Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 56

R A D I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y

a journal of socialist and feminist philosophy

81 CONTENTS
Editorial collective
Chris Arthur, Ted Benton, Nadine Cartner,
COMMENTARY
Andrew Collier, Diana Coole, Peter Dews, Coming In: Lesbian and Gay Politics in the Nineties
Roy Edgley, Gregory Elliott, Howard
Feather, Jean Grimshaw, Kathleen Lennon, Angela Mason ................................................................................................ 2
Joseph McCarney, Kevin Magill, Peter
Osborne, Stella Sandford, Sean Sayers,
Kate Soper ARTICLES
Issue editor Gilles Deleuze and the Redemption from Interest
Kevin Magill
Peter Hallward ............................................................................................... 6
Reviews editor
Sean Sayers Unhewn Demonstrations
Andrew Collier ............................................................................................. 22
Contributors
Angela Mason is Executive Director The Culture of Polemic:
of Stonewall, the lesbian and gay rights Misrecognizing Recognition
pressure group. Alexander García Düttmann ...................................................................... 27
Peter Hallward is based at Yale
University, working on contemporary Poor Bertie
literature and philosophy. Jonathan Rée ............................................................................................... 35
Andrew Collier teaches philosophy at
the University of Southampton and is the
author of Critical Realism (Verso). REVIEWS
Alexander Düttmann is the author of
At Odds with Aids (Stanford University István Mészáros, Beyond Capital
Press, 1996) and The Memory of Thought: Chris Arthur .................................................................................................. 41
An Essay on Heidegger and Adorno
(forthcoming from Athlone Press). Keith Burgess-Jackson, Rape: A Philosophical Investigation
Jonathan Rée teaches philosophy at Sue Lees, Carnal Knowledge: Rape on Trial
Middlesex University. His next book David Archard............................................................................................... 44
is The Voice: A Philosophical History
(forthcoming from HarperCollins). Morwenna Griffiths, Feminisms and the Self: The Web of Identity
Meena Dhanda............................................................................................. 46
Typing (WP input) by Jo Foster
Tel: 0181 341 9238 Alan D. Schrift, Nietzscheʼs French Legacy
Layout by Petra Pryke David Macey................................................................................................. 47
Tel: 0171 243 1464
Chris Hables Gray, ed., The Cyborg Handbook
Copyedited and typeset by Judith Halberstam and Ira Livingston, eds, Posthuman Bodies
Robin Gable and Lucy Morton
Tel: 0181 318 1676 John Armitage ............................................................................................. 48
Design by Peter Osborne Cairns Craig, Out of History: Narrative Paradigms in Scottish and
British Culture
Printed by Russell Press, Radford Mill,
Norton Street, Nottingham NG7 3HN Stephen Cowley .......................................................................................... 49
Adriana Cavarero, In Spite of Plato: A Feminist Rewriting of
Bookshop distribution Ancient Philosophy
UK: Central Books,
99 Wallis Road, London E9 5LN Stella Sandford ............................................................................................ 50
Tel: 0181 986 4854 Bill Martin, Humanism and its Aftermath
USA: Bernard de Boer, 113 East Centre
Street, Nutley, New Jersey 07100, Gideon Calder .............................................................................................. 51
Tel: 201 667 9300; Ubiquity Distributors Ulrich Beck, Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk
Inc., 607 Degraw Street, Brooklyn, Ulrich Beck, Ecological Enlightenment
New York 11217, Tel: 718 875 5491; Fine
Print Distributors, 500 Pampa Drive, Austin, Matthew David and Iain Wilkinson ........................................................... 52
Texas 78752-3028. Tel: 512-452-8709
William E. Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization
Cover: Vit Hopley and Yve Lomax, from Chris Erickson .............................................................................................. 53
ʻTropeʼ 1996

Published by Radical Philosophy Ltd.


NEWS
http://www.ukc.ac.uk/cprs/phil/rp/ Friendly Fire: The Hoaxing of Social Text
Peter Osborne ..............................................................................................54
Jan/Feb 1997

© Radical Philosophy Ltd


COMMENTARY

Coming in
Lesbian and gay politics in the nineties

Angela Mason

A
s the countdown to the general election begins, there is a rising tide of expecta-
tion among lesbians and gay men in Britain. This time we can surely expect a
new government to sweep away discrimination and finally give lesbians and gay
men the same rights and recognition enjoyed by other citizens in our society. But nothing,
of course, is that simple. Here I want to offer an assessment of where the lesbian and gay
movement stands now, the nature of our political project, the forces that will help us win
change, and the obstacles and barriers that are still to be overcome.
The turning point for the lesbian and gay movement today was undoubtedly the
passing of Section 28 of the Local Government Act, which made it unlawful for a local
authority or local education authority intentionally to promote homosexuality or teach in
schools the acceptability of homosexuality as a ʻpretend family relationshipʼ. The clause
was an attempt by the Conservative government to use the ʻgay cardʼ against ʻloony
leftʼ councils, and it played with considerable success. Within the Labour Party, ʻgaysʼ
were blamed for losing the pensionersʼ vote. Whether this was true or not, the passing
of Clause 28 marked a new beginning for lesbian and gay politics in Britain, involving a
new strategy for change and a new relationship with all the three main political parties.
The enormous anger that Clause 28 generated remobilized the lesbian and gay
community, bringing many into politics for the first time. Having resisted the first
terrible backlash against AIDS, we began to feel a growing confidence that something
could be done. Perhaps unconsciously borrowing from the concept of niche marketing,
at the same time we developed ways of organizing that recognized political differences
within our community. Stonewall and Outrage were set up almost contemporaneously:
Stonewall to create a cross-party political lobby for lesbian and gay rights, and Outrage
to keep these issues on the front pages through peaceful direct action. Although at times
both groups have wrongly sought hegemony, intense discussion about tactics has always
belied an underlying unity on the fight for equality. Indeed, legal discrimination in this
country is so universal and extreme that it is impossible for any lesbian or gay group not
to demand equality. Of course, there are differences about priorities, and it is quite clear
that over issues like marriage or gays in the military there are conflicting philosophies.
But whilst we are unequal, the egalitarian agenda is the most powerful force unifying a
community that contains so many differences in social class, race and gender.
Moreover, in the context of lesbian and gay politics the demand for equality, for human
rights, also sends a powerful message about sexual identity. The despised status of homosexu-
ality has meant literally living outside society, an existence in the demimonde, the ʻtwilight
zonesʼ. The partial decriminalization of homosexuality in 1967 did not fundamentally chal-
lenge that status. It was precisely the difference between homosexuals and other men that
was used to justify reform. Leo Abse, one of the architects of the Sexual Offences Act, said
that ʻIt was only by insisting that compassion was needed by a totally separate group, quite

2 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


unlike the absolutely normal males of the Commons, that I could allay the anxiety and
resistance that otherwise would be provoked.ʼ The compromise settlement was, in a sense,
the ʻprivatizationʼ of homosexuality. The offence of gross indecency remained, but homo-
sexual acts were declared lawful between consenting adults ʻin privateʼ, when both parties
were over twenty-one. Privately homosexuality could be tolerated, but not its existence
within the public arena.

A growing recognition
The modern lesbian and gay movement dates from the Stonewall riot of 1969, and the Gay
Liberation Movement to which it gave rise has precisely been about a refusal to accept
ʻprivacyʼ as a tolerable settlement, and the demand for public status and recognition. In this
sense, ʻqueerʼ theory and politics are as much a part of that aspiration as campaigns for an
equal age of consent. The right to be recognized for who we are, not tolerated or pitied in
practice, unites the queer activists and the lobbyists campaigning for civil rights. They might
understand different things about their sexuality, yet they both demand the right to be out
and recognized. Breaking down the closet doors, demanding public status, necessarily also
involves an appeal to universalistic human values, equality under the law, the right to free
expression.
But translating these aspirations into the discourse of British party politics was not
easy. The absence of a written constitution also made it difficult to challenge discrimi-
nation through the courts. Prior to 1988 much of the original force of gay liberation
politics had been lost. Lesbians largely worked in the womenʼs movement; despite many
successes, the Campaign for Homosexual Equality was not able to operate successfully
at a national political level. Much was going on. Gay News – a national lesbian and gay
weekly – was established; national counselling and self-help groups like Icebreakers and
Friend were set up. There were the beginnings of gay organization within the political
parties, but national politics remained relatively uninfluenced.
A breakthrough seemed to come when the London Labour Party recaptured the
Greater London Council, and under the leadership of Ken Livingstone embarked on
radical programmes which gave sexual politics and lesbians and gay men a central
position. Equal opportunity units seemed to provide opportunities for funding and, more
importantly, to change political practice to acknowledge the needs of lesbians and gay
men. Lesbian and gay activists flocked to join local government and the Labour Party.
However, the change was shortlived. The unthinkable happened. The GLC was closed
down by the Thatcher government, and the political backlash which led to the passing of
Section 28 left municipal socialism and the Labour Party in defensive retreat. Lesbians
and gay men had certainly achieved a new visibility. However, the débâcle of Section
28 showed how dangerous it can be for a cause to be hitched exclusively to one political
party – and, indeed, one political tendency. Lesbians and gay men were not going to be
able to piggy-back change by capturing sections of the Labour Party. It became clear
both that we were going to have to rely on our own organization and strength and that,
by whatever means, we had to win a broader basis of support and understanding through-
out society.
So how has this strategy fared? I think few would deny its success. Public awareness
of lesbian and gay issues has never been greater. Support for what I have called the
public status of lesbians and gay men is growing. A Guardian/ICM poll in 1996 found
that over 70 per cent of respondents thought that ʻa declared homosexual living in a
stable relationship with a partnerʼ should be a allowed a job in teaching, the Church, the
police, and as an MP. The number of people who admit to personally knowing lesbians
and gay men has also increased dramatically. ʻComing outʼ does work. Numerous
surveys also show major generational changes. Speaking in the House of Lords in the
age-of-consent debate, Lord Russell, with a distinctive historical flourish, said that his
students found the idea of discriminating against lesbians and gay men as inconceivable
as a proposal to burn heretics.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 3


Within the corporate sector
there is growing recognition
of lesbians and gay men as
employees and as consum-
ers. Numerous public bodies,
including the Bar Council and
the Law Society, have profes-
sional codes of practice which
deal with sexual orientation.
Many trade unions have lesbian
and gay groups, and during
the age-of-consent campaign
trade-union support was strong
and significant.
The ʻpink poundʼ is certainly
a media reality and the argu-
ment now is whether events like
ʻPrideʼ, which attracts a quarter of a million people, have too much corporate sponsor-
ship. Certainly in retail, fashion, computing and the drinks industry, the gay market
is seen as increasingly important. Alongside this there has been an explosion of gay
culture and media. There is a thriving gay press and a seemingly insatiable media appe-
tite for gay stories in the straight press. If there was to be an award for the programme
that has done most to break down discrimination, it would surely be EastEnders.
Pioneered by the Lesbian and Gay Switchboards, specialist service agencies dealing
with housing, legal advice, violence, mental health, young people and the elderly are
developing and statutory funding is slowly becoming available.

The turning point


Politically, too, we have made the most enormous advances since the dark days of
Section 28. The turning point was the age-of-consent debate in 1994. In 1990 the
Guardian had carried out a survey for the ʻOut this Weekʼ series on Channel 4, and
found that only 11 per cent of MPs would support an equal age of consent for gay men
of sixteen. However, in the event 280 MPs voted for sixteen, including 37 Conservative
MPs and all but one Liberal Democrat. Among Labour MPs, 36 voted against sixteen
or abstained. The amendment for equality, which was supported by Edwina Currie, Neil
Kinnock and Robert Maclennan, was lost by only 27 votes.
For the first time, MPs were inundated with letters from gay men and lesbians, who
clearly recognized that this was a debate about the status of homosexuality in Britain
today. This was partly made possible through Stonewallʼs database of 30,000 supporters
and the growing infrastructure of lesbian and gay, HIV and AIDS groups throughout
the country. Stonewall also produced an influential pamphlet, The Case for Change,
which was distributed freely by the gay press. The pamphlet contained detailed lob-
bying tips; for the first time the lesbian and gay community not only found a voice
in Parliament, but quickly became one of the most conscious and politically aware in
the country. Heaven, one of the largest nightclubs in London, produced leaflets asking,
ʻDoes your MP know you exist?ʼ Weekly meetings of all the major lesbian and gay
organizations, including Outrage, were held to co-ordinate and advance the campaign.
Lesbians and gay men, who probably thought St Stephenʼs Gate was a local gay bar,
thronged to the House of Commons to attend packed meetings and mass lobbies. It
became acceptable, and even fashionable, to support equality.
Why then did we lose? We didnʼt win enough of the traditionalists in the Labour
Party, despite the support of the leadership and the trade unions. Most Conservative
MPs took their lead from John Major, who supported eighteen as an acceptable com-
promise. At a deeper level, the concept of rights for lesbians and gay men had still

4 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


not taken a deep enough hold in public thinking to allow us to make the jump from
what Edwina Currie called the ʻdark shadowsʼ to equality. We were still a moral issue,
not a human-rights issue. In this we suffered not just from the lingering vestiges of
prejudice that certainly exist, but also from a political culture which is stony ground
for human rights. There has been no major civil-rights movement on mainland Britain
since the war. The modern Womenʼs Liberation Movement obviously touched on these
issues, but was primarily informed by a struggle over gender and power. Both the Race
Relations and the Sex Discrimination Acts were informed by an attempt to overcome
disadvantage, rather than an appeal to basic rights. We lack any clear constitutional
protection of human rights, as the numerous appearances of the British government at
the European Court of Human Rights testify.

The edge of change


The question for us now is whether it will be any different under a Labour government.
There is no doubt of the sea change in attitudes within the Labour Party since the late
1980s. Support for gay rights is no longer the preserve of a section of the Left. This
yearʼs Party Conference even voted unanimously to lift the ban on lesbians and gay
men serving in the armed forces. Within the Shadow Cabinet there is strong personal
support for equality. Tony Blairʼs speech in the age-of-consent debate was a powerful
plea for inclusion of lesbians and gay men within the framework of society. Yet the best
we can hope for in the manifesto is probably a one-word reference to sexuality. The
weight of legislation to which the Labour Party is committed will make it very difficult
to get lesbian and gay issues onto the parliamentary agenda.
More fundamentally, many fear that the leadershipʼs espousal of ʻfamily valuesʼ and
law and order – the traditional clothes of the Right – will create a climate hostile to
lesbian and gay rights. It is certainly a dangerous game. But the evidence, I believe,
is that Blair is trying to create an inclusive, rather than exclusive, moral agenda. In
a recent speech on the subject he was at pains to say that a return to family values
did not mean a return to Victorian hypocrisy and homophobia. The Labour Party is
perfectly conscious of the strength of the gay movement and will be reluctant to stand
against us. But it is also aware that, whilst there is broad support for equality, issues
such as lesbian and gay partnerships and parenting are still at the margins. It is very
aware of the disastrous effect of Clintonʼs fumbled attempt to lift the ban on lesbians
and gays in the military, although it may take consolation from the failure of the moral
Right to win electoral support for Dole and the Republican Party.
There are also other options. Stonewall is supporting applications to the European
Court of Human Rights on the age of consent and the ban in the armed forces. The
International Governmental Conference is considering a new equality provision in
the Treaty which would cover race, sexual orientation and disability discrimination.
European law is likely to provide good political cover for gay rights legislation.
We are poised on the edge of change. Everything is possible, but nothing is certain.
If a Labour government quickly runs into trouble, if the Conservatives adopt a right-
wing moral (as well as political) agenda, the window of opportunity that now exists
will close. Alternatively, we could in the next five years see lesbian and gay rights
finally enshrined in law, and the lesbian and gay movement moving into its own third
age.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 5


Gilles Deleuze and the
redemption from interest
Peter Hallward

Deleuze writes a redemptive philosophy. In conjunction impersonal, asignificant).2 This transcendence is the
with its mainly artistic allies, it is designed to save its enabling gesture of Deleuzeʼs entire project. It is also,
readers from a situation contaminated by ʻconscious- perhaps, the source of its ultimate incoherence.
nessʼ, ʻrepresentationʼ, ʻanalogyʼ, ʻrepressionʼ, ʻlackʼ, and For Deleuze as much as for Spinoza or Suhrawardî,
ʻthe Other [autrui]ʼ. Redemption from these things, Being is defined by its singularity or univocity. ʻThere
according to Deleuze, provides immediate access to has only ever been one ontological proposition: Being
a very different kind of situation – a situation defined is univocalʼ, and ʻthe One expresses in a single
by its radical self-sufficiency, its literal, absolute, all- meaning all of the multiple.ʼ3 The Real is that which
inclusive immanence to itself. In a whole variety of creates what it perceives (or conceives, in both senses).
ways, Deleuze writes the passage from our given, Here, ʻdesire and its object are one and the same
contaminated situation, to the purer, more primordial thingʼ, and ʻthere is only one kind of production, the
situation. production of the real.ʼ4 But we, ourselves ʻproducedʼ,
Just how this self-sufficiency allows itself to be so are somehow led to distinguish between ʻrealʼ and
contaminated is the first question which Deleuze, like ʻunrealʼ (either ʻimaginaryʼ or ʻsymbolicʼ). We are
so many other redemptive writers, must confront. Like led to figure the literally true. If Real is self-constitu-
Spinoza, most obviously – but also, like the Christian ent, self-sufficient and self-expressive – originally and
St Paul or the Muslim Suhrawardî1 – Deleuzeʼs work immediately determinant – such knowledge that we
begins with the problem of an all-powerful, all-deter- have of this immanent determining force is derivative,
mining ontological principle somehow repressed or, second-order, the product of an eventual mastery. The
denied through its own power of creation. Consider- Real, in other words, is immediate but not given. What
ation of this problem throws into question some of is first given to us is a worldly condition governed
our most cherished assumptions about Deleuzeʼs work by mediation, a world ruled by plurivocal relations
– his alleged subversions of authority and the subject, between perceptions and perceived, between subjects
his refusal of ʻtotalizingʼ knowledges, and his affirm- and objects, between transcendent and transcended
ation of a radical pluralism or ʻdifferenceʼ. forces. For Deleuze as much as for Paul and Spinoza,
I will argue that Deleuze, like Spinoza, Suhrawardî the great task is to overcome such relations, to over-
or Paul, writes a relentless attack on specific, worldly come a worldly or interested mediation, so as to return
knowledges and worldly differences, in favour of an to a wholly immanent immediacy.
other-worldly redemptive force. This force is defined
by its absolute power to negate or transcend relation Models of redemption
as such. If Deleuzeʼs radical philosophy of imma- Consider briefly the more familiar models of redemp-
nence of course entails the critique of transcendence tion associated with Paul, Suhrawardî and Spinoza. If
just as it implies the refusal of negation, this very Spinozaʼs example is the most important for Deleuze,5
critique obtains only through a preliminary trans- the logic of salvation is comparable in each case. For
cendence of what might be called the ʻGivenʼ (relative, all, it follows from the definition of an all-powerful
worldly, specific, human, significant) as opposed to the God that, in Paulʼs words, ʻall that may be known of
ʻRealʼ (absolute, other-worldly, singular, inhuman or God by men lies plain before their eyes; indeed God

6 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


himself has disclosed it to them. His invisible attri- perception are, for Suhrawardî as for the Sufi tradi-
butes, that is to say his everlasting power and deity, tion, mutually exclusive.15 When I move toward God,
have been visible, ever since the world began, to the ʻI separate myself from this world and join myself
eye of reason, in the things he has made.ʼ The ʻRealʼ with the world above.ʼ16 Above all, with Rûmî as with
is immediately and primordially evident; it inheres in Suhrawardî, ʻthe goal of all ascesis is a vision in which
all creation, by definition. Necessarily, ʻnothing in all there is no longer a difference between the knowing
creation can separate us from the love of Godʼ.6 But and the known.ʼ17 Only God can proclaim the Being of
we live in the world as if separate from God. We live God (ʻthroughʼ the speaker). Illuminated, the knowing
as positioned, interested, specified (Greek, Roman, subject ʻis not a subject opposed to an objectʼ; rather,
Jew…). As worldly creatures, we try to relate to a ʻthrough the soul which knows, the real knows itself,
God imagined as transcendent, to figure God through becomes conscious of itself. Knowledge is illumination
the law, and this effort brings only ʻconsciousness of of the real in reality itself, it is Light reflecting on
sinʼ.7 The solution is simple: we must escape the world light.ʼ18 Not ʻI thinkʼ, but ʻI am thought.ʼ19
(the ʻas ifʼ), the legal organization of relations, so as With Spinoza, finally, ʻGod acts and directs every-
to become-immediate to God, literally God. ʻAdapt thing by the necessity of his own nature and perfection
yourselves no longer to the pattern of this present aloneʼ; ʻhis decrees and volitions are eternal truths,
world, but let your minds be remade and your whole and always involve necessity.ʼ20 Godʼs creatures are
nature thus transformed. Then you will be able to simply modes or actualizations of Godʼs power to
discern the will of God, and to know what is good, various degrees. In the Given state of nature assumed
acceptable and perfectʼ. Die to the world, so as to by Spinoza as much as Hobbes, these modes remain
be reborn in a spirit unlimited by the mediate speci- ignorant of their ʻReal natureʼ, remain ʻslavesʼ of their
ficities of the world. ʻYou are on the spiritual level, positioned interests, ʻpassionsʼ and ʻappetitesʼ.21 If God
if only Godʼs Spirit dwells within you.ʼ8 Then ʻthere is all-powerful, we – and it is a point Deleuze stresses
is no such thing as Jew or Greek … for you are all in his reading of Spinoza – do not begin as God (as
one person in Christ Jesus.ʼ9 Unlimited and therefore reasonable). We must become the reason that we are,
all-inclusive, Paulʼs Spirit announces the dawn of what and eventually reasonable modes are those which see
Deleuze will call ʻa world without othersʼ10 – a world themselves as actualizations of Godʼs univocal power,
of one singularity–multiplicity, a world beyond worldly as wholly and immediately identical to the one Real
mediation or relation altogether. interest, the interest of divine reason itself. In a fully
Like all visions of the Islamic deity, Iranian phil- reasonable polity, then, it follows that the ʻliberty of
osopher Suhrawardîʼs ʻLight of Lightsʼ is radically the Subject [is] consistent with the unlimited power of
sovereign, autarcique, ʻthat which subsists through the sovereignʼ.22 By becoming immediate to reason,
itselfʼ.11 The purely original One is wholly unknowable subjects as much as rulers become literally unlimited,
(deus absconditus), a blinding light. The One is not an redeemed from the limits of interest. In this way the
accessible whole but what, inaccessible, gives rise to ʻgreatest freedomʼ is identical to the ʻgreatest obedi-
the multiple. Deleuze will use the term ʻthe Unthoughtʼ enceʼ, on the Pauline (or Ismâʼili) model: the two are
(or ʻnon-senseʼ) to describe much the same thing. The unlimited in themselves. ʻWe are bound to perform all
multiple is invariably expressive of the One, but to the commands of the sovereign without exceptionʼ,23
variable degrees. Hence a strictly vertical arrangement, and the ʻmore absolute a governmentʼ, ʻthe more suit-
determined by proximity to God. The aim of any given able for the preservation of freedom.ʼ24 ʻThe greater
being is to return, to the degree possible, toward the the right of the sovereign the more does the form of
One Light from which it springs. For Suhrawardî, the state agree with the dictate of reasonʼ – that is, the
since ʻto turn entirely towards God is liberationʼ, so more it ʻform[s] one body directed by one mindʼ.25
ʻeverything that gets in the way of the Good is Evil. Despite obvious differences in doctrine and
Everything which erects an obstacle on the spiritual approach, all of these thinkers assert an essentially
path is human impiety.ʼ12 We begin as impious. Our similar redemptive sequence. The elements of much the
ʻvisible world is not itself the Temple, it is the Tem- same sequence obtain in Deleuzeʼs philosophy: onto-
pleʼs cryptʼ, the place of an inherited ʻexileʼ from the logical univocity; a critique of its repression or mis-
Temple.13 To gain access to the Temple of Light, from representation; its restoration (redemption) declared
ʻthis dark lump that is our earthʼ,14 the seeing subject through an escape from worldly mediation; dissolution
must pull away from the world and grasp a spiritual of the subject (or equation of subject and object); a
and only spiritual existence. Sensual and spiritual consequent insistence upon the literal and immediate.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 7


Always, Deleuze tries to break out of a Given situa- volatile [through] an irreducible pluralism of discur-
tion (positioned, related, specified, mediated, figured) sive figures and modes of behaviour.ʼ37
towards a situation in which ʻeverything divides, but Third, while the redemptive orientation of Deleuzeʼs
into itselfʼ.26 Deleuzeʼs philosophy of difference has work reduces the play of relations with others to the
nothing to do with the articulation of positions or immediacy of conversion in the Pauline sense, the pub-
interests as such, any more than with the ʻcomplica- lished Deleuze readers generally emphasize his utility
tionʼ of mediation. The mediate conflict of interests as ally in the articulation of a world of pure ʻothernessʼ.
has no more place in Deleuzeʼs ʻworld without othersʼ Massumi finds with Deleuze a ʻhyperdifferentiatedʼ
than it does in Spinozaʼs ʻreasonable commonwealthʼ, subject, which exists only ʻin the interactions between
in Suhrawardîʼs luminescent ʻimaginal worldʼ, or in peopleʼ, expressed through ʻincreasingly nuanced local
Paulʼs ʻone body of Christʼ. The prevailing reception reactionsʼ.38 Hardtʼs Deleuze provides ʻtools for the
of Deleuzeʼs work renders this reading difficult on constitution of a radical democracyʼ, ʻopen to the will
four counts. of its constituent membersʼ.39 Again, Boundasʼs explicit
In the first place, his mainly pluralist followers aim as editor of the Deleuze Reader is to promote his
refuse or restrict the ontological univocity basic to the thought for the reinvigoration of American discussions
redemptive enterprise. With this Deleuze we discover of ʻpostmodernismʼ and ʻdeconstructionʼ: ʻthe ritornello
the ʻforces of difference that compel thought to move of their [Deleuze and Guattariʼs] minor deconstruction
outside a logic of identityʼ.27 As Pierre Zaoui argues in coordinates the manifesto of their radical pluralism.ʼ40
one of the best recent studies, Deleuze provides ʻone There is no room here for the redemptive coordination
of the most fruitful philosophies of differenceʼ because of interests in favour of the one disinterest.
he so insistently dismantles ʻthe identity of the One, The fourth and final point: redemption turns on
the identity of the origin of Being in Platonismʼ.28 As judgement, on definitive, unequivocal (univocal) judge-
Boundas presents him through the Deleuze Reader, ment – a last judgement. But readers of Deleuze are
Deleuze writes the ʻinteraction of differential intensi- virtually unanimous in their assumption that to radical
ties, incommensurable with respect to each otherʼ, and social pluralism corresponds a competing chaos of
disruptive of any teleological coherence.29 Deleuzeʼs evaluations, the dissolution of all hierarchy. Deleuze is
asserted ʻtotal oppositionʼ to Hegel has long been read as the prophet of the equivocal, rather than the uni-
a standard point of departure for the reading of his vocal. He is said to elaborate ʻa theoretical programme
work.30 It is the basis for the distinction of a ʻpureʼ,
ʻnondialecticalʼ difference from a difference which,
ʻin the dialectical relation, is only thinkable in terms
of the implicitly presumed Wholeʼ.31 I will argue, on
the contrary, that Deleuzeʼs redemptive philosophy
always works from, within and toward the assumption
of ontological univocity, the redemptive identity of the
One and the multiple.
Second, our deleuziens generally refuse or limit
the conceptual space Deleuze allots to the agent
of redemption – that is, the thinker, artist or phil-
osopher.32 Hardtʼs Deleuze is especially vigorous
in ʻcombatting the privileges of thoughtʼ, in under-
mining ʻany account that in any way subordinates
being to thoughtʼ.33 With Lecercleʼs Deleuze, ʻthere
is no Totality, and there is no Subject to grasp itʼ,34
but rather a surging ontological delirium, the subver-
sion of all conceivable subjective order.35 According
to Gros, Deleuze refuses all aspects of an ʻoriginary
experienceʼ,36 in favour of what Janicaut describes as
a radical shattering of perspectives: ʻmore than ever,
[with Deleuze] being articulates itself in multiple
ways, on the condition that the unity of the ontologi-
cal signified is hitherto declared false, and becomes

8 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


which aims to be beyond system – and consequently as God thinks, we experience the very feelings of
opposed to all doctrinaire conceptsʼ.41 Lecercleʼs Godʼ.51
assessment is typical: ʻ[Deleuze and Guattariʼs] main The third kind of knowledge achieves a complete
objective was a critique of all the forms of theoretical fusion of self and God, or of Given and Real. And
imperialism that had dominated French philosophy in so the formation of ʻa reasonable being may in this
the 1960s and 1970sʼ,42 and the affirmation of a place sense be said to reproduce and express the effort of
ʻwhere interpretation waversʼ before the profusion of Nature as a wholeʼ52 – creation is expressive of its
possibilities, an ongoing moment of ʻhesitationʼ.43 I creator. It is not a process that separates outcome from
will argue, on the contrary, that Deleuzeʼs redemptive origin, but one which actualizes the initial, virtual
authority is absolute by definition, an authority liter- identity of origin and outcome. The result is original
ally and explicitly beyond discussion, beyond appeal. in both senses (ʻprimordialʼ and ʻunprecedentedʼ). The
Rather than limit or eliminate judgement, Deleuze process itself, the three steps, abolish themselves in
makes it literally unlimited; his judgement is no longer their realization. The equation leaves no remainder.
relative to a judge, a faculty, a place, a constitution or ʻWe do of course appear to reach the third kind of
a set of criteria of judgement, but coincides with itself knowledge… [but] the “transition” is only an appear-
alone – as redemptive of all. ance; in reality we are simply finding ourselves as we
are immediately and eternally in Godʼ53 – very much
The constitution of the Given
on the Pauline model.
Like Spinoza or Nietzsche, Deleuze takes as his criti- In other words, the Real requires an archaeolo-
cal starting point that the Real nature of things has gist. Its original immediacy must be uncovered and
been concealed from us by inherited human tenden- reconstructed through its Given fragments. Hence
cies, by ressentiment, by vicious relations with and the exemplary importance of Foucault, archéologue
between others. Deleuze begins with a version of what par excellence. ʻEverything in [Foucaultʼs] statements
Suhrawardî called our ʻoccidental exileʼ – an exile is real and all reality is manifestly presentʼ, but it
from the Light, from the pole of genuine Orientation.
is nevertheless ʻnot given in … a manifest wayʼ.54
The Real ʻ“Whole” is never “given”ʼ.44 For us, the
The statement ʻis not immediately perceptible but is
Real exists only as repressed or, at best, as partially
always covered over by phrases and propositions.…
expressed, and the fundamental question must be,
We are forced to begin with [Given] words, phrases
ʻhow is the Real led to desire its own repression?ʼ45
and propositionsʼ,55 in order then to extract the virtual
Philosophy as Deleuze conceives it serves to struggle
problem or statement which (ʻfirstʼ) determines them.
with this repression; philosophers and artists have,
For example, what is said about sexuality in the Vic-
first and foremost, a ʻclinicalʼ or ʻsymptomalogicalʼ
torian age is Given as repressed, and it ʻsaysʼ the
function.46
In Spinozaʼs all-important terms, the idea of God repression of sexuality; what is Really stated, however,
is the only adequate basis for the ordering of reality, is the proliferation of determining discourses which
but ʻthat one cannot begin from the idea of God, that define and manipulate the sexual, without respite.56
one cannot from the outset install oneself in God, is Statements ʻare never hiddenʼ but, somehow, a ʻstate-
a constant of Spinozismʼ.47 Divine thought alone is ment does remain hidden if we do not rise to its
authentically Real, original in both senses – but we extractive conditions; on the contrary, it is there and
must become thinkers. ʻThinking is not innate, but says everything as soon as we reach these conditions.ʼ57
must be engendered in thoughtʼ, for ʻwe are born Once extracted, the virtual statement is all-determin-
cut off from our power of action or understanding.ʼ48 ing; this is for Deleuze ʻFoucaultʼs greatest historical
Spinozaʼs exemplary becoming-thinker takes place in principleʼ.58 To become-Real is to be extracted from
three stages. First, we begin in a (Given) ʻchild- the Given. This ʻextractionʼ of virtual from actual is
likeʼ state of ʻimpotence and slaveryʼ, governed by the process which eliminates a situated specificity or
ʻignoranceʼ and ʻchance encountersʼ.49 Second, we context, which makes the Real independent of context
create expressive common notions through such or scale, on the fractal model.59 It is achieved through
encounters which ʻlead us to the idea of Godʼ.50 And annihilation, explosion, or paralysis of the Given.
third, ʻas quickly as possibleʼ, we attain knowledge If the Real is (transcendental) immanence to itself,
of God as from Godʼs perspective, ʻthe knowledge the Given forces which literally ʻcover upʼ or mediate
of Godʼs essence, of particular essences as they are the Real are necessarily transcendent.60 If the Real
in God, and as conceived by Godʼ. Here ʻwe think is one and consequently immanent to itself, trans-

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 9


cendence establishes a world of plurality (as opposed of the subject of work and lack (critique of Oedipus);
to multiplicity); it relates beings to other beings and and (iii) with Foucault, the constitution of the subject
concepts to things.61 Deleuzeʼs critical task is thus in modern thought (critique of ʻManʼ, of the ʻMajorʼ).
ʻto hunt transcendence down in all its formsʼ,62 to Together, they allow us to situate Deleuzeʼs work as
eliminate what he calls ʻthe four shackles of mediation: a refusal of the Given on two levels, one ʻcosmicʼ
… [immediate d]ifference is “mediated” to the extent (with Bergson), the other historical (with Oedipus and
that it is subjected to the fourfold root … of identity, Foucault). On the first level, Deleuze mixes what might
opposition, analogy and resemblance.ʼ63 Immanence be called ʻprophetic fragmentsʼ of the ʻdeath of Manʼ
will exist, then, as beyond identity and beyond oppo- from any available source (ʻnomadicʼ pre-history or
sition, as literal and non-resembling. futuristic post-history; the Stoics as much as Artaud;
For Deleuze as for Spinoza or Paul, the great ques- Spinoza as much as Nietzsche). On the second level,
tion is, how does the Real which is alone creative allow Deleuze aligns himself with a particular moment in
itself to be transcended by its own creations? In some the development of philosophy, working towards this
mysterious way, the Real creates a world in which it death, today, alongside Foucault, Klossowski, Lyotard,
weakens itself, becomes wordly, much as God creates Virilio, Godard, Beckett, Artaud, Michaux, Simondon,
a creature which denies Him. Real ʻvirtual difference Guattari, Badiou, and others, as allies in this effort to
tends to actualize itself in forms which cancel itʼ,64 overcome the Given.
and for Deleuze–Bergson, ʻlife as movement alienates
itself in the material form that it creates; by actual- Bergson and the alienation of life
izing itself, by differentiation itself, it loses “contact Bergsonʼs great virtue, for Deleuze, is his effort to
with the rest of itself”. Every species is thus an arrest account for a mediate, perceiving organism within
of movementʼ.65 Consequently, the restoration of Real the wholly immediate, inorganic Reality of Life, ʻthe
movement will require the extinction of species. If powerful, non-organic Life which grips the worldʼ.69
ʻemergence, change, and mutation affect composing According to Deleuze, Bergson was the first of our
forces, not composed formsʼ,66 the task of philosophy contemporaries to realize that it is strictly ʻimpossibleʼ
is simply to explode the coherence of composed forms. to relate ʻobjectiveʼ things or movements to ʻsubjectiveʼ
In the terms of Anti-Oedipus, for example, the explo- images of movements – this would be to posit two
sion of the mediate, ʻmolarʼ or specific category of the (equivocal) orders of being, in violation of Real uni-
person liberates the immediate desiring-production of vocity. ʻIt [is] necessary, at any cost, to overcome this
singular molecular machines.67 In the terms of Cinema duality of image and movement, of consciousness and
2, dissolution of the sensory-motor schema (roughly, thing.ʼ70 In place of images in the mind and movements
the subject) reveals ʻtime in the pure stateʼ.68 Deleuzeʼs in space, Bergson insists that ʻIMAGE = MOVEMENTʼ.71
philosophy always aims to move from the composed Rather like that of Suhrawardî, Bergsonʼs ʻplane of
to the composing, to restore the original dimensions immanence is entirely made up of Lightʼ.72 Within
of the immanent Whole – to redeem the Real from this Real coherence, the seeing eye is not directed at
its given, worldly condition. Philosophy is both a objects, but rather
becoming-Real of the Given and a critical account of
the eye is in things, in luminous images in them-
how the Given comes to constitute itself at the heart selves. ʻPhotography, if there is photography, is
of the Real. already snapped, already shot, in the very interior
For Deleuze, then, the preamble to any possible of things and for all the points of spaceʼ [Bergson].
philosophy is an account of the Given. This account Things are luminous by themselves without anything
figures, variously, as: the constitution of the moral man illuminating them: all consciousness is something, it
is indistinguishable from the thing … immanent to
or slave in Nietzsche and Philosophy; the constitution
matter.73
of representation and of merely specific difference in
Difference and Repetition; the constitution of worldli- Given consciousness, then, what Deleuze here calls
ness (mondanité, amour) in Proust and Signs; the limi- ʻour consciousness of factʼ, is ʻmerely the opacity
tation of schizophrenia to a ʻclinical conditionʼ and the without which light “is always propagated without its
castration of desire in Anti-Oedipus, and so on. Three source ever having been revealed” [Bergson]ʼ.74 It is,
accounts of the Given stand out as particularly impor- in other words, a gap [écart] in the continuous Real
tant: (i) with Bergson, the constitution of the human fabric of matter-light, a separation of movement and
in its most general form (critique of the organism); (ii) image, maintained in the interests of a coordinated
with capitalism and psychoanalysis, the constitution motor-schema of perception and action. For Deleuze,

10 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


this is mediation, the organism (or ʻOther structureʼ75) mediation. Subjective identity as it exists in relation
at the most basic level. Organisms isolate, reflect to other identities is the privileged Given bulwark
or ʻperceiveʼ only that aspect of Real light which established against Real becomings-imperceptible.
interests them (the herbivore, for example, perceives Deleuzeʼs first book, Empiricism and Subjectivity
food in grass, and only food). Whereas Real percep- (1953), is an attempt to determine with Hume what
tion is disinterested and concrete, Given perception permits the constitution of the transcendent subject
is limited by interest and consequently abstract; ʻwe within a Real field of immanence.82 His first collabora-
perceive only what we are interested in perceiving, tive book, Anti-Oedipus, provides his fullest and most
or rather what it is in our interest to perceive.ʼ76 celebrated answer to this question, now posed as: how
Such a subjectivity is ʻsubtractiveʼ, ʻincomplete and is desire led to desire its own repression?83
prejudicedʼ, while an ʻobjectivelyʼ Real perception is According to Deleuze and Guattari, the Oedipal
ʻcomplete, immediateʼ.77 To become adequate to the subject achieves this repression by linking the two
complete, impartial Real, then, is to overcome the major forms of transcendence: a ʻprivateʼ (subjective)
organic interval, to restore the continuous luminous transcendence of immanence as invoked by the phil-
flow in all its immediacy. It is to overcome interest osophy of representation, and a public (subjected)
and thereby return to the ʻprimary regime of variation, transcendence as performed by the state. In the
in its heat and its light, while it is still untroubled first case, the subject is led to figure the world, to
by any centre of indetermination [i.e. an organism]. represent the world, and, through imagination and
How can we rid ourselves of ourselves, and demolish analogy, negate the literal or immediate presence
ourselves?ʼ78 of the world. This negation is maintained by the
In short, Bergson suggests how we might ʻattain
ʻtheatricalʼ mediation of psychoanalysis. Specifically
once more the world before man, before our own
subjective desire – a subjectʼs desire for an object
dawn, the position where movement was … under
– detaches Real composing desire from its immediate
the regime of universal variation …, the luminous
creation of objects, in order to relate to ʻcomposedʼ
plane of immanenceʼ.79 Deleuzeʼs persistent dream is
objects which it (now) lacks. The paradigm for this
to be thus
missing object is the elusive object of Oedipal desire
present at the dawn of the world. Such is the link (Artaudʼs ʻmommy daddyʼ). To the ʻprivateʼ trans-
between imperceptibility, indiscernibility, and im- cendence of the subject corresponds, in the second
personality – the three virtues. To reduce oneself to
case, the ʻpublicʼ transcendence of the state as over-
an abstract line, a trait, in order to find oneʼs zone
of indiscernibility with other traits, and in this way coding, external instance ʻbeyondʼ production. The
enter the haecceity and impersonality of the creator. state figures in Anti-Oedipus as a kind of primor-
One is then like grass…80 dial super-ego, detached, standing watch above the
now coordinated field of social action. The subject is
Deleuze equates origin and outcome, the realization
thus harnessed to work, under the supervision of the
of the Real in an apocalyptic dawn. The properly
state, in its endless pursuit of the missing object (the
eternal or ʻuntimelyʼ aspect of Deleuzeʼs work is a
fulfilment of desire-as-lack). According to Deleuze
function of his affirmation, wherever he finds them,
of means (nomadic, schizophrenic, stoic, surreal, and Guattari, the capitalist organization of labour, the
aphasic, genetic, fractal, aesthetic…) to this wholly distribution of familial roles across the whole social-
extra-historical end. symbolic field, and the pyschoanalytic interpretation
of desire, are all aspects of a single apparatus for the
repression of the Real (or consolidation of the Given,
Oedipus and the repression of desire of ʻlackʼ). Oedipus is the mechanism which cements
these two subjective–subjected poles of transcendence
ʻOedipusʼ is the broadest term given to what Deleuze
with Guattari analyses as the specifically subjective together. Oedipus is what establishes and relates a
form of transcendence, the most ʻconcentratedʼ form psychological interiority to external social author-
of the organism or ʻbody with organsʼ. Oedipus is that ity;84 the ʻpersonʼ is doubly subjected through the
which unites transcendence and organism in a single mediate ʻcastrationʼ of desire and the transcendent
repressive form. If ʻsubjectivity appears as soon as over-coding of the state.85 A Deleuzian recovery of
there is a gap between a received and an executed the Real, then, will begin with the dissolution of
movementʼ,81 it is because, according to Deleuze, the these two forms of subjection, and the evocation of a
subject is our privileged locus of transcendence or space without person or state.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 11


Foucault and the death of Man the attempt to carry the forces of finitude across
Foucaultʼs famous thesis concerning the imminent the limit of ʻManʼsʼ coherence. The goal is to make
ʻdeath of Manʼ helps specify the historicity of Deleuzeʼs finitude itself the basis of an active or creative infinity.
project – its contemporary urgency. As Deleuze To ʻknowʼ is here to affirm the infinitely disjunctive
presents it, the ʻMan-formʼ analysed by Foucault is forces of life, labour and language in themselves,
our particular version of the Given mediate form as they radiate out along their separate evolutionary
analysed in general by Bergson, and only slightly paths, and in this way restore the infinite of the first
more specifically through Oedipus. Deleuze takes from stage, through the finite, so to speak. That is, within
Les Mots et les choses three stages in the constitu- a finite living organism (ʻManʼ), to affirm an infinite
tion and dissolution of this form: pre-Man (classical), power of Life; within a finite speaking organism,
Man (modern), and after-Man (apocalyptic). Deleuzeʼs to affirm an infinite power of Language; and so on.
thought can be considered quite precisely as an attempt ʻNietzsche said that man imprisoned life, but the
to equate the first and second stages in the third. superman is what frees life within man himself, to
In the first stage, the Real is (correctly, in Deleuzeʼs the benefit of another form.ʼ93
view) identified with the Infinite, with God as infinite So although the infinite now passes through ʻManʼ,
power of understanding, infinite power of creation, and it is no longer located; it explodes all possibility
so on.86 ʻSo long as God exists … then man does not of location. In this, it surpasses the infinite of the
yet exist.ʼ87 But, rather than immediate to the Real, first stage. It has become identical to the immediacy
the human is here identified with a limitation placed of time or being itself. Such contemporary thought
upon such an infinity (for example, the human power of runs like a ʻligne de fuiteʼ through the fractured ʻIʼ
understanding as a limited form of a divinely infinite of Kantʼs constituent cogito.94 Such has been, for
understanding88). The objects of science include only example, the task of a specifically modern litera-
those things which can in principle be extended to ture as Deleuze everywhere endorses it: through and
infinity, constructed in indefinite series out from one alongside the ʻdissemination of languagesʼ recognized
central ʻcreativeʼ point (money or wealth in ʻecon- by philological linguistics, modern literature ʻtook on
omicsʼ, specific differences in ʻbiologyʼ, and so on). a completely different function that consisted, on the
contrary, in “regrouping” language and emphasizing
The great effort of knowledge in the classical age is
a “being of language” beyond whatever it designates
thus the effort to represent or locate itself within the
and signifies.ʼ95 In other words, through a finite liter-
infinite,89 and to explain is here to extend to infinity,
ary mechanism, language ʻturns back on itself in
to ʻunfoldʼ the Real without losing this location.90
an endless reflexivityʼ.96 This is very precisely how
In the second stage, human finitude becomes more
Deleuze envisages his own effort: through the finite
ʻpositivelyʼ constituent (with Kant) than negative or
power of the philosopher, the infinite expression of
limiting. Rather than construct general series referring
the Real.
back to one infinitely creative point, each element
Why canʼt Deleuze simply return to the first, pre-
in a series takes on a self-constituent energy, and
Man stage? Because classical philosophy remains
diverges in an ongoing ʻevolutionʼ of living beings
limited and located, governed in the end by a conver-
(Lamarck, Cuvier, Cournot, Darwin); the force of
gence with God. The third stage, by contrast, puts
work becomes constituent of wealth, and ʻwork itself
Man ʻin charge of the animalsʼ, ʻof the very rocksʼ,
falls back on capital (Ricardo) before the reverse takes
ʻin charge of the being of language (that formless,
place, in which capital falls back on the work extorted
“mute, unsignifying region where language can find
(Marx)ʼ;91 languages no longer refer back to a universal
its freedom” even from whatever it has to say)ʼ.97 In
general grammar but to ʻcollective willsʼ (Bopp, Sch-
legel). Specific, comparative histories replace a general other words, only the third stage effects a kind of
deductive order, histories in which the coordinating becoming-God of man, a becoming infinite of the
finite, and it is this becoming which, as we shall see,
agent is of course ʻManʼ himself, specified as living,
enables Deleuzeʼs redemptive paradigm. The failure
working, speaking, being. In short, ʻManʼ dominates
of classical thought (excepting Spinoza) lies not in
the most powerful order of the Given yet produced,
its affirmation of the infinite and serial, of ʻGodʼ, but
and the only ʻcritique of knowledgeʼ is an ʻontology of
in its timid humility, its refusal to identify itself with
the annihilation of beingsʼ, that is, the annihilation of
God. In the end, it is the specifically human ability
beings specified as living, working or speaking.92
to become inhuman, to become infinite, which will
Hence the third stage, Deleuzeʼs own stage, the stage
redeem the whole of the finite universe. Only the
of the superman, involves affirming this annihilation,

12 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


inhuman is Real, but only the human, of course, can a natural, primordial order. A Real outcome, in each
become inhuman. case, is attained through a loss of interested partial-
ity. History is the remainder that disappears with the
Art and the dissolution of the Given perfect realignment of calculation. For Deleuze as for
Like Spinoza, Deleuze studies the Given for one and dʼAlembert, historian of human knowledges, history
only one reason: to announce the manner of its dissolu- and worldly consciousness have only one purpose: to
tion. Tautologically, in order to regain the immediate achieve their own redundancy.
Real we must ʻforgetʼ or ʻescapeʼ the mediate, on This task defines the purpose of the philosopher and
the model of the ʻschizophrenic escapeʼ.98 An ʻobjec- artist as Deleuze defines them, allies in an ongoing
tiveʼ redemption begins with a subjective paralysis. redemption from the Given. Like the mystic or the
Our ʻmistake [is to] postulate the contemporaneity of Enlightened philosophe, Deleuzeʼs philosopher is
subject and object, whereas one is constituted only defined as the being most capable of renouncing all
through the annihilation of the otherʼ.99 By Deleuzeʼs conceivable interest or specificity. By definition, only
logic this is a properly (and merely) binary logic the most singular subject can renounce a worldly
– either one or the other. ʻThe identity of the self interest – that is, exchange a personal or specific
is lost … to the advantage of an intense multiplicity coherence for an impersonal, cosmic coherence. The
and a power of metamorphosis.ʼ100 To overcome oneʼs ʻembodiment of cosmic memory in creative emotions
limited, interested coherence is, immediately, to par- undoubtedly only takes place in privileged soulsʼ, the
ticipate without reserve in an absolute coherence. ʻThe vehicles of genius.106 This embodiment takes place in
indefinite aspects of a life lose all indetermination ʻisolationʼ, and only occasionally, elliptically, ʻleaps
to the degree that they fill a plane of immanence.ʼ101 from one soul to another, “every now and then”, cross-
To become-Real is to become perfectly automatic, ing closed deserts.ʼ107 The artist or philosopher exists
automated – in Spinozaʼs phrase so often cited by alone, outside history, following the path of Beckettʼs
Deleuze, the ʻspiritual automatonʼ, the model thinker, characters toward pure self-exhaustion (épuisement),
ʻthe identity of brain and world, the automaton.ʼ102 If the solitude of Blanchotʼs espace littéraire.108
ʻthe automaton is cut off from the outside world, there However, the solitude of the artist in no way implies
is a more profound outside which will animate itʼ.103 the ʻprivateʼ idiosyncracy of an artistic vision, a pat-
The figure of the automaton equates a ʻpersonalʼ or ented ʻoriginalityʼ to be treasured by collectors; ʻa
ʻprivateʼ disempowerment with absolute determination statement never refers back to a subjectʼ.109 A Real or
by pure, pre-existent power. ʻminorʼ literature is defined not only by a minimum of
On the one hand, the great spiritual automaton mediation or a ʻhigh coefficient of deterritorializationʼ,
indicates the highest exercise of thought, the way in but by its political, collective articulation. Everything
which thought thinks and itself thinks itself.… On in a minor literature ʻis politicalʼ; its ʻcramped space
the other hand, the automaton … no longer depends forces each individual intrigue to connect immediately
on the outside because he is automonous but be- to politicsʼ.110 ʻKafkaʼs solitudeʼ, for example, ʻopens
cause he is dispossessed of his own thought.104
him up to everything going on in history todayʼ,111
Through our dispossession – through the dissolution of for there is literally nothing and no-one to limit his
the Given – the Real reclaims its own productive auto- articulation of the Real. The solitary minor artist
coincidence. The rise and fall of the Given appears as produces ʻintensive quantities directly on the social
one gigantically redundant exercise. body, in the social field itself. A single, unified process.
Such is the basis of Deleuzeʼs insistent discus- The highest desire desires to be both alone and to be
sions of the eternal return, the eschatological identity connected to all the machines of desire.ʼ112
of origin and outcome, considered as a redemptive The writer is thus defined by his or her lack of
principle, as principle of ʻontological selectionʼ.105 definition, positioned by the lack of position. In this
Eternal return is Deleuzeʼs version of a Last Judge- sense, Deleuze is firmly positioned at the extreme
ment, the determination of what qualifies for eternal limit of what Bourdieu has famously analysed as ʻle
life. Deleuzeʼs redemptive paradigm is not essentially champ littéraireʼ.113 The artist is focus for the abolition
different from the Christian or Enlightened versions of worldly values, in the name of the ʻother-worldlyʼ;
– through sin or superstition, through worldly inter- like the masochist, the genuine Artist ʻsuspendsʼ all
est, a return to original harmony or Reason, pure relations-with and between114 and ʻstops the worldʼ115
disinterest. An Enlightened eventual order, become so as to leave it absolutely, so as to grasp ʻlife in its
actual in history (Mercierʼs Lʼan 2440), will duplicate pure stateʼ.116 As Spinoza is the ʻfulfillment of phil-

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 13


osophyʼ, so ʻArtaud is the fulfillment of literature, narrator stops loving Albertine so as to begin com-
precisely because he is a schizophrenic.ʼ117 Deleuze posing the Recherche. He swaps a worldly position
and Guattariʼs schizophrenic exists ʻas close as pos- (mondaine, amoureuse, sensible) for that artistic coher-
sible to matter, to a burning, living center of matterʼ, ence that excludes our own, ʻthe original complication,
ʻclosest to the beating heart of reality, to an intense the struggle and exchange of the primordial elements
point identical with the production of the realʼ.118 which constitute essence itselfʼ.130 Deleuzeʼs Proust
The ʻschizoʼ is a pure in-between without terms, an writes the shift from specific to singular, relative to
ʻindivisible distanceʼ.119 The artist–schizophrenic has absolute, Given to Real. Deleuze distinguishes four
absolutely nothing to learn from the world. There is regimes of signs in his work, organized in relative
nowhere the artist has not already been. The schizo is proximity to the Real. Worldly signs are the lowest or
from the outset ʻsituated wherever there is a singularity ʻlast degree of essenceʼ,131 the most related, the most
… because he is himself this distance that transforms specific to a place and a group. Next, the signs of
him into a womanʼ, a child, an ʻEskimoʼ, and so on.120 love offer insight into the true solitude or singularity
It is an exemplary definition of the champ littéraire: of the lover, but do so only negatively, through what
the writer is this distance which transforms the related, Spinoza would call ʻbad encountersʼ, the specificity
actual world into an immanent composition whose of a positioned personality, and the perception of
value is precisely that it has no worldly value. others as specific to a world which excludes the lover
So, in a sense, every ʻgreat artistʼ always does (love as jealousy). Closer still to absolute singularity,
the same thing, performs the same radical ascesis of the signs of involuntary memory offer a perfect but
self. The thinker is always Dionysius, or a synonym temporary coincidence between two distinct times.
of Dionysius, a reincarnation of the Real-in-person, They reveal a shared ʻidentical qualityʼ beyond all
the Real depersonalized. Artaudʼs ʻHeliogabalus is specificity, but remain limited as a relation between
Spinoza, and Spinoza is Heliogabalus revivedʼ,121 rather than external to its terms. Artistic signs, finally,
and everything converges toward ʻla grande identité are wholly and sufficiently immediate to the Real,
Spinoza–Nietzscheʼ.122 ʻNo art is imitative, no art can pure essence, beyond all forms of the specific and
be imitative or figurativeʼ,123 because art is Real, and the relative. Art composes the ʻpure and empty form
vice versa. Art, in other words, follows the very move- of timeʼ, immediacy or le temps retrouvé as ʻfinality
ment of the Real, with a minimum of mediation, on the of the worldʼ – ʻthat birth which has become the
model of metallurgy.124 The Real ʻmatter-flow can only metamorphosis of objectsʼ,132 dawn of a world before
be followedʼ, and ʻone writes [then] on the same level (or after) the human. Proust thus composes the Real
as the real of an unformed matter, at the same time by decomposing it in the world; he extracts the Real
as that matter traverses and extends all of nonformal from the specific.133
languageʼ;125 ʻwriting now functions on the same level Francis Bacon so interests Deleuze because his
as the real, and the real materially writes.ʼ126 It is painting retains enough of the figural for Deleuze to
ʻa writing that is strangely polyvocal, flush with the argue that ʻno art is figurativeʼ, that ʻby virtue of its
realʼ,127 and ʻthe only aim [in] writing is life.ʼ128 Real most profound theme, the visual image points to an
or ʻlivingʼ writing is not somehow outside language innocent physical nature, to an immediate life which
(that is, equivocal, in another realm of Being) but the has no need of languageʼ.134 According to Deleuze,
ʻoutside of languageʼ: language become immediate to Bacon like every other Real artist produces a wholly
things; language and things collapsed together in a literal art. His painting ʻreveals presence, directly
single plane.129 [donne à voir la présence, directement]ʼ; with Bacon
Among Deleuzeʼs many artistic models, there is as with Cezanne, ʻpainting aims to extract directly
space to consider only three, chosen from fields as the presences beneath and beyond representation …; it
disparate as possible – Proust, Bacon, and cinema as puts the eye in everythingʼ, and thereby allows a wholly
a whole. (Certainly, Beckett, Kafka, Artaud, Michaux, de-positioned, wholly objective vision, immediate to
Bene, Masoch, and Cézanne are no less important.) the exclusive ʻintensityʼ of the Real, a ʻpure vibrationʼ
The fundamental sequence (Given to Real) is much unlimited by extension of any kind, unqualified by
the same in each case, driven by the immediate as any adjective.135 ʻFreedʼ from positioned or intentional
both means and end – redemptive immediacy as telos representation, painting ʻacts directly upon the nervous
and technique of art. systemʼ, and puts ʻthe emancipated senses into direct
The choice narrated by Proust is typical of the relation with time and thoughtʼ, in a single material
general redemptive pattern. As Deleuze reads it, the plane without intermediaries.136 In short, rather than

14 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


some kind of relation between ʻsubject and object … the person who provokes or is subject to themʼ, but
it is both things at onceʼ; ʻI become in sensation, and consist of ʻwanderings, immobilizings, petrifications
at the same time something happens because of it. In and repetitionsʼ;147 finally, ʻthere is no more [refer-
the last analysis, the same body gives it and receives ential] out-of-fieldʼ but only an ʻautonomous imageʼ
it, and this body is both object and subjectʼ.137 that ʻdestroysʼ, ʻreplacesʼ or ʻcreatesʼ its object and
Perhaps the most vivid and exhaustively detailed of its world.148 Literal images replace figures. ʻThere is
Deleuzeʼs artistic examples is the becoming-immediate no longer association through metaphor or metonymy,
of modern film described in the two Cinema books. but relinkage on the literal image.ʼ149 There is no more
Deleuze aims to show that cinema duplicates the path an ʻin-betweenʼ art and life; ʻit is the whole of the
taken by modern philosophy beginning with Kant,138 real, life in its entirety, which has become spectacleʼ,
from Given to Real – from an indirect, mediate presen- ʻlife as spectacle, and yet in its spontaneity.ʼ150 In
tation of time through relative, positioned movements, other words, the new cinema eliminates the specific
to a direct, immediate presentation of time based through ʻthe extraction of an any-question-whateverʼ.151
on an absolute movement constitutive of all possible Cinema restores ʻour faithʼ in the world, by moving
positions. In the first phase, the ʻmovementʼ or ʻaction- beyond (above or beneath) it. It redeems the world,
imageʼ of cinema is based on the coordination of by exploding it.
perceptions and actions through an intentional subject, According to Deleuze, we regain in the process the
what Deleuze calls the ʻsensory motor schemaʼ which Reality of ʻnon-organic lifeʼ, the identity of Brain and
mediates time in the interests of action.139 It is a Universe, of art and ʻpure thoughtʼ as the very ʻtruth
cinema of the specific and related,140 which orders the of cinemaʼ.152 This truth puts an end to intermediaries.
parts of a ʻchanging open wholeʼ through figurative At the limit, through ʻcontact independent of distanceʼ,
association with a referential ʻworldʼ of some kind, cinema becomes pure resolution of binaries, ʻco-pres-
an ʻout-of-fieldʼ.141 In the second phase, the Given ence or application of … negative and positive, of place
dissolves to reveal the Real in its pure immediacy, in and obverse, of full and empty, of past and future, of
its singular and exclusive element – ʻtime in the pure brain and cosmos, of the inside and the outsideʼ.153 For
stateʼ.142 The ʻsensory-motor schema is shattered from Deleuze, this is always and everywhere the artistic
the inside. That is, perceptions and actions cease to achievement par excellence, a kind of supreme self-
be linked together, and spaces are neither co-ordinated sacrifice, the transcendence of all interests in the
nor filledʼ; the actors become ʻpure seers, who no absolutely singular interest of something else. Such is,
longer exist except in the interval or movementʼ, ren- precisely, the redemptive interest of Thought.
dered ʻhelplessʼ, paralysed within a ʻpure optical and
sound situationʼ.143 Place becomes ʻuninhabitableʼ, ʻany- Thought and the redemptive choice
space-whateverʼ, ʻwaste groundʼ;144 situations become For Deleuze, thought creates what it thinks, as percep-
dispersive rather than integrative;145 the association of tion creates what it perceives (and therefore does not
images becomes ʻellipticalʼ, ʻirrationalʼ and ʻdirectʼ, relate to it). ʻThe philosophical concept does not refer
without ʻintermediariesʼ;146 events no longer ʻconcern to the lived … but consists, through its own creation, in

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 15


setting up an event that surveys [survole] the whole of the modern fact is that we no longer believe in
the lived no less than every state of affairsʼ.154 Deleuze this world. We do not even believe in the events
does not establish a relationship between philosophy which happen to us, love, death as if they only
half concerned us… The link between man and
and other disciplines, other ways of making sense, but
the world is broken. Henceforth this link must
eliminates this relationship to the advantage of a kind become an object of belief: it is the impossible
of ʻgreater philosophyʼ. Thought or philosophy thinks which can only be restored within a faith.… [The
the sufficient reason of the actual. In this way, sensory motor] reaction of which man has been
dispossessed can be replaced only by belief.164
thinking and being are … one and the same …;
movement is not the image of thought without being It is precisely because thought paralyses us as pos-
also the substance of being… It is a single speed on itioned thinking beings, that it is, in a second moment,
both sides: ʻthe atom will traverse space with the redemptive of all positions. Thought allows us to
speed of thoughtʼ (Epicurus). The plane of imma-
recognize and affirm our unjustifiable state (as Paulʼs
nence has two facets as Thought and as Nature, as
Nous and as Physis.155 ʻgraceʼ is beyond relation, beyond merit). In the terms
of Deleuzeʼs Cinema 2, thought destroys the ʻsensory
The power of Thought is for Deleuze very much motor schemaʼ – that is, the ʻsubjectʼ who perceives
that of an unlimited creator God, natura naturans, and reacts to situations – and this ʻbreak makes man a
the union of spontaneity and necessity. Following seer who finds himself struck by something intolerable
Spinoza, ʻpurest of philosophersʼ,156 ʻwe have a power in the world, and confronted by something unthinkable
of knowing, understanding or thinking only to the in thought …; we should make use of this power-
extent that we participate in the absolute power of lessness to believe in life, and to discover the identity
thinkingʼ.157 We think because we are (ʻobjectivelyʼ) of thought and life.ʼ165 It is only ʻthis belief that makes
Thought: ʻthe power of thinking is asserted, by the unthought the specific power of thought, through
nature or by participation, of all that is “objective”.… the absurdʼ.166 Ultimately, ʻthe power of thought gives
But objective being would amount to nothing did way, then, to an unthought in thought, to an irrational
it not itself have a formal being in the attribute of proper to thought, a point beyond the outside world,
Thought.ʼ158 That is why the true thinker is ʻspiritual but capable of restoring our belief in the worldʼ.167 To
automatonʼ, ʻthought as determined by its own laws.ʼ159 choose means to accept what is, to become what we
The automaton reaches that ʻsecret point where the are, and nothing more.
Again, what determines this densely argued
anecdote of life and the aphorism of thought amount to
sequence is immediate coincidence pure and simple.
one and the same thingʼ.160 Thought in itself dissolves
Deleuzeʼs obscure account of ʻthe choiceʼ equates
the thinker as subject.161 As with Suhrawardî or Paul,
chooser and chosen; it joins the supremely ʻsubjec-
the redeemed subject is thought, immediately – on
tiveʼ moment of decision (the moment of Pascal and
condition that he or she stops thinking as a subject. Kierkegaard) and the moment of supreme, absolute
ʻThe activity of thought applies to a receptive being, to automation (the moment of Spinoza and Leibniz).
a passive subject which represents that activity to itself The Real choice is a choice ʻincreasingly identified
rather than enacts it …. Thought thinks only on the with living thoughtʼ.168 To choose the Real is to reach
basis of an unconscious … the universal ungrounding a ʻspiritual space where what we choose is no longer
which characterizes thought as a faculty in its trans- indistinguishable from the choice itselfʼ,169 a place
cendental exercise.ʼ162 where ʻspace is no longer determined, it has become
Thought redeems. To think requires a ʻclean breakʼ, the any-space-whatever which is identical to the power
a leap altogether out of the world, an escape from all of the spirit, [its] “auto-affection”ʼ.170 To ʻbelieveʼ is
worldly opacity and particularity.163 To think is to to return to the all-productive origin of immediacy;
become transparent or insubstantial – to present no ʻit is only, it is simply believing in the body. It is
resistance to the impersonal movement of thought. To giving discourse to the body, and, for this purpose,
think is to escape the Given. With Deleuze, thought reaching the body before discourse, before words,
is not a transitive activity. Thought coincides with its before things are namedʼ.171 Like Humeʼs theory of
own constitution as thought. association developed in Empiricism and Subjectivity,
In other words, to think is also to choose to think the choice is wholly external to its terms.172 Choice
– to choose Real over Given, to refuse the world. chooses the dissolution of terms. ʻIn short, choice
Deleuze, like Paul or Pascal, erects a logic of choice as spiritual determination has no other object other
at the very centre of thought. According to Deleuze, than itself: I choose to choose …[choice] in this way

16 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


confirming itself by itself, by putting the whole stake choice of one motive over another, but entails the
back into play each timeʼ.173 The choice, like the dice- absence of a specific motive as such, the absence of
throw of Difference and Repetition and Nietzsche and a subjective specificity.181 With Leibniz, ʻeverything
Philosophy, equates player and play, rules and game, is sealed off from the beginning and remains in a
stakes and ʻstakerʼ. condition of closureʼ.182 To be ʻfreeʼ, in other words,
According to Deleuze, ʻthe true choice, that which can only mean, to be free of worldly interest as such.
consists in choosing choice, is supposed to restore Freedom is here an expressive state, rather than situ-
everything to us. It will enable us to rediscover every- ated action. Since ʻeach monad is nothing other than
thing, in the spirit of sacrifice, at the moment of the a passage of Godʼ, ʻthe voluntary act is free because
sacrificeʼ. To be thus redeemed is to renounce the the free act is what expresses the entire soul at a given
world in favour of a ʻpure, immanent or spiritual light, moment of its duration.ʼ183 What a free monad does is
beyond white, black and grey. As soon as this light include or express what inheres in it – ʻinherence is
is reached it restores everything to usʼ.174 In the eco- the condition of liberty and not of impedimentʼ.184 For
nomical terms of Deleuzeʼs Foucault, ʻonly forgetting Deleuze, freedom has only a literal value: free equals
(the unfolding) recovers what is folded in memory (and unlimited, free of specific limits. Free is all-inclusive,
in the fold itself)ʼ.175 or dis-interested. The properly ʻethicalʼ or political
Why does Deleuzeʼs choice restore the world? issue for Deleuze is never what is conventionally dis-
Simply because it claims to be wholly, perfectly cussed as human liberty but rather liberation from the
identical to it, in its creativity, as natura naturans. human – ʻla liberté devenue capacité pour lʼhomme de
It restores not a world Given for us (naturata), but vaincre lʼhomme.ʼ185 Since ʻmanʼ is itself the ʻprisonʼ,
the world as it is in itself, in its ʻgenitalityʼ. In the ʻlife becomes resistance to power [only] when power
chosen immediacy, the chooser gains access to ʻthe takes life as its objectʼ, to the exclusion of the merely
power of a constitution of bodiesʼ, and carries ʻout a living as such (ʻmanʼ, the organism).186
primordial genesis of bodiesʼ: ʻconstituting bodies, and In other words, Deleuzeʼs ʻfaith in the worldʼ is
in this way restoring our belief in the world, restoring restored, ultimately, because his chosen ʻbreak with
our reason…ʼ.176 What Deleuze says of the German the worldʼ is offset by a still more radical fusion with
expressionists, artists of the ʻdynamic sublimeʼ, applies its ʻcreatorʼ or sufficient reason.187 He breaks with the
nicely to his own redemptive paradigm: Given so as to return to the Real. He restores faith in
it is intensity which is raised to such a power a ʻworldʼ to which he has perfectly immediate access
that it dazzles or annihilates our organic be- – access beyond the mediation of a ʻpriestʼ, beyond
ing, strikes terror into it, but arouses a thinking ʻinterpretationʼ188 – much as the Enlightened think-
faculty by which we feel superior to that which ers restore their faith to a Reason they immediately
annihilates us, to discover in us a supra-organic incarnate (Montesquieuʼs principes, Diderotʼs arbre
spirit which dominates the whole inorganic life
encyclopédique). We cannot, of course, question the
of things; then we lose our fear, knowing that
our spritiual ʻdestinationʼ is truly invincible.177 validity of Deleuzeʼs choice without transforming it
into the very choice which, like Melvilleʼs Bartelby,
What is really ʻinvincibleʼ here is the immediate equa- he ʻprefers notʼ to choose. But we can demonstrate
tion of all the terms involved (chooser, choice, chosen). its consistency with other logics (Pauline, Enlight-
The identity of the terms ensures their perfect revers- ened…) which equate redemption with the sacrifice of
ibility. Deleuzeʼs Real chooser is, as with Nietzsche a positioned interest, and consider for whom Deleuzeʼs
or Paul, himself chosen (élu): ʻonly he who is chosen choice is valid. Who can afford this sacrifice? Who
chooses well or effectivelyʼ.178 To be chosen is to fuse has an interest in disinterest? Like Spinoza, like Paul,
with ʻgraceʼ, to become, in the mystical formula of Deleuze writes for the establishment of one univocal
Cinema 2, one with ʻthe Spirit, he who blows where order, ʻone body directed by one mindʼ. His univocal
he willʼ.179 excludes the equivocal; his One-multiple excludes the
That is why, again, Deleuze always equates the many; his literal excludes the figural. Deleuzeʼs phil-
ʻfreedomʼ of Real choice with the purest form of osophy proclaims a redemptive dislocation of interests
automation. In Spinozaʼs exemplary ʻethical vision every bit as radical as that asserted, in their very
of the world it is always a matter of capacity and different ways, by his contemporaries Lévinas and
power, and never of anything else. In a sense every Badiou.
being, each moment, does all it can.ʼ180 With Deleuzeʼs Whatever the virtues of Deleuzeʼs philosophy, then,
Leibniz, likewise, a free act is not determined by a we should not mistake it for what it most emphati-

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 17


cally is not – a philosophy that complicates the realm Real than others. Univocity guarantees the integrity of
of immediate expression, that subverts a univocal a single quantitative scale of reality, a single matrix of
order, that disrupts a strict ontological homogeneity, salvation (the more or less redeemed). In a way, this
that promotes a world of complex relations between matrix is more ʻdamningʼ, more ʻinclusiveʼ, than Paulʼs
distinct, specific individuals or others. If most of dualism. Deleuzeʼs redemptive philosophy, coupled
Deleuzeʼs commentators look to his work for tools in with his ontological univocity, ensures a hierarchy of
the building of a ʻradical democracyʼ, to advance the beings every bit as dizzying as the vertical layering
deconstruction of ʻMajorʼ narratives and hierarchies, of Lights in Suhrawardîʼs cosmology. With Deleuze,
to support the assertion of ʻMinor identitiesʼ and dif- everything is physical, but our world is proclaimed
ferences, they seldom consider the terms upon which minimally physical. Everything is Real, but positioned;
this apparent pluralism rests. Invariably, ʻmultiplicityʼ specific actors are confined – once again – to a world
with Deleuze is the predicate of a radical, self-differ- of illusion. This is a world that lacks even the paltry
ing singularity. His multiple is not the plural, but the autonomy accorded the negative term in a binary
internal consequence of univocity. opposition: it is merely the weak, diluted aspect of
Despite his own very practical engagement in politi- the philosophy that exceeds it.
cal struggle, Deleuzeʼs political philosophy thus leaves
Notes
little no room for a confrontation with the equivocal
1. As Christian Jambet puts it, ʻSuhrawardî is like a Spino-
as such. With Hume, Deleuze knows that ʻparticular
za of Lightʼ, La Logique des Orientaux, Seuil, Paris,
interests cannot be made identical to one another, or be 1983, p. 142; cf. pp. 108–12, 163.
naturally totalized. Nonetheless, nature demands that 2. Throughout this article, I capitalize this meaning of
they be made identicalʼ.189 So with Spinoza, Deleuze ʻGivenʼ to form an antithetical pair with ʻRealʼ.
3. Difference and Repetition (hereafter DR), trans. Paul
looks for a way to accomplish this identity that is Patton, Columbia University Press, New York, 1994,
ʻnaturalʼ yet not given as such. Only something like p. 35. ʻLʼun se dit en un seul et même sens de tout le
Spinozaʼs ʻsovereign City has power enough to institute multipleʼ, A Thousand Plateaus (hereafter TP), trans.
Brian Massumi, University of Minnesota Press, Min-
indirect conventional relations through which citizens
neapolis, 1986, p. 254; ʻa single and same voice for
are forced to agree and be compatibleʼ:190 Deleuzeʼs the whole thousand-voiced multipleʼ, DR, p. 304. Cf.
own political philosophy assumes comparable power. Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Hab-
The sovereign interest is built on the renunciation of berjam, Zone, New York, 1988, p. 29.
4. [with Félix Guattari] Anti-Oedipus (hereafter AO),
interests, and the ʻreasonableʼ citizen is precisely that
trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and Helen R. Lane,
ʻpersonʼ beyond the reach of ʻany personal affections University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1977, pp.
whateverʼ.191 The multiple, always, is impersonal and 26, 32: ʻthe objective being of desire is the Real in
ahistorical, and has nothing to do with the aggrega- and of itselfʼ and ʻdesire does not lack anythingʼ (pp.
26–7).
tion let alone the negotiation or mediation of personal 5. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (hereafter EP),
affections or interests.192 The multiple is a function trans. Martin Joughin, Zone, New York, 1990, p. 11.
of what the One can become – as One. Deleuzeʼs 6. The Letters of Paul to the Romans 1.19–20; 8.39. I
ʻbecoming-otherʼ, in short, is precisely the tendency refer to the text of The New English Bible, Oxford
and Cambridge University Presses, 1961, volume 2. I
of a ʻworld without others.ʼ193 ʻBecoming-otherʼ is the
draw here, in part, on Alain Badiou, ʻSaint Paul et la
very movement of redemption, the movement away fondation de lʼuniverselʼ, lectures given at the Collège
from relations with others. Deleuzian ʻbecomingsʼ are International de la philosophie, 1995–96.
not of this world. 7. Romans 3.20; cf. Romans 7.7–10.
Hence the lasting ambiguity of Deleuzeʼs work. 8. Romans 12.2; 8.9.
9. The Letter of Paul to the Galations 3.28; cf. The First
Unlike Paul or Suhrawardî, of course, Deleuze is Letter of Paul to the Corinthians, 12.13.
a self-declared empiricist, a radical materialist. The 10. The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles
Deleuzian version of univocity certainly means that Stivale, Columbia University Press, New York, 1990,
ʻone must find a fully physical usage for principles p. 306.
11. Shihâboddîn Yahya Suhrawardî (Shaykh al-Ishrâq), Le
whose nature is only physical…ʼ, geared to a single Livre de la Sagesse orientale, translated and edited by
ʻMechanosphereʼ194 There is no ontological dualism Henri Corbin, introduction by Christian Jambet, Ver-
here, of spirit and flesh, life and death, light and opacity. dier, Lagrasse, 1986, §129–30, pp. 112–13.
12. Suhrawardî, LʼArchange empourpré, Quinze traités et
With Deleuze, we know that everything is Real, that all
récits mystiques, translated and edited by Henri Corbin,
inheres on the same plane. Yet the redemptive move- Fayard, Paris, 1976, p. 431.
ment remains. The enabling conclusion follows neces- 13. Henri Corbin, Temple et contemplation, Flammarion,
sarily: everything is Real – but some things are more Paris, 1981, p. 293; En Islam iranien, Gallimard, Paris,
1971, pp. i, 46; Histoire de la philosophie islamique,

18 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


Gallimard, ʻFolioʼ, Paris, 1986, pp. 129, 138. phrenia, MIT Press, Cambridge MA, 1992, pp. 26,
14. Suhrawardî, Archange, p. 57. 69.
15. Suhrawardî, Le Livre des tablettes, ch. vii, in Archange, 39. Hardt, Gilles Deleuze, pp. 119–20.
p. 104. 40. Boundas, ʻIntroductionʼ, Deleuze Reader, pp. 21, 13–
16. Suhrawardî, Archange, pp. 101–2; cf. Corbin, En Islam 14.
iranien, pp. ii, 22. 41. Guilmette, Deleuze et la modernité, p. 20. Cf. Boun-
17. Eva de Vitray-Meyerovitch, ʻLa Poétique de lʼIslamʼ, das, Deleuze Reader, p. 2; X. Papaïs, ʻPuissances de
in Julia Kristeva, ed., La Traversée des signes, Seuil, lʼartificeʼ, Philosophie 47, September 1995, p. 86.
Paris, 1975, p. 216. 42. Lecercle, Philosophy through the Looking-Glass, p.
18. Jambet, Logique, p. 38; Henri Corbin, Philosophie 185.
iranienne et philosophie comparée (1977), Buchet- 43. Ibid., pp. 107, 110; Bogue, Deleuze and Guattari, p.
Chastel, Paris, 1985, p. 118. 161. It follows that Deleuzeʼs concepts are supposed to
19. Jambet, Logique, pp. 118, 224–5; cf. p. 231. be ʻindefinitely variableʼ (Jean-Clet Martin, Variations.
20. Baruch Spinoza, Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, in The La Philosophie de Gilles Deleuze, Editions Payot et
Political Works, edited by A. Wernham, Oxford Uni- Rivages, Paris, 1993, p. 11).
versity Press, Oxford, 1958, p. 83. 44. Bergsonism, p. 104.
21. ʻHuman nature is such that everyone pursues his pri- 45. Cf. AO, pp. 29, 119.
vate advantage with the greatest eagernessʼ (Spinoza, 46. Cinema 1: The Mouvement-Image (hereafter C1), trans.
Tractatus Politicus, in The Political Works, p. 337). Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, University
22. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, edited by C.B. Mac- of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1986, p. 125; Maso-
pherson, Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1968, pp. 263–4. chism: An Interpretation of Coldness and Cruelty (here-
The deduction of sovereignty, for Spinoza as much as after MC), G. Braziller, New York, 1971, pp. 15–16;
for Bossuet, ʻrequires no belief in historical narratives Negotiations: Interviews 1972–1990, Columbia Uni-
of any kindʼ (Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, p. 73) but versity Press, New York, 1995, p. 195.
is, rather, ʻself-validating and self-evidentʼ (p. 75). It 47. EP, p. 137.
follows immediately from itself. 48. DR, p. 147; EP, p. 307.
23. Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, p. 133. 49. EP, pp. 263, 289–90.
24. Tractatus Politicus, p. 367. 50. EP, pp. 296, 297.
25. Tractatus Politicus, pp. 373, 383. 51. EP, pp. 303, 308.
26. AO, p. 76; cf. The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, 52. EP, p. 265.
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1993, p. 53. EP, p. 308.
7; TP, pp. 153, 335. 54. Foucault (hereafter FC), trans. Seán Hand, University
27. Ronald Bogue, Deleuze and Guattari, Routledge, New of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1988, pp. 3, 16, my
York, 1989, p. 156. emphasis. Again, ʻcinemaʼs concepts are not given in
28. P. Zaoui, ʻLa grande identité Nietzsche–Spinoza, quelle the cinema. And yet they are cinemaʼs concepts, not
identité?ʼ, Philosophie 47, September 1995, pp. 64–5. theories about cinemaʼ (Cinema 2: The Time-Image
29. C. Boundas, ʻIntroductionʼ, The Deleuze Reader, Co- (hereafter C2), trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara
lumbia University Press, New York, 1992, p. 11. Habberjam, University of Minnesota Press, Minne-
30. Michael Hardt, Gilles Deleuze: An Apprenticeship in apolis, 1989, p. 280, my emphasis).
Philosophy, University of Minnesota Press, Minne- 55. FC, pp. 16–17.
apolis, 1992, pp. 52–3; xii, 8–13, 27–8, 115; François 56. FC, p. 53.
Zourabichvili, Deleuze: Une philosophie de lʼévéne- 57. FC, pp. 53, 54; cf. p. 59.
ment, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1995, 58. FC, p. 54.
pp. 56–8; Bogue, Deleuze and Guattari, pp. 2, 15–17, 59. ʻThe task of philosophy when it creates concepts, en-
156; Armand Guilmette, Gilles Deleuze et la modernité, tities, is always to extract an event from things and
Trois-Rivières, Les Editions du Zéphyr, Ottawa, 1984, beingsʼ ([with Félix Guattari] What is Philosophy?
p. 14. It is consequently typical to assume that, rather (hereafter WP), trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham
than Spinoza, it is Nietzsche – the same radically anti- Burchell, Columbia University Press, New York, 1994,
Hegelian Nietzsche of Klossowski and Foucault – who p. 33), just as ʻthe essence of the cinematographic
is the decisive model and ally. movement-image lies in extracting from vehicles or
31. Zourabichvili, Deleuze, p. 53. moving bodies the movement which is their common
32. Hardt, Gilles Deleuze, p. 38. Cf. Philippe Mengue, substanceʼ.
Deleuze: Le système du multiple, Kimé, Paris, 1995, 60. Cf. Mireille Buydens, Sahara: Lʼesthétique de Gilles
pp. 10, 53, 291–3; Jean-Jacques Lecercle, Philosophy Deleuze, Vrin, Paris, 1990, p. 22.
through the Looking-Glass, Open Court, Lasalle, 1985, 61. WP, p. 47; Gilles Deleuze, ʻLʼimmanence: une vieʼ,
pp. 40–41; Bogue, Deleuze and Guattari, pp. 141–2. Philosophie 47, September 1995, p. 5.
33. Hardt, Gilles Deleuze, pp. 79–85, xiii. 62. WP, pp. 48–9.
34. Lecercle, Philosophy through the Looking-Glass, 63. DR, p. 29.
p. 163. 64. DR, p. 228.
35. Ibid., pp. 38, 41. 65. Bergsonism, p. 104.
36. F. Gros, ʻLe Foucault de Deleuze: une fiction méta- 66. FC, p. 87.
physiqueʼ, Philosophie 47, September 1995, p. 56. 67. AO, p. 285.
37. D. Janicaut, ʻFranceʼ, in R. Klibanski and D. Pears, eds, 68. C2, pp. xi, 169.
La Philosophie en Europe, Gallimard, ʻIdéesʼ, Paris, 69. C2, p. 81.
1993, p. 161. 70. C1, p. 56.
38. B. Massumi, A Userʼs Guide to Capitalism and Schizo- 71. C1, p. 58; ʻbodies in themselves are already a lan-

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 19


guageʼ, and ʻlanguage is always the language of bodiesʼ 107. Ibid., p. 111.
(Proust and Signs, trans. Richard Howard, G. Braziller, 108. Deleuze, LʼEpuisé, Minuit, Paris, 1992. Cf. Blanchot,
New York, 1972, p. 91). LʼEntretien Infini, Gallimard, Paris, 1969, pp. 304–5;
72. C1, p. 61. ʻThe Essential Solitudeʼ, in The Space of Literature,
73. C1, p. 61. trans. Ann Smock, University of Nebraska Press, Lin-
74. C1, p. 61. coln, pp. 19–34; Faux Pas, Gallimard, Paris, 1943, pp.
75. The Logic of Sense, p. 306. 10–11.
76. C2, p. 20, my emphasis. ʻIt is grass in general that 109. [with Félix Guattari] Kafka: Toward a Minor Litera-
interests the herbivoreʼ and ʻit is in this sense that the ture, trans. Dana Polan, University of Minnesota Press,
sensory-motor schema is an agent of abstractionʼ as Minneapolis, 1986, pp. 83–4; cf. TP, p. 84, FC pas-
opposed to Deleuzeʼs Real ʻconcreteʼ (C2, p. 45). sim.
77. C1, pp. 64, 63. 110. Kafka, p. 17, my emphasis.
78. C1, p. 66. 111. Ibid., pp. 17–18.
79. C1, p. 68, my emphasis. 112. Ibid., p. 71.
80. TP, p. 280 – ʻlike grassʼ, rather than ʻinterested in 113. P. Bourdieu, Les Règles de lʼart, Seuil, Paris, 1992.
grassʼ. Cf. AO, p. 281. 114. MC, pp. 28, 31; Kafka, p. 84.
81. C2, p. 47. 115. C1, p. 85; C2, p. 68.
82. ʻThe mind is not subject; it is subjectedʼ (Empiricism 116. MC, p. 63.
and Subjectivity, trans. Constantin Boundas, Columbia 117. WP, p. 48; AO, p. 135.
University Press, New York, 1991, p. 31). 118. AO, pp. 19, 87.
83. Cf. AO, pp. 29, 119. 119. AO, p. 76.
84. AO, p. 79; cf. TP, p. 124. 120. AO, pp. 76–7.
85. AO, pp. 54, 73, 269. 121. TP, p. 158.
86. FC, p. 88. 122. Negotiations, pp. 185, 199.
87. FC, p. 130. 123. TP, p. 304; Francis Bacon: Logique de la sensation,
88. FC, pp. 124–5. Vol. 1, Editions de la Différence, Paris, 1981, p. 14.
89. Deleuze relies here on M. Serres, Le Système de Leib- 124. See TP, p. 411.
niz, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1982, pp. 125. TP, p. 512.
648–57. 126. TP, p. 141, my emphasis.
90. FC, p. 126. 127. AO, p. 87.
91. FC, p. 128. 128. Dialogues, with Claire Parnet, trans. Hugh Tomlinson
92. FC, p. 130. and Barbara Habberjam, Columbia University Press,
93. FC, p. 130. New York, 1987, pp. 6, 50.
94. Kantʼs Critical Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and 129. Critique et clinique, Minuit, Paris, 1993, p. 16.
Barbara Habberjam, University of Minnesota Press, 130. Proust and Signs, p. 47.
Minneapolis, 1984, p. vii; DR, pp. 85–6, 194, 199. 131. Ibid., p. 79.
95. Deleuzeʼs examples include ʻMallarméʼs Livre, Péguyʼs 132. Ibid., pp. 49, 48.
repetitions, Artaudʼs breaths, the agrammaticality of 133. ʻFrom every finite thing, Proust makes a being of sens-
Cummings, Burroughs and his cut-ups and fold-ins, as ation that is constantly preserved, but by vanishing on
well as Rousselʼs proliferations, Brissetʼs derivations, a plane of compositionʼ (WP, p. 189).
Dada collage, and so on. And is this unlimited finity 134. Francis Bacon, pp. 39, 13–14.
or superfold not what Nietzsche had already designated 135. Francis Bacon, pp. 37, 33.
with the name of eternal return?ʼ (FC, p. 131). 136. Ibid., p. 37; C2, p. 17; Francis Bacon, p. 14.
96. FC, p. 131. 137. Ibid., p. 27.
97. FC, p. 132. 138. C2, p. xi.
98. AO, p. 341. 139. C1, p. 152.
99. The Logic of Sense, p. 310. 140. C1, p. 134.
100. Ibid., p. 297. 141. C2, p. 179.
101. Deleuze, ʻLʼImmanence: une vieʼ, p. 6; cf. C2, p. 142. C2, p. xi.
245. 143. C2, p. 41.
102. C2, p. 206. ʻThe spiritual automaton, ʻmechanical manʼ 144. C1, p. 121; C2, p. xi.
is … a little time in the pure stateʼ (C2, p. 169). 145. C1, p. 207.
103. C2, p. 179, my emphasis. 146. C1, pp. 207, 168.
104. C2, p. 263. 147. C1, p. 207; C2, p. 103.
105. TP, p. 508. ʻEternal return alone effects the true selec- 148. C2, p. 181; C2, p. 251.
tion, because it eliminates the average forms and un- 149. C2, pp. 214, 42.
covers “the superior form of everything that is” … the 150. C2, pp. 83–4, 89. ʻThe whole cinema becomes a free,
superior form is not the infinite, but rather the eternal indirect discourse, operating in realityʼ (C2, p. 155).
formlessness of the eternal return itselfʼ (DR, p. 55, my 151. C1, p. 189.
emphasis). 152. C2, p. 214; C1, p. 215; C2, p. 151.
106. Bergsonism, p. 111. For Deleuze as much as for Berg- 153. C2, p. 215.
son, ʻthe great souls … are those of artists and mystics 154. WP, pp. 33–4.
… The mystical soul actively plays the whole of the 155. WP, p. 38.
universe, and reproduces the opening of a Whole in 156. Negotiations, p. 140.
which there is nothing to see or to contemplateʼ (ibid. 157. EP, p. 142.
p. 112). 158. EP, p. 122.

20 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


159. EP, pp. 158, 115, 131, 160.
160. The Logic of Sense, p. 128. CALL FOR PAPERS
161. DR, p. 85; Kantʼs Critical Philosophy, p. viii.
162. DR, pp. 85–6, 199, 194; Kantʼs Critical Philosophy, UK Association for
pp. viii–ix.
163. ʻA clean break is something you cannot come back Legal and Social Philosophy
from; that is irretrievable because it makes the past
cease to existʼ (Dialogues, p. 38). 24th Annual Conference
164. C2, pp. 171–2.
165.
166.
C2, p. 170, my emphasis.
C2, p. 170. Communitarianism
167.
168.
C2, p. 181.
C2, p. 177.
and Citizenship
169. C1, p. 117.
170. C1, p. 117.
171. C2, pp. 172–3, my emphasis.
3–5 April 1997
172. Empiricism and Subjectivity, pp. 108–9. Faculty of Law,
173. C1, pp. 114–15.
174. C1, p. 116, my emphasis.
University of Edinburgh
175. FC, p. 107.
176. C2, pp. 201; 200–201. Papers should last 30 minutes. Ab-
177. C1, p. 53.
stracts (one side of A4) should be
178. C2, p. 178.
179. C2, p. 178. sent to Emilios Christodoulidis as
180. EP, p. 269. Modern cinema is likewise ʻautomatism soon as possible and no later than
become spiritual artʼ; through cinema, ʻthe moving ma-
February 28. A booklet of abstracts
chine becomes one with the psychological automaton
pure and simpleʼ (C2, p. 263). will be circulated to participants in
181. The Fold, p. 69. the conference packs. It is likely that
182. Ibid., p. 68. a selection of conference papers will
183. Ibid., pp. 73, 70.
be published after the conference.
184. Ibid., p. 70.
185. Gilles Deleuze, Périclès et Verdi: La philosophie de The Austin Lecture is planned for the
François Châtelet, Minuit, Paris, 1988, p. 11; cf. FC, evening of April 3. It will be given by
p. 90.
186. FC, p. 92. Cf. Périclès et Verdi, p. 13.
Professor Philip Selznick, University
187. C2, p. 188. of California at Berkeley, and will ad-
188. AO, p. 111, 171. Cf. Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. dress themes developed in his recent
Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, University
of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1983, p. 131. The Moral Commonwealth.
189. Empiricism and Subjectivity, p. 43.
190. EP, p. 266.
Prices:
191. EP, p. 267.
192. Ultimately, Deleuzeʼs philosophy of the choice chooses
£170 fully residential
ʻthe erasure of the unity of man and the world, in favour £100 non-residential
of a break which now leaves us with only a belief in this Non-members please add £20 to cover
worldʼ (C2, p. 188). His nomads ʻdo not exist in historyʼ one year’s membership of the asso-
(TP, pp. 23, 393–4), his ʻmultiplicities are made up of ciation, including subscriptions to Res
becomings without historyʼ (Dialogues, p. viii), and
Publica.
with Guattari he insists, of course, that ʻno, we have
never seen a schizophrenicʼ (AO, p. 380) – this is his
ʻfavourite sentence in Anti-Oedipusʼ (Negotiations, p. For further information and to obtain
12). registration forms, contact
193. The Logic of Sense, pp. 306ff.
Emilios Christodoulidis,
194. Empiricism and Subjectivity, p. 119; TP, p. 514.
Centre for Law and Society, Faculty of
Law, University of Edinburgh,
Old College, South Bridge,
Edinburgh EH8 9YL
fax: 131 6624902
e-mail: Emilios.Christodoulidis@ed.ac.uk

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 21


Unhewn demonstrations
Andrew Collier

Compell the Reasoner to Demonstrate with unhewn spontaneously, when we are not making experiments.
Demonstrations. How can such experiments yield such knowledge,
Let the Indefinite be explored, and let every Man be rather than just the knowledge of what happens in the
Judged
experiments themselves? And why is it necessary to
By his own Works. Let all Indefinites be thrown
force nature in this way, rather than just observe what
into Demonstrations,
To be pounded to dust & melted in the Furnaces of nature would do without our interference?
Affliction. Bhaskarʼs answer, which forms the basis of
He who would do good to another must do it in critical realism, is that an experiment isolates one
Minute Particulars: mechanism of nature from the others. Under normal
General Good is the plea of the scoundrel, hypocrite (non-experimental) conditions, the course of events is
& flatterer. co-determined by a number of mechanisms working
For Art & Science cannot exist but in minutely
together. By preventing some of these mechanisms
organized Particulars
from working, or keeping their operation constant, or
And not in generalizing Demonstrations of the Ra-
tional Power. measuring and discounting their operation, an experi-
William Blake, ʻJerusalemʼ1 ment isolates one mechanism, and shows what it is.
We may assume that when no experiment is going
This article is intended as a contribution to criti- on, the same mechanism works, but in conjunction
cal realist philosophy, not a criticism of it, but my with others.
starting point is a paradox about the critical realist An experiment, in other words, abstracts from
corpus, and my conclusion a rather surprising practi- certain mechanisms to identify others. It does not
cal consequence of it. Indeed the conclusion involves just do so in thought, but makes the abstraction real.
incorporating into a scientific realist position some It gives rise therefore to abstract laws – laws which
views which are normally associated with romantic would predict how something behaves other things
or Green critiques of science, though there is nothing being equal, but do not predict how anything will
essentially anti-scientific about them.2 behave in the real world where other things never are
The motivation of critical realist work has mainly equal. Other things are only equal when we artificially
been the rectification of method in the human sciences. make them equal – and that is just what an experi-
Roy Bhaskar in particular is explicit about his desire ment is. Experiments give rise to what may be called
that critical realism shall do this underlabouring not the abstract sciences, since they are each about one
only for the work of science but for the work of human set of laws which we have discovered by abstraction.
emancipation. This could hardly be claimed if critical They are not about particular entities of one sort or
realism limited itself to theorizing the natural sciences, another. Physics is not specially about the physical
and indeed it has been in the human sciences that world; chemistry is equally about the physical world.
critical realism has had most impact. Yet the central Chemistry is not about ʻchemicalsʼ in the sense that the
and most fundamental argument of critical realism has chemical industry produces chemicals. It is about the
been an argument from the possibility and necessity of chemical aspect of the whole physical world, including
experiment in science – and there are no experiments living organisms, for instance.
in the human sciences. Bhaskarʼs argument confirms and explains the
The central argument to which I refer goes as importance of experiments for the abstract sciences,
follows. In experiments, we make nature do what it but it also shows that the laws defining those sciences
would otherwise not have done. We do so in order to are not actualized; nothing is more fundamental to the
find out how nature produces the effects that it does physical sciences than the law of inertia, which states

22 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


that bodies tend to remain at rest or in uniform motion Note that this diagram4 is not saying that mechanisms
in a given direction. But nothing in the universe has are somehow more real than events or experiences, as
ever remained at rest or in uniform motion in a given is sometimes alleged, but just that they are also real.
direction. This is no skin off the physicistsʼ noses But the concrete sciences are real sciences too,
though, for although a cricket ball does not exemplify or at any rate they are an essential part of the body
inertia, we need the law of inertia alongside the law of of knowledge outside of which the abstract sciences
gravity and the laws governing air resistance in order would make no sense. For while the concrete sciences
to explain its flight. can certainly draw on the knowledge yielded by the
Now some natural sciences – for instance geog- abstract sciences, they can also do quite a few things
raphy, meteorology, medicine – are about particular that the abstract sciences canʼt, and without which
entities. They may be called the concrete sciences. things being done all science would lose its point.
When making the distinction between abstract and In the first place, they have in their practical deal-
concrete sciences, Husserl says that abstract sciences ings with their objects a source of knowledge indepen-
ʻare nomological in so far as their unifying principle, dent of the abstract sciences. Second, they can carry
as well as their essential aim of research, is a lawʼ, out a depth analysis of concrete beings, which abstract
whereas in concrete sciences ʻone connects all the sciences cannot. And third, they can draw practical
truths whose content relates to one and the same conclusions from their knowledge. I shall return to
object, or to one and the same empirical genusʼ. He these points with reference to the human sciences.
tells us that ʻthe abstract or nomological sciences are Let me illustrate this with reference to a practical
the genuine, basic sciences, from whose theoretical discipline, which, while it would not normally be
stock the concrete sciences must derive all that theo- described as a science, can be more or less scientifi-
retical element by which they are made sciences.ʼ3 cally done, and which brings out many of the strengths
It is only by getting the relation between the and weaknesses of the concrete sciences. I refer to the
abstract and the concrete sciences right that we will teaching of singing, particularly operatic singing.5
be able to understand the position of the human sci- I have said that concrete sciences have two sources
ences. The abstract sciences – for example, physics of knowledge: what they borrow from the abstract
and chemistry – are self-standing in the sense that sciences and what they pick up from practical experi-
they can justify themselves experimentally, and so ence. They also have two tasks which abstract sciences
donʼt need to rely on the concrete sciences in which cannot undertake, namely depth analysis and practical
they are applied in order to vindicate their claims. conclusions. They are tied to the practice in which
But there are no such self-standing abstract sciences they are applied in a way that the abstract sciences are
in the human world. Instead, there are abstract parts not, since the latter have their own internal practice in
of sciences whose whole connection with reality is at experiment. I have elsewhere called practical concrete
the concrete level. sciences ʻepistemoidsʼ. Some are quite science-like in
Husserlʼs reference to the ʻgenuineʼ sciences as their rigour and explanatory power; others, like the
abstract reflects (surprisingly for him) what might one chosen here, are much more problematic. But this
be called common sense in a positivistic culture; but is a matter of degree, not of kind.
another apparently contradictory idea goes along with First of all, a singing teacher is or has been a singer
this as part of positivistic common sense: that only the herself. She knows what it feels like. Here is some
concrete is real. It is quite widely taken for granted that knowledge ʻin a practical stateʼ, as Althusser would
only the abstract sciences are real sciences, but that say, which however she must put into words if she
only the concrete world really exists. We are then at a is to teach it. I am not denying that some non-verbal
loss to explain how the abstract sciences map onto the communication may take place (for instance, feeling
concrete world. Critical realism denies both poles of each otherʼs bodies to see what happens when some
this contradiction. The mechanisms corresponding to specific vocal or respiratory instruction is carried out),
the laws of the abstract sciences are also real, hence: but the teaching would not get far without the medium
of language. But ʻputting it into wordsʼ is a genuine
Domain of Domain of Domain of problem in communicating practical knowledge of this
real actual empirical sort. It is often done by asking the pupil to imagine
Mechanisms / him- or herself doing something that he or she could
not literally do. For instance: ʻpretend your voice is
Events / / coming out of the back of your headʼ; ʻsing from the
top of your head and make the sound come down
Experiences / / /
your noseʼ; or ʻdraw the sound inʼ. Taken literally, of

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 23


course, these instructions would be nonsense. But they neither contradicted by claims that all female orgasms
succeed in telling the singer how to make it feel, and are clitorally triggered, nor confirmed by claims about
hence what to do. the G-spot. They are based on the self-experience of
However, some instructions sound plausible enough some women whom Freud analysed, and make no
to be quite easily taken as literally true, as descriptions physiological claims.
of what can take place in the singerʼs body, though a These points may I think be generalized to the
physiologist could show that they are not. For instance: concrete sciences: their concepts are arrived at partly
ʻuse your sinusesʼ (i.e. make your sinuses contribute by retroduction from practical experience – ʻhow can
to the sound by their vibrations). Now apparently the we explain the way things seem in practiceʼ – and
vibration of the sinuses cannot appreciably contribute partly borrowed from the abstract sciences. By these
to the sound. However, if the singer sings in such a two methods, the concrete sciences build up a stock
way that she can feel her sinuses vibrating, she will of abstract concepts of their own. But here we may
be singing in the right way. Sometimes the descrip- note a difference between concrete natural sciences
tion of how it feels is the opposite of what is physi- like meteorology and concrete human sciences like
ologically the case. Thus a singer may be advised to psychoanalysis. The borrowings are in both cases
ʻmake more spaceʼ when singing high notes. But the from natural sciences since only in these are there
action which feels like making more space actually experiments. This means that the human sciences
makes less space in the singerʼs throat. This does not can learn far less by borrowing than can the natural
vitiate the instruction as a direction in teaching, since concrete sciences. This is what justifies my claim that
it is understood and the required effect produced. the human sciences relate to their objects only through
Nevertheless the physiologist should not be entirely their concrete parts, even though there is some input
ignored by the singing teacher. His or her findings from experimental sciences into human sciences and
do make certain judgements possible about good and disciplines (e.g. from physiology into psychoanalysis
bad practice, since it can be discovered physiologically or singing teaching). That input is alien in a way that
that certain singing techniques do harm to the vocal the input from physics to meteorology is not.
cords, and so on. Sometimes such information could Now let us look at what one of the only three people
have been discovered or guessed at by a good singing with a credible claim to have founded a human science
teacher on the basis of experience, but not necessarily. says about the relation of abstractness to concreteness.
Physiology can correct singing practices in ways that I refer to Marx (the other two are Freud and Chomsky).
phenomenology canʼt – yet it would be absurd to think Marx sometimes stresses the importance of abstraction
that it could replace the phenomenological knowledge in science, while at other times he seems to be quite
that the singing teacher has. One could never become a rude about it. Most of his followers follow either one
singer or a singing teacher by studying the physiology or the other of these examples, but it may be that the
of the vocal organs. two can be reconciled. First, it should be mentioned
Similar considerations apply in psychoanalysis, that for Marx as for Kant, the term ʻabstractionʼ often
whose raw data are entirely phenomenological, but refers to a process rather than a result: abstracting from
some of whose abstract parts sound like speculations something, bracketing it off. Now to one rude remark
about neurology and sexology. Those biological sci- about abstraction:
ences do not vitiate the practice of psychoanalysis First of all, an abstraction is made from a fact;
when they appear to conflict with it, yet it would be then it is declared that the fact is based on the
obscurantist for psychoanalysis to ignore their findings. abstraction. That is how to proceed if you want
Freudʼs metapsychology has a status much like the to appear German, profound and speculative.
For example: Fact: The cat eats the mouse.
metaphorical physiology used by singing teachers. At
Reflection: Cat = nature, Mouse = nature;
certain points – for instance, the concept of instinct or consumption of mouse by cat = self-consumption
drive which Freud explicitly says is a border-concept of nature.
between the biological and the psychological sciences Philosophical presentation of the fact: the de-
– a tie up with physiology is useful and helps to confirm vouring of the mouse by the cat is based upon the
or refute the metapsychological theory. At others it self-consumption of nature.6
would be inappropriate to take the psychoanalytical Here the point about abstraction is that it gives you
idea physiologically and look for confirmation or poorer, less specific information than more concrete
refutation from physiology, since the concept may language. Wherever abstraction means no more than
be justified phenomenologically, by its clarification leaving something out in order to arrive at a more
of the patientʼs self-experience. For instance, Freudʼs general and less specific description, Marx is rude
distinction between clitoral and vaginal orgasms is about it.

24 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


But in the section on the method of political retroduce explanations from them. It cannot read off
economy in the 1857 introduction, he says that to the explanations from the statistical correlations. But
start with ʻthe real and concreteʼ, e.g. the population, if statistics has no explanatory role in social science,
commits the same error, since ʻThe population is an neither has any other form of mathematics, since we
abstraction if I leave out, for example, the classes cannot measure abstract forces without actualizing
of which it is composedʼ.7 We should therefore start them as is done in an experiment.
by moving analytically towards ʻever thinner abstrac- To return, then, to the original paradox: the analysis
tionsʼ, and then put them together again in their due of experiment has not been useless for the human
order to arrive at ʻthe population again, but this time sciences, since it shows something very general about
not as the chaotic conception of a whole, but as a rich the real world, namely that it is structured and strati-
totality of many determinations and relationsʼ.8 We fied, that the concrete really is a union of many
arrive at this full conception of a concrete entity by determinations, and hence that abstraction and analysis
showing the relations between its features which taken are appropriate methods of developing knowledge of
separately would be abstractions, but of which the real concrete beings. But it also shows that where experi-
concrete entity is composed: ʻThe concrete is concrete ment is not possible, this analysis and abstraction is
because it is the union of many determinations, hence not measurable, and is testable only by its capacity
unity of the diverse.ʼ9 to explain the minute particulars of concrete enti-
Good abstraction consists in specifying the many ties. It shows, in short, the ontological similarity of
interrelated aspects of something, and this is how natural and human sciences – they are both analysing
a concrete science should proceed; bad abstraction concrete structured wholes and explaining them in
consists in ignoring the specificity of something, to terms of the abstractions arrived at – and also the
subsume it under some more general concept. Thus methodological dissimilarity of natural and human
a social scientist who wanted to provide knowledge sciences: the latter cannot use mathematics and should
of Britain in the 1990s should analyse out the many look rather to paradigms like Freudʼs analysis of the
aspects of that society and show how they are related; Rat Man (or any full psychoanalytic case-history), or
and not abstract from many of its specific features in Trotskyʼs History of the Russian Revolution. In short,
order to place it in a statistical population of somewhat social science can exist only ʻas minutely organized
similar societies, and produce statistical data about particulars, and not in generalizing demonstrations of
them. If social science were an experimental science, the rational powerʼ.
it would be possible to actualize these abstractions Now to the question of practical applications. Many
and test them separately – for example, to test what of the concrete sciences are inseparably tied to a prac-
the effect of exposure of British capital to Continental tice (for example, medicine to healing, psychoanalysis
competition would be in the absence of trade unions. to therapy, Marxian theory to working-class politics),
But it is not. Hence ʻin the analysis of economic but whether this is so or not, all sciences, abstract
forms neither microscopes nor chemical reagents are or concrete, deliver their discoveries into a world of
of assistance. The power of abstraction must replace ongoing practices which they often transform in some
both.ʼ10 We make abstraction in thought – ʻexperi- way. I want to argue in conclusion that as a matter of
ments in thoughtʼ – and cannot do more than this. scientific ethics and good public policy, abstract sci-
But we stay with the concrete reality which we are ences ought never to be allowed to influence practice
analysing and try to tease out as many details as we directly, but only through the assistance they give to
can, rather than ignoring details in order to subsume concrete sciences. This applies not only to natural sci-
it under generalizations. The abstract parts of good ences, where it has important ecological implications,
social science are speculative explanations of concrete but also with respect to the abstract and concrete parts
particulars, which are tested only by their capacity of human sciences.
to explain those concrete particulars. To take them Abstract sciences can yield practical advice of a
out of their use in such explanation and use them to sort; for instance, ʻhere is a way w to make product
compare different concrete particulars in the attempt x with half the labour that it took before.ʼ This may
to arrive at ʻstatistical causalityʼ is always a mistake, justify the conclusion: ʻother things being equal, we
since the other determinants of events and differences should make x by process w.ʼ But other things are not
are being ignored without their having been rendered equal and in this sort of case that is crucial. Process
ineffective as in a real experiment. Statistics has an w may also deplete a scarce resource or cause pollu-
important place among the descriptive preliminaries tion or produce sickness in the workers. To establish
of social science; information about the simultaneous whether this is so, we need a concrete study of the
increase in unemployment and crime may be the start- process in context – environmental, human, economic
ing point of a fruitful social-scientific analysis. But the and so on. That study may yield real practical advice,
analysis itself must focus on concrete particulars, and without the ʻother things being equalʼ clause. However,

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 25


it is a feature of our economic system that the ʻother ought to stand between these two would include in
things being equalʼ clauses of the practical advice of their objects the state of the soil, water and air, and
abstract sciences are not taken seriously – the advice various ecosystems dependent on that state. It is a
is carried out as if it were conclusive, which only the matter of ʻpractical wisdomʼ to determine in any given
advice of a concrete scientific study can even approxi- case what the scope of the requisite concrete science
mate to being. This is a feature of modern economic should be.
life because if the ʻother thingsʼ do not relate to The application of abstract science is irrational
profitability, they are equal to the commercial appliers and the application of concrete science is rational.
of science – all equally indifferent. But it is important But concrete science can never give you what abstract
to notice that all advice from abstract science is subject science appears to give: a method of calculating which
to an other-things-being-equal clause, just because it course of action is rational. For the discovery that w
is abstract, having abstracted from some of the other is the most economical way of producing x can be
things that affect the outcome. An economic system quantified: it costs half what process v had cost. But as
that systematically applies science in an abstract state soon as a multiplicity of incommensurable reasons for
is a systematically irresponsible system. using or not using w is delivered by the concrete study
There is a tradition of hostile criticism of science of w-in-context, we have to make a decision between
which makes very similar points to those that I have incommensurable alternatives. Calculation becomes
been making. Blake in some moods is part of that useless. But that is not an objection to basing action
tradition. Today it often comes from those within on concrete science, for calculation between the actual
the Green movement who blame science rather than alternatives was always impossible anyway. It was only
its commercial use. There is also a tendency within because many of the incommensurable values were left
ʻpostmodernismʼ to counterpose the practical concrete out of account or assigned arbitrary commensurable
knowledge of (for instance) shepherds to the preten- values that the issue looked calculable in the first
sions of the Ministry of Agriculture experts, trained place. Deciding on the basis of an abstract science
in abstract science. In so far as these tendencies have just is leaving some things out of account – that is
directed attention to the necessity of concrete knowl- what abstract means. If we have to decide between a
edge and its sole right to guide practice, they are motorway and an ancient wood of special scientific
absolutely right. Yet the fault lies not with abstract interest, there is nothing we can rationally do but sit
science but with the tendency of its commercial and down and think ʻwould life be better with a wood and
military users to apply science in its abstract state, no motorway or with a motorway and no wood?ʼ At
rather than treating abstract sciences as contributory which point I can perhaps conclude as I started with
disciplines whose results must flow together into the a quote from Blake:
sea of concrete science before they are in a fit state
to be applied practically. Improvement makes strait roads; but the crooked
Since I am claiming that the rationality of the roads without Improvement are the roads of Gen-
practical application of science depends on following ius.11
the full sequence abstract sciences – concrete science
Notes
– practice rather than the abridged sequence abstract
1. William Blake, Complete Writings, Oxford University
science – practice, I should perhaps say something
Press, London, 1966, p. 687.
about what sort of discipline counts as a concrete 2. An earlier version of this paper was read to the Seminar
science, as distinct from an abstract science on the on Critical Realism organized in the Faculty of Econom-
one hand and a practice on the other. I have given ics and Politics at the University of Cambridge.
examples of concrete sciences such as meteorology and 3. Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations, Vol. 1,
medicine, but it is not always easy to identify them. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1970, pp. 230–31.
4. Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science, Harvester
Whereas abstract sciences are individuated (as physics,
Wheatsheaf, Hemel Hempstead, 1978, p. 13.
chemistry, biology and the like) by the kinds of laws 5. I am grateful to Heather Collier for information in this
that they discover, and practices are individuated (as part of the article.
agriculture, health care, war and so on) by the aims 6. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, The German Ideology,
that they pursue and the means that they use, concrete edited by Pascal, International Publishers, New York, pp.
114–15.
sciences are individuated by their concrete objects,
7. Karl Marx, Grundrisse, Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1973,
which may be of greater or lesser scope, so that the p. 100.
concrete science required for a given bit of application 8. Ibid.
of science to practice may not have a ready-made 9. Ibid., p. 101.
name. To take the instance of pesticides, the abstract 10. Karl Marx, Capital, Vol. 1, Penguin, Harmondsworth,
1976, p. 90.
science of chemistry is applied in the practice of
11. Complete Writings, p. 152.
agriculture. The concrete scientific disciplines which

26 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


The culture of polemic
Misrecognizing recognition

Alexander García Düttmann

One would like to be recognized as this or that indi- overcoming subject: they neither conceive the limits of
vidual, according to this or that description, since this subject nor seek its transformation.
recognition promises to overcome the splitting of what For this subject and this theory of recognition the
is to be recognized, to facilitate the incorporation question arises as to how, where and when such recog-
of what is split into some unified identity or unified nition can be recognized. When can one say, and when
life-context. According to María Zambrano in her can one know, that an individual or a group has indeed
book The Agony of Europe, first published in 1945, been recognized? That the group or the individual is
ʻEuropean manʼ strives ceaselessly towards a projected no longer recognized? Or is yet to be recognized? Is
self that is yet to be, while fleeing constantly from recognition intrinsically bound to a shared experi-
another self that still continues to lead a shadowy ence, to a regulated practice, to certain gestural or
existence within him. That is why we can supposedly specifically linguistic conventions and rules, to legal
describe European history as the story of a heresy entitlements and socio-political institutions? Or does
which procures the birth of the European individual. the process of recognition perhaps evince resistance to
The human being who splits apart into a doubled self its own recognizability, to the subject and the theory
(a given self and a projected self) is a ʻEuropeanʼ of recognition which would seek conceptually to grasp
because he or she decides to exist, to exist inde- that process? Might the struggle for recognition be
pendently of every already prevailing order. This self permanently bound to a testimony which cannot be
is grounded in a deficiency, in an absence, in a lack: measured through recourse to unambiguous criteria?
it represents a violence of existing.1
From the perspective of reflections such as these one ‘We’re queer, we’re here, so get fuckin’ used
might also understand the demand for recognition, and to it’
not merely the confession of which Zambrano speaks, Take the slogan currently circulating in North America,
as a historical attempt to overcome that splitting and ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ used to itʼ, at
diremption of the human being which results from this once elliptical and utterly unambiguous. As long as
resolute decision to exist. The limits of recognition it works as a slogan, a caesura which cannot simply
would then constitute the limits of decision and of be bridged over by transferring and integrating the
resolution, because a resolute and decisive existence offensively and polemically intended phrase into a
always presupposes a self which decides to exist, a legitimate, legitimated and legitimating discourse, this
self which constitutes itself precisely in and through exclamation effectively testifies to a struggle for recog-
this founding act. There is a double limit here: first, nition. But if this slogan, this phrase, this exclamation
the limit of the birth and death of the historical or works merely as a provocation, one which ultimately
ʻEuropeanʼ subject as the limit of two comprehensive lives, like every provocation, off a secret complicity
orders (pre- and post-historical); second, the limit and solidarity with what it seeks to provoke; if those
inherent in any recognition which would enable the self who proclaim this slogan bear an already presup-
successfully to overcome its splitting into a given self posed identity, confess themselves as such bearers
and a projected self. Projects directed towards success- and thereby direct themselves toward bearers of a
fully ʻaccomplishedʼ recognition only perpetuate the different identity, precisely in order to secure equality
history of the deciding, projecting, recognizing and of treatment and status for themselves through legal,

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 27


social, institutional and political recognition – then demanding recognition here in your very midst. On
the struggle for recognition disappears in a reformism the other hand, only when you, to whom our demand
which only accepts, and only can accept, differences is addressed, get used to something you must get used
on the ground of some more fundamental unity. It to, something which in a certain sense you already
disappears in the purist and puritanical equality of a have got used to, only then are we what and who we
ʻpolitical correctnessʼ that is merely the complement are, in your very midst. The necessary contradiction
of misinterpretation, exclusion and oppression. Yet a harboured within the demand for recognition allows us
reformism that excludes the process of recognition to translate the phrase in the following way: We, who
finds itself confronted with the difficulty of procuring raise our voice in our own name, because this name
recognition for that fundamental unity, which does not and this voice are not yet our name and our voice,
have to be substantial, but which can simply exist on because we must first appropriate them for ourselves,
the assumption of a formal equality in principle. Thus we are here without being here, we are what we are
every reformism risks slipping into that very strug- without being what we are, and this is why we demand
gle for recognition, the uncertain outcome of which that you recognize us and get used to our being here
it attempts to transform into stability and security as what we are. Only when you have got used to our
precisely through regulation, limitation and direction. being here, and that we are what we are; only when
Although reformism seeks to incorporate the struggle you have thereby recognized us, whom you do not
for recognition within itself, it simultaneously exposes even need to recognize since we are already here, in
itself to this struggle. your midst – only then shall we be able to say that we
Who is it that generally raises this demand for are here, that we are what we are, and that we have
acceptance and what is intended by it? If there is a name and a voice.
indeed no unambiguous, but merely a more or less
plausible or probable, answer to either of these ques-
tions, and if the plausibility and probability of any
possible answer depends upon some contextual inser-
tion (for which there can be no ultimate criterion),
then the resulting dissemination of this demand can be
regarded as an effect of iterability. The interpretation
of the demand itself demands and needs recognition.
To interpret is to recognize. Yet it is just this need
for a recognitive interpretation and an interpretive
recognition – the dissemination of the demand, the
iterability – that allows the demand to be raised as a
demand at all. We could never even raise the demand
ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ used to itʼ, we
could never even interpret the phrase as a demand,
as the intrication of an assertion and a demand, if it
were possible to determine unambiguously what the
demand in question signified; if it could be shown
indubitably that it represented nothing but a demand.
For a demand without the moment of uncertainty
remains inconceivable.
ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ used to
itʼ: if this phrase implies a demand for recognition,
then it seems, like all demands for recognition, for
confirmation and institution, to be torn through by a
contradiction, to be suspended by a certain irony – it
is demanded that one recognize what one no longer The demand for recognition is a demand for con-
needs to recognize. We who demand recognition are firmation and institution. The phrase in question
already what we are, not merely someplace else, some- at once binds and separates assertion and demand
where to which you have no access, or which you through the paradoxical blind spot of the ʻsoʼ. The ʻsoʼ
could simply avoid, and that is precisely why we are marks the simultaneity of a continuity and a caesura,

28 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


of a closing and an opening. The contradiction, the as Michael Walzer puts it;3 bestowers of recognition
irony, the diachrony within this simultaneity robs whose generosity does not consist in their miserliness,
speakers and agents of any possibility of straightfor- their hesitation, their reticence, their reluctance, in a
wardly counterposing their own ʻweʼ to the ʻweʼ of sense of responsibility – such bestowers of recognition
others, of any possibility of marking an unambiguous stand more in need of recognition than those who are
distinction between those who make the demand and still to be recognized. This open economy of recog-
those upon whom it is made, between those who are to nition harbours a certain undemocratic moment, a
bestow recognition and those who are to receive it. The one-sided dependency, which renders it unsuitable for
skandalon of the phrase, its irreconcilable polemic, procuring a closed economy of reciprocal re-cogni-
the illegitimacy it possesses prior to any possible tion in which that moment of dependency could be
legitimacy and legitimation, lies in the equivocation overcome or ʻsublatedʼ in a Hegelian fashion.
it generates in conflating the ʻweʼ of those to whom This does not imply that the process of recogni-
the demand is addressed and the ʻweʼ of those who tion exercises a disintegrative effect. On the contrary,
make it. At the same time, the latter seem to segregate to the degree that the process of recognition never
and delimit themselves all too unambiguously, for they comes to a final conclusion; to the degree that it is
constitute the ʻweʼ who hurl the phrase like a shaft constantly unsettled and placed in tension by a one-
which, once the others recognize the danger of its sided dependency, by an asymmetry, by a relationship
whistling flight, has already struck home. of heterogeneous forces, it seems rather to solicit that
ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ used to itʼ: decisionistic resistance which exercises an integrating
a recognisable phrase and a barely intelligible exclam- effect that is crystallized in a servile collective soli-
ation; an impertinent suspicion and an act of violence darity with what is arbitrarily recognized. A thinking
beyond all argument; a declaration of war and a decla- and a politics of recognition that underestimates or
ration of love; an exclamation whose pointed contours is even incapable of perceiving the danger of such
permit no divided, wrangling or sentimental foes to decisionism remains impotent against it, precisely
take its measure; an exclamation whose measure can because this thinking and this politics confuse the
only be taken by that foe whom Jean Genet sought out process of recognition with a process of simply re-
in his imaginary newspaper advertisement – one who cognizing (Wiedererkennen).
is ʻblind, deaf and dumbʼ, because he is permitted no The insuperable difficulties which the exclamation
possible room for manoeuvre, ʻwithout legs, without and expression ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ
arms, without a stomach, without a heart, without a used to itʼ presents for both a theory and a subject of
sex, without a headʼ.2 On the one hand, there is hardly recognition are clearly revealed where this exclamation
any doubt who the demanding subject is and what the and expression functions as a privileged example for
demand consists in. On the other hand, the boundaries other possible demands for recognition, and where
between these subjects, who are not yet subjects, prove it strives to ensure and maintain an accomplished
to be shifting and impermanent. The demand cannot relation of recognition as a familiar and habitually
immediately be re-cognized (Wiedererkennen).* accepted fact. A demand for recognition cannot just
This unsettling opening up of borders and limits is represent a demand for the establishment of a relation
furthered once we grasp ʻfuckinʼʼ as the object of that of recognition which brings the struggle for recogni-
habituation which is demanded: get used to a different tion to an end. For it must also represent a demand
kind of fucking! Again, the ones who proclaim the for the maintenance of this established relation, since
phrase suddenly become those who recognize, while without such maintenance the fulfilment of the demand
those who encounter it and to whom it is addressed would merely prove to be a further postponement. In
suddenly become those who require recognition and other words, when we ʻget usedʼ to what is recognized,
have to struggle for it. From this perspective, those then this process of habituation and familiarization
who are targeted and struck by the phrase must them- – which permits the establishment of the relation of
selves struggle to earn the recognition from those who recognition and is simultaneously suspended by its
recognize only with reluctance and for that very reason unfamiliarity, an unfamiliarity which first makes the
are themselves recognized as bestowers of recognition. act of recognition what it is – must eventually come
Bestowers of recognition who are not ʻreluctant giversʼ, to an end. It must produce something utterly habitual
if the demand for recognition is to be properly and
* The distinction between Anerkennen (recognition) and Wie- effectively fulfilled. No subject of recognition would
dererkennen (re-cognition) is awkward to render in English.
ever be secure if the process of habituation – where
Anerkennen has the sense of acknowledging.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 29


version inflicted upon those who are to be recognized;
as an unacceptable, ideological, politically strategic
and controlling subsumption of recognition under a
process of exclusive and excluding re-cognition.
The expression ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get
fuckinʼ used to itʼ is a speech act which is incapable
of being controlled. It is an exclamation that one can
appropriate for oneself, but only at the cost of relin-
quishing it to a different process of appropriation,
in the very moment of appropriation, domestication,
coordination. ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ
used to itʼ is a contrary expression, a very queer phrase
indeed, a homeless orphan that always behaves other-
wise than its family expects, an irregular combatant, a
deracinated and deracinating partisan, a fighter whose
extreme mobility defies enclosure and containment,
whose tactical agility even displaces and unsettles the
ʻtellurianʼ character and the defensive posture of the
ʻclassical partisanʼ (Carl Schmitt). But it is because
the act of recognition is one of confirmation, and
simultaneously one of institution, that every demand
for recognition resembles this exclamation and this
expression; that every attempt at thinking recogni-
tion proves to be a queer and contrary thinking, a
contrary thinking of the queer. One who demands
recognition has already arrived, has already reached
those who recognize get used to those who are to be the destination still to be attained, and does not require
recognized, and those to be recognized get used to the recognition that is demanded. The polemical pre-
those who recognize them – itself failed to become sumption here lies in the way in which the one who is
habitual. The fatal character of this necessity, however, to be recognized transforms those who are to bestow
lies in the fact that such habitual familiarity threat- recognition into those who require recognition. The
ens the very re-cognition of recognition upon which roles, the functions, the positions in question thereby
the permanence of the already established relation of find themselves caught up in a constant and uncon-
recognition rests. trollable process of exchange – in the final analysis
Does not the very process of habituation destroy it is impossible to decide who should be recognized
the act of recognition which requires that process? here and now and who is recognizing whom here
Is it not inevitable that the discriminating indiffer- and now.
ence and the concealed domination should assume the
form of habitual recognition? And is it not the case ‘Spain is different’
that such habitual recognition renders the recognized The pressure exerted on this here-and-now is all the
invisible and obliterates them in their very difference? more exacerbated by the fact that there is no longer any
Is there any more effective remedy for recognition or horizon from the perspective of which that exchange
means against it than that process of habituation with- could either be recognized as deviant or perverse, or
out which there can be no recognition? Acceptance be transformed into a more regular and acceptable
through habit: the monument and ruin of recognition. one. Thus the process of recognition, duplicating every
Even a theory of recognition; a historical, conceptual, integrating effect with a disintegrating one, but without
historico-philosophical investigation – an investigation permitting this integration and disintegration to be
which must always also exempt itself as such from the captured by any positive dialectic, does not properly
struggle for recognition and attempt to justify its own lend itself to any all-englobing act of identification
exemption on the grounds that this is the only way of which would ensure stability. Yet recognition is indis-
doing justice to recognition itself – can be denounced pensable if one is to identify oneself with a group,
as an oppression, a repression, an eradication, a per- with a people, with a country, with a state, with a

30 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


tradition; if one is to be capable of identifying these such a ʻcontemporary nationalismʼ. But as a nationalist
in the first place, capable of re-cognizing them, of project this justification tends to promote a certain
re-cognizing oneself in them, of being re-cognized extremism, an exclusive appropriation of a totality,
by them. For all identifications must transgress a a positing of boundaries which would mark some
limit. They therefore require an act of recognition if permanent belonging, through which interruptions are
that re-cognition to which they aspire is to be made subjected to control and by which the sentiment of
possible. Recognition thus intersects and transfixes, for diverse identity only comes to serve an undisturbed
example, every attempt to justify a form of national- self-assertion. The interrupted identity, the identity
ism, even that supposedly enlightened ʻnationalism which is exposed to the dynamic of recognition and
of the presentʼ or ʻcontemporary nationalismʼ which finds itself suspended there, finally transforms itself
Oriol Pi de Cabanyes, the director of the Institució de into a unified identity, into the identity of a re-cogni-
les Lletres Catalanes, would like to derive from the
zable and (self-) re-cognizing subject. The plan, the
ʻinterrupted identityʼ of a people.
projection, the programme of the new nationalism
Instead of simply opposing ʻthe Catalan traditionʼ
is the ideological projection of a unification without
to other traditions; instead of attempting to anchor
interruption, of a will to undisturbed self-presence
the sense of national ʻbelongingʼ in the ʻdense texture
which would place past and future alike in its own
of the pastʼ or to acquire it from ʻplanning the futureʼ
service:
– Pi de Cabanyes addresses himself to the present. The
here-and-now of a Catalan ʻversionʼ of the universally The full responsibility for what we shall be at every
human is supposed to furnish the basis for an appro- moment will fall all the more clearly to ourselves.
priate contemporary nationalism.4 Such a ʻcontem- In the precise and appropriate conscious awareness
that we have been Catalans for a thousand years,
porary nationalismʼ springs from fears of nationalistic
that we are precisely what we are, that we shall be
extremism, ʻdiseased forms of nostalgiaʼ and ʻfuturistic what we wish to be, our own grasp of temporal-
fanaticismʼ. But if this idea of an ahistorical, purely ity will be more evenly developed. This sense of
ʻpunctualʼ or instantaneous here-and-now – which equilibrium will in all probability prove to be our
appeals to a suprahistorical and utterly abstract con- strongest protection against all presumptuous forms
ception of human essence without effectively clarify- of interference, against all forms of undesirable
interruption and intervention.5
ing the relationship between the universality of this
essence and the particularity of its specific versions and
manifestations – proves to be unconvincing, then such Legal indifference
vaunted ʻcontemporary nationalismʼ proves equally to But even if the one demanding recognition is the
be a familiar nationalism after all, and thus already to one bestowing recognition, and the bestower of rec-
represent the extremism it was supposed to contain.
ognition is the one requiring recognition; even if the
The symptoms of contamination here vividly reveal
here-and-now of recognition is also a there-and-then
themselves when Pi de Cabanyes speaks of those
– why can we not interpret this internal splitting as
ʻundesirableʼ cases of interference and interruption
an equilibrium or balance of reconciling completion?
which his ʻcontemporary nationalismʼ would have to
Why must we insist upon the vertiginous movement
exclude from the ʻinterrupted identityʼ of the Catalans.
of an uncontrollable exchange of positions, upon a
The identity of the Catalans is an interrupted one.
universal resistance and displacement? Because the
Like all forms of identity, it cannot insulate itself against
difference between the confirmation and institution
the irruption of an alien externality or foreign element.
If this identity could insulate itself against such forms of what has been demanded is a difference between
of irruption, it would only ossify immediately. Pi de heterogeneous acts, and this heterogeneity can only be
Cabanyes distinguishes between heritage, experience bridged by the dogmatic or postulated presupposition
and interruption in order to emphasize the violent and of a re-cognizable unity and a unified re-cognition,
unavoidable moment of ʻinterferenceʼ, of interrupting by the elimination of the process of recognizing. The
and disrupting intervention. But if the identity of a phrase ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ used
people is essentially an interrupted one, a non-identical to itʼ represents a caesura charged with tension, an
one, then it can appeal neither to an organic totality interruption which cannot be bridged over, an invasive
grounded in a past nor to the frictionless or seamless and invading presumption, a queer and contrary self-
appropriation of a future. The justification of its inter- disowning exclamation, elusive over and against all
rupted identity leads necessarily to the projection of attempts to own or appropriate it.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 31


Consequently it would be a euphemistic interpre- should be reserved for the anonymous social order
tation, an essential domestication, if one were to which is always presupposed by the ʻnon-politicalʼ or
reduce this expression to a demand for pacifying and ʻsub-politicalʼ spheres of recognition. For the opening
habitual recognition, for the willing readiness to put which repeatedly suspends recognition, the opening to
up with something, for the reasonable acceptance and which the challenge of that unpredictable and uncon-
toleration of those nameless individuals intended by trollable expression ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get
the first-person-plural pronoun. As little as one can fuckinʼ used to itʼ bears testimony, itself belongs to
or should exclude an interpretation which regards the the political dimension and to the politics of recogni-
expression as a demand for the ʻtransformation and tion. It is precisely this opening which makes politics
reconfiguration of socially binding rules and regula- necessary. Must the effective political securing of
tionsʼ, for the creation of that in-difference of nameless that open domain we supposedly require in order to
recognition which alone is capable of doing justice to experience the significance of what has already taken
difference within society,6 one must equally recognize shape in the ʻnon-socialʼ, ʻsubsocialʼ, ʻnon-politicalʼ
that there always remains something unacceptable and ʻsubpoliticalʼ forms of recognition,8 must this too
and unreasonable about the phrase, something which not remain exposed to the possibility of suspension
is directly connected to the exclamatory character of and disturbance if such ʻin-differently binding validityʼ
the expression itself. For the latter resists both the over against difference is not ultimately to lead to a
ideological preformation of the legal system, which levelling process of assimilation, to the namelessness
disadvantages those who raise the demand, and the of eradicated names?
anonymity of a social cohesion regulated by legal If the framework within which differences exist
norms, the ʻin-differently bindingʼ character of all is quite obvious; if it is obvious that there is an
rules and regulations, whether it is purely ʻformalʼ or overall framework which comprehends and includes
substantively ʻeffectiveʼ in nature. For this ʻin-differ- these differences; if it is already decided, for example,
ently bindingʼ validity is either selective in character, that it is exclusively ʻrelationships of adult love and
and has its condition of possibility in the by no means friendshipʼ9 which effectively characterize a determin-
ʻin-differentʼ decision concerning who can actually be ate ʻnon-socialʼ, ʻsubsocialʼ, ʻnon-politicalʼ, ʻsubpoliti-
intended by the regulation in question, or, alternatively, calʼ open domain of recognition; then difference has
it possesses an undifferentiated ʻin-differently binding already been robbed of what makes it different in the
validityʼ which intends in principle everyone, so that first place. Difference has been domesticated and the
no real recognition transpires at all. In truth this phrase ʻWeʼre queer, weʼre here, so get fuckinʼ used
means: by virtue of the indispensable and constitutive to itʼ has been deprived of its political virulence. It
selection mechanism involved in it, this ʻin-differently is not merely in the juridical sphere that the phrase
binding validityʼ of nameless individuals represents the represents a caesura that cannot simply be bridged,
binding validity of a virtual normality, a normality but rather in all spheres in which recognition proves
which saves and keeps itself intact, which builds up to be decisive. Certainly, the irreducible tension in
an arsenal of power, which has already withdrawn the process of recognition is a tension between asym-
from its exclusionary, minimalizing and marginalizing metry and symmetry (otherwise the recognition would
manifestations once we attempt to call it by its proper be nothing more than a re-cognition), so that the
name. As in Andrew Sullivanʼs apologetic pamphlet demand for effectively secured political spaces of
Virtually Normal ,7 the difference of the recognized, openness and free play, for a certain leeway, is just
in which the virtuality in question has accumulated as inscribed within the struggle for recognition as
and concentrated itself, is merely that distance which is the destabilizing disjunction of play and space.
allows normality to assert itself all the more fiercely Politics is nothing other than the name for sustaining
and inexorably. and enduring the conflict within this tension, between
Of course one does not have to pay the price of a name and anonymity.
naive intentionalism or contextualism, if one wishes Asymmetry and symmetry, confirmation and insti-
to distinguish ʻpolitical recognitionʼ from another tution, do not have the invariant form of a concept.
kind of recognition and to utilize this distinction Rather, they are stabilized elements of a recognition
in order to mark a difference between the sphere which is and must be distinguished from mere re-cog-
of namelessness and the sphere of names. But one nition, a recognition whose tensile character consists
does fall back into a naive intentionalism or contex- in the fact that dissolving it into an accomplished
tualism if one claims that the name of ʻthe politicalʼ form of recognition only eliminates the difference

32 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


between recognizing and re-cognizing. But the possible Against majorities and minorities
modes and opportunities for recognition, which result The misconceiving of recognition which is involved in
from the constellations and configurations of the ele- the reformist conception of the latter, a misconceiving
ments involved, cannot in principle be located within which cannot even be thought without the continual
a hierarchical relationship, within any relationship of destabilization of recognition, has one important con-
precedence or derivation, presupposition or depend- sequence: drawing distinctions between the various
ency. Recognition precisely promotes the subversion majorities and minorities that struggle for recognition
of such relationships wherever they have assumed a may well serve as a reformist strategy within the
fixed and independent existence. It makes a difference overall horizon of a unity based upon formal equal-
whether we are speaking of the recognition accorded ity, but it also afflicts the majorities and minorities
to a people struggling for its own autonomy or the rec- struggling for recognition with a perilous social blind-
ognition involved in love or friendship; but the various ness. For anyone who distinguishes majorities from
forms of recognition and their respective configurations minorities and ascribes him- or herself to this majority
are nonetheless simultaneously subject to a process of or that minority, can only address the essentially
deformation. They are themselves part of a movement incommensurable and measureless moment which is
whose dynamic cannot be grasped either by concepts harboured within the very movement of recognition by
of form or by concepts of formlessness. Recognition is attempting to reduce this resistance to all measurability
misconceived if we attempt to divide it up into forms precisely to some measure, to a range of quantifying
and modes which are laboriously segregated from and identifying factors. In an essay discussing the
one another in order thereby to control the process of question of measure, of minorities and majorities in
recognition. Recognition is misconceived if we make the debate concerning multicultural societies, Werner
the reformist attempt to relate it to the underlying unity Hamacher writes:
of a universal ʻin-differently binding validityʼ or of an
For any claim that is incommensurable with a
accomplished and effective recognition. Recognition
purely quantitative representation according to
is misconceived if we believe we can simply know or equivalents, there is a voice which still ineluctably
re-cognize it, or even measure the misconceiving of makes itself heard precisely in this representation
recognition against this possibility. – an other voice, and perhaps something other than
a voice. The commensurable must render itself in-
commensurable, and the countable uncountable.10

Minorities that struggle for recognition, and the


majorities that recognize them, must intrinsically blind
themselves before the anarcho-revolutionary power of
the measureless. Expressed in another way: a group
that identifies itself as a minority can, fundamentally
speaking, no longer struggle for recognition and has
already become powerless in this struggle. When some-
one on the street of a North American city shouts
ʻHey, faggot!ʼ to a supposedly recognized individual,
the latter feels outraged. Alternatively, someone who
makes no appeal to the recognition of a fixed identity
invents other, more novel, war machines.
The suspicion that no one is more powerless
than someone who has struggled for recognition as
a member of some minority or majority, adducing
more or less convincing reasons and obtaining more
or less successful results – the suspicion that, all
appearances to the contrary notwithstanding, the one
who has achieved recognition is the most powerless
of all – this suspicion is transformed into an insight
once we perceive that recognition, precisely because it
only remains recognition to the degree that it does not
solidify and objectify itself as recognition, suspends

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 33


the possibility of the ʻasʼ: the possibility of ʻrecog- Notes
nition asʼ. The moment of equilibrium, of equality in This essay is excerpted from Alexander García Düttmannʼs
the struggle for recognition, may repeatedly promise book Zwischen den Kulturen. Spannungen im Kampf um
Anerkennung (Between Cultures: Tensions in the Struggle
or even open up this possibility, but it also suspends
for Recognition), Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1997.
it precisely because it can never be wholly isolated
1. María Zambrano, La agonía de Europa, Mondadori,
or dialectically defined as a determinate result. The Madrid, 1988, p. 42.
pre-predicative or linguistically articulated ʻasʼ which 2. Jean Genet, Lʼennemi déclaré, Gallimard, Paris, 1991,
determines what is present in its specific quiddity gets p. 9.
3. Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice, Basic Books, New
separated from itself in the struggle for recognition,
York, 1983, p. 254.
even before it can constitute itself as a unity, as the 4. Oriol Pi de Cabanyes, Repensar Catalunya, Edicions 62,
ʻasʼ itself, as the ʻasʼ of an originary or subsequently Barcelona, 1989, pp. 88–9.
modified understanding. 5. Ibid., p. 91.
6. Christoph Menke, ʻWarum und wie?ʼ, in Babylon, no.
Following a suggestion of Michael Walzer it would 13–14, Neue Kritik, Frankfurt am Main, 1994, p. 92.
appear useful to distinguish an explicit and complex 7. Andrew Sullivan, Virtually Normal: An Argument about
ʻrecognition as this or thatʼ from a ʻsimple recog- Homosexuality, Picador, London, 1995.
nitionʼ,11 from the universal expectation with which 8. Menke, ʻWarum und wie?ʼ, p. 94.
9. Ibid., p. 92.
one member of society may reasonably approach and 10. Werner Hamacher, ʻOne 2 Many Multiculturalismsʼ,
engage with another. But every recognition which is manuscript 1994, pp. 30–31.
supposed to serve the successful establishment of an 11. Walzer, Spheres of Justice, p. 258.
equilibrium, an order or a framework, which is sup-
posed to satisfy universal expectations, is implicitly
or explicitly a form of ʻrecognition asʼ, a recognition
through which the recognized party can be re-cog-
nized as a member of that group whose parameters
are circumscribed by the framework and which is
sustained in equilibrium by the order. Thus the strug-
gle for recognition reveals itself as a struggle for
the ʻasʼ, for the structure of the ʻas-suchʼ; it reveals
itself as a struggle for revealing-oneself-as-something.
Consequently we should not confuse the reification of
recognition – something which eliminates the process
of recognition and merely grasps recognition itself
as the repetition and confirmation of a presupposed
identity, precisely as ʻrecognition asʼ – with recog-
nition and the struggle for recognition itself.
In the last analysis ʻrecognition asʼ proves inevitably
to have concealed or excluded the alterity of the
process of recognition. As a consequence of this con-
cealment and this exclusion one no longer recognizes
nor is recognized, because fundamentally one only
ever recognizes oneself: the struggle for recognition
becomes the struggle of the subject which strives either
to include otherness within itself or to exclude other-
ness from itself. The politics of recognition becomes
a fundamentalist and immanentist politics, irrespective
of the intentions or the means with which it oper-
ates. Another limit to recognition: the annihilation
of otherness through an absolute re-cognition, which
is precisely what my struggle, mein Kampf, has in
its sights.
Translated by Nicholas Walker

34 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


Poor Bertie

Jonathan Rée

In the dark midwinter of 1916, Londoners had an as the Bismarckian state itself, and the young Rus-
unusual opportunity to see radical philosophical prin- sellʼs conclusion was that the only hope for ʻcommon
ciples applied to the urgent issues of the day. The peace justice and common humanityʼ was some kind of
campaigner and feminist C.K. Ogden had hired the synthesis between liberalism and socialism.
Caxton Hall for a series of eight weekly lectures on Just a century later, the young Russellʼs view of the
politics, to be given by Bertrand Russell. It was a risky prospects of Marxist politics may appear far-sighted;
venture, both financially and intellectually. Russell but it was not deeply considered and he attached
was a small-voiced weedy-looking man; although he little importance to it. He was determined to devote
was still in his early forties, he was grey-faced and his attention to mathematical logic instead, and to
grey-haired, and wore old-fashioned dark clothes. The founding a British tradition of ʻlogical analysisʼ which
fact that he was also a philosopher and mathematical would at last bring ʻscientific methodʼ to bear on
logician and Fellow of the Royal Society was not the problems of philosophy. He interrupted himself
guaranteed to compensate for his inexperience as a briefly in 1907, to stand for the National Union of
public lecturer on politics. Womenʼs Suffrage Societies in a parliamentary by-
The monumental Principia Mathematica (written election in Wimbledon. (He won a remarkable 3,000
with A.N. Whitehead) had been published in three votes, compared with 10,000 for the Tory.) He also
huge volumes between 1910 and 1913, but, as Russell took an interest in Fabian and Liberal affairs, though
knew, very few people could understand it, and most his involvement took the form of supper parties with
of them lived in France, Poland or Germany anyway. Beatrice and Sidney Webb or the philosophical prime
On the other hand, its sheer impenetrability could minister Arthur Balfour, rather than rubbing shoulders
give Russell (like Einstein a little later) a bankable with a broad political public.
reputation as a symbol of absolute braininess. Russell But by the end of 1914, apart from feeling burnt-out
himself, though, was haunted by doubts (he had been as a logician, Russell was galvanized into action by the
shaken by Wittgensteinʼs criticisms); and in any case Great War – or rather, not so much by the war itself as
he thought he had lost his capacity for doing original by the bloodthirsty relish with which it was welcomed
work in logic. So with Ogdenʼs help, he was going to by the people of Britain. He soon became an activist
launch himself on a new career, earning his living in the Union for Democratic Control and the No-Con-
as a freelance political commentator rather than a scription Fellowship, and in 1915 took a period of leave
mathematician and fellow of a Cambridge college. from Cambridge to pursue his political activities, and
He had dabbled in politics before of course; indeed prepare for the Caxton Hall lectures in January 1916.
he had been brought up political, in the home of the ʻI have something important to say on the phil-
great Victorian reforming prime minister, Lord John osophy of life and politics,ʼ Russell thought; ʻsome-
Russell, who was his grandfather. And in 1896, when thing appropriate to the times.ʼ He needed to present
he was 24, he had published a book about revolu- an account of the origins of war in general, an attack
tionary socialism called German Social Democracy. on the war then being waged against Germany, and
His experiences as a political tourist in Germany and a sketch of the prospects of socialism, liberalism and
his interviews with Liebknecht and Bebel had led feminism; and it all had to be permeated by the author-
him to fear that the nascent Marxist movement might ity of a great logician. Russell was naturally nervous;
eventually prove as violent, repressive and illiberal but in the event he was pleased with the response:

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 35


My lectures are a great success – they are a rally- tion, and Russell came to regard them as the ʻleast
ing-ground for the intellectuals, who are coming unsatisfactoryʼ of all his political works. But it is quite
daily more to my way of thinking.… All sorts of hard to see, reading them today, what all the excite-
literary and artistic people who formerly despised
ment was about. Political problems of all kinds, as
politics are being driven to action, as they were
in France by the Dreyfus case.… In philosophy, Russell saw it, sprang from a single conflict: the battle
when I was young, my views were as unpopular between ʻthe impulses that make for lifeʼ and those
& strange as they could be; yet I have had a very that ʻmake for deathʼ. His main argument was that
great measure of success. Now I have started on a ʻtraditional Liberalismʼ was breaking down because
new career, & if I live & keep my faculties, I shall it lacked a proper appreciation of psychology, and
probably be equally successful.
could not comprehend the fact that social processes
The audience included nearly all the members of are governed not so much by rational calculation as
the Bloomsbury group. Even Lytton Strachey – who by ʻthe instinctive part of our natureʼ. In particular, it
had long ago come to the conclusion that Russell was a could not see that war was an outgrowth of ʻordinary
ridiculous threadbare remnant of Victorian worthiness, human natureʼ, or that the only way to prevent it in
and a ʻpoor manʼ who ʻlooks about 96ʼ – described future was to engineer a ʻfundamental reconstruction
the lectures as ʻa wonderful solace and refreshmentʼ. of economic and social lifeʼ.
Although feeling ʻnearer the grave than usualʼ, Strachey The social revolution proposed by Russell was to
would drag himself to the ʻghastly Caxton Hallʼ every be grounded in the principles of syndicalism and
Tuesday afternoon, to hear what Russell had to say. co-operation, combining all the benefits of socialist
ʻOne hangs upon his wordsʼ, he wrote; ʻit is splendid equality, industrial prosperity, and liberal freedom.
the way he sticks at nothing – Governments, religions, But Russell did not enter into any analysis of politi-
laws, property, even Good Form itself – down they go cal or economic trends, because so far as he was
like ninepins – it is a charming sight!ʼ
The ʻutterly immoralʼ Ottoline Morrell was
impressed as well, though her sense of the ridicu-
lous did not desert her.
All the cranks who attend lectures on any
subject were there, and amongst them was a
Captain White, who was slightly crazy, and
would make a long speech about sex and free
love, pointing out that if children were born
from parents who were in love with each other
they would never want to fight.… Then Vernon
Lee got up and made a long speech about a
cigarette case, waving her hands about …; and
of course, a representative of Arts and Crafts
made an impassioned harangue. Bertie sat look-
ing miserable on the platform. At last he had to
ask them to sit down.

Altogether, Lady Ottoline found the lectures


ʻrather a comic occasionʼ. But about a hundred
people turned up to each one, paying three shil-
lings a lecture, or one guinea for the whole course.
Russell and Ogden both scooped a satisfactory
profit, and by the end of it Russell had settled
his destiny as the most celebrated public British
intellectual of the twentieth century. (Only four
years later, he would be welcomed in China as
ʻthe greatest social philosopher of the worldʼ;
even Mao Tse-Tung, in his mid-twenties, turned
up to admire him.)
The lectures themselves were published a few
months later as Principles of Social Reconstruc-

36 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


concerned the key obstacles to progress were not faulty to follow the agenda set by Wallas, Cole, Laski and
social structures, or the vested interests of those who Wells, concerning eugenics, land tax and guild social-
benefited from them, but the outmoded superstitions ism, though he also had a very congenial proposal of
and irrational beliefs that still gave sustenance to the his own, for what he called a ʻvagabondʼs wageʼ – a
instincts of death and destruction. basic income to be paid to all who chose to sacrifice
Religion, for instance, despite its incidental beau- the comforts of social respectability and lead a bohe-
ties, always ʻsteels the hearts of men against mercy mian life of philosophy, art and innovation, thereby
and their minds against truthʼ, so what was needed was sustaining ʻa much-needed element of light heartedness
not so much economists as atheistic iconoclasts, who which our sober, serious civilisation tends to killʼ. In
could destroy the last vestiges of belief. Nationalism, 1931, though, Russell gave up on vagabonds: on the
too, was ʻnoble, primitive, brutal and madʼ, and what death of his brother, he became an earl – and a very
was needed was not sociologists but forthright rational sober and serious Labour peer. As Beatrice Webb said
humanitarians, who could face down the primitive after she heard the news: ʻpoor Bertie; he has made a
instincts of the herd. What was needed, in short, miserable mess of his life and he knows it.ʼ
was logicians, but logicians who also understood the Ironside seeks for some consistent doctrine at the
ʻinsinctiveʼ side of life. What was needed, for example, heart of Russellʼs political thought, and comes up
was Bertrand Russell. with the surprising but – when you think about it
– quite plausible suggestion that, with his constant
Philip Ironsideʼs The Social and Political Thought of harping on ʻlifeʼ and ʻcreativityʼ, Russell belongs ʻin
Bertrand Russell* is a work of contextualizing intel- that line of English cultural criticism which extends
lectual history which explains many of the peculiari- forward through the influence of Leavis and Scrutiny
ties of Russellʼs conception of politics. Ironside charts, and backward to Arnoldʼ. But so far as Russellʼs con-
for instance, his fluctuating estimate of the relative crete political views are concerned, Ironside concludes
importance of ʻreasonʼ and ʻinstinctʼ, connecting it that they were in a permanent muddle. He oscillated
with his wish to ingratiate himself with an artistic elite between dull Fabian gradualism and crazy bohemian
– Berenson, the Cambridge Apostles and Bloomsbury. impossibilism: as Ironside perceptively puts it, Beat-
He also highlights some more surprising elements in rice Webb and D.H. Lawrence marked ʻthe boundaries
Russellʼs political complexion – his ferocious support of Russellʼs eclecticism in much the same way as
of British imperialism in the Boer War, his indiffer- Bentham and Coleridge had provided Millʼsʼ.
ence to New Liberalism, and his standing obsession There are plenty of gaps in this account, however,
with racial degeneration – which now make him seem and Ray Monkʼs excellent biography** does a lot to
far more reactionary than he appeared to his audience fill them. Bertrand Russell: The Spirit of Solitude is
at the Caxton Hall. an attempt to repeat the success of Monkʼs marvellous
But Russellʼs converts in 1916 were utterly enchanted Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (1990),
by his insouciant philosophical way with politics. which managed to integrate lucid explanations of the
Some of the younger ones, according to Ironside, philosophical issues that troubled Wittgenstein into
ʻseriously discussed the possibility of making him a fascinating account of his daily life. Russell poses
Prime Ministerʼ – which suggests that they shared a far bigger problem for his biographer, however.
Russellʼs rather sketchy approach to the machinery Wittgenstein – as Monk showed – concentrated all his
of political power. Ironside also explains a range of energy on making himself into a supremely fastidious
other influences, from the British Idealistsʼ conception genius: writing was a slow torture for him, and he
of the state as a moral force, which he found utterly was assiduous in destroying all traces of imperfec-
repellent, to the theory of instinct as elaborated in tion. Russellʼs life, by contrast, was determinedly
the early stages of English Freudianism, which he multi-track, and he never threw things away. And
found attractive, and the wild irrationalism of D.H. his literary productivity is one of the wonders of the
Lawrence, about which he came to have reservations. world: he published seventy books or more, including
In the 1920s, though, he ran out of steam and began a three-volume Autobiography. Monk calculates that

*Philip Ironside, The Social and Political Thought of Bertrand Russell: The Development of an Aristocratic
Liberalism, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995. 280 pp., £30.00 hb., 0 521 47383 7.
**Ray Monk, Bertrand Russell: The Spirit of Solitude, Jonathan Cape, London, 1996. xx + 695 pp., £25.00
hb., 0 224 03026 4.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 37


he wrote an average of two or three thousand words are glad to turn away again – as Russell did too – with
a day, throughout his ninety-seven years. He worked, a rekindled passion for logic.
it seems, all the time: sometimes on pure philosophy; Monk is unable to find much connection between
sometimes on political theory and agitation; and some- the logic and the love in Russellʼs daily life, except
times – rather a lot of the time, in fact – on himself that each had the attraction of not being the other.
and his affairs with women. But when it comes to Russellʼs political evolution,
Faced with these mounds of Russelliana, a biog- the integrated biographical approach becomes more
rapher might be tempted to recount Russellʼs activities illuminating. Ironside has expounded Russellʼs belief
in a multiple narrative, like Doris Lessingʼs Golden that political questions are basically a matter of psychol-
Notebook perhaps: a red book for politics, a white ogy, especially the psychology of ʻlife instinctsʼ and
book for philosophy, and a blue one for sex. But it ʻdeath instinctsʼ, and he follows the Autobiography
would be hard to cap them all with a golden book that in describing how, in the period just before he wrote
would bring his lives together: they were essentially Principles of Social Reconstruction, Russell discussed
separate, it seems, and Russell never threw himself these matters with D.H. Lawrence, and even contem-
wholeheartedly into one field of activity unless he plated some literary collaboration with him.
was in full flight from the other two. So Monk has But as Monk shows, in the most gripping section
taken the sensible course of presenting Russellʼs activi- of his book, there was rather more to it than that.
ties side-by-side in an episodic day-to-day story. And Lawrence had met Ottoline Morrell early in January
although he has kept his focus quite narrow – most 1915, responding to a fan letter which had delighted
of his sources are Russellʼs own writings, or those of him as coming from an ʻaristocratʼ. At that time he
Russellʼs friends – this volume, though it looks like a was elaborating a ʻgospelʼ – a Germanic ʻphilosophyʼ,
doorstep, only gets up to 1920: the forests must still he hoped – which was going to escape from the past
be saplings that will bring us Russellʼs remaining half and institute a ʻnew lifeʼ on earth. Lawrence told
century in the second volume. Lady Ottoline that ʻevery strong soul must put off
Monk has been extremely selective all the same. He its connection with this society, its vanity and chiefly
gives far less attention to philosophy than he did in its fear, and go naked with its fellows, weaponless,
his book on Wittgenstein, and within Russellʼs strictly armourless, without shield or spear.ʼ She was mildly
philosophical output he ignores most of the work on entertained by such talk, until Lawrence announced
knowledge, sense-data and reality – issues that bulked that she herself was to become the ʻnucleusʼ of a
large in works like D.F. Pearsʼs Bertrand Russell and prefigurative community of love, and indeed that it
the British Tradition in Philosophy or A.J. Ayerʼs should be established at once in her estate at Garsing-
Russell. (It would be interesting to know whether ton, just outside Oxford. Perhaps it was sheer mischief
Monk would accept that Russellʼs epistemology is so on her part, but she then told Lawrence that she knew
hopelessly misconceived as to hold no interest at all.) a man who would be interested in helping him with
But Monk gives beautiful explanations of Russellʼs his schemes: Bertrand Russell.
logical achievements in Principia Mathematica and Lawrence was excited by the thought of collaborat-
the 1905 essay ʻOn Denotingʼ, which he regards as ʻhis ing with Russell (ʻthe Philosophic – and Mathematics
undoubted philosophical masterpieceʼ. (This leaves man,ʼ he mused, ʻa Fellow of Cambridge University
Russell sixty-five years in which to go downhill, and – F.R.S. – Earl Russellʼs brotherʼ), and when they met
Monk understandably avoids the question as to whether he immediately won the heart of the great logician.
there is anything worth preserving in Russellʼs logic ʻHe is infallibleʼ, Russell said after their first meeting;
that had not been done already, and rather better, by ʻhe sees everything and is always right.ʼ Lawrence
Frege.) sent him a long letter proposing a socialist revolution,
But the ordinary sensual reader cannot put up with starting with ʻthe nationalising of all industries and
very much mathematical logic. Like Russell himself, means of communciation, & of the land, in one fell
in fact, we are glad to take a break after a few pages, blow.ʼ (That should ʻsolve the whole economic ques-
and Monk, a gifted storyteller, unfailingly gives us tionʼ, he said.) He was under the impression that he
what we want. After learning a bit about Russellʼs and Russell had sworn Blutbrüderschaft in the name
stupendous cruelty to his first wife, however, or the of the new order, and by May they were planning to
clumsy manipulativeness of his intrigues with Ottoline give a joint lecture series, Russell dealing with ʻEthicsʼ,
Morrell (who could look after herself) and of numer- Lawrence with ʻImmortalityʼ. Russell said that the
ous insignificant others (who unluckily could not) we unifying theme of the series would be the idea that

38 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


existing institutions are ʻa prison for the infinite in usʼ, cally no material to be indelicate with. The Russell
and Lawrence envisaged the lectures being presided archives, carefully tended at McMaster University in
over by Ottoline Morrell, whose task would be to Ontario, are a very different matter, and the result
keep him and Russell striving ʻtowards the Eternal is that Monk has had to spend a lot of time sorting
thingʼ. After all, as Lawrence observed with entreating out the ups and downs of Russellʼs well-documented
urgency, ʻWe mustnʼt lapse into temporality.ʼ penile career. But even those who dote on revelations
No indeed. By July, Lawrence was spelling out about illicit love affairs will be slightly disappointed
the details of socialism to his philosophical blood- by this saga. We may experience a little elation the
brother. The state must be all-powerful; in fact it first few times Russell is exposed as a self-righteous
ought to become an object of worship; and of course old goat, a liar and two-timer; but the pleasure does
ʻthere must be a ruler: a Kaiser: no Presidents & not increase with repetition. Compared with other
democracies.ʼ There should also be a clear politi- earls or other logicians, Russellʼs sexual experience
cal division between the sexes, with a ʻDictatorʼ to may have been quite wide; but compared with most
control the ʻindustrial side of the national lifeʼ, and ordinary human beings, it was numbingly boring. It
a ʻDictatrixʼ to command ʻthings relating to private is not just that he was more interested in the hunt, so
lifeʼ. When, after a few months, Russell at last began to speak, than the kill, but that his top priority always
to quibble with some of these opinions, Lawrence seems to have been to give it verbal expression, so as
savaged him in a monstrously wounding letter, and to avoid at all costs the prudish secretiveness associ-
abandoned him and Ottoline Morrell as ʻtraitorsʼ. It ated with ʻVictorianismʼ. His obsession with putting
was then that the unhappy Russell started work on sex into words – plain ones or flowery, and many
the Caxton Hall lectures, whose emphasis on a time- of them – is a striking confirmation of Foucaultʼs
less psychology of instincts, we can now see, was a famous paradox: that the advocates of free love and
response to Lawrenceʼs precocious National Socialism, libidinal liberation were prisoners of the ʻrepressedʼ
as well as to the horrors of the Great War and Russellʼs conceptions of sexuality from which they imagined
need for a role. they had escaped. Sex, in Russellʼs opinion, was an
But the main thing in this biography is the sex, or ʻinstinctive impulseʼ, a base bodily function which,
rather the business surrounding it. Monkʼs life of Witt- unluckily, may sometimes pester us importunately, like
genstein has been praised for the restraint and delicacy a raging tooth or a bursting bladder. It never seems
with which it described Wittgensteinʼs intimate life; to have occurred to him that sexual experience might
but then, Wittgenstein left his biographer with practi- focus on the bodies of other people instead of the
efficient gratification of oneʼs own needs. As
the inexhaustible Ottoline Morrell noted, he
habitually complained that his lovers were
selfish, because they would not sacrifice
themselves entirely to him: ʻHe is intensely
self-centred, poor man.ʼ
What Russell sought in his sexual encoun-
ters, it seems, was simply a helping hand.
In 1920, for instance, when he was invei-
gling Dora Black into becoming his second
wife, he forestalled any misunderstanding
by explaining that ʻI must find a place for
sex with the smallest possible damage to
work.ʼ And she had already written to him
on the same lines: sex, for a modern girl
like her, was ʻa need, to be satisified now
& then as it presents itself, like hunger and
thirstʼ. ʻI am all for triviality in sexʼ, she
announced; and in Bertrand Russell she had
found her man.
There is something quite disconcerting
about the way Russell related to his ʻneedʼ

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 39


for love. It was as if he simply glanced inside himself some attention to the reasons for their difficulties, and
to observe a set of libidinal traffic signals alternating, a lot of severe circumspection if we imagine we have
sometimes rather rapidly, between three blunt mes- finally come up with The Answer. Instead, Russell
sages: Halt, Caution and Go. Although he was often comes on all cocky, assured, and tendentious: as blind,
baffled by what his ʻemotionsʼ were telling him, he it seems, to the layered ambiguities of philosophy as
never seems to have realized that it might be in their to those of either politics or love.
very nature to be ambiguous, and always capable of And there is another side to Russellʼs vaunted
absorbing new interpretations. And, come to think of ʻstyleʼ. He combined a rhetoric of self-admiring clever-
it, the same is true of his attitude to language and ness with a surprising weakness for purple platitudes
philosophy as well. Disciples like A.J. Ayer used to about how – to quote the peroration of his History of
refer to the ʻpower and elegance of his literary styleʼ, Western Philosophy – philosophy can ʻsuggest and
but what is really striking in Russellʼs writings is that inspire a way of lifeʼ. It is to these sentiments, indeed,
they show absolutely no talent or care for overall com- that Monk has traced the force that drove Russellʼs
position. They contain points, sharply made, but never astonishing productivity. Russell, like the rest of us,
lines, firmly drawn: the result is always disjointed and suffered from a recurrent sense of cosmic loneliness.
unsustained, with punctual clarity in the details but But he sought his solace amongst impersonal things,
obscurity and fudge on the whole. ʻabstract and remoteʼ, such as mathematics and espe-
It may be true that Russell never wrote a really cially philosophy. Traditional philosophy could not
duff sentence; but surely he never wrote a fine and delight him, though: he dismissed it as unscientific,
memorable one either. True, there are his celebrated and we may also suspect that it was too probing and
quips, like the one in ʻOn Denotingʼ about the bald- personal for his comfort – not remote and abstract
ness of the present King of France. There is no King enough. So he sought a new theoretical dispensation,
of France, of course, so, as Russell pointed out, ʻif as immaculate as the Lawrentian state: a perfect philo-
we enumerated the things that are bald, and then the sophical science, isolated from the past and untouched
things that are not bald, we should not find the present by superstition, grief or love. He was intent, in other
King of France in either list.ʼ But in that case, how words, on annihilating everything in philosophy that
could it be meaningful to say that the King of France might remind him of contingency; but in the end,
is bald? Before giving his solution to the conundrum, inevitably, he could never find any that did not.
Russell makes a characteristic joke: ʻHegelians, who Monk evidently came to his biographical task with
love a synthesis, will probably conclude that he wears the intention of praising Russell. He hoped to find
a wig.ʼ – as he had with Wittgenstein – a deep unity between
The one about the King of Franceʼs wig is the the life and the work, a single passion that would
paradigm joke of British analytic philosophy, still vindicate and redeem them both. By the end of the
much imitated by the kind of philosophers who fancy book, though – and this is only volume one – Russell is
themselves as wits. But it is a rotten joke. It is neither almost buried. Against the odds, Monk has succeeded
accurate nor funny; and it is both showy and beside the in unifying the life, by elaborating on the theme of
point. What is more, it is exultantly complacent: not Russellʼs solitude, and his quest for security in phil-
only conceited, but pleased with its conceit as well. osophy as in politics and sex. Russell wanted to exist
The same unhappy clever-dick style is to be found in an unequivocal world where his intellect would
in another typical sentence of Russellʼs, from the reign supreme. But the biography shows – as biog-
Lectures on Logical Atomism: ʻI think an almost raphies will – that he kept falling back into another
unbelievable amount of false philosophy has arisen world, the only world there is; and it is enigmatic
through not realising what “existence” means,ʼ Russell through and through. When Monk demonstrated the
says. You can hear the prose pausing to allow readers unity of Wittgensteinʼs life, he portrayed an astonish-
to applaud the great logicianʼs audacity in suggest- ing and touching philosophical hero; but when the
ing that philosophers have overlooked something so same service is performed for Russell, he appears as
elementary as the meaning of ʻexistenceʼ. But the superficial, mediocre and unwise: exceptional only
invitation is quite fraudulent. It may well be true that in his productivity, and his titanic imperceptiveness
past philosophers have all been wrong about existence, about others and about himself. Poor old Bertie. Poor
but that ought surely to inspire a little humility in us, old us.

40 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


REVIEWS

Capital futures
István Mészáros, Beyond Capital, The Merlin Press, London, 1995. xxvi + 994 pp., £45.00 hb., £14.95 pb.,
0 85036 454 X hb., 0 85036 432 9 pb.

It is now a quarter of a century since István Mészáros Lukács. Mészáros brilliantly underscores the continu-
had his first big success in Britain with Marxʼs Theory ity in the latterʼs outlook right up to the late essay
of Alienation. In the Preface to the third edition (1971) on democratization; he also shows that to the end
he promised to complement that masterly work of Lukács stuck to the Stalinist shibboleths of ʻsocialism
conceptual excavation with a study of actually exist- in one countryʼ and ʻtheʼ party as the sole agent of
ing capitalism and socialism. Other work intervened transformation. Mészáros explores Marxʼs theoretical
(notably a study of Sartre), but finally the promise difficulties, highlighting epigraphically an important
is redeemed. Beyond Capital is the first substantial unnoticed reservation expressed by Marx himself:
restatement of the case against capital, and for social- ʻwill revolution in Europe not be necessarily crushed
ism, since ʻthe fallʼ (indeed, for a good while longer), in this little corner of the world, since on a much larger
and very welcome on that account. In the face of those terrain the development of bourgeois society is still
who preach ʻthe end of historyʼ, and the dogma that in the ascendant?ʼ Today the world market predicted
ʻthere is no alternativeʼ, Mészáros remains intransi- by Marx is finally being established; for the first time
gent. He subjects capital in all its manifestations to we now live in one world (as Mészáros says, talk of
merciless critique, exposing the crying contradictions a ʻThird Worldʼ is nonsense), with all the attendant
of its apologists and the vacuity of the nostrums of its economic, ecological and ideological consequences.
would-be ʻsavioursʼ. However, it is not just a matter of Any coherent socialist project must encompass this
forcefully restating known truths (such as the fact that reality. Accordingly, the crucial question is this: under
capitalism is still founded on an alienated, and alienat- what conditions can the process of capital-expansion
ing, power, consequent on the structural subordination come to a close on a truly global scale, bringing with
of labour to capital), but pushing the argument further, it necessarily the end of crushed and perverted revo-
to overcome the limitations of Marxʼs own work and lutions, opening thereby the new historic phase of an
assess the significance of contemporary trends. Here irrepressible socialist offensive?ʼ
Mészáros has much to offer. Although deeply rooted in Part Three explores the present structural crisis of
the Marxist tradition, his thinking incorporates the new the capitalist system in detail. Here Mészáros demon-
determinants of development in the postwar period. strates the devastating effect of the ʻdecreasing rate of
The title of the present volume must be under- utilisationʼ, including its bizarre manifestation in the
stood in three senses. First it means ʻgoing beyond military-industrial complex. As he rightly points out,
capital as such and not merely beyond capitalismʼ much of the debate over ʻgrowthʼ ignores the relevance
(this important idea I will take up later); second, it of the fantastic wastefulness inherent in the capital
means going beyond what Marx himself managed to system. While the necessity of the socialist alterna-
achieve; finally, it means going beyond the original tive is reasserted, the reasons for the collapse of the
Marxian project, formulated when the full range of USSR are not evaded. As Mészáros correctly says, ʻthe
capitalʼs powers of adaptation lay beyond the horizon tragedy of Soviet type post-capitalist societies was that
of its century. they followed the line of least resistance by positing
This huge sprawling work has three main parts. socialism without radically overcoming the material
Part One analyses the nature of capital and debunks presuppositions of the capital system.ʼ In contrast, ʻthe
the claims of its apologists (e.g. Hayek). Part Two radical negation of the capitalist state and the like-
meditates on the legacy of the Russian Revolution, wise negative “expropriation of the expropriators” was
notably theorizations formulated in its shadow: here always considered by Marx only the necessary first step
History and Class Consciousness is exemplary and we in the direction of the required social transformation.ʼ
are offered what is virtually a book-length critique of He insisted that the hegemonic alternative to capitalʼs

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 41


social order can only be an inherently positive enter- and replacing it; tinkering with surface phenomena
prise. This is why the socialist revolution could not (e.g. juridical arrangements) will not change such
be conceived as a single act, no matter how radical in fundamentals. Thus Mészáros argues that ʻthe real
intent, but only as an ongoing, consistently self-critical target of emancipatory transformation is the complete
social revolution, as a ʻpermanent revolutionʼ (Marx). eradication of capital as a totalising mode of control
The object is to build an economy in the hands of from the social reproductive metabolism itself, and
the ʻassociated producersʼ (self-management), who put not simply the displacement of the capitalist as the
qualitative considerations above quantitative measures. historically specific “personification of capital”.ʼ As he
As for socialist strategy, Mészáros argues that, since put it in our interview with him in Radical Philosophy
capital is itself an extra-parliamentary force, it would (no. 62, p. 31):
be foolish to restrict radical politics to parliament. A You can overthrow the capitalist but the factory sys-
politics from below (ʻsocialist pluralismʼ) must generate tem remains, the division of labour remains, nothing
a global opposition to a global system. has changed in the metabolic functions of society.
As the title indicates, central to Beyond Capital Indeed … you find the need for reassigning those
is the thesis that it is necessary to go not merely forms of control to personalities, and thatʼs how the
bureaucracy comes into existence. The bureaucracy
beyond ʻcapitalismʼ but beyond ʻcapitalʼ itself. A lot
is a function of this command structure under the
therefore hangs on the coherence of this distinction. changed circumstances where in the absence of the
For example, it is used to characterize Soviet-type private capitalist you have to find an equivalent to
regimes of production as ʻpost-capitalistʼ, yet still that control … very often the notion of bureaucracy
under the sway of ʻcapitalʼ. This is outlined in a is pushed forward as a kind of mythical explana-
fascinating chapter on ʻchanging forms of the rule tory framework… [But] the bureaucracy itself needs
explanation… [It is said that] if you get rid of bu-
of capitalʼ. Mészárosʼs analysis of no-longer-existing
reaucracy then everything will be all right. But you
socialism is of more general importance; for it is clear
donʼt get rid of bureaucracy unless you attack [its]
that the lessons are not specific to the extremities of economic foundation…
the Russian situation, but are germane to the theory
It is indeed possible to smash the bourgeois state and
and practice of transition in general. It is crucial here
conquer political power. However, it is quite impossible
to recognize that ʻMarx was not concerned with demon-
strating the deficiencies of “capitalist production” but to ʻsmashʼ labourʼs inherent structural dependence on
with the great historical task of extricating humankind capital. For that dependency is materially secured by
from the conditions under which the satisfaction of the established hierarchical division of labour. Without
human needs must be subordinated to the “production the positive transcendence of capitalʼs metabolic
of capital”.ʼ Capitalʼs metabolism, based on its dom- functioning, ʻlabour itself self-defeatingly continues
ination of alienated labour, on the predominance of to reproduce the power of capital over against itselfʼ,
exchange over use-value, and on a hierarchical division Mészáros concludes.
of labour, is driven by the imperative of expansion. As In one version the distinction between capital
a system with its own logic and coherence it cannot be and capitalism is already familiar to us; for it is a
changed without tackling this central metabolic order commonplace that merchants and usurers employed
money as capital long before
capital seized hold of pro-
duction and established the
modern system of industrial
capitalism. But it is novel
to argue that capital may
survive capitalism. (It should
be noted that on Mészárosʼs
account the USSR was not
ʻstate-capitalistʼ, as Tony
Cliff among others argues.)
So let us look first at his
definition of capitalism.
Mészáros argues that the
capitalist formation extends

42 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


over only that particular phase of capital production of profit, which happens to be an absolute necessity
in which (1) production for exchange is all pervasive; only in the capitalist variety of the capital system.
(2) labour power itself is a commodity; (3) the drive … During several decades of Soviet economic
development high levels of capital accumulation
for profit is the fundamental regulator; (4) the vital
[were] secured by means of the politically con-
mechanism for the extraction of surplus-value – the trolled extraction of surplus labour, without remote-
radical separation of the means of production from ly resembling the capitalist system in its necessary
the producers – assumes an inherently economic orientation towards profit.
form; (5) surplus value is privately appropriated by
This seems odd to me; for I would have thought
the members of the capitalist class; and (6) following
that the accumulation-fetish was not rooted in ʻthe
its economic imperative of growth and expansion,
metabolic orderʼ but in the hopes of the controllers,
capital production tends towards a global integra-
who imposed external ʻtargetsʼ, terroristically driven.
tion. It follows from this definition, according to
Moreover, if Mészáros insists that the USSR as a
Mészáros, that one cannot ʻspeak of capitalism in
capital system was expansion orientated, how is that
post-revolutionary societies when out of these essen-
compatible with the failure to innovate which led to
tial defining characteristics only one – number four
permanent stagnation? No matter how much political
– remains, and even that in a radically altered form,
authority, for external reasons of state, tried to coerce
in that the extraction of surplus labour is regulated
or stimulate the producers, the economy responded
politically and not economicallyʼ. Yet at the same
only sluggishly in quantitative terms, and innovation
time Mészáros argues that capital maintains its rule
became completely bogged down. This was politically
in such post-revolutionary societies. What, then, is
crucial; for the failure to ʻcatch upʼ with the West,
the definition of ʻcapitalʼ that would be congruent
and the failure to achieve real growth in the Brezhnev
with this survival?
years, stripped the system of legitimacy, even in the
According to Mészáros, the necessary conditions of
eyes of its beneficiaries, and brought about its implo-
all conceivable forms of the capital relation – including
sion. Mészáros is clearly right to argue that socialist
the post-capitalist forms – are: (1) the separation and
revolution is not merely a matter of political power,
alienation of the objective conditions of the labour
or of redistribution, but of changing the fundamental
process from labour itself; (2) the superimposition of
social metabolism established by capital; it means
such alienated conditions over the workers as a sepa-
transforming the very structure of material production
rate power exercising command over labour; (3) the
and abolishing the hierarchical division of labour. He
personification of capital as ʻegotistic valueʼ pursuing
is clearly right that post-capitalist social formations
its own self-expansion – the bureaucrat is the post-
failed to achieve this positive transcendence; and the
capitalist equivalent of the private capitalist; (4) the
emergence of ʻthe bureaucracyʼ is explicable primarily
equivalent personification of labour whether as wage-
on that basis. His conceptualization of the problem in
labourer under capitalism or as the norm-fulfilling
terms of the survival of ʻcapitalʼ beyond ʻcapitalismʼ
ʻsocialist workerʼ under the post-capitalist system.
is the most interesting analysis since that of Trotsky,
ʻCapital can change the form of its rule as long as
these four basic conditions – which are constitutive of and deserves to be widely discussed.
its “organic system” – are not radically supersededʼ, For me Mészáros pays insufficient attention to the
Mészáros concludes. Additionally, he maintains that value-form of capital and the positing of expansion
since the inherited social division of labour and the inherent in it. I therefore find incoherent the notion of
objective structure of production remained in the post- capital without profit. Certainly, if the factory system
capitalist economies we have witnessed, capital in this in which capital materialized itself endures, then one
sense persisted. cannot speak of socialism; but, conversely, if the law
Clearly there is considerable room for discussion of value enforced through capitalist competition is no
about such a definition of capital. But in one respect longer operative, we have a clock without a spring. I
– namely, that capital is inherently accumulation driven would argue that in the USSR capitalʼs metabolism
– everyone would agree. Mészáros goes out of his way was disrupted without an alternative being established;
to argue that this was still true of the USSR: lacking organic coherence, the system could not sur-
The imperative of accumulation driven expansion vive once the exceptional conditions of revolutionary
can be satisfied under changed economic circum- mobilization, and of war, had passed.
stances not only without the subjective ʻprofit
motiveʼ but even without the objective requirement Chris Arthur

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 43


Without consent
Keith Burgess-Jackson, Rape: A Philosophical Investigation, Dartmouth, Aldershot and Brookfield VT, 1996.
xi + 224 pp., £42.50 hb., 1 85521 485 7.
Sue Lees, Carnal Knowledge: Rape on Trial, Hamish Hamilton, London, 1996. xxvii + 292 pp., £20.00 hb.,
0 241 13629 6.

These two books form an admirably complementary draw attention to serious problems that attend this
pair. Burgess-Jacksonʼs is a jurisprudential study of simple definition.
what the crime of rape is, why it is a crime, the forms Burgess-Jackson in fact disputes the view that there
it can take, and the defences that may be offered. is a single understanding of rape. He argues that there
Leesʼs is a study of how, in practice, rape cases are can be – and is – deep disagreement about what is
handled by the police and the judiciary, from their and is not rape, and suggestions that there are several
initial reporting through to the conduct of any even- conceptions of rape. The conservative theory construes
tual trial. Both authors are feminists and both studies rape as a trespass upon the property of the man, the
provide good reasons to be dissatisfied with the way wrong done being to he who owns the woman violated.
in which the law does deal with rape. Both write The liberal theory regards rape as an unconsented
against the background of sustained public debate sexual battery, the wrong done being to the individual
about what should and should not be regarded as rape woman whose own choices with regard to her body
at law. This debate has, in Britain, been prompted by are denied. The radical theory regards rape as but
a number of celebrated recent cases – most notably, one instance of the subordination of women by men,
the acquittal of the student Austen Donnellan and the wrong done being to the gender as a whole whose
the conviction of the solicitor Angus Diggle. It has entitlement to equal respect and consideration is dis-
also been fuelled by claims, mainly made in the con- honoured. Burgess-Jackson claims not to endorse any
servative press, that men are now being stigmatized one of these three conceptions (though his sympathies
as rapists merely for misreading sexual cues in a are clearly with the last). He does seek to show how
world where communication between the genders if their application yields different conclusions as to
fraught with difficulties and ambiguities. However, whether some act is one of rape, what makes rape
the debate has also heard contributions from feminists wrongful, and what may serve as a defence to the
worried about the overextension of the term ʻrapeʼ, the charge of rape. Some of his analyses are exemplary.
representation of women as perpetual victims, and the The chapter on ʻMarital Rapeʼ, for instance, exposes
overdramatization of the offence if unaccompanied and rebuts, with admirable clarity and conciseness,
by violence. all of the various arguments that might be offered
Both writers regard rape as a sexual crime. This to the conclusion that a husband cannot be guilty of
does not imply that it is in some sense a less serious raping his wife.
crime. Nor does it imply that rape occupies a place A problem with Burgess-Jacksonʼs approach is that,
on a continuum of behaviours which extends to con- although he is surely right to display the differences
sensual sexual interaction. Nor does it imply that between the views of the conservative, liberal and
sexual pleasure is the sole end of the rapist. Nor does radical, it is not always clear on his account whether
it imply that a number of all too familiar stereotypical these really do differ about what rape is, or only about
assumptions about the sexual character of men and what makes it wrong. If rape is unconsented sex, then
women, and about the nature of heterosexual inter- it is possible to disagree about what is wrong with
action between men and women, are true. It does mean unconsented sex for being unconsented. And this need
that rape is other than simple assault. It also requires not be a trivial dispute. But it is not a dispute about
that the crime of rape be clearly distinguished from all what rape is. We can have a single concept of rape
other kinds of sexual encounters, however unwanted, – unconsented sex – and various conceptions of rape.
regretted, unsatisfactory, or loveless some of these These conceptions can be distinguished in two regards
may be. Evidently, the matter of consent is central – how they understand consent and its absence; and
to the crime of rape. Rape is unconsented sex. What what it is about the lack of consent which makes rape
distinguishes rape from sexual intercourse is lack of morally problematic. The liberal may be wrong to
consent. However, both books, in their different ways, think that rape is only wrong for being the violation

44 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


of an individualʼs wishes; the radical may be right in wake of some publicized cases – that more than 4,500
seeing each and every such violation as signifying women each year are mendacious, spiteful accusers.
a more general oppression of women. Neither need Leesʼs monitoring of the British police and judicial
deny that some sexual act is one of rape only if it is process at work provides some explanation of what is
unconsented. going wrong. A dangerous combination of bad legal
What counts as consent is a separate and further practice and general, misogynistic attitudes is exposed.
matter of dispute between the liberal and radical. The When consent is the central issue at stake, and the
radicalʼs view (and Catharine MacKinnon is the most complainant is no more than a witness within an adver-
notable protagonist) is that the liberal is prepared to sarial hearing which requires proof beyond reasonable
countenance as consensual what she views as com- doubt and tolerates the admission of certain kinds of
pelled or passive acquiescence. Again there is no evidence, the stage is set for a shameful display of
reason to see this dispute as one over the concept of prejudicial attitudes and procedures which favour the
rape. It is one about the concept of consent. The radical defendants at the cost of humiliating their accusers.
is prepared to view ʻnormalʼ heterosexual intercourse Despite all the supposed improvements in law and
as perhaps no less non-consensual than a paradigmatic rules of procedure, Leesʼs evidence is damning. Time
instance of rape – because a woman, socialized into and again testimony regarding the behaviour, lifestyle,
the role of passive acceptance of the eroticized dom- clothing, character and past sexual conduct of women
inance that is heterosexuality in our society, cannot be is not only admitted, but seen as bearing directly on
said ʻreallyʼ to consent to any sexual encounter with the question of whether a rape occurred.
a man. Burgess-Jackson, it must be said, invokes this Many of Leesʼs recommendations for change are
understanding without mentioning any of the serious to be welcomed: better training of the judiciary, more
worries that have been expressed about it by many stringent controls on the admission of sexual character
feminist philosophers and jurisprudential theorists. and sexual history evidence, an acceptance of some
The problem Sue Lees reveals is that the current forms of corroborative evidence, and – especially
system simply does not do justice to women and fails in the light of cases of serial rapists who are being
to convict the rapists it should. Whilst the number of acquitted time after time – a greater disposition to
reported rapes in England and Wales has trebled in the admit evidence from several women of similar rapes.
last ten years, the conviction rate has fallen. It is ludi- However, other of her comments are less welcome.
crous to suppose – whatever the press may say in the That rules permit misogyny does not mean that the
rules are themselves misogynistic. Nor should rules be
devised to punish misogyny as such. If it is thought
proper to allow a womanʼs past behaviour some weight
in assessing the validity of her charge, it should at
least be permitted to count a manʼs past behaviour as
bearing on the present accusation. However, it is not
proper, as Lees suggests, to see his views on women
and sex as relevant. Least of all should any revealed
ʻsexismʼ ʻbe seen as evidence for his guiltʼ (p. 253).
Both books raise all the right empirical and norma-
tive questions about how we define, try, excuse and
punish the crime of rape. They do not settle matters.
At the end of the day this may be because, although
rape just is sex without consent, the law and its tri-
bunals have proved deeply inadequate to the task of
understanding what non-consensual sex is. Whether
that is the fault of present practice, or is due to the
straightforward impossibility of legally regulating
sexual conduct, is unclear. But both authors afford an
admirable brief for either argument.
David Archard

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 45


Patchwork selves and others
Morwenna Griffiths, Feminisms and Self: The Web of Identity, Routledge, London and New York, 1995. x +
220 pp., £37.50 hb., £12.99 pb, 0 415 09820 3 hb., 0 415 09821 1 pb.

If a book can be heaped with praise for the scale of tative philosophersʼ. In her terms, philosophy is simply
its ambition, then this one deserves mountains of it. another language, and she inhabits the community of
It aspires to convince the reader of the incapacities of philosophers just as she inhabits other communities.
the Anglo-Saxon tradition of philosophy in the fields In re-creating herself as a feminist philosopher, she is
of ʻepistemology, ethics, mind and politicsʼ, while involved in a politics informed by an understanding
simultaneously engaging us in a process of renewal of how judgements are validated by a new community
and reconstruction. The move we are enjoined to and get into circulation. Indeed, it is her view that one
make is from the ʻfalse universalisation inherent in is theorizing, in a sense, ʻsimply by publishingʼ.
mainstream philosophy towards a situated abstractionʼ Is one also doing philosophy simply by publishing?
(p. 70), particularly in discussions of personal identity Manifestly not. The mistake lies in identifying phil-
and the self. osophy as another language, rather than as an activity
Mainstream philosophy is ʻrepresentedʼ by Williams, of unravelling the grammars of languages. It is the
Parfit, Nagel and Dennett. Griffiths warns feminists not politically structured character of their involvement
to expect the work of these philosophers to illuminate with these languages that marks the exclusionary/
their concerns with the question of ʻwho or what I inclusionary features of the philosophical activity of
amʼ. In the absence of a credible analysis of their male/female, white/black, Western/Eastern philoso-
views, her warning amounts to advocating the view phers. It follows that the activity of philosophy cannot
of ʻknowledge by testimonyʼ in traditional terms. But be seriously undertaken if one fails to listen to those
it can also be redescribed as ʻtrusting othersʼ judge- who have been set up as the Other. Here the Other
mentsʼ in a certain sort of feminist terminology. This is the ʻmaleʼ philosopher. Richard Rorty is criticized
supports implicitly a dismissive attitude towards ʻmaleʼ for valorizing fear and cruelty in self-creation, when
philosophers, disappointing in a book which is duly the whole point of his work is to show how a liberal
self-conscious of its diverse audience. ironist can fulfil his only clearly articulated desire
In other contexts, trust, co-operation, love and of preventing the actual and possible humiliation of
acceptance are indeed attractive notions from most others. It may have been more appropriate to differ
feminist perspectives and, in this book, form the with him about how the job of opening oneself to
guiding pattern for a conceptual revision of the notion the pain of others is accomplished, in particular by
of self-identity as self-creation. Several good argu- questioning his commendation of the private–public
ments are offered for accepting these notions as politi- division. Ironically, his preference for literature rather
cal values. The most crucial one is that fear debilitates, than philosophy in forging human solidarity is echoed
and therefore any commitment to increasing autonomy in Griffithsʼ own use of critical autobiography. More-
for self-creation must recognize the need for ʻgenerous over, her commitment to vigilance about oppression is
patterns of cultural and political life, and the reduction not very different from Rortyʼs plea that ʻwe should
of fearʼ (p. 143). To this end, we are provided with an stay on the lookout for marginalized people.ʼ
absorbing description of how emotions and feelings are Charles Taylorʼs communitarianism is likewise
socially and interpersonally constructed in a politically found wanting for its insufficient attention to the politi-
structured environment, which opens the way for self- cal. While it is true that Taylor does not specifically
creation via a ʻpolitics of the selfʼ. focus on feminist concerns, to extend this charge to
This, for me, is where a problem emerges. If the accusation that his view is ʻnot about political
politics is about creating public spaces where fearless individualsʼ is intriguing. Once again insufficient argu-
exchanges can occur between more or less autono- ment leaves one dissatisfied. Paul Gilroy is quoted
mous selves, and these public spaces are constituted with approval; however, the claim to ʻgo beyondʼ him
by various languages of expression and communica- is made without warrant.
tion, what exactly is the role of philosophy in this The merit of Griffithsʼ constructive arguments
political process? ʻMainstream/academic philosophyʼ is seriously threatened by her brief and ineffective
is frequently derided in this book, while the author attempts to critique the position of others. Comparable
continues to identify herself as one of ʻus argumen- preceding accounts, such as Jonathan Gloverʼs on self-

46 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


creation and Elizabeth Potterʼs on moral identity, are Schriftʼs concern is not with the rectitude of the
surprisingly omitted. A more sustained discussion of many interpretations of Nietzscheʼs work that have
the work of other feminists might have added to the been proposed in France. He is concerned, rather,
appeal of the book. Repetitive and insubstantial refer- with what might be termed Nietzscheʼs use-value
ences to othersʼ work can often perplex the uninitiated. within recent French philosophy, and with the way in
A case in point is Pratibha Parmarʼs writing on Asian which Derrida, Foucault, Deleuze and Cixous have
women. We are told that the creation of authentic made use of him in developing their own projects.
works of art by black and migrant women asserts both Neither Deleuzeʼs pioneering study, Derridaʼs Spurs,
their unity and their difference, without any indication nor Foucaultʼs essays on Nietzsche are dealt with
of how this creative process works for these women. here. Schrift further restricts his field of enquiry by
Shortcomings apart, Griffithsʼ novel use of auto- ruling himself incompetent to deal with the philo-
biographies to illustrate the problems and resolutions sophical projects of Bataille, Blanchot or Irigaray.
to some of the paradoxes of self-identity is a refreshing His modesty sounds genuine rather than feigned, and
turn. Her overriding preference for ʻvariety, confu- the admission is refreshingly honest. More refreshing
sion, colour, hotchpotch … of patchwork selvesʼ has still is Schriftʼs lucidity and clarity of expression. He
undoubtedly left its mark on the production of this is no vulgarizer, but his readings of the more abstruse
book. It deviates from many norms; how successfully pronouncements of Deleuze and Derrida in particular
is a debatable matter. are happily free of the clogged prose that obscures so
many accounts.
Meena Dhanda
The primary use-value of Nietzsche for the
so-called ʻpoststructuralistʼ generation (Schriftʼs
delicate inverted commas are a timely reminder
that ʻFrench poststructuralismʼ is largely an Anglo-

Nietzsche’s French American construct) is that he offers an alternative


both to the phenomenological privileging of subjec-

futures tivity and to the anti-subjectivism of structuralism.


Nietzsche makes it possible, that is, to raise new
questions about individual agency without relapsing
Alan D. Schrift, Nietzscheʼs French Legacy: A Geneal- into either voluntarism or scientism. The attraction
ogy of Poststructuralism, Routledge, New York and for those wishing to escape the codified confines of
London, 1995. xvii + 198 pp., £40.00 hb., £12.95 pb.,
academic philosophy was irresistible. As Foucault
0 415 91146 X hb., 0 415 91147 8 pb.
once remarked, some things are more fun to think
In his Ecce Homo, Nietzsche referred to the French about than others. And for a long time, Nietzsche
as ʻcharming companyʼ, and he often regretted having was certainly fun.
to write in German, rather than in a more playful and For Derrida, Nietzscheʼs rejection of the binary
fluid language like French. He was also conscious logic of ʻgood or evilʼ opens up a new line of approach
of having been ʻborn posthumouslyʼ, predicting that that avoids a history of philosophy replicating binary
he would eventually find his true readers amongst divisions and choices. At this level, Nietzsche is a talis-
the philosophers of the future. As Schrift notes in man, a guarantee of otherness rather than an author
passing, Nietzscheʼs French incarnation was for a long to be expounded in any detail. Similarly, for Deleuze,
time a cultural-literary one, and it was sustained by a Nietzsche often stands for symbolic deterritorializ-
variety of literary writers from Malraux and Camus to ation; his aphorisms are always elsewhere, always
Klossowski, Blanchot and Bataille; oddly, no mention resistant to codification. In the case of Cixous, the
is made here of the Gide of Fruits of the Earth link seems more tenuous, and her proposal that gift-
(1897) and The Immoralist (1902). During the years giving can provide the foundations for a feminine
when French philosophy was dominated by alternative libidinal economy, as opposed to a masculine economy
imports such as the ʻthree Hʼsʼ (Hegel, Husserl and predicated on a desire to possess, appears to owe
Heidegger), Nietzsche remained a shadowy and even more to Derridaʼs passing comments on Nietzsche
suspect figure. It was, it is generally agreed, Deleuzeʼs than to Nietzsche himself. Schriftʼs reading of Cixous
Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962) that turned him into does, however, demonstrate just how widely Nietzsche
a French philosopher. Henceforth Nietzscheʼs future was disseminated in the 1970s, albeit in a sometimes
appeared to be both French and solidly assured. indirect manner.

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 47


Schrift does not always avoid the obvious danger rallying cry ʻWe are not Nietzscheansʼ has become one
inherent in an essay like this, and at times tends to of the main slogans of a turn away from – and against
ascribe a little too much influence to his subject. That – poststructuralism. Kant appears once more to be the
Deleuzeʼs notions of desire as a productive force and only (or last) good German philosopher, as he was fifty
of the perpetual nature of becoming are indebted to years ago. This is in part no doubt a banal generational
the Nietzschean will to power is not in dispute. But quarrel and a critique of a marginality that has become
one would like to learn more about how Deleuzeʼs an orthodoxy. More worryingly, it signals a rejection
Nietzscheanism relates to the Bergsonian rhizomes that of relativist perspectivism in the name of a return to
sprout throughout his work. With Foucault, matters ʻRepublican valuesʼ and a ʻuniversalismʼ that is in
may be more complex still. Thus, the Nietzschean fact disturbingly Gallic in flavour. The new binary
genealogy of his theory of power as a network of choice appears to be: either Kant and the Republic,
relations of force, rather than an object to be taken, or Nietzsche and barbarism.
held or lost, may have been filtered through Canguil- Schrift is, however, optimistic about Nietzscheʼs
hemʼs work on vitalism, and Canguilhem himself often next French future, and suggests that the critique of
claimed to be a Nietzschean. To disentangle that line nationalisms and identity politics made in Human, Too
of descent would no doubt require a new book, and it Human has considerable contemporary relevance. It
is to be hoped that Schrift will write it. is hard to disagree. ʻSupposing truth to be a woman
In his final chapter, Schrift argues that Nietzscheʼs – what?ʼ, asks Nietzsche. Sections of the French media
French future is over for the moment, and that he is currently suppose a young Arab woman with a veil to
now little more than another figure in the history of be a threat to the Republic. And supposing that she
philosophy. For Descombes in his influential Modern has something to say about the truth of Republicanism
French Philosophy, for Ferry and Renault in their – what?
French Philosophy of the Sixties, as for Lyotard, the
David Macey

Beyond the flesh


Chris Hables Gray, ed., The Cyborg Handbook, Routledge, New York and London, 1995. xx + 540 pp., £40.00
hb., £16.99 pb., 0 415 90848 5 hb., 0 415 90849 3 pb.
Judith Halberstam and Ira Livingston, eds, Posthuman Bodies, Indiana University Press, Bloomington and
Indianapolis, 1995. x + 275 pp., £27.50 hb., £13.50 pb., 0 253 32894 2 hb., 0 253 20970 6 pb.

There is growing interest in the human body as a cybernetic organisms, or cyborgs, which began with
subject of investigation within philosophy. Although Donna Harawayʼs powerful essay ʻA Manifesto for
primarily driven by the traditions of phenomenology Cyborgsʼ (1985). Since then, cyborgism has become a
and poststructuralism, significant contributions have central concept for many postmodern, ʻcyberfeministʼ
been made by radical feminists and in the developing philosophers and cultural critics like Anne Balsamo,
queer literature. Allucquere Rosanne Stone and Sadie Plant.
The Cyborg Handbook, however, is really concerned The Cyborg Handbook is a collection of articles
with the relationship between the body and new cyber- which attempt to define and explore these ques-
netic and prosthetic technologies like virtual reality. tions. It brings together the most important historical
For the evolution of technology renders the possibility and theoretical documents on cyborgs, particularly
of substituting physical operations and attributes, to with respect to their development in space, warfare,
restore and enhance the functioning of the body. This medicine, politics, anthropology and the technological
is achieved by assembling synthetic appliances and imaginary. It suggests that there is not just one type
modifying individual competencies through facilities of cyborg but many different types, ranging from the
contrived to heighten human effectiveness. The tech- merely ʻrestorativeʼ (i.e. replacing lost functions/limbs)
nologized body is thus furnished with a redesigned through to the ʻenhancedʼ jet pilots of the Gulf War.
exterior made up of precisely modelled electronic The editor argues that the distinction between humans
instruments, robotics and machinic devices. Not and machines is now almost imperceptible. Indeed, for
surprisingly, there has been a considerable amount him, humanity is on the threshold of a new stage of
of fascination with the philosophical significance of human-machine evolution; a stage which brings with it

48 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


not only cybernetic technologies but also vastly altered
linguistic capabilities and sense perceptions. The measure of
Posthuman Bodies, by contrast, is specifically con-
cerned with how the body, in conjunction with various
some things
reproductive and cinematic technologies, impacts upon Cairns Craig, Out of History: Narrative Paradigms
feminist and queer cultural politics and identities. The in Scottish and British Culture, Polygon, Edinburgh,
book is an assortment of articles that relate to disparate 1996. 240 pp., £11.95 pb., 0 7486 6082 8.
postmodern cultural confrontations with the rationality
This is a thoughtful analysis of conflicting modern
of the technologized body. The argument of the editors
cultural identities written from a Scottish perspective.
is that ʻthe posthuman condition is upon us, and that
Craig lectures on English literature at Edinburgh Uni-
nostalgia for a humanist philosophy of self and other,
versity, and this collection, largely a reprint of essays
human and alien, normal and queer is merely the
in Cencrastus and Radical Scotland from 1981 to the
echo of a battle that has already taken placeʼ (p. vii).
early 1990s, is notable for its informed discussions
Posthuman Bodies is an exhortation to employ a wide
of a shelf-full of classic Scottish (and other) novels
range of corporeal forms that supplant both the human
and books.
and the humanities. Halberstam and Livingston suggest It is a mark of the rapid movement of debate and
that such an undertaking arises out of the knowledge recovery of cultural self-confidence in Scotland that
that the licence that these singular identities pretend the early essays already have a slightly dated feel to
to advance is extortionate, since it makes valueless them. Do we still need to be lectured on ʻparochial-
much of what matters to them. The pieces included ismʼ, for example, or told that ʻScottish culture has
draw on a variety of disciplines, including film and cowered in the consciousness of its own inadequacyʼ
literary studies, cultural studies of science and science (p. 11)? The core of the book, however, is a fascinating
fiction, feminist and queer studies. Whilst there is no essay entitled ʻGeorge Orwell and the English Ideol-
posthuman manifesto on offer, the contributors do ally ogyʼ which ranges widely over the themes of English
themselves with a variety of hyphenated (post-, sub-, poetry, self-image, and their resonances in popular
inter-, trans-, etc.) methodological principles. politics in Britain. The cultural Right in England, from
The body is now firmly on the agenda. But a T.S. Eliot to C.S. Sissons, is seen as employing a model
number of theoretical problems remain. First, there is of tradition based on assumed continuities of language
an underemphasis in both these volumes on defining and landscape. Its echoes in Edwin Muirʼs Scott and
the modern body and its history. Second, there is no Scotland (1936) give it a relevance to Scottish self-per-
attempt to define what a postmodern body might be: is ceptions. The English Left from Orwell on, so Craig
it a ʻbody without organsʼ (Deleuze and Guattari)? A argues, implicitly accepted this idea of continuity,
body without a self? A self without a body? Certainly, theorizing for example about the distinctive ʻpatienceʼ
the posthuman body seems to have the capacity to and ʻfundamental decencyʼ of the common people. The
become monstrously Other when, as White puts it in older ʻNew Leftʼ writers (Raymond Williams or E.P.
Thompson) thus popularized culture-specific English
Posthuman Bodies, ʻthe menagerie withinʼ is let loose
ʻtraditionsʼ to counter both the rival traditionalism of
on celluloid, as in Inoshiro Honda and Eiji Tsuburayaʼs
Eliot, and the crude and suspect ʻinternationalismʼ
Attack of the Mushroom People. Third, neither of these
flowing from the Soviet Union. In this way, following
books contributes significantly to the development of
Marxʼs foregrounding of the development of English
a critical theory of technology, although The Cyborg
capitalism in the nineteenth century, they prioritized
Handbook does at least highlight the fact that imman-
English history in a kind of unwitting cultural impe-
ent cyborgization also presages alarming mutations
rialism. Even their critics in the New Left Review
that may possibly transform human beings into mere
prioritize England, Nairn in The Break-up of Britain
automatons. Posthuman dilemmas are multiplying (1981) seeing Scottish popular culture as peculiarly
daily. Unfortunately, it is clear that our understanding ʻdeformedʼ in comparison with Englandʼs.
of the moral implications of technologized bodies is More questionable is Craigʼs final essay, ʻPosting
not going to be enhanced by a postmodern philosophy Towards the Futureʼ. It is hardly a model of clarity.
which is devoid of ethical foundations, let alone ethical Craig imperceptibly blends in exposition of othersʼ
prescriptions. views with his own argument, and deals in vague, ill-
John Armitage defined contrasts. He begins by contrasting Marxism

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 49


(in its Soviet ʻHistmatʼ version) with a Nietzsche- and they will cease to be unacceptable prisons to their
inspired ʻpostmodernismʼ, and ends by suggesting that tenants. The style is the meaningʼ (pp. 212–13). Never
both overvalue a Western idea of history at the expense mind fuel poverty, dampness or poor design then:
of other perspectives. This last point, in so far as it tells Protagoras lives.
against Marxism, was made with considerably greater As for the Scottish literary criticism, we might wish
clarity by John MacMurray in the 1930s. at times that Craig took his own advice and validated
In the section on ʻpostmodernismʼ, the abandon- perspectives other than those of the political-cultural
ment of England as the yardstick of all historical activist. Moreover, admiration for the ʻliberation of
development becomes an excuse for an unwarranted the voiceʼ in modern Scottish fiction and poetry is less
rejection of the rationality of historical analysis per se. than convincing when accompanied by neglect of what
Thus we are told: ʻthough we may wish to fight for the ʻliberatedʼ voice actually says. All in all though,
the truthfulness of our discourse, in the last analysis Out of History represents a sustained and closely
we have to accept that if one discourse succeeds in argued effort, from a liberal standpoint, to nurture a
vital literary culture in Scotland.

Stephen Cowley

The last laugh


Adriana Cavarero, In Spite of Plato: A Feminist
Rewriting of Ancient Philosophy, translated by Serena
Anderlini-DʼOnofrio and Aine OʼHealy, Polity Press,
Cambridge, 1995. xxii + 136 pp., £39.50 hb., £11.95
pb., 0 7456 1259 8 hb., 0 7456 1572 4 pb.

With few translations available, Italian feminist phil-


osophy has received little attention in the Anglophone
world. This welcome addition helps redress that situ-
ation and also demonstrates the inadequacy of the still
popular classification of feminist philosophy into either
French or Anglo-American branches. For, whilst it is
true that the influence of Luce Irigaray pervades her
book, Cavarero is by no means an acolyte or imitator;
to think so would be to ignore the mutual exchange of
ideas that Irigaray has enjoyed with Italian feminists
over the years. Furthermore, the influence of Irigaray
replacing another it is only as a function of the “will
nestles here amongst many others (Le Dœuff, Arendt,
to power”, or as a shift in some deep-structure of our
Kristeva, Clément, Cixous, Daly, Lispector, and no
social organization that we cannot control, not as a
doubt several Italians whom I did not recognize),
function of its superior valueʼ (p. 212). Yet when a
making this work the very embodiment of feminist
newspaper owner replaces the ʻdiscourseʼ with a left-
intertextuality.
wing journalist like Paul Foot on the Daily Mirror
Cavarero starts from the assumption that the mythic
with ʻalternative discoursesʼ, this is surely not merely
figures of any given culture represent the ʻsymbolic
an expression of the ʻwill to powerʼ outside of our
orderʼ which has shaped it, and that through these
ʻcontrolʼ. It is better – more accurate – to speak of
figures a culture may recognize and understand itself.
something essential (e.g. the control of public space
What the mythic figures of ʻwestern cultureʼ reveal,
by capital) occurring behind superficial appearances.
then, is a symbolic order in which ʻa male subject
According to Craig, by contrast, ʻThe “postworld”
claiming to be neutral/universal declares his central
is a world in which it is impossible to distinguish
position, disseminating a sense of the world cut to
appearance from reality, because appearance is the
his own clothʼ. This culture, so Cavarero argues, lacks
only realityʼ – an argument illustrated as follows: ʻbolt
any female mythic figures not constructed according
art nouveau decorations on to modernist tower blocks to patriarchal codes, figures in whom a woman could

50 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


recognize herself as ʻa female subjectivity capable feminism more generally, that it is less successful in
of taking shape within her own symbolic orderʼ. To its reconstructive, ʻpositiveʼ aspects than as a critical
accede to the demand of such a female or feminine discourse. But this would probably be to make an
(the Italian does not differentiate) subjectivity, new overly rigid distinction. As the mocking laughter of
figures are needed; but, rather than creating them from the Thracian maid gets louder and louder, pointing to
scratch, Cavareroʼs strategy is to steal. Each of the four the sheer phenomenological implausibility of Platonic
sections of the book is named after a female figure idealism, the philosophical analysis simultaneously
ʻstolenʼ from Platoʼs dialogues and relocated within a picks apart the dualistic system on which it is based,
ʻfeminine symbolic orderʼ, which gives them new life until the laughter and the philosophical voice of the
and us the possibility of new mythic identifications. text merge. Much satisfaction is to be had from the
To that end, the book is probably written for the sisterly complicity, but Cavareroʼs fine readings of
woman reader, the active ʻfemale feministʼ reader Plato are accessible without it.
identified in Rosi Braidottiʼs useful foreword to the
Stella Sandford
English edition.
Lest this encourage the tendency to marginalize
feminist philosophy, it must at once be pointed out
that there is much in Cavareroʼs book which ought to
make the non-feminist mainstream of philosophy sit up Turning ethical
and take notice too. This is particularly evident in the
Bill Martin, Humanism and its Aftermath: The Shared
section which centres on the figure (in Platoʼs Thea-
Fate of Deconstruction and Politics, Humanities Press
etetus) of the Maidservant from Thrace who laughed
International, Atlantic Highlands NJ, 1995. xvi + 199
at Thales when, too busy gazing at the heavens, he
pp., £29.95 hb., £9.95 pb., 0 391 03893 1 hb., 0 391
neglected to look at his feet and fell into a well. For
03894 X pb.
Plato the Maidservant illustrates the inability of simple
folk to appreciate the concerns of the genuine philoso-
Much has been made of deconstructionʼs supposed
pher. Cavarero, by contrast, uses the womanʼs laughter
ʻethical turnʼ. But not enough, according to Bill Martin
as the starting point for a rigorous and compelling
– at least not in a practical sense. This book is a spir-
reading of the philosophical relationship between
ited, lucid, often highly polemical attempt to ʻthinkʼ
Parmenides and Plato, a critique of their dualistic
a deconstructive politics which can be engaged at
distinction between being and appearance, and an
a practical level. Martinʼs main opponents in this
invigorating account of the way in which Platonic
enterprise are those on the Left who would dismiss
philosophy was able to conceal the fact of sexual dif-
Derridaʼs work as a politically irrelevant species of
ference with the idealization and false universalization
idealist posturing and wordplay, and those in the
of ʻManʼ. So, whilst it is true that sexual difference is
deconstructive camp who play straight into the hands
Cavareroʼs theme, such an intelligent and interesting
of this caricature by presuming that there is nothing
analysis of Plato ought to be of concern to more than
more to do than tinker with texts.
just ʻfeministʼ philosophers.
The book has three main parts. In the first, Martin
In the other sections, Cavarero has Penelope illus-
examines the relevance to deconstruction of trad-
trate the interweaving of the intelligence and the
itionally Marxist preoccupations (class, history, the
senses, and Diotimaʼs speech from the Symposium is
concrete nature of social change). He criticizes existing
exposed as the mimetic device by which Plato ambigu-
deconstructionist treatments of the political (namely,
ously attempts to justify the exclusion of women from
conceptions of the ʻunavowableʼ or ʻinoperativeʼ com-
philosophy. Demeterʼs refusal to generate life becomes
munity in Blanchot and Nancy), for their rejection of
the inspiration for an understanding of motherhood
the very idea of a political ʻprojectʼ, and their con-
as choice and act rather than natural function, an
sequent ʻgloomy nihilismʼ. Deconstructive talk of ʻthe
understanding in which the phenomenon of chosen
otherʼ and ʻthe marginsʼ is rendered vacuous unless
abortion is invoked to illustrate the power of ʻmaternal
supplemented by some sort of analysis of the workings
subjectivityʼ to act outside of patriarchal control.
of capitalist imperialism. At the same time, Marxism
Of course there is much to take issue with in
cannot begin to confront deconstructive themes, or
Cavareroʼs thought. Recurrent references to the
ʻthe possibility of justiceʼ, without shedding its more
ʻGreat Motherʼ and the unexplained assumption of
crudely positivistic aspects. A concern for the other
the ʻfeminine symbolic orderʼ, for example, will
is hard to ground in classical historical material-
understandably worry some readers. It would be easy
ism. It needs something more: Martin seeks ʻa praxis
to say of Cavareroʼs work, as is sometimes said of
that strives toward the good within the open-ended

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 51


structure of the infiniteʼ (p. 42) – and suggests that it stated aim (in the back-cover blurb) is ʻto make sense
lies in an interweaving of Marxist and deconstructive of the politics of deconstruction for those outside the
concerns. academyʼ. Iʼm not sure that Martin succeeds in this,
Part 2 explores the trajectory of the humanist ideal but his book is a worthy attempt.
from Descartes, via Kant, down to Habermas and
Gideon Calder
Rorty. For Martin the promise of humanism has been
almost entirely hidden by its practice. There is a
tension between Cartesian, ʻcalculatingʼ, positivistic
humanists (for example, Hobbes, Mill and present-
day utilitarians) and those, like Kant and Derrida,
Anxious times
for whom the key aspiration is the concern for the Ulrich Beck, Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk,
other. (Marx, incidentally, moves between these two translated by Amos Weisz, Polity Press, Cambridge,
strands.) Unsurprisingly, Martin has strong objections 1995. 216 pp., £39.50 hb., £12.95 pb., 0 7456 07632
to Habermasʼs depiction of Derrida as a ʻYoung Con- hb., 0 7456 13772 pb.
servativeʼ, and suggests that Habermasʼs own empha-
sis on communication as the vehicle of emancipation Ulrich Beck, Ecological Enlightenment: Essays on
is both internally problematic and reductively Euro- the Politics of the Risk Society, translated by Mark
centric: not the universalism he might think. Rorty, A. Ritter, Humanities Press International, Atlantic
too, comes in for extended criticism. Martin finds Highlands NJ, 1995. v + 159 pp., £29.95 hb., £12.95
that, for all his freewheeling anti-foundationalism and pb., 0 391 03831 1 hb., 0 391 03832 X pb.
prioritization of imagination and poetry over social
Although translated from different original German
theory, Rorty deals in a domineering and chauvinis-
titles, both English volumes contain much identical
tic instrumental rationality which seeks to assimilate
material. The former is longer and contains a greater
other cultures into that of the contemporary bourgeois
amount of qualification and elaboration. Each appears
West, without any self-questioning of the violence
to have been written in an attempt to address at least
that this involves.
some of the diverse critical reactions prompted by
Finally, Martin looks at Derridaʼs treatment of the
Beckʼs Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity (1992;
language of humanism in The Other Heading. For
reviewed by Caroline New, RP 66, Spring 1994). It
Derrida, as for Kant, thinking is condemned to strug-
is frustrating that they read very much as collections
gle with metaphysics, and they are equally committed
of essays rather than as sustained arguments. The
to pursuing ʻthe infinite task set by the thinking of
reader has to work hard to reconstruct the underlying
justiceʼ, which ʻwill provide the kind of totalizing
thread of Beckʼs argument, and is often forced to
ideal that is both necessary to and resistant to closureʼ
ask how each isolated skirmish fits into some overall
(p. 129). Martin rejects Alex Callinicosʼs ʻorthodox
framework of analysis. Criticism has come at him from
Marxistʼ challenge to Derrida for presuming that he
many directions, and he appears overly concerned to
takes no concrete political positions and is unaware of
address all his detractors at once. Nevertheless, it is
the claims of materiality. In fact, Derrida poses ques-
possible to recognize three major sources of underlying
tions about the nature of the humanist project which
controversy which may help to structure a reading of
point not in the direction of political detachment but,
his latest work.
on the contrary, towards a politically indispensable
Is our heightened sense of insecurity in ʻrisk
rethinking of what he calls the ʻidea of Europeʼ and
societyʼ the result of a greater consciousness of self-
thus the idea of humanism itself.
generated ecological risk? Or, contrariwise, is our
Martin pursues his arguments with great passion
sense of heightened ecological risk the result of greater
and inventiveness. His marshalling of Derridaʼs texts social insecurity (as Mary Douglas suggests in her
is impressive, if selective, and his quest to forge a link commentary on Beck in Risk and Blame, 1994)? Beck
between the ethical insights of deconstruction and a wants to go beyond the either/or; to accept that increas-
sort of Kantian-Marxist political commitment is both ing risk consciousness is bound up with a deficit of
shrewdly conducted and highly readable. Whether it trust in authoritative institutions and the break-up
works is another question. At one stage Habermas is of ʻtraditionalʼ forms of social solidarity, while still
accused of giving up on the goal of a participatory maintaining that society is increasingly confronted
socialist society. Has Derrida ever had such a goal? with the very real threat of self-annihilation.
The humanistic continuum between Kant and Derrida A second question might be posed as follows:
is vigorously asserted, but Martin never quite connects does nature still grow on trees, or is ʻnatureʼ the
it to a Marxist-deconstructionist political project. A social construction of our technological interventions

52 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


and/or our ideological representations? Many of Beckʼs us with a paradox. Acting in the name of unity – what
German reviewers felt he was too uncritical towards Michael Walzer might call ʻshared understandingʼ
claims about nature made by the environmental move- – pluralism exacerbates disunity.
ment. The naturalistic fallacy of a pure nature, ʻout In his collection of essays, William Connolly
thereʼ, underlies both romantic, deep-ecological theor- addresses the paradox in terms of the relationship
ies of ʻequilibriumʼ and instrumentalist-technocratic between fundamentalization and pluralization. Every
approaches to the ʻecological crisisʼ. Nevertheless, doctrine rests on some set of foundational assump-
Beckʼs rejection of a pure nature is tempered by a tions. Fundamentalism is a political strategy to protect
distrust of knee-jerk social constructivism: ʻEcology is those assumptions from interrogation. It defines its
guilty of forgetting about society, just as social science critics as possessing all those defects which ʻGod,
and social theory are predicated on the forgetting of nature, reason, nation or normalityʼ dictate must
ecologyʼ (Ecological Politics, p. 40). Beck argues be eradicated. There is a creative tension between
that it is through the growing contradictions within fundamentalization, which seeks to fortify and defend
technocratic modernity that the weaknesses of our boundaries, and pluralization, which challenges and
sense of ʻcoherenceʼ, both of natural and social order, enlarges them. Every challenge risks adopting the
increasingly impinge upon our senses. strategy of its counterpart and may become ʻfun-
Finally, how can ecological politics hope to damentalizedʼ itself. Connolly attempts to break
reappropriate the same rational resources of moder- this cycle, using the techniques of genealogy and
nity (science, technology and bureaucracy) which are deconstruction to expose the hidden contingency and
so central to the ecological crisis in the first place contestability of any set of ontological presuppositions
(a criticism of Beck made by Zygmunt Bauman in that claim absolute authority.
his book Postmodern Ethics)? Can ʻreflexivityʼ save Though indebted to the ʻpostmodernistsʼ, Connolly
modernity from itself? Beck seeks to demonstrate the departs from them in his opinion that a viable alter-
force of modern technocracyʼs own contradictions in native is available. The contestability of all founda-
undermining its rationality claims. The nuclear indus- tional claims – he calls them ʻontopoliticalʼ rather
tryʼs own worst enemy is itself, and not the marginal than ʻontologicalʼ, to avoid the implied singular logic
protesters at the gate. Reflexivity emerges from within. of the latter – opens a space of ambivalence in which
Beckʼs revolution without a subject, ʻwhich the prevail- political action may occur. Here an ʻethic of critical
ing conditions have instigated against themselves with responsivenessʼ and an air of ʻagonistic respectʼ may
the objectified power of the industrial momentumʼ, be cultivated. Such an ethos may be said to obtain
seems to suggest that a deterministic technological when an individual or group is aware of both the con-
dynamic may undermine itself and set us free. tingent nature of his/her/its identity and of the exclu-
These three issues help mark out the territory ʻat sions thereby imposed. This enables the individual
stakeʼ in the current debate over ʻriskʼ and ʻmodernityʼ. or group to respond to difference not with hostility,
No doubt they will remain hotly contested; not simply but with respect for that which allows his/her/its own
because of disagreements with what Beck writes, but identity to be consolidated. Such responsiveness is
over interpretations of what he means. anticipatory, critical and self-revisionary. It responds
to pluralization before the constituency in question is
consolidated into a positive identity. It asks whether
Matthew David and Iain Wilkinson this emergent constituency will attempt to impose
its identity as predominant and punish those who
transgress it. According to Connolly, the task of ethics
is to disallow any single moral code to dominate the
field. It is self-revisionary in that those responding to

Radical democracy pluralizing movements must revise their own identities


to allow room for new ones.
William E. Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization, At a time when the foundations of the ʻmodernityʼ of
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1995. Hegel and Marx are collapsing under their own weight,
243 pp., $49.95 hb., $19.95 pb., 0 8166 2668 5 hb., 0 Connollyʼs ʻpost-Nietzscheanʼ stance, prioritizing the
8166 2669 3 pb. richness of life over identity, is most compelling. At
a time when we are told that democracy has won,
The Cold War is over and democracy, we are told, has Connolly urges us to consider what exactly democracy
won; the end of history has arrived and all that remains is and what it might mean to live democratically.
is to drag the few remaining holdouts into the light of
reason. Yet the ʻvictoryʼ of pluralist democracy has left Chris Erickson

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 53


NEWS

Friendly fire
The hoaxing of Social Text

W
hen the editorial committee of the US journal Social Text chose ʻScience Warsʼ
as the title for last yearʼs special double issue (nos 46–47, Spring/Summer
1996), they could hardly have guessed how apt it would prove to be – not as
a description of its contents, but of the furore it would provoke. For with this issue of
Social Text, a new front was opened up in the ʻculture warsʼ which rage in the USA over
the disputed terrain where academic discourse meets mainstream politics in the distorting
mirror of the media: a complex and treacherous battlegound of ʻscienceʼ, where political
allies can be swiftly transformed into ideological foes in a hail of friendly fire.
The spark was the revelation that Social Text had been subjected to a carefully
managed hoax. Several months previously, Alan Sokal, a professor of physics at New
York University, had submitted an article, ʻTransgressing the Boundaries: Toward a
Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravityʼ, claiming to offer support from
recent physics for various ʻpostmodernʼ epistemological positions. After some hesitation,
Social Text decided to carry it in their special issue on science. However, the day after
it appeared, another article by Sokal was published in the bimonthly Lingua Franca, in
which he exposed his own Social Text piece as a ʻparodyʼ of cultural studies of science,
intended to unmask its ʻshoddy scholarshipʼ.
His method, Sokal revealed, was to structure the article around ʻthe silliest quotes
about mathematics and physicsʼ from ʻthe most prominent academicsʼ, ʻinventing an argu-
ment praising them and linking them together.ʼ All of which, he claimed, was ʻvery easyʼ,
since he ʻwasnʼt obliged to respect any standards of evidence and logicʼ – although it will
have taken considerable industry, since the text is liberally referenced, being accompanied
by over twenty-one pages of notes and bibliography. Furthermore, Sokal argued, he had
perpetrated his hoax on behalf of the Left: specifically, that section of the Left increas-
ingly fed up with the ʻtrendyʼ obscurantism and wrong-headedness of a postmodern
cultural studies which, it believes, is undermining the prospect for ʻprogressive social
critiqueʼ by insisting upon the ʻsocial constructionʼ of reality. Nowhere are its idiocies
more apparent, so the argument runs, than in the ʻculturalʼ treatment of physical theory.
We were thus presented with a set-piece confrontation between a new, culturally-based
academic Left and its scientifically-oriented predecessor, in which the latter, apparently,
worsts the former by publicly revealing the illusory character of its clothing (intellectual
standards), and gains a rare opportunity to show off its own sense of humour into the
bargain.
The media had a field-day. The story made the cover of The New York Times (18/5/96);
it was picked up in Britain by The Observer (19/5/96); it became a subject of debate on
National Public Radio; and follow-up articles and exchanges appeared in everything from
Newsweek (3/6/96), the THES (7 & 21/6/96) and The Village Voice (21/6/96) to a host
of smaller US Left periodicals such as Tikkun and In These Times. Letters columns were
clogged with competing voices, with Sokal comically complaining about the number of
Stanley Fishʼs column-inches in the NYT (38) and refusing to continue playing there when
his own 12-incher was cut down to ʻ7.3ʼ by the lettersʼ editor (7.3!). Sokal chose instead
to post his reply on the Internet (with commentary on his threatened inches), although
how many inches it can be said to have occupied there is anyoneʼs guess. Sokal was not
alone in making use of the Internet, though, and its communities of interest have played a

54 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)


significant role in framing and sustaining the affair. But what, exactly, is the affair about?
And what does it actually show?

Misplaced solidarity
For Sokal and his supporters, there is little doubt (they have few doubts): it demonstrates
the bogus intellectual credentials of ʻpostmodernʼ cultural studies and reaffirms the
need for the Left to turn away from ʻwishful thinking, superstition and demagogueryʼ,
to reclaim its Enlightenment roots in the ʻscientific worldviewʼ (Sokal, talk at the NYU
Forum, 30/10/96). For the editors of Social Text, matters are predictably more complex.
Clearly, they regret the publication of Sokalʼs essay and acknowledge it to have been an
error of editorial judgement. But, they argue, it was a mistake generated by a misplaced
sense of cultural-political solidarity, rather than any particular intellectual affinity with the
offending piece –as its comparison with any of the sixteen other articles in the ʻScience
Warsʼ issue (by the likes of Steve Fuller, Sandra Harding, Ruth Hubbard, Joel Kovel,
Emily Martin, Les Levidow and Hilary Rose) shows.
Both stylistically and in tone, Sokalʼs essay stands out as an anomaly, but in Andrew
Rossʼs words: ʻthe editors considered that it might be of interest to readers as a “docu-
ment” of that time-honoured tradition in which modern physicists have discovered har-
monic resonances with their own reasoning in the field of philosophy and metaphysics.ʼ
And in its own perverse way, it undoubtedly is. According to Robbins (the other main
editor of the journal, besides Ross): ʻSocial Text was hoaxed not because it liked Sokalʼs
jargon-filled references to postmodern authorities – in fact we asked him to cut them out
– but because we thought he was a progressive scientist, a physicist who was willing to be
publicly critical of scientific orthodoxies.ʼ
The mistake was thus to allow the lure of an ally within the scientific establishment
to dictate judgment about the piece; to allow political convenience to suspend intellectual
judgment. In this respect, for some, it was a representative error, whatever oneʼs concep-
tion of physics, and however much one may disagree with Sokalʼs views about science:
representative of an overly strategic approach to intellectual matters, characteristic of that
section of the cultural Left to which Social Text, broadly speaking, belongs. (Although it
should be noted that it also represents a certain cultural Marxism, which is one reason it
fell for the hoax in the first place. It takes science seriously; seriously enough to be scepti-
cal of its conventional self-understanding.) But what of the politics of the hoax itself?

Media Wars
One of the most salient aspects of the affair has been Sokalʼs recourse to the mainstream
media to conduct an ideological campaign against another section of the Left. Sokal has
used the media skilfully, both to register his hoax and to
generalise its point into a full-scale attack on ʻcultural studies
of scienceʼ and ʻpostmodern cultural studiesʼ (which he tends to
treat as equivalents). And for many on the Left, his hoax was
a welcome public counter to the attention-grabbing ʻrelativismʼ
of much recent cultural theory. Yet Sokal has also provided
the press with an ideal occasion to prosecute two of its favour-
ite pastimes – disparaging intellectualism, of any kind, and
travestying the Left – while bolstering the sagging image of
the ʻscientistʼ as a figure of authority and a man of reason and
good sense. (Relishing the ʻimpenetrable hodge-podge of jargon
[and] buzzwordsʼ in Sokalʼs hoax essay, the New York Times
(18/5/96) selected ʻhegemonyʼ and ʻepistemologicalʼ for especial
derision ... postmodern nonsense indeed!)
This was Sokalʼs major media card: his status as an ʻexpertʼ
in modern physics legitimated his views about the philosophy
of science, and thereby about the cultural study of science,

Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997) 55


from whence it was but one small step to cultural studies as a whole. That these views
are simplistic, at best, and never short of commensensical was an added bonus. Stanley
Fish (Professor of English and Law at Duke University and executive editor of its Press,
which publishes Social Text) was wheeled in by the NYT to provide an alternative account
of ʻsocial constructionʼ, but nobody in the press thought to ask the likes of Hilary Putnam
what he thought about Sokalʼs bracingly down-to-earth conception of ʻrealityʼ, or the
confidence with which he distinguishes ʻtruthʼ from ʻclaims of truthʼ, and ʻknowledgeʼ from
ʻpretensions to knowledgeʼ. Nor was anybody interested in the decidedly non-commonsensi-
cal character of Sokalʼs own scientific work, as spelled out in such papers as ʻNew Lower
Bounds on the Self-Avoiding-Walk Connective Constantʼ.
Philosophy has been notable by its absence, which is just as well for Sokal, since as
Linda Martín Alcoff has pointed out, his robust views would be rejected by nearly all con-
temporary philosophers of science - irrespective of their politics. Yet, weirdly, philosophy
is precisely what Sokal now claims his hoax was all about. ʻSocial Text is not my enemy,
nor is it my main intellectual targetʼ, he insisted at the recent Forum at NYU. In fact, ʻthis
affair is in my view not primarily about science ... What I believe this debate is principally
about ... is the nature of truth, reason and objectivityʼ. But this is not what it has been
about for the media. Nor is it what it was originally about for Sokal, when he started it all
off by feeding the press yet another version of one of its most relentlessly promulgated nar-
ratives: the story of a decline in a ʻstandardsʼ. It was about knocking the cultural Left, and
if that meant reinforcing conservative dogmas about ʻdeclining standardsʼ, the ʻemptinessʼ
of fashion and the ʻobscurantismʼ of cultural minorities, so be it.
There has always been a section of the radical Left which is more comfortable in the
company of Burkeans than sexual libertarians. And it is here, perhaps, rather than in the
philosophical disputes about science (which have been going on since the 1960s), that the
heart of the matter lies: in a heightening of intellectual antagonisms between generations of
the Left. It is an aspect of the affair that has been most prominent in the parade of opin-
ions on the Internet.
Fantasies of ‘pomos’
One of the functions of the Internet has been to expose to immediate public scrutiny
exchanges that would previously have taken place in private, over a longer period of time.
One of the dangers of this exposure is that intemperate and hastily conceived thoughts
can readily take on the character of ʻpositionsʼ in highly charged debates. One of the
advantages, however, is that the motivations underlying different views are more legible
than usual. So it is that the ad hominem attacks on Stanley Aronowitz and Andrew Ross
– against which Sokal himself has recently protested – have much to tell us about the
anxieties, fantasies and displacements sustaining what is an increasingly harmful divide
between an older ʻscientificallyʼ-oriented and a younger ʻculturallyʼ-oriented Left.
It is tempting (and no doubt, to some, reassuring) to conceive of the divide as structured
by differing attitudes to Marxism. But this is too simple. Not just because the intellectual
culture of Marxism is pervasive, if uneven, on both sides, but because antipathy to the cul-
tural Left tends to be focused on a particular composite image: ʻpomosʼ (postmodernists),
who have alledgedly taken over the academy, dismissing material interests and laying waste
to intellectual standards in their dogged pursuit of identity politics, fashionable clothing
and academic careers. In the exchanges provoked by Sokalʼs hoax, ʻpomosʼ are the ideal
imaginary others of the ʻtrue Marxistsʼ (and vice versa), and they are modeled on the
mediaʼs fantasy projection of Andrew Ross. (Clothing places a key metaphorical role in
these invectives.)
One might, I think, be forgiven for finding this spectacle both intellectually irritat-
ing and politically depressing: irritating, because of the lowering of the level of debate that
it involves; depressing, because it is so clearly the product of a political defeat, from which
it distracts attention. At a time when the Left needs all the solidarity it can muster just to
survive, there has to be a better way for it to conduct its debates than this.
Peter Osborne

56 Radical Philosophy 81 (Jan/Feb 1997)

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi