perhaps, a change in the notion itself, a

shift from a traditional ideology towards the ideology preached by Sthenelaidas. The

answer might be found in Archidamus' case for caution in aiding their allies:

μόνοι γὰρ δι᾽αὐτὸ εὐπραγίαις τε οὐκ ἐξυβρίζομεν καὶ ξυμφοραῖς


ἧσσον ἑτέρων εἴκομεν.

34
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 131.
35
Smith, The Peloponnesian War, 146. In the context of “brave” allies (186.3). “Deserving or
befitting' the dignity of Sparta” (1.86.5). See Allison, June, "Sthenelaidas' Speech," 12,14.

21
it is a policy which has saved us from growing insolent in prosperity or giving
way under adversity, like other men. (1.84.2)36

He argues against rushing to the aid of their allies without careful thought and for the sole

purpose of satisfying their own vanity and their own desires for glory and success. The

reason this is so vital is that it serves in opposition to what he holds are Athenian, or

generally non-Spartan, characteristics. Athens is thus insolent by virtue of their military

success, as they go to war for vanity's sake. 37 For that reason, the Spartans must be

different, must maintain their military ideology. This is not to say, as will be discussed

shortly, that the two states always act consistently as opposites, only that Archidamus is,

in this instance and according to Thucydides, a paragon of Spartan military leadership.

III There is no evidence to place Thucydides in Sparta at the time at which these

speeches were given. Therefore, the goal here is to discern why Thucydides might have

chosen to include this specific scene in his critique of Spartan military ideology, to

pinpoint what made this instance so vital to this end. The parallel that emerges in light of

the Sicilian Expedition of Book VI suggests that Thucydides presented much of the

content up to this point as what the characters ought to have said in accordance with his

critique, as I shall hope to show below.

Both the instance in question and the debates preceding the Sicilian Expedition

mark the beginning of two separate phases in the war. The first phase, the Archidamian,

was defined by Spartan invasions into Attic territory. The second phase was itself

36
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III, 128. This policy is one of
‘σωφροσύνη,' prudence, (1.84.2) in light of military success or failure.
37
Wassermann, "The Speeches of King Archidamus in Thucydides," 195, 196. "Ruthless
ambition," "self-assured pride of the Athenians."

22
defined by the aforementioned expedition. Alcibiades, the Athenian statesmen and

general, makes the same case for war as offered previously by Sthenelaidas:

ἐπειδή γε καὶ ξυνωμόσαμεν.

we have sworn to help them. (6.18.1) 38

The priority, again, lies in the allies who have appealed to the regional power, Athens in

this case, for aid. One may posit that Thucydides made this notion of aiding their allies a

staple aspect of each speech for the purpose of highlighting these parallel appeals.

Similarly, Nicias, also an Athenian statesmen and general, argues against haste:

ὥστε καὶ χρήμασι καὶ τοῖς σώμασιν ηὐξῆσθαι.

so as to recruit our strength both in money and in men. (6.12.1) 39

Again, the case is not made entirely against war, only against immediate declaration and

mobilization on the grounds that the state lacks sufficient resources.40 One may surmise,

then, that Thucydides chose these two strikingly similar scenes to demonstrate how each

state reacts, or would have reacted in accordance with their respective military ideologies,

when faced with similar situations. What follows, then, is why Thucydides depicts these

four speakers as he does.

38
Hornblower, Simon, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books 5.25-8.109, 350. “them” are the
Egesta.
39
Smith, The Peloponnesian War: Books V and VI, 204.
40
Westlake, "Nicias in Thucydides," 61. Thucydides disagrees with Nicias' assertion that the state
is ill-prepared for war (6.26.2), suggesting he is not a complete parallel of Archidamus, whom
Thucydides appears to hold in higher regard.

23
The parallel offered by the Sicilian Expedition points to a repeating notion of

political conflict between the two pairs of focal speakers. This notion is perhaps best

demonstrated by Thucydides' depiction of Alcibiades' political relation to Nicias:

ὢν καὶ ἐς τἆλλα διάφορος τὰ πολιτικὰ.

who was always his political enemy. (6.15.2) 41

Thucydides point to a rivalry between the two speakers, suggesting that much of what he

credits them with saying is likely shaped to adhere to this fact.42 Therefore, Alcibiades'

case for war was less perhaps out of his own warmongering insomuch as it was an

attempt to challenge Nicias. If in fact this urgency on Alcibiades' part to go to war was

politically inspired, how might the earlier situation at Sparta be perceived as parallel?

This answer lies in how the speakers appeal to their respective audiences. Both Nicias

and Archidamus are depicted as having appealed to reason, both well aware of the glory

and fame young men associated with military incursions; yet still, they urge patience:

ὥστε μήτε ἀπειρίᾳ ἐπιθυμῆσαί τινα τοῦ ἔργου,ὅπερ ἂν οἱ πολλοὶ πάθ

οιεν (1.80.1) ... καίτοι ἔγωγε καὶ τιμῶμαι ἐκ τοῦ τοιούτου.

41
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books 5.25-8.109, 338.
42
Westlake, H D, "Nicias in Thucydides," 61. Nicias may have only agreed to lead the expedition
despite his reservations as a result of this rivalry (Cohen, op. cit 233) though it is more likely he
feared further damaging his reputation at home.

24
no one of them, therefore, is eager for war through lack of experience, as would

be the case with most men... and yet I get honour from this sort of thing'

(1.80.1, 6.9.2)43

The reason they fail, then, is that they address the virtues held by the older members of

their audience. 44 Granted, if both make a similar case, is Nicias, then, acting like a

Spartan? At the same time, Sthenelaidas and Alcibiades appeal to emotion, and while

Thucydides offers nothing that directly states that Sthenelaidas was out to ingratiate his

name, his argument, or rather pandering, for war would no doubt ingratiate himself with

the lust for war Archidamus articulates just prior to his speech. Therefore, is

Sthenelaidas acting like an Athenian, in accordance with what Archidamus previously

argued? One may conclude, then, that political ambitions and subsequent discourse are

largely responsible for instilling an eagerness for battle insofar as this is what Thucydides

depicts. If this is in fact the case, what follows addresses the possibility that any notions

of Spartan or Athenian military ideology are strictly nominal.

The two previous discussions in this section point, then, to a larger picture,

namely, a notion that the facets of military ideology that have been the focus of this

chapter up to this point are universal. This is evident in Nicias' declaration that no one

who is against the war ought to vote for it to maintain his or her own appearance, to bend

to social pressures and μὴ καταισχυνθῆναι, ‘not to be ashamed’ (6.13.1).45 As

43
Smith, History of The Peloponnesian War: Books I and II, 134. Archidamus refers to the men
of his own generation in the audience. Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books 5.25-
8.109, 325. This is the “honor” that comes from leading a military expedition.
44
Wassermann, "The Speeches of King Archidamus in Thucydides," 195.
45
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books 5.25-8.109, 335. This alludes to the fear of
appearing a coward to their fellow Athenians should they agree the expedition to be impractical

25
previously discussed, Thucydides holds that Sthenelaidas called for a non-anonymous

vote with the intention that such a vote would compel people to vote for the war; they

would vote out of fear of being thought a coward. Nicias recognizes this to be a common

problem, as the Athenians appear to be just as prone. After Alcibiades speaks, Nicias

makes a second plea to the Athenians. This plea, however, is a ploy of deceit. He

stresses the magnitude of military force needed to secure a victory in hopes of

discouraging the Athenians:

οὐ ναυτικῆς καὶ φαύλου στρατιᾶς μόνον δεῖ.

more is needed than an insignificant naval force. (6.21.1) 46

His plan backfires:

πολὺ δὲ μᾶλλον ὥρμηντο.

they were more eager than ever. (6.24.2) 47

Nicias tells the Athenians he is in support of the war if all the necessary, and

uncommonly extensive, preparations are made, while at the same time intending for them

to forfeit their eagerness in light of the seemingly impossible task ahead. One may

conclude, then, that Thucydides chose these two scenes to demonstrate that the facets of

'military ideology' associated with each state are, in the end, common human traits.

46
Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides: Books 5.25-8.109, 357.
47
Ibid., 360. Hornblower notes that while it may seem odd to send Nicias, having just protested
against the war, in command of the expedition, (26.1) it could be that his hesitation, his apparent
humility, perhaps, served as a counter to Athenian impiety scandals

26
The discussion up to this point suggests that Thucydides was trying to highlight

an entirely different set of qualities inherent in all military ideologies. Amongst these are

fear and ambition, two qualities that Thucydides' speakers, no doubt by virtue of their

being human and further attesting to his skill as an historian, possess. Therefore, we

should not think that, according to Thucydides, militarism, understood as a marked

eagerness or enthusiasm for war, is in line with Spartan military ideology. Therefore,

what follows in the following chapter addresses the passive type of militarism posited in

my Introduction, narrowing in upon Leonidas’ last stand at Thermopylae.

27
Herodotus Book Seven: Reconsidering Military Deference at Thermopylae

In Book Seven of the Histories Herodotus describes the reasoning underlying

Leonidas’ decision not to abandon Thermopylae upon learning of Ephialtes’ treachery

(7.219-234). Herodotus condones the decision to fight, and it is the praise of this

sacrifice that is so often interpreted as proof that Herodotus recognizes the unique

militarism that is definitive of Spartan behavior in the eyes of some.48 However,

Herodotus’ account for Leonidas’ reasoning is not so simple, as he notes a number of

external factors that conceivably weighed upon Leonidas’ decision to remain. It will,

therefore, be worthwhile to explore the extent to which Herodotus offers the type of

praise that is so often interpreted as indicative of supporting a militaristic conception of

Spartan behavior. To this end, this chapter aims to answer the following questions: What

allegedly militaristic characteristic is it exactly that Herodotus seems to be praising in the

Spartans? And, what reasons do we have to think that, in fact, this characteristic is not

intended to be a reflection of Spartan militarism?

48
See discussion on 300 film and militarism in Introduction. Also see Chapter Four for the
implicit connection between militarism and the notion of a “beautiful death.”

28
I Unlike the scene in the Chapter One, there is no apparent hesitation among the

Spartans in their decision to remain at Thermopylae. Herodotus presents his reader with

resolute Spartan men, who are set in their decision to die. However, the degree to which

he is praising them for their militarism, and their decision to remain for the reward of war

itself, ought to be considered contentious. Therefore, this section looks to identify what

characteristic it is, precisely, that Herodotus holds in such high regard.

Herodotus notes the composure and wit of the Spartans in the face of their

inevitable doom. He highlights Leonidas’ composure upon allowing the allied Greeks to

leave:

ταύτῃ καὶ μᾶλλον τὴν γνώμην πλεῖστος εἰμί, Λεωνίδην, ἐπείτε


ᾔσθετο τοὺς συμμάχους ἐόντας ἀπροθύμους καὶ οὐκ ἐθέλοντας
συνδιακινδυνεύειν,κελεῦσαι σφέας ἀπαλλάσσεσθαι, αὐτῷ δὲ ἀπιέναι
οὐ καλῶς ἔχειν: μένοντι δὲ αὐτοῦ κλέος μέγα ἐλείπετο.

I, however, tend to believe that when Leonidas perceived that the allies were
dispirited and unwilling to run all risks with him, he told then to depart. For
himself, however, it was not good to leave; if he remained, he would leave a name
of great fame. (7.220.2)49

Faced with such impossible odds, Leonidas, having already elected to remain, might have

entreated his allies to stay in order to increase the odds of survival or delay the inevitable.

However, Leonidas, aware that the allies want to leave, simply allows them to do so.

Without objection, he accepts his fate, and rather than risking the lives of others he

calmly allows the allies to leave, showing no signs of the fearful pleading that one might

otherwise expect. That being said, he is cognizant of the glory that comes with such a

49
Godley, Histories, 7.220.2.

29
sacrifice. Therefore, seeing that his allies are afraid, he does not bother trying to reassure

them. He wants to keep the glory for his own name. In this way, he acts rather selfishly -

hardly an object of praise, particularly in the military sphere. Granted one might argue

that this selfish desire for glory, which is so extreme that he refuses to share it with the

allies, is in fact a mark of militarism, for he pursues battle because he values the military

ideal of glory in battle. However, Herodotus’ use of κλέος suggests that this is not the

case. He is aware of how his death would affect his name or story into perpetuity, but he

does not seem to pursue glory, understood as a military ideal, for glory in and if itself, but

rather he pursues it for his own sake or his name’s sake. In other words, he does not exalt

military glory but the notion that this sacrifice will benefit his memory; glory here is the

means, not the end. Therefore, even if Herodotus is praising Leonidas’ composure in the

face of death, this composure is not a mark of militarism.

Herodotus’ most famous reference to Spartan wit comes in the form of Dienekes’

clever response to a Trachinian’s warning about the Persian missile barrage. Dienekes

says in a speech before the Greeks that his response to this warning was the following:

εἰ ἀποκρυπτόντων τῶν Μήδων τὸν ἥλιον ὑπὸ σκιῇ ἔσοιτο πρὸς


αὐτοὺς ἡ μάχη καὶ οὐκ ἐν ἡλίῳ.

If the Medes hid the sun, they could fight them in the shade instead of in the sun.
(7.226.2).50

He means to suggest that the Medic missile/arrow barrage will provide shade for the

Greeks to fight under, granting them relief from the hot Greek sun. Furthermore,

50
Godley, Histories, 7.226.2.

30
Herodotus praises this instance of courageous behavior (7.226.1).51 Like composure in

the face of death, Laconic wit could be treated as a staple militaristic, Spartan

characteristic. It reflects an enthusiasm for war insofar as the playfulness of laconic wit

suggests not only that the Spartans were composed in the face of death and battle but that

they delighted in and enjoyed the prospect of the coming battle. Insofar as Dienekes’

joke is concerned, it humorously implies that the Spartans were, in fact, looking forward

to the battle, as it would offer them relief from the sun. It is not clear, however, that

Herodotus draws any connection between Laconic wit and militarism. Herodotus offers

numerous examples of Laconic wit in the Histories.52 However, he gives us little reason

to think that this wit is a virtue of Sparta’s military ideology, having said almost nothing

about Spartan military education. In contrast to the notion that Spartans are simple-

headed, narrow-minded military machines, Plato maintains that the Spartans are in fact

very clever, and one should not be inclined to think that Spartan education is devoid of

training in rhetoric and philosophy.53 If Herodotus agrees with Plato, then we should be

hesitant to draw any connection between Laconic wit and militarism, as one should not

confuse their natural tendency to jest with an eagerness for battle. Many of the other

witty expressions from Thermopylae do not come from Herodotus but from Simonides

and ultimately figures like Plutarch, including the latter’s report of a saying made famous

by its association with the battle, Μολὼν λαβέ (‘come and take them!’) (Apoph. 51.11).54

Therefore, while Plutarch’s proclivity to include Laconic wit in military situations might

point to an association between wit and enthusiasm for war, the same cannot be

51
Ibid., 7.226.1.
52
Godley, Histories, 3.46. The Spartans mock a plea from the Samians, dismissing their analogy
of a bag “wanting” flour.
53
Plato, “Protagoras,” 342b, d-3.
54 Plutarch, Moralia, apoph. 51.1.

31
confidently said of Herodotus. Of course, even if one is to entertain the possibility that

Herodotus believes that telling this joke reflects an excitement for war and a sincere

enthusiasm for the battle ahead, it has no bearing on the actual decision to go to war. In

other words, even if he both praises Spartan wit and sees it as a reflection of the joy the

Spartans find in battle, it cannot be said that the Spartans have chosen to face such a

death because they were witty. Rather, they were witty because they just chose to face

such a death.

II The militaristic characteristic with which Herodotus is concerned is a sense of

obligation. One might argue that he praises the extent to which the decision to remain is

motivated by an obligation to defer to military authority. That is to say, the Spartans

remain at the Hot Gates, choose to fight the Persians despite certain doom, because they

adhere unquestionably to their military command. I maintain, however, that this is a

misconception and that while the Spartans do remain out of a sense of obligation, this

obligation does not stem from militarism. Herodotus states that some believe Leonidas

allows the allies to leave because he did not think it fitting for the Spartans to desert their

post at the Hot-Gates:

αὐτῷ δὲ καὶ Σπαρτιητέων τοῖσι παρεοῦσι οὐκ ἔχειν εὐπρεπέως


ἐκλιπεῖν τὴν τάξιν ἐς τὴν ἦλθον φυλάξοντες ἀρχήν .

but felt it not fitting for himself and the Spartans to desert that post which they
had come to defend at the beginning. (7.220.1)55

Their post is their military assignment. They were sent by Sparta to defend the Hot-Gates,

and they cannot stray from that command regardless of the circumstances. In other

55
Godley, Histories, 7.220.1.

32
words, this deferral to military authority, to their assigned post, reflects an unwavering

obligation to the battle at hand.

This notion of obedience or deferral appears again in the epitaph of Simonides

that Herodotus quotes, but we find here reason to doubt that Herodotus is concerned,

specifically, with military authority. The epitaph of Simonides reads:

“ὦ ξεῖν᾽, ἀγγέλλειν Λακεδαιμονίοις ὅτι τῇδε

κείμεθα τοῖς κείνων ῥήμασι πειθόμενοι” (7.228.2)56

Frank Miller, in his graphic novel 300, provides a translation of this verse that reads:

Go tell the Spartans, passerby, that here

by Spartan law we lie.57

While ῥῆμα translates roughly to ‘something spoken,’ different variations of this epitaph,

including one by Strabo, replace ῥῆμα with νομίμοις (‘comfortable to custom’),

corroborating a translation closer to obedience to law.58 However, there is no reason to

think that Leonidas was legally bound to remain at Thermopylae in light of such

unfavorable odds.59 As such, in an attempt to avoid reading into Herodotus through the

lens of later interpretations, I posit that we should understand ῥῆμα prima facie as

alluding to what the Spartans were told to do – their military orders. I maintain,

therefore, that this epigraph was intended to be sarcastic. Unlike the epitaph to Megistias

(7.228.3), it is written in the first person and, therefore, is meant to be read in the voice of

56
Godley, Histories, 7.228.2.
57
Miller, 300 #5, n.p.
58
Macan, Herodotus, 7.228.2. Cicero (Tusc. 1. 42. 101) offers the translation,
“dic hospes Spartae, nos te hic vidisse iacentes, dum sanctis patriae legibus obsequimur.”
59
Grant, "Leonidas' Last Stand," 15.

33
a Spartan. Furthermore, this graphic epitaph is briefer and arguably terser than the

Megistias epitaph, as the former expresses the same information as the latter, albeit in

less words; it tells us who died (the Spartans; Megistias), where they died (we lie here;

Slain by the Medes who crossed the Spercheius river), and why they merit such an honor

(obedient to their commands; The seer knew well his coming doom, / But endured not to

abandon the leaders of Sparta) (7.228.2-3).60 Finally, I noted earlier in this chapter that

Herodotus praises laconic wit. Therefore, the epitaph’s perspective, brevity, and

terseness lend credence to the view that it is another example of laconic wit. This is to

suggest that the Spartans found humorous the idea that military orders would incite them

to undertake such a sacrifice. If anything, the Spartan decision disregards military

authority. The Spartans act in such a way that runs contrary to the interests of their

military. Their defeat, which Herodotus tells us they are sure will come, means the loss

of at least three hundred highly trained Spartan soldiers, the loss of several officers and

captains to be sure, and the loss of a King. None of these, one might assume, are assets

the Spartan military would be keen to lose in a single battle, particularly one that can be

avoided. Therefore, if the Spartans remained out of a sense of obligation, it was not an

obligation to military authority but to their own convictions.

The notion that the Spartans had a tendency to disregard military authority

appears in later authors, such Plutarch, giving credence to the view that the Spartans were

not concerned with military interests when they decided to remain at Thermopylae.

Plutarch says of the tendency of Spartan men to sneak out to see their wives,

καὶ τὸ λοιπὸν οὕτως ἔπραττε, τοῖς μὲν ἡλικιώταις συνδιημερεύων


καὶ συναναπαυόμενος, πρὸς δὲ τὴν νύμφην κρύφα μετ᾽ εὐλαβείας
60
Godley, histories, 7.228.2-3.

34
φοιτῶν, αἰσχυνόμενος καὶ δεδοικὼς μή τις αἴσθοιτο τῶν ἔνδον

And so he continued to do from that time on, spending his days with his
comrades, and sleeping with them at night, but visiting his bride by stealth and
with every precaution, full of dread and fear lest any of her household should be
aware of his visits. (Lyc. 15.4)61

He makes it clear that this is by no means an encouraged act, as the couples fear the very

real repercussions of their actions should they be caught. Still, this disregard for military

authority, disregard for the military rules that dictate their sleeping arrangements, speaks

to the argument that the Spartans, despite their military institutions, acted on fairly

universal urges, in this instance, love and lust – and in the other instance, honor.

Granted, one might argue that the aforementioned convictions are definitively,

uniquely Spartan. Herodotus argues that part of the reason Leonidas sends the allies

away is so that the Spartans exclusively might gain the distinction accompanied by the

upcoming massacre:

ταῦτά τε δὴ ἐπιλεγόμενον Λεωνίδην, καὶ βουλόμενον κλέος


καταθέσθαιμούνων Σπαρτιητέων.

Considering this and wishing to win distinction for the Spartans alone.
(7.220.4).62

Therefore, one might argue that it is by virtue of Spartan military training, a consequence

of being told that there is no higher aspiration than to enjoy the virtues of battle, that

Leonidas and his Spartans decide as they do; they, more so than their allies, relish the

opportunity to achieve glory and honor.

61
Perrin, Plutarch's Lives, Lyc. 15.4.
62
Godley, Histories, 7.220.4.

35
Herodotus suggests, however, that this obsession with glory and honor is held in

common by all Greeks. He notes in Book Eight, for instance, a conversation between

Tigranes and Mardonius:

‘παπαῖ Μαρδόνιε, κοίους ἐπ᾽ἄνδρας ἤγαγες μαχησομένους ἡμέας, οἳ


οὐ περὶ χρημάτων τὸν ἀγῶνα ποιεῦνται ἀλλὰ περὶ ἀρετῆς.’

“Good heavens, Mardonius, what kind of men are these that you have pitted us
against? It is not for money they contend but for glory of achievement!”(8.26.3).63

This characteristic that Herodotus seems to be praising does not seem to be unique to the

Spartans, as it is held by all Greeks to be a virtue, one which they all strive, when

possible, to put into practice. Of course, the question then emerges as to why it is the

Spartans and not the other Greeks present (save perhaps for the Thespians) that actually

demonstrate this characteristic, that choose to remain to fight. Having up to this point

accounted for the possibly militaristic characteristic that Herodotus praises, what follows

analyses the extent to which Herodotus depicts its exercise to be unique to the Spartans

by virtue of external, non-militaristic factors, not by virtue of their being Spartans.

III This chapter turns now to the reasoning Herodotus maintains is behind the

Spartan decision to remain. Although, as posited in the previous section, Herodotus gives

a picture of the Spartans as having a sense of obligation to remain that is unique amongst

the Greeks in this situation (save for the Thespians), he gives the reader reason to doubt

that this sense of obligation is a consequence of militarism, painting a picture of the

Spartans as having made the decision to act in accordance with a universal Greek virtue

63
Godley, Histories, 8.26.3.

36
that others could not have made by virtue of fundamental religious, political, and tactical

circumstances.

Herodotus maintains first and foremost that Leonidas’ decision to remain was in

some capacity influenced by oracular prophecy. He states that at the war’s inception the

Oracle at Delphi had delivered a prophecy to the Spartans that presented them with two

options in the face of the coming Persian invasion. The final verses of the prophecy read

as follows:

ὑμῖν δ᾽, ὦ Σπάρτης οἰκήτορες εὐρυχόροιο, ἢ μέγα ἄστυ ἐρικυδὲς


ὑπ᾽ ἀνδράσι Περσεΐδῃσι πέρθεται, ἢ τὸ μὲν οὐχί, ἀφ᾽ Ἡρακλέους δὲ
γενέθλης πενθήσει βασιλῆ φθίμενον Λακεδαίμονος οὖρος.

“For you, inhabitants of wide-wayed Sparta,


Either your great and glorious city must be wasted by Persian men,
Or if not that, then the bound of Lacedaemon must mourn a dead king, from
Heracles' line.” (7.220.4)64

That is to say, either Sparta falls or a king dies. What he seems to suggest then is that

Leonidas, cognizant of this prophecy, decided that the oncoming, inevitable slaughter

would be the catalyst for his death and a guarantee, therefore, of Spartan perpetuity.

Granted, it is likely that no such prophecy existed and that it was added after the fact.65

That it is not historical truth, however, is irrelevant, as, again, the concern here is the

picture Herodotus presents to us and our tendency to read it through the lens of a

distorted understanding of Spartan decision making.66 Herodotus, it seems, gives

64
Godley, Histories, 7.220.4.
65
Grant, "Leonidas' Last Stand," 15.
66
See Flower, ‘“Spartan 'Religion' and Greek 'Religion,’” footnote 1.

37
considerable credence to the impact of this prophecy on Leonidas, and, if we are to lend

credence to the notion that the Spartans were particularly religious or superstitious when

compared to other Greeks, then there might be something to be said for this factor’s

weight on the decision to remain.67

One might argue that Herodotus is inconsistent in asserting that Leonidas strictly

adhered to prophecy, as he leads his forces to the Hot Gates during the Karneia, a festival

dedicated to Apollo:

τούτους μὲν τοὺς ἀμφὶ Λεωνίδην πρώτους ἀπέπεμψαν


Σπαρτιῆται, ἵνατούτους ὁρῶντες οἱ ἄλλοι σύμμαχοι στρατεύωνται
μηδὲ καὶ οὗτοιμηδίσωσι, ἢν αὐτοὺς πυνθάνωνται ὑπερβαλλομένους:
μετὰ δέ, Κάρνεια γάρσφι ἦν ἐμποδών .

The Spartans sent the men with Leonidas on ahead so that the rest of the allies
would see them and march, instead of medizing like the others if they learned that
the Spartans were delaying. At present the Carneia was in their way.
(7.206.1)68

How could it be said that Leonidas is committed to Apollo and would heed Apollo’s

prophecy if he is willing to abandon the Karnea? However, the text suggests that it was

the Spartan state, not Leonidas, which made the decision to send an advance group.

Leonidas does not seem to have shown any initiative to leave early. 69 If Leonidas is as

pious as Herodotus suggests him to be – having chosen to heed the prophecy to his doom

– then we should think that the presence of this prophecy in the text allows Herodotus’

Leonidas to act in a way that the other present Greeks could not; he sincerely believes,

Most scholars reject the notion that Leonidas remained behind for religious reasons. This is
irrelevant to the purposes of this Chapter, as I am here concerned with interpreting Herodotus’
own opinion.
67
See Chapter Three on religious adherence.
68
Godley, Histories, 7.206.1.
69
Macan, Herodotus, 7.206.

38
according to Herodotus, that his sacrifice will ensure Spartan perpetuity. If these

religious or oracular considerations allowed or even encouraged the Spartans to exercise

this sense of obligation in a way that the other Greeks could not, then what follows turns

to the extent to which political considerations had a similar effect.

As previously noted, Herodotus tells us that the glory of the sacrifice at

Thermopylae does not belong to the Spartans alone, as the Thespians and Thebans

decided to remain behind as well. He maintains, however, that the latter of these

companies was forced to remain behind by the Spartans as hostages. Herodotus states,

τούτων δὲ Θηβαῖοι μὲν ἀέκοντες ἔμενον καὶ οὐ βουλόμενοι: κατεῖχε


γὰρσφέας Λεωνίδης ἐν ὁμήρων λόγῳ ποιεύμενος.

The Thebans remained against their will and desire, for Leonidas kept them as
hostages. (7.222.1).70

It seems somewhat odd that the Thebans could have been kept as hostages, as the only

way they could have been coerced into staying in the face of what Herodotus makes clear

is certain doom is if they had been threatened with death by the Spartans, staying behind

only to live a bit longer. What is far more likely, however, is that the Thebans stayed

behind willingly, and Herodotus’ depiction is an instance of anti-Theban sentiment on his

part.71 Herodotus tells us that Thebes was medizing at the time, undergoing a substantial

70
Herodotus, The Histories, trans. A. D. Godley, 7.221.1.
71
Macan, Herodotus, 7.222.1. Plutarch (Mor. 865) is highly critical of Herodotus’ depiction.
This may be written this way because of the Theban position in the war at this time. Flower,
"Simonides, Ephorus, and Herodotus," 371 notes that Diodoros’ account of the battle puts 400
Thebans at Leonidas’ side voluntarily, suggesting an alternative reading that may have

39
political shift. It is for this reason, he holds, that Leonidas chooses to recruit a company

from amongst them:

ὅτι σφέων μεγάλως κατηγόρητο μηδίζειν: παρεκάλεε ὦν ἐς


τὸν πόλεμον, θέλων εἰδέναι εἴτε συμπέμψουσι εἴτε καὶ ἀπερέουσι ἐκ
τοῦ ἐμφανέος τὴν Ἑλλήνων συμμαχίην. οἳ δὲ ἀλλοφρονέοντες
ἔπεμπον.

because they were accused of medizing; he summoned them to the war wishing to
know whether they would send their men with him or openly refuse the Hellenic
alliance. They sent the men but intended something quite different. (7.205.3).72

Because of this shift, it is likely that Thebes was split between pro-Persian and anti-

Persian sentiments. One might assume, then, that the group that was sent ahead, though

reluctantly by the medizing Thebans, was mostly anti-Persian. When faced with the

onslaught that awaited them, this group, had they chosen to return to Thebes, would not

have been welcome.73 They would be returning to a city that surely would have punished

them for fighting against the Persians, giving them legitimate reasons to remain at the

Hot Gates. To leave the Hot Gates while the Thebans remained would have been a

political catastrophe for the Spartans. Therefore, one might surmise that the Spartans

were allowed and in fact encouraged to act as they did, to choose to fight in accordance

with a sense of honor, because of their vested interest in not being outdone by their

political adversaries, and Herodotus, though he slanders the Thebans, gives the reader a

picture of the political situation in Thebes that illuminates the aforementioned decision.

What follows turns to the extent to which tactical and strategic considerations may have

highlighted Herodotus’ anti-Theban sentiments. He provides a list of corroborating authors


offered in his footnote 34 (he does not hold this view).
72
Goldey, Histories, 7.205.3.
73
Lazenby, The Defence of Greece, 144-45.

40
allowed the Spartans to act in accordance with this sense of obligation while others could

not.

Herodotus gives the reader reason to think that the Spartans, and the Spartans

alone, were positioned to act tactically as they did. He maintains that when news reaches

the Greeks about Ephialtes’ treachery and Xerxes’ discovery of a pass that goes behind

the Greek lines, the Greeks convene a meeting. Herodotus tells us the following:

ἐνθαῦτα ἐβουλεύοντο οἱ Ἕλληνες, καί σφεων ἐσχίζοντο αἱ γνῶμαι:


οἳ μὲν γὰρ οὐκ ἔων τὴν τάξιν ἐκλιπεῖν

The Hellenes then took counsel, but their opinions were divided. Some advised
not to leave their post. (7.219.2)74

The second half of this statement, starting with οἳ μὲν γὰρ οὐκ, informs the reader that

the Greeks were split on whether or not to remain at the Hot Gates. One possible reading

is that this debate was over the virtuous merits of staying. On one hand the Greeks can

stay and die and achieve glory, and, on the other hand, the Greeks can leave, abandon

their posts, and return, if they can, to their cities. However, one might read this as a

debate over the strategic or tactical benefits of staying or leaving. The text is ambiguous,

but should they stay, the Spartans might accomplish certain strategic goals, though surely

at a great price.

One might suppose that the decision to remain was made with certain tactical

goals in mind, as Herodotus tells us after all that the final, hopeless stand of the Spartans

and their allies was successful in at least some capacity. After noting the death of

Leonidas, Herodotus tells us,

74
Godley, Histories, 7.219.2.

41
Ξέρξεώ τε δὴ δύο ἀδελφεοὶ ἐνθαῦτα πίπτουσι μαχόμενοι.

Two brothers of Xerxes accordingly fought and fell there. (7.225.1)75

Even though Herodotus describes the final assault as a desperate, wild bloodbath fought

at one point with teeth and fists, this frenzy does not begin until after two of Xerxes’

brothers are killed. They no doubt would have held prominent military positions.

Therefore, a calculated strategy might have been needed to ensure that they were both

killed. It goes without saying that the Spartans were the best equipped to carry out such a

maneuver; while their militaristic character is in question their military skill is not.

Diodoros (11.9) suggests that the night before the final assault, Leonidas attempted a

stealth attack against Xerxes’ camp, making it as far as Xerxes’ tent and suggesting that

eliminating the military hierarchy was a prerogative.76 Therefore, one might surmise that

the Spartans decided upon an organized assault against prominent figures of the Persian

military in an attempt to maximize their gains in light of their inevitable loss, and after

this is accomplished the Spartan ranks dissolve and the bloodbath ensues. Therefore, one

may surmise that although the Spartans no doubt acted valiantly, their decision to do so

was inspired not by any internal sense of duty greater than that of their allies – a result of

their militaristic upbringing – but a consequence of circumstances that allowed them to

act in accordance with a universal Greek virtue.

The purpose of this chapter has been twofold. First, I posited that Herodotus does

not show that the Spartans remained out of deference to military authority, nor is their

75
Godley, Histories, 7.225.1.
76Macan, Reginald W, Herodotus: The Seventh, Eighth, & Ninth Books, With Introduction, Text,
Apparatus, Commentary, Appendices, Indices, 7.219.2.

42
defining characteristic, an obligation to a sense of honor, glory, or duty, shown to be

definitively Spartan. Next, I argued that the decision to remain could not be attributed

solely to this defining characteristic, as there were certain external factors that permitted

and in fact encouraged the Spartans to decide as they did. I maintain that the account

Herodotus offers is often read through the lens of a misplaced understanding of Spartan

militarism. However, while we are given much reason to doubt the historical accuracy of

the account one should not be inclined to look to this account as a major participant to the

myth of Spartan militarism.

43
Sparta’s Institutions: Why Sparta Went to War

If the decision to go to war was not militaristic, then what was it? In other words,

when Sparta went to war, what reasons did it have to do so? To answer this question, I

will examine three distinct institutions of Spartan society: The political, the economic,

and the religious. The goal of this examination is twofold. First, I want to establish that

these three institutions, generally understood, had a direct influence on the decision to go

war. This is to say that when Sparta went to war (or chose not to go to war), these

institutions provided the reasons for their doing so. Second, I want to argue that the

reasons these institutions lent to the decision were not militaristic; while they influenced

the decision, it was not in pursuit of militarism. My analysis of the textual evidence

shows both that these institutions had tremendous influence on the decision to go to war

and that their decisions were by no means militaristic. Rather, these institutions acted in

accord with their own respective interests, often refusing or deterring the prospect of war.

Thus, we find reason to doubt that Sparta decided to go to war militaristically.

I The political organization of classical Sparta was characterized by a mixture of

hereditary diarchy, and gerontocracy. The four major political entities, the Diarchy,

Ephorate, Gerousia, and Assembly were distinct both in reference to their composition

and to their larger role in Spartan society.77 The dynamic that existed between these

political entities was one of checks, as each entity competed with one another for political

and legal power. This political dynamic had two major components. The first

77
Hodkinson, "Social Order,” 104.

44
component is the internally hostile relationship that existed between the two kings and

their families. The second component is the external relationship that stood between the

Diarchy and the Ephorate. As such, I maintain that insofar as Sparta’s political institution

influenced the decision to go to war, the decision itself was not militaristic but, rather,

was largely driven by political interests.

We have reason to doubt that the Spartan kingship was wholly and

unquestionably obedient to Spartan law. On the contrary, Spartan kings seem to have

been able to extend and manipulate the law to a degree by means of their personality,

their character, and their public perception.78 Moreover, the hostility between the two

kings manifested primarily as a sort of competition for public perception, as this

perception was the means to greater political freedom. When Agis II failed to defeat the

Argives in 418, Thucydides tells us, the Spartan populace was furious, threatening to tear

down his home and fine him substantially (5.63)79. In other words, popular perception

mattered. It mattered that Agis II did not ultimately battle with Argos, and it matters so

much that the Spartan population threatened to do everything short of killing or banishing

the king to show it.80

In the pursuit of positive public perception and, therefore, greater political

authority, the diarchy would internally check itself, as one king attempted to quell the

authority of the other by limiting his ability to gain the popular favor that came with

78
Millender, "The Spartan Dyarchy,” 14
79
Ibid., 13. After this episode the king was assigned ten advisors without whom he could not
march to war.
80 One might suggest that this action points to a degree of militarism amongst the general

population, as they were notably angry after being deprived of war. See Chapter Four for why it
was probably not the case that Spartan character was militaristic. One might interpret their anger
as a consequence of their inherent fear; a failure to engage in battle might be interpreted as
weakness or vulnerability, exposing the Spartans to danger.

45
military success.81 We see, for instance, that when Cleomenes leaves for Athens to put

Isagoras in power, his Eurypontid counterpart Demaratus recalled him (Her. 5.74-6). As

a result, Cleomenes would latter successfully attempt to delegitimize his counterpart and

replace him with Leotychidas (6.61-67.1).82 Because the diarchy was largely dependent

upon public perception for augmenting personal authority, a given king had a vested

interest both in achieving military success, on his own part, and in preventing it, as any

success won by his counterpart might mitigate his own authority. Therefore, we have

reason to doubt that the kingship acted militaristically, as the decision to go to war (or not

got to war) was a consequence of a kings’ own political ambitions.

The second component of this political game then is the dynamic that existed

between the Diarchy and the Ephorate. Herodotus suggests that the Ephorate was both

able to directly interfere in a King’s behavior and to impose certain checks upon him. The

Ephorate and the Gerousia were able to coerce King Anaxandridas II into taking a second

wife when his first had been unable to bear him a son and heir to the hereditary line.83

This episode suggests that the Ephorate possessed the means by which to coerce the king,

though whether through threat or political promise is unclear, when they had a vested

interest in the outcome, which, in this case, was likely state stability. Moreover, the

Ephorate was heavily involved in military campaigns beyond the power to appoint

81
See Hamilton, “Spartan Politics and Policy," 295. “The two kings, coming from rival houses
and meant to serve as a check on one another... The extent to which a given king provided
political leadership or direction would depend, of course, on his personality....” Also see
Thomas, "On the Role of the Spartan Kings," 260. “... it was only when a king revealed his
personal powers of leadership through successful military direction that his policy was likely to
prevail. When, on the other hand, [he] was judged to be militarily unsuccessful... his initiative
was likely to be overruled....”
82
Millender, "The Spartan Dyarchy,” 11.
83
Ibid., 12.

46
commanders, as they sent representatives to accompany the king on campaign.84 In other

words, the Ephorate made sure that the king did not act in accordance with some interest

other than its own. The Ephorate alone was able to imprison or punish the king, and

there is reason to think that they did so when they perceived a king’s military behavior to

be inappropriate. Thucydides tells us, for instance, that Pleistoanax was exiled on

accusations of bribery in 446, having failed to complete the invasion of Attica (Thuc.

2.21.1; 5.16.3; 1.114.2).85 This episode is important because it demonstrates the extent to

which a Spartan king might decide against war and the extent to which the Ephorate

could check the authority of the king.

Xenophon gives us a similar picture of the Ephorate’s ability to check the King’s

ability to go to war in his conflicting images of Agesilaus. One image paints Agesilaus

as wholly obedient to the will of the Ephorate, abandoning his ambition to destroy Persia

in deference to the home authorities (Xen. 1.36).86 Another scene, however, shows

Agesilaus to be less so, as he refuses to lead an expedition against Mantinea in 385

(5.2.4) and Thebes in 379 (5.2.13).87 Here again one sees a Spartan king refusing the

option of going to war in favor of peace. This lack of uniform decision making suggests

that Agesilaus, rather than pursuing war for war’s sake at every possible occasion,

pursued war when he wanted to insofar as he risked no rebuttal from the Ephorate, whom

we have seen did have the ability to check the king with punitive threats. Therefore, we

do not see Sparta’s political institutions decising upon war because of the virtues and

ideals of war but going to war, or refusing to go to war, out of their own respective

84
Millender, "The Spartan Dyarchy," 11.
85
Ibid., 13.
86
Ibid., 19.
87
Ibid., 21.

47
interests. Having up to this point looked at the political sphere, what follows turns to the

question of economic influence over the decision to go to war.

II The Spartan economy was largely defined by a hierarchy of social classes. The

lowest class was comprised of Helots, a state-owned population of slaves from

Lakedaimon and neighboring Messenia. The Helots functioned as the primary source of

unskilled labor for the Spartan economy. The Perioikoi were free citizens of Lakedaimon

who contributed to the Spartan economy as laborers, tradesmen, and artisans, but who

lacked the same political rights and military obligations as the Spartans.88 Plutarch

claims that Spartan citizens were discouraged from working in the same trades as the

Perioikoi (Lyc. 24), suggesting that there existed a pronounced distinction between the

economic affairs of the Perioikoi and Helots and the military concerns of the Spartan

citizenry. However, we have reason to think that this was not the case, that Spartans

were, in fact, engaged in the production of essential goods and artistic pieces, such as

vases that clearly depict definitively Spartan ideals.89As such, I maintain that the

economic sphere had a profound affect on the decision to go to war. Furthermore, we

have no reason to think that this effect was markedly militaristic.

One might suppose that the systematized enslavement of the Helots was an

economic institution that instigated military action. Plutarch tells us that every so often,

the Krypteia, an elite squadron of young Spartan men, would go into Helot settlements at

night and massacre the local population (Lyc. 28.2).90 Other times, citing Aristotle, the

Ephors would declare war upon the Helot population, exempting any would-be murderer

88
Cartledge, Sparta and Lakonia, 140, 153-155,
89
Ridley, “The Economic Activities of the Perioikoi,” 281-292.

48
from impiety or criminal charges (Lyc. 28.2). Plutarch’s account of the murder of the

Helots is largely problematic. In some instances the Krypteia seems to operate freely, at

liberty to slay whatever Helots happen to pass by. In other instances, they would slay

only the strongest of the Helots. In Book Four Thucydudes recounts an incident whereby

2,000 Helots are massacred in a clandestine operation because of their notable bravery.91

The murder of the strongest and the bravest would suggest an attempt to quell potential

rebellion. Therefore, the exact purpose of the Krypteia is unclear.

While one prevailing theory maintains that the Krypteia functioned as a sort of

regulating mechanism designed to quell potential rebellion and, therefore, ensure

economic stability, other have posited that it functioned as a sort of training program in

stealth warfare.92 The former theory would support the notion that the systematic murder

of the helots was military action driven by the need for stability amongst the primary

labor force. On the other hand, the annual Ephorate declaration of war against the Helot

population points to an alternative interpretation whereby Helots were murdered for

symbolic reasons. This is to say that the annual massacre was a reenactment of the

Spartan conquest of Messenia, which was symbolically significant insofar as it constantly

reignited the hostile sentiments upon which the institution of Helot slavery was

founded.93 Therefore, while there may be evidence to suggest it, it is difficult to say

definitively that the occasional massacre of the Helot population was a consequence of

economic demands.

91
Harvey, "The Clandestine Massacre of the Helots,” 206-7. Harvey argues, however, that the
incident to which Thucydides is referring would not have been publicly known. Rather, it would
have been carried out in secret and the ultimate effect would have left the other Helots unsure of
what had actually happened. Therefore, one might have reason to suspect that the purpose was to
eliminate potential threats for rebellion, not to send a message.
92
See Whitby, "Two Shadows,” 106-7.
93
Ibid., 106.

49
Instead, one can argue that the concept of xenia in Sparta, made possible only by

the unequal distribution of wealth, influenced the decision to go to war. According to

Plutarch (Mor. 226c-d) and (Lyc. 8.3), Lycurgus’ constitution implemented an economic

system that relied upon the exchange of iron bars as currency and the relatively equal

distribution of land as its foundation.94 There is reason to think, however, that this

system was largely not in effect, as there is cause to doubt the use of iron bars and the

equal distribution of land. The extent to which iron bars were the exclusive form of

currency in classical Sparta is dubious.95 While Sparta did not mint its own coinage until

the Hellenistic period, it is likely that it had access to gold and silver currency. 96

Furthermore, by the fifth century the distribution of land had become largely unequal, as

elite classes of Spartans emerged who controlled larger shares of land, and, therefore,

greater wealth.97 The combination of these two, the possession of movable wealth and

the creation of elite Spartan groups, would have contributed to the establishment of xenia,

or guest-friendship, in Spartan society, as wealthy, elite Spartans were able to form gift

and favor-exchanging connections with other Greek peoples.

There is reason to think, therefore, that the presence of xenia is Sparta conditioned

the decision to go to war. Cartledge (1982) argues that the Spartan campaign against

Polykrates in 525 (Hdt. 3.56) was a consequence of elite Spartan assistance to their xenoi

in Samos.98 Beyond this, it seems to be the case that the Spartans relied heavily upon the

94
Hodkinson, Property and Wealth, 154-56.
95
Ibid., 160-65. Iron currency might have existed concurrently, as there are examples of iron
coins having been in circulation elsewhere. It could have had a conversion rate and was not
deemed worthless.
96
Ibid., 154. Despite the influx of gold and silver in Sparta by Lysander in 404, the prohibition
on gold and silver currency was shortly after retained, albeit entirely ignored.
97
Ibid., 399. Aristotle attests to the unequal distribution of wealth (Pol I. 1270a11-18).
98
Ibid., 348.

50
xenoi both of the royal houses of Sparta and of the oligarchs in the greater Peloponnese

for acquiring troops and supplies in time of war. Xenophon tells us, for instance, that the

Spartan commander Antalkidas was given twenty ships by the satrap Ariobarzanes to

defend the Hellespont in 387 by virtue of xenia between their two families.99 Therefore,

we should think that the decision to go to war was conditioned by xenia, by whether or

not one could secure the means by which to undergo a military campaign. Granted, it is

not enough just to show that economics could lead to war, for it must also be shown that

economics could prevent war.

We find evidence in favor of the notion that economic needs outweighed the

desire to go to war. This is to say that the two, militarism and economics, were at odds

with one another in Sparta. Thucydides tells us that during the vote on whether to go to

war against Athens, Archidamus entreats the Spartans to delay military action until they

have procured sufficient wealth to finance the campaign. He urges his fellow Spartans

that, “war is a matter not so much of arms as of money, which makes arms of use... First,

then, let us provide money, and not allow ourselves to be carried away by the talk of our

allies before we have done so...” (1.83.1-3).100 He maintains that at the time being it

would be foolish to start such a campaign, as the Spartans lack the material means - the

wealth - by which to do so. In other words, no matter how desperately one may seek war,

economic conditions must take priority. Granted, the Spartans ultimately vote in favor of

war. However, the reasons as to why this is ultimately the case has much to do with the

nature of the vote itself, not its respective arguments.101 Nonetheless, Archidamus’

maxim about war and wealth gives the reader reason to think that the Spartans were

99
Hodkinson, Property and Wealth, 346.
100
Crawley, The Peloponnesian War, 83.1-3.
101
See Chapter One for a detailed discussion on the dubious nature of the vote.

51
cognizant of the extent to which economic concerns outweighed military ambition.

Therefore, having just discussed the possible role of Spartan economics on the decision to

go to war, what follows turns to the influence of religious institutions.

III While Sparta maintained a pantheon and a religious tradition that was more or

less common to most Greek-speaking peoples of the classical period, there is reason to

think that Sparta was unique insofar as it adhered more strictly to religious or oracular

obligations. Suffice it to say, Lycurgus’ laws, and ultimately Lycurgus himself, were

considered fundamentally divine in nature. The essential underlying institutional

structure of Spartan society was directly linked to Lycurgus and the divine sanction of the

Great Rhetra. Therefore, because Sparta’s institutions were at their core religiously

sanctioned institutions, religious adherence was understandably emphasized in Spartan

society; participation in Spartan society presupposed religious adherence.102

This notion of strict adherence may have catalyzed the decision to go to war.

Herodotus states in Book Seven of the Histories that the Spartan decision to remain at

Thermopylae was such an instance. Leonidas and his small force of Spartan hoplites

decided to remain not despite their inevitable doom but because of their inevitable doom,

as a Delphic oracle had prophesized that either a Spartan king must die, i.e. Leonidas, or

Sparta would burn (7.220).103 An in-depth analysis of this episode can be found in

Chapter Four. Suffice it to say, this episode speaks to the notion that an increased

adherence to religion and oracular prophecy played a significant role in the decision to go

102
Flower, ‘“Spartan 'Religion' and Greek 'Religion,’” 193. Flower posits that this notion can be
separated into two separate albeit related truths about Spartan religion. First, Spartans paid more
attention to religious scruples than other Greeks. Second, religion was the “bedrock” of society
because Lycurgus’ laws were sanctioned by Apollo. I take the argument for why religious
adherence is so crucial offered above to be what he had in mind when he says the two are related.
103
Ibid.

52
to war or, in this case, to engage in battle. That being said, there is reason to believe that

no such prophecy existed and that Herodotus added the Delphic prophecy to Book Seven

only after the fact. 104 Furthermore, many scholars have rejected Herodotus’ claim that

the Spartans remained for religious motives.105

Herodotus offers another such instance in Book Five: Herodotus tells us that the

Spartans decided to adhere to a Delphic prophecy to expel the Peisistratidae from Athens

in 510, “despite close ties of guest friendship, because ‘they put the things of the god

above the things of men” (5.63).106 In this episode, again, the Spartan’s strict adherence

to religious obligation drove the decision to go to war. However, there is some possible

inconsistency with Herodotus’ account, as violating guest-friendship (ξενία) would have

in itself been a sacrilegious act.107 Still, whether or not these accounts are historically

valid, they are consistent with the notion of strict religious adherence echoed elsewhere in

Herodotus and Xenophon as well as implicitly in Thucydides.108 In other words,

Herodotus finds religious adherence to be a palatable reason – one his audience would

presumably accept - for Sparta to go to war.

One might argue that the act of going to war because of oracular prophecy is in

itself militaristic. Spartan religion, though largely similar to the religions and beliefs of

other Greek states, was arguably unique, as it had unique traditions and practices that

104
Grant, "Leonidas' Last Stand," 15.
105
Flower, ‘“Spartan 'Religion' and Greek 'Religion,'” 193, footnote 1.
106
Ibid., 198. Quote taken from Flower, not Herodotus.
107
See Herman, Ritualised Friendship and the Greek City, n.p. for a comprehensive treatment of
the concept of ξενία.
108 See Flower, ‘“Spartan 'Religion' and Greek 'Religion,'” 198 for the claim that the Argives
exploit Spartan piety in Thucydides. Also, Ibid., 200 for Xenophon’s belief that Agesilaus is
sincerely pious. For a treatment on discerning the underplayed religious features of the
Peloponnesian War in Thucydides see Hornblower, "The Religious Dimension to the
Peloponnesian War," 169-97.

53
existed largely to reinforce the lessons and virtues of Lycurgus’ reforms, emphasizing the

fundamental role of heroes and other military themes. Spartan kings, as definitively

religious figures, were treated upon their deaths to heroic honors and given funerals that

served to venerate them beyond what one would have found in other city-states.109

Furthermore, one would have found heroic statues in Sparta dedicated to the not so long

deceased, which would themselves have been venerated in the fashion of gods.110

Moreover, Plutarch attests that Spartan deity statues were often armed and were so

equipped to inspire military excellence.111 Therefore, to go to war for the sake of Spartan

religion, to go to war in the name of religious adherence, was to go to war for the sake of

military excellence.

However, this increased sense of adherence seems to have been great enough also

to postpone military action, not just incite it. In other words, the two - war and religion -

were at odds with one another. Herodotus attributes the Spartan absence from Marathon

and the unusually small force sent to Thermopylae to coincidence with the Karneia

(6.106).112 Also, he maintains that the Spartans were unable to fight Maridonius in 479

because of the Hyakinthia (9.7).113 Thucydides likewise maintains that the Argive

democrats waited for the Gymnopadia in 417 before attacking the oligarchs, taking

advantage of Spartan religious adherence. For this same reason, “the Spartans postponed

109
Flower, ‘“Spartan 'Religion' and Greek 'Religion,'” 213.
110
Ibid., 211.
111
See Ibid., 205, 212-213. Plutarch (Mor. 239a) argues that armed deity statues were intended to
inspire military excellence, establishing a connection between the realm of battle and the realm of
the divine. Though Plutarch would have visited Sparta long after the classical period, his account
of the prevalence of hero sculptures is consistent with the general archeological evidence, as
“Laconia was an area exceptionally rich in hero shrines” (212-13). Pausanias relates a similar
account of the statue of an armed Aphrodite both on Cythera (3.23.1) and Corinth (2.5.1).
112
Ibid., 198.
113
Ibid.

54
giving military aid to Argos” (5.28).114 Therefore, we have reason to think that the

decision to go to war, if it was religiously influenced, was in conflict with militarism, as

religious obligations took precedence over the prospect of war.

This chapter analyzed the roles of Spartan institutions in the decision to go to war.

The results suggest that Spartan institutions, when they did influence the decision to go to

war, did not do so militaristically. Rather, the decision was largely a consequence of the

distinct non-militaristic interests of the political, economic, and religious institutions of

classical Spartan society, as these institutions acted in accordance with their own

respective prerogatives. One might argue that these institutions alone are not indicative of

the whole of Spartan society, that while the reasons to go to war were not militaristic, this

is not to say that Spartans in general were militaristic. Therefore, what follows presented

a theory against the notion that Spartan character was itself militaristic.

114
Flower, ‘“Spartan Religion’ and Greek ‘Religion,’” 198.

55
Spartan Character: Sparta as an Inherently Fearful Polis

One might contest that the treatment thus far is insufficient, as it might still be the

case that Spartans were militaristic insofar as the general populace was itself eager for

war and deferred to military authority. This is to say that the general populace was

unable to act on this militarism, for the decision to go to war was the prerogative of the

state’s institutions. In other words, Sparta’s political, economic, and religious

institutions, as the instigators of Spartan military action, did not represent the whole of

the Spartan populace, so it is worthwhile to briefly note the extent to which Spartan

character was itself not militaristic.

I To say that Spartan character was not militaristic is to claim that Spartans did

exalt military values and ideal. However, there is a sense in which the Spartans glorified

war in the form of a beautiful death, namely, the notion that the greatest way in which

one could hope to die was in military service to the state. In other words, one of the

reasons military action was valuable in and of itself was because it might entail the

ultimate fulfillment of one’s life, namely, his death in battle. This notion is evident in

what is arguably Plutarch’s most famous expression concerning a beautiful death: ἢ τὰν

ἢ ἐπὶ τᾶς (‘Either [with] it [your shield] or on it’) (Mor, 241.16).115 One should either

return with his shield, implying victory, or return as a corpse on his shield, implying that

he did not abandon his shield but faced death with courage. This is how a Spartan ought

to die. Granted, we have reason to doubt the historicity underlying this expression, as it

is unlikely that Spartans would have carried their war-dead back from battle. While we

115 Babbitt, Moralia, 241.16.

56
may have reason to doubt the historicity underlying this expression, this notion of a

beautiful death appears elsewhere in the ancient literature. Pericles notes in his famous

Funeral Oration in Book One, for instance, that,

...while in education, where our rivals from their very cradles by a painful
discipline seek after manliness, at Athens we live exactly as we please, and yet are
just as ready to encounter every legitimate danger (2.39.1)... So died these men as
became Athenians (2.43.1)... And surely, to a man of spirit, the degradation of
cowardice must be immeasurably more grievous than the unfelt death which
strikes him in the midst of his strength and patriotism! (2.43.6)116

While both the Spartans and the Athenians courageously die on behalf of their state, the

Athenians do not need the same military institutions to instill the courage necessary for

this to be the case. Rather, they are by nature courageous. Therefore, Thucydides

endorses the view that Spartans was perceived, by Pericles at the very least, to hold this

notion of a beautiful death. That being said, it does not necessarily follow that holding a

concept of the beautiful death translates into pursuit of a beautiful death. In other words,

it could be the case that they believed the best way to die was to die courageously in

battle in service of Sparta, but it is not necessarily the case that Spartans then actively

sought out war in pursuit of this death.

II On the contrary, I maintain that the Spartans were a generally fearful people,

averse to the prospect of war. Generally speaking, Spartans were not uniformly

courageous in the face of battle. Numerous sources point to the existence of tremblers.

These tremblers were those Spartans who demonstrated cowardice in battle and were

116 Crawley, The Peloponnesian War, 2.43.6.

57
subsequently punished severely for their lack of courage.117 Granted, the extent to which

one would have needed to display cowardice as to merit the label trembler is unclear. In

Xenophon’s account of the battle of Lechaion in 390, three hundred and fifty Spartans

“escaped” the battle but did not earn the title trembler (Hell. 4.5.17). At Leuctra in 371,

however, Plutarch notes that the retreat merited disgrace per Spartan custom.118 One

might argue that the difference between these two events lies in the retention of the

shield, having been retained in the former but abandoned in the latter. As such, the

Spartans used abandonment of one’s shield as an indicator of flight from the hoplite line

and, therefore, an indicator of cowardice. Because it was such a massively cumbersome

item, abandoning one’s shield “was a reliable criterion” to judge that a soldier had fled.

If one retains his shield, however, then there is less reason to think that he displayed

cowardice.119 Therefore, that Spartan tremblers were punished so severely suggests that

Spartans were, generally speaking, a courageous people, ready and willing to face death,

and sought to severely punish those who did not and were not.

That being said, one might argue that the severity of the punishments enacted

upon the tremblers points to a preponderance of fear in Spartan society. There is reason

to think, after all, that fear played a significant role in Spartan religion, for at some point

the Spartans established a shrine to Fear (φοβόν), unique amongst the Poleis.120 Sparta’s

military institutions were designed in such a way as to apprehend fear in battle. Constant

military training and conditioning from a young age was intended to turn warfare into an

117
Ducat, "The Spartan Tremblers," 1. See Epps, "Fear in Spartan Character," 16-17 for an
account of the varied punishments a trembler might face, including public humiliation and social
ostracism.
118
Ducat, "The Spartan Tremblers, " 11. Xenophon never uses the term for tremblers employed
by Plutarch, οἱ τρέσαντες, but characterizes them indirectly as κακός or εἲ τις ἀποδειλιάσειε.
119
Ibid., 12.
120
Flower, ‘“Spartan Religion’ and Greek ‘Religion,’” 211-212.

58
efficient, mechanized process that was executed by force of habit. This in turn eliminates

any room for fear and replaces it with trust in preset movements. However, in an attempt

to mechanize and systematize the military sphere, Sparta’s military institutions increased

Spartan fearfulness by making Spartans dependent upon this systemization.121

Thucydides says of the Spartans in Book Four,

After the severe and unexpected blow that had befallen them on the island, the
occupation of Pylos and Cythera, and the apparition on every side of a war whose
rapidity defied precaution, they lived in constant fear of internal revolution ...
and became more timid than ever in military matters, finding themselves involved
in a maritime struggle, which their organisation had never contemplated...and
thus scarcely dared to take the field... they had lost all confidence in themselves.
(4.55.1-2,4)122

Upon learning that their method of battle is not conducive to the tactics of the Athenians,

the Spartans panic. This is to suggest that the Spartans relied heavily upon the rigid

systemization of their military institutions, for when that system failed them they had a

tendency to panic. Therefore, Tremblers were punished and humiliated not because

Spartans loved courage but because Spartans feared the subversive nature of cowardice.

Moreover, one should not be inclined to think that the Spartans were enthusiastic for war,

as in the absence of a rigid military system, the Spartans become “timid... in military

matters.”123 Furthermore, one should not be inclined to think that the Spartans deferred

to military authority, but rather, it seems to be the case that they relied upon military

authority, that Spartans adhered to their rigid military system because the alternative was

“constant fear.” This does not conflict, however, with the notion that Spartans

disregarded military authority at times. Recall, Plutarch notes that when young men

121
Ducat, “The Spartan Tremblers,” 13-14.
122
Ibid., 16. Also Crawley, The Peloponnesian War, 4.55.1-2,4.
123
See Chapter One, Section II for an argument against military preparedness.

59
snuck out of barracks to meet their wives they were afraid.124 They feared the

consequences of what this disregard would entail. Furthermore, while Leonidas

disregarded Sparta’s military by remaining at Thermopylae and sacrificing valuable

soldiers and military leaders, he exercised his own military authority as king, retaining

military order. The phalanx only breaks apart, as I noted in Chapter Two, when the

Spartans achieve their tactical goals. Therefore, panic, chaos, and fear only take hold

where the military structure, the plan so to speak, ends.

The purpose of this chapter was to argue against the notion that Spartan character,

understood separately from Spartan institutions, was militaristic. To this end, I employed

the example of Spartan tremblers to highlight the way in which Spartans treated

cowardice. As such, their harsh treatment might suggest that they valued courage and

sought to deter cowardice. I posit, however, that this treatment is more likely indicative

of a fear of cowardice than it is of a love of courage. Spartans were reliant upon their

military institutions. When military structure broke down, the Spartan fell into a frenzied

state of panic and fear. Therefore, it should not be said that Spartan character was,

generally speaking, militaristic.

60
Conclusion

This thesis has argued that classical Sparta was not a militaristic society. We

have reason to doubt that when Sparta decided upon war, this decision was

characteristically militaristic. In this respect, these decisions reflected neither military

enthusiasm nor military deference.

I In Chapters One and Two I offered an analysis of critical moments of alleged

militarism in the seminal works of Thucydides and Herodotus, analyzing the former’s

vote in Book One in Chapter Three and the latter’s final stand at Thermopylae in Chapter

Four. We have reason to doubt that the respective works of Thucydides and Herodotus

intentionally participate in the propagation of the militarism in question. On the contrary,

their writings give no indications of militarism in critical scenes involving the decision to

go to war. This analysis relied primarily upon the respective works of these two classical

authors, contemporary commentaries, and contemporary work on the Spartan Mirage. In

Chapter Three of this thesis I offered a treatment of the historical evidence against

militaristic decisions, relying both upon ancient sources and the literature of the

contemporary Spartan Mirage. To his end, Chapter Three explored the roles of Sparta’s

institutions, turning in Chapter Four to the nature of Spartan character.

We have reason to believe that Spartan institutions declared war out of non-militaristic

interests. Furthermore, while one may doubt that the institutions of Spartan society were

actually indicative of larger social militarism, there is reason to think that Spartan

character was equally incompatible with militarism. Rather, Spartan character, in respect

61
to the question of militarism, was averse to the prospect of war and deferred to military

authority as a consequence of fear.

II I want to conclude this thesis by highlighting objects for further study. These

include two subjects that I had initially wanted to touch upon but ultimately did not and a

question this thesis raises that I believe deserves further consideration.

The first subject is a theoretical, abstract approach to the question of militarism.

This entails a theoretical approach to the phenomenon of norm-crossover, which might

be understood as the adaptation of military norms into general society. Because military

institutions played such an integral role in Spartan society, might it have been the case

that Spartan citizens, having cultivated certain norms while in the agoge, continued to act

in accordance with these norms in every day life? While the research herein might imply

that this was not the case, why might that be so? In other words, how theoretically would

this process of norm-crossover occur? If it did not, why is that the case? An earlier

version of this thesis addressed this subject, but it was removed because I felt it was

insufficient.

The second subject is a side-by-side comparison of how certain features of

militarism, such as an eagerness for war, manifest in Spartan society as opposed to, say,

Cretan society. This would entail using other poleis as control variables for certain

features of militarism. In other words, in order to discern whether or not Sparta was

militaristic, one would use other city-states as standards of militarism to which Spartan

behavior would be compared. By using other poleis as foils for Spartan behavior, one

could better discern the extent to which a Spartan approach to war was definitively

unique amongst the Greeks. This is how I had originally planned to format this thesis,

62
but I had abandoned it due to changing interests. Given these omitted subjects, what

follows looks at a question this thesis raises that I believe merits further consideration.

The limited chronological scope of this thesis raises an important question about

militarism over time. While this thesis looked at a fairly narrow window of time, albeit a

significant one, might it have been the case that militarism was an historical reality at

different points in time? Put another way, while this thesis argued that Spartan decisions

for war in the classical period were inconsistent with militarism, might the conditions of

earlier or later periods of Spartan history, particularly those closer to the establishment of

the Lycurgan constitution, have been conducive to militarism? It does not seem

farfetched to suppose that the novelty of Lycurgus’ Sparta had a profound ideological

effect on Spartan society, one that gradually diminished over time. One might suppose

that such a phenomenon is apparent in the emergence of rigid, utopian-esque societies,

wherein adherence to their original ideological tenets fades over time. On the other hand,

one might argue that changing historical circumstances effected militarism. Might a

study of changing political or economic institutions over time reveal pockets of increased

or decreased militarism, if present at all? I offer this for further consideration.

While the Spartan Mirage is an expansive field of study and the question of

militarism only a notably small facet of it, debunking the myth of Spartan militarism has

implications for how we understand and perceive classical Sparta. It subverts a

provincial conception of Spartan society, one that unfairly characterizes a highly dynamic

people as a one-dimensional, war-crazed social experiment. It has resounding

implications not only for the study of Sparta and antiquity today but for the study of any

63
such society shrouded in the myth of militarism. It acts as a foil with which to compare

other apparent instances of the phenomenon of militarism.

64
Bibliography

Ackrill, J.L., ed. "Politics I." A New Aristotle Reader. Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1987.

Allison, June W. "Sthenelaidas' Speech: Thucydides 1.86." Hermes 112 (1984): 9-16.

Babbitt, Frank, trans. Moralia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London.
William Heinemann Ltd, 1931.

Bradford, Alfred S. “The Duplicitous Spartan.” In The Shadow of Sparta, edited by


Anton Powell and Stephen Hodkinson, 59-85. London: Routledge, 1994.

Cartledge, Paul. "Another View: Paul Cartledge, Professor of Greek History,


on 300." The Guardian (London), 2007. Web.

Cartledge, Paul. "Introduction: the Spartan tradition — a personal re-view." British


School at Athens Studies 16, Sparta and Laconia: From Pre-history Pre-modern
(2009): 1-4.

Cartledge, Paul. Sparta and Lakonia. London: Routledge, 1979.

Cartledge, Paul. "Sparta and Samos: A Special Relationship?" The Classical


Quarterly 32.2 (1982): 243-65.

Cartledge, Paul. Sparta and Lakonia: A Regional History 1300 to 362 BC (2 ed.). Oxford:
Routledge, 2002.

Crawley, Richard, trans. History of The Peloponnesian War. London: J. M. Dent; New
York: E. P. Dutton, 1910.

Dillon, Matthew, and Lynda Garland. Ancient Greece: Social and Historical Documents
from Archaic Times to The Death of Alexander The Great. 3rd ed. Abingdon:
Routledge, 2010.

Diodorus, Siculus. Diodorus of Sicily in Twelve Volumes. trans. C. H. Oldfather. Vol. 4-8.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann, Ltd.
1989.

Ducat, Jean. "The Spartan Tremblers." In Sparta and War, edited by Stephen Hodkinson
and Anton Powell, 1-49. Swansea: Classical Press of Wales, 2006.

Edmonds, J.M., trans. Elegy and Iambus. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1931.

65
Epps, Preston H. "Fear in Spartan Character." Classical Philology 28.1 (1933): 12-29.

Flower, Michael A. ‘“Spartan 'Religion' and Greek 'Religion.’” In Sparta: Comparative


Approaches, edited by Stephen Hodkinson, 193-229. Swansea: Classical Press of
Wales, 2009.

Flower, Michael A. "Simonides, Ephorus, and Herodotus on the Battle of


Thermopylae." The Classical Quarterly 48.2 (1998): 365-379.

Grant, John R. "Leonidas' Last Stand." Phoenix 15, no. 1 (1961): 14-27.

Godley, A.D., trans. Herodotus, with an English Translation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1920.

Hamilton, Charles D. "Spartan Politics and Policy, 405-401 B.C." The American Journal
of Philology 91.3 (1970): 294-314.

Harvey, David. "Lacomica: Aristophanes and The Spartans." In The Shadow of Sparta,
edited by Anton Powell and Stephen Hodkinson, 35-58. Swansea: Classical Press
of Wales, 1994.

Harvey, David. "The Clandestine Massacre of the Helots (Thucydides 4.80)." In Spartan
Society, edited by Thomas J. Figueira, 199-217. Swansea: Classical Press of
Wales, 2004.

Herman, Gabriel. Ritualised Friendship and the Greek City. New York, NY: Cambridge
University Press, 1987.

Hodkinson, Stephen. Property and Wealth in Classical Sparta. Swansea: Classical Press
of Wales, 2009.

Hodkinson, Stephen. "Social Order and Conflict of Values in Classical Sparta," In


Sparta, edited by Michael Witby, 104-130. New York: Routledge, 200.

Hodkinson, Stephen. “Was Classical Sparta a Military Society?” In Sparta and War,
edited by Stephen Hodkinson and Anton Powell, 111-162. Swansea: Classical
Press of Wales, 2006.

Hornblower, Simon. A Commentary on Thucydides: Books I - III. Vol. 1. Oxford:


Clarendon, 1991.

Hornblower, Simon. A Commentary on Thucydides: Books 5.25-8.109. Vol. III. Oxford:


Clarendon, 1991.

66
Hornblower, Simon. "The Religious Dimension to the Peloponnesian War or, What
Thucydides Does Not Tell Us." Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 94
(1992): 169-97.

Kennel, Nigel M. Spartans: A New History. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010.

Lazenby, J.F. The Defence of Greece 490–479 BC. Oxford: Aris & Phillips Ltd., 1993.

Luraghi, Nino. "Thucydides and Spartan Power in Archaeology and Beyond."


In Thucydides, a Violent Teacher? History and Its Representations, edited by
Vassiliki Pothou and Georg Rechenauer Gottingen, 185-196. Vandenhoeck &
Ruprecht, 2011.

Lytle, Ephraim. "Sparta? No. This is madness." Toronto Star, 2007. Web.

Macan, Reginald W. Herodotus: The Seventh, Eighth, & Ninth Books, With Introduction,
Text, Apparatus, Commentary, Appendices, Indices. Vol. 1. Part 1. London: The
Macmillan Company, 1908.

Millender, Ellen. "The Spartan Dyarchy: A Comparative Perspective." In Sparta:


Comparative Approaches, edited by Stephen Hodkinson, 1-68. Swansea:
Classical Press of Wales, 2009.

Miller, Frank. 300 #1. Dark Horse Comics, 1998.

Miller, Frank. 300 #5, Dark Horse Comics. 1998.

Ollier, F. Le mirage spartiate: étude sur l’idéalisation de Sparte dans l’antiquité grecque,
2 vols. Paris. 1933-43.

Plato. “Protagoras.” Plato: Complete Works. Edited by. John M. Cooper and D. S.
Hutchinson. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997.

Perrin, Bernadotte, trans. Plutarch's Lives. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press;
London: William Heinemann Ltd, 1914.

Rawson, Elizabeth. The Spartan Tradition in European Thought. Oxford: Oxford


University Press, 1991. Paperback reprint.

Ridley, R.T. “The Economic Activities of the Perioikoi.” Mnemosyne 27 (1974): 281-
292.

Sihler, E. G. "Aristotle's Criticisms of the Spartan Government." The Classical Review 7,


no. 10 (December 1893): 439-43.

67
Smith, Charles F., trans. History of The Peloponnesian War: Books I and II. Edited by G
P. Goold. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1919.

Smith, Charles F., trans. History of The Peloponnesian War: Books V and VI. Edited by
G P. Goold. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1919.

Thomas, C. G. "On the Role of the Spartan Kings." Historia: Zeitschrift fur Alte
Geschichte 32.3 (1974): 257-270.

Tigerstedt, E. N. The Legend of Sparta in Classical Antiquity. Vol. 1. Stockholm:


Almquist & Wiksell, 1965.

Wassermann, Felix M. "The Speeches of King Archidamus in Thucydides." The


Classical Journal 48.6 (1953): 193-200.

Westlake, H. D. "Nicias in Thucydides." The Classical Quarterly 35.1/2 (1941): 58-65.

Whitby, Michael. "Two Shadows: images of Spartans and Helots." In The Shadow of
Sparta, edited by Anton Powell and Stephen Hodkinson, 87-126. London:
Routledge, 1994.

Xenophon. Xenophon in Seven Volumes, 1 and 2. Edited by Carleton L. Brownson.


Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann, Ltd.
vol. 1:1918; vol. 2: 1921.

68

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi