Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 11

Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol.

38 (4)

Reflection and Metacognition in education. Also, in his studies on a reform of


mathematics education on late high school and
Mathematics Education – undergraduate level in the USA, Dubinsky
Tools for the Improvement of (1991a, b) emphasises the usefulness of reflec-
Teaching Quality tion for an understanding of mathematics. By
saying
Christa Kaune, University of Osnabrück „ … that we somehow move into another dimen-
(Germany) sion when we reflect on what we have done.“
Kilpatrick (1986, p. 9) indicates that reflection is
Abstract: On the basis of a category system that done from a superordinate point of view and that
classifies metacognitive activities, the first part activities on the object level are viewed from a
of this paper shows to what extent reflection can meta-perspective.
be understood as one of several metacognitive
Since the 1970s, the term “metacognition” has
activities. It is then demonstrated that it proved
been established in cognitive psychology for this
to be useful to consider different nuances of re-
kind of cognitive activities (cp. Boekaerts 1996).
flection.
The prefix “meta” suggests that internal proc-
Illustrated by examples taken from math classes
esses are central to this concept.
on grammar school level, the second part of the
essay shows what assignments look like that Wang, Haertel & Walberg (1993, p. 272f) em-
cause pupils to reflect, and how pupils face up to phasise the relevance of metacognition for learn-
the demands to reflect on different matters in ing achievements in general. In their meta-
mathematics education. analysis of empirical studies on the success of
school learning, they observe that metacognition
ZDM-Classification: D43, E44, E53, H33 is in an excellent rank regarding the influence on
learning achievements. Schoenfeld (1992) and
De Corte (1995) report on the importance of
1. Reflection, understood as a metacog- metacognitive activities to improve mathemati-
nitive activity cal thinking and learning processes.
The demand to cover central ideas concerning Konrad (2005, p. 23) and Sjuts (1999a, p. 40-44)
mathematics education in a challenging and differentiate the terms “cognition” and “meta-
thorough way, and to stimulate pupils’ thinking cognition” from one another. However, Flawell
processes about mathematical matters, has been (1979) shows on the one hand that “reflection”
present in math didactics literature throughout is not used consistently in everyday speech, and
the last two decades. Thereby, the term “reflec- on the other hand his examples also indicate that
tion” is frequently used. Kilpatrick (1986, p. 8) both concepts are not clearly differentiable in
describes how the connotation of this term, everyday situations.
originally used to depict physical and geometric
Sjuts (1999b) characterised different metacogni-
phenomena, changed and now serves as a meta-
tive activities and documented their relevance to
phor for a variety of cognitive processes.
explain pupils’ achievements. By means of tran-
Sjuts (1999a, p. 40) specifies “reflection” as script passages and pupils’ solutions, the mecha-
“comparing and scrutinising cogitation, think- nism of action will be demonstrated, with a par-
ing, and examination, directed to the matter at ticular focus on the question, which metacogni-
hand, which is characterised through differentia- tive activities bear on which cognitive processes.
tion, detachment, and deepening.” One can find
other descriptions like “to engage in soul-
searching”, “to pass in revue”, as well as “to re- 2. Category system to classify metacogni-
late things”. Thus, “reflection” is used to de- tive activities
scribe a particular kind of high-level cognitive
thinking process. The main lecture of Kilpatrick 2.1. Formation of a category system
at ICME5 (Kilpatrick 1986) is considered trend-
From 2001 to 2004 a project supported by the
setting in the international discussion about
“Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft” (German
making reflection a central part of mathematics
Research Foundation), subtitled “Analysis of
350
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

educational situations practicing reflection and matical logic): computability theory, formal
metacognition in secondary school mathematics logic, axiomatic set theory.
education” was conducted at the “Institut für
kognitive Mathematik” (IKM) (Institute for
Cognitive Mathematics) of the University of Os- 2.2. Application of the category system to the
nabrück. The title already indicates the connec- analysis of scenes of lessons
tion between metacognition and reflection. A scene of a lesson on “equation-solving” is
1
In the present project , the construct “metacogni- chosen to illustrate to what extend the processes
tion” was decomposed under mathematics didac- “reflection” and “metacognition” interact. It also
tical aspects. Single activities were identified shows which criteria are suitable to differentiate
and used to build an extensive category system reflection from other metacognitive activities.
for metacognitive activities that were observed Transcripts and pupils’ solutions that are ana-
in teacher-pupil interactions in mathematics lysed in the following are part of the mathemat-
education. This system was then applied to some ics educational databank MUMAS3.
transcript passages. The analysis emanated from
algebra lessons. In the process of the category Initial setting of the scene4:
formation, however, it became apparent that the The pupil Michaela stands in front of the black-
observed and identified activities are also de- board which contains the equation
0, 6 ⋅ ( x − 5) − 2 ⋅ (11 − 2 x ) = 1 + x that is sup-
scribable in a more general way. Consequently,
the category system can more generally be ap- 3
plied so that it can now subsume metamathe- posed to be solved. Michaela moderates the
matical activities as well (cp. Cohors-Fresenborg procedure; she calls up pupils, who are allowed
& Kaune 2005a). to dictate one term rewriting only and she writes
This at first astonishing connection between as they dictate. It is part of the classroom-culture
metamathematics and metacognition can there- that the pupil standing at the blackboard is not
fore be explained. In the context of an education supposed to control the inputs given by the class
according to the “Osnabrücker Curriculum” concerning their completeness and correctness.
(Curriculum of Osnabrueck, Cohors-Fresenborg, Also, he or she is not allowed to change the con-
2001), an incentive could be to transform cogni- tents of what is dictated.
tion, through metamathematical approaches, into
Transcript5:
a metacognition on mathematical prodedures2.
2
The importance of metacognition for the com- Rainer: Yeah, well, first I’d turn the 0, 6 into 3
,
2
prehension of mathematics is revealed by an- because then it is a little more consistent.
other observation: In mathematical science, the [Michaela draws an equivalence sign and writes the
2
thinking about the nature of mathematical con- 4 fraction 3 below the 0, 6 . She then turns to
ceptions and the typical procedures that are used Rainer.]
when practising mathematics (calculating, prov- 6 Michaela: It’s not done yet, is it?
ing, abstracting, reifying) lead to the classical Rainer: And now, of course, write down the rest
main components of metamathematics (mathe- 8 again. And, well, you could of course directly
apply the distributive law, too, hum, write it in
10 front, then you’d have to put two hum thirds
1
Supported by the German Research Foundation times x hum minus two-thirds times five hum
12 minus two-thirds times eleven minus two-thirds
under reference Co 96/5-1. In German-speaking times two x equals one plus x.
countries, this project is the first and so far only pro-
14 [Michaela writes down what Rainer dictates. Noisy
ject that intensely investigates the role of metacog-
agitation in class. Clearly visible in the video:
nition in mathematics education. All the examples 16 Moni turns to her neighbour Elfi, talks to her,
mentioned in the present study were analysed within
this project. 3
2
Examples are the scene of the lesson on the barrel MUMAS: MUltimedia-based Mathematics didac-
rule at the end of this paper as well as the episodes tical Analysis System, presented for example in
“Proving is nothing else but calculating” (Cohors- Kaune (2005).
Fresenborg & Kaune 2005b) and “Do we need a 4th 4
MUMAS-scene 254_01
5
binomial formula?” in Kaune (2001). Only the coloured text passages of this transcript are
analysed in this paper.
351
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

and shows up at the same time.] Interpretation:


18 An analysis of the preceding lines uncovers dif-
ferent discursive6 and metacognitive activities of
the participants:
Michaela: Moni! Moni not only criticises a classmate’s mistake
20 Moni: I think, (...) in the second row it doesn’t work “in the second row it doesn’t work out com-
out completely, namely at the second time two- pletely” (line 20f), but she demonstrates her
22 thirds, the algebraic sign shows up for the sec- awareness of mathematical methods: she ob-
ond time in front of the number and in front of served an incorrect application of the distribu-
24 the two-thirds there’s a negative sign, hum, after
the first parenthesis, thus, negative two-thirds
tive law (line 29). This is a specification of
26 and if you then… monitoring, one category of the category system
[While Moni speaks, Michaela already changes the “Metacognitive activities at calculating and
28 minus in front of the term 2 ⋅ 2 x into a plus.]
proving” (Cohors-Fresenborg & Kaune 2005a),
3
that is used to classify metacognitive activities in
... apply it with the distributive law and then you mathematics education at the IKM. As a reflect-
30
should, it should be: well, − 23 ⋅ 11 and then, and ing judgement and evaluation of the procedure,
32 then, hum, Rainer did, did dictate "plus" but her later utterance (line 36f) “…it works now”
then there would have to be a negative sign belongs to a second category, called reflection.
again in front of the two-thirds. Rainer’s positioning “I didn’t get it yet, the
34 Michaela: Yes, I just put it there. whole thing” (line 42f) falls in another subcate-
Moni: Yeah, but hold on a second. Oh, I see, gory of monitoring. The same holds for his way
36 Michaela already put it there. Yeah, it works, to address his wrong conceptions (lines 43-53)
now.
after the mistake had been discussed on the ob-
38 Rainer: So, did I make a mistake?
ject level. It is evident that he wonders by him-
T.: Rainer just asks if he made a mistake. Can we self to what extend concrete mistakes can be
40 look for that on the right hand side and check it
again on the blackboard? explained as results of generally wrong concep-
42 Rainer: I didn’t get it yet, the whole thing. tions. It can be assumed that an interplay in the
following sense is taking place: Since Rainer
addresses his wrong conceptions, Sven, in his
The mistake is clarified on the object level. In
explanation, feels obliged to refer to his concep-
particular, the pupils explain the substitution of
tions and the related metacognitive procedures.
the variables when applying the distributive law.
Michaela’s activity has to be evaluated differ-
Rainer: Well, now, I’ve made that mistake quite of- ently: During the calculation, she monitors her
44 ten. I overlooked that minus, after the, hum, af- classmates’ contributions “It’s not done yet, is
ter the x − 5 -parenthesis, because, hum, I just it?” (line 6). She already corrects the mistake
46 had the idea in my head that I always, well, at before Moni finishes her sentence (line 27f).
the first term in front of the equals sign, hum, I This accompanying monitoring, the ongoing
48 divided it into two parts, 0, 6 ⋅ ( x − 5) is the first control of what is written or said, and its correc-
50 part and the other part was 2 ⋅ (11 − 2 x ) . And in tion if needed, falls in another subcategory of
3
between hum I have the minus, which means monitoring.
52 that I somehow always have to subtract the se- Rainer’s utterance (line 1) comprises a com-
cond part from the first. That’s how it looked li- pletely different metacognitive activity: he ex-
ke in my head. And that was the mistake.
presses in advance, before dictating a term re-
Sven: Well, hum, I wanted to add something to what
writing, a next step in the calculation: “first I’d”.
54 Rainer just said, that he makes mistakes with
things like that, well, hum, when I do these as- He also explains this step: “because then it is a
56 signments at home or so, and they are hum a lit- little more consistent”. Thereby, he refers to a
tle longer and contain things like this minus, consistent notation of the numbers. The action of
58 then I underline those parts most of the time. expressing the next step of a calculation or a
Well, hum, that way I see that there is a negative
60 sign in front and that you have to take it into ac-
strategy in advance, as observed here in the local
count later, when you apply the distributive law.
62 Yeah, this way it works pretty well, if you keep 6
it in mind all the time. A deeper analysis of transcripts of this lesson under
the perspectives “discursive classroom-culture” and
“cognitive structures of pupils” can be found in Co-
hors-Fresenborg & Kaune (2003).
352
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

justification that produces an advantage in the the teacher was additionally underlined for bet-
calculation, falls in the category of planning. ter accentuation. See Cohors-Fresenborg &
The teacher’s impulse to organise a controlling – Kaune (2005a) for information concerning the
“check it again on the blackboard” (line 40f) – is procedure of constructing the category system
associated with the same category, but a differ- and its exemplary application on further lessons.
ent subcategory.
The pupils’ metacognitive activities documented
In his contribution to the discussion, Sven shows
in the transcript reflect the results of measures
discursive qualities as well as metacognitive ac-
persistently taken in the special mathematics
tivities that are evaluated differently: In lines 55-
education during one school year. The probabil-
57, he explains to his classmates how he organ-
ity of students acting the way we observed in the
ises his controlling at home. In line 57f he re-
transcript was raised by theses measures.
ports on a deliberately chosen display format, a
deliberate marking of certain parts of the equa- One of these measures is displayed in the modi-
tion “I underline those parts most of the time”. fied role of the teacher: proposals to improve
Finally, he evaluates his procedure “this way it mathematics education (Bundesministerium für
works pretty well”. This involves the reflection Bildung und Forschung [German Federal Minis-
on a planned measure of monitoring. try of education and research], 2001, p. 49) em-
phasize that math teachers should ideally take
The three activities planning, monitoring, and
the role of a mediator that does not “feed” in-
reflection are main categories – containing sev-
formation to the pupils, but that offers opportu-
eral subcategories each – of a larger category
nities to develop and exchange their own
system that includes metacognitive activities of
thoughts. As a mediator, the teacher places pu-
learners and teachers.
pils’ ideas into the context of the lesson, relates
At first glance, the activities “planning”, “moni- the uttered thoughts to one another, and supports
toring” and “reflection” are clearly differenti- pupils in the formulation and realization of
ated. Planning is targeted at the future, monitor- ideas. While these goals are expressed as goals
ing is „online“ in the process of a mental activ- for the behaviour of the teacher, individual pu-
ity, reflection deals with an activity with hind- pils of this class already express some of those
sight, after it has been completed. Obviously, the behavioural patterns and activities.
reference to time serves as a differentiator for
these metacognitive activities. However, on
closer examination, planning or monitoring 3. Further occasions for reflection
processes can also be subject to analysis, moni-
Since working on assignments is by far the most
toring processes can be planned, maybe planned
important activity of pupils in math lessons, it is
measures can also be designated for reflection.
obvious and often postulated by didacts to use
Even a monitoring of reflection and planning
the assignments as a starting point to improve
processes is thinkable. This analysis shows that
the quality of instructions.
the activities “planning”, “monitoring”, “reflec-
tion” need to be differentiated relative to each Pupils will only change their focus of attention in class
if it becomes less important for written tests to exclu-
other. Also, the differentiation by time that was sively learn the formulas written on the blackboard. In
mentioned is not an absolute one, but merely order to achieve comprehending learning, a reorienta-
relative. This can be well observed in the analy- tion of education needs to be expressed simultane-
sis of lines 55-63. ously in tests by a rebalancing of “calculating-
assignments” and “thinking-assignments”. (Bundes-
We are here dealing with a phenomenon that is ministerium für Bildung und Forschung [German Fed-
not untypical in mathematics: Processes on one eral Ministry of education and research] 2001, p. 90)
level can become the objects of a superordinate So, how do these special assignment-types
level. In mathematics, we are used to the idea stimulating metacognitive activities and espe-
that functions themselves, understood as objects, cially reflection look like?
can become the argument of other functions (for
example when differentiating or integrating). 3.1. Reflection on calculation steps and on the
All parts of the preceding transcript that are as- adequacy of a method used
sociated with one of the categories are marked In 1997, in the recommendations concerning
with different colours. A classifying statement of curriculum design and further education of
353
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

teachers, the MNU7 demanded the “presentation Analysis of the problem


and reflection of different ways to find solu- Silke’s comments in problem part ‚a’ reveal pu-
tions” for mathematics education on non- pils’ attitudes which can be described as the
grammar secondary-school level8. This includes careless manipulation of terms. They do not
a special kind of cognitive thinking process consider any underlying basic rules. They adjust
while working on an own solution, as well as a parts of the term in a way that favours further
comparison of different ways to come to a solu- processing.
tion. Sjuts (1999b) used the example of equa-
A mixture of correct and incorrect calculations,
tion-solving-assignments to describe a method
inadequate attitudes as well as misconceptions
that supports monitoring as well as reflection:
of pupils is presented in terms of a fictive dia-
While dissolving an equation, pupils explain
logue. In the problem, the pupils discuss the
their procedure in a second column. For each
non-observance of the domain of the root func-
step, they write down the abbreviations for the
tion and the meaning of term-equalities. In order
theorem, definition, or axiom. This is a comment
not to make the problem obvious at first glance,
on a meta-level.
a difference was inserted in the root function
The following example9 is taken from a written while constructing the term. The inner term does
test of a class that was instructed according to describe the name of a number; however, it does
the “Osnabrücker Curriculum” (curriculum of not belong to the domain of the outer root func-
Osnabrück) (Cohors-Fresenborg 2001) in the tion.
third year. It demonstrates the way in which pu-
This problem belongs to the type „Take up a
pils, after having simplified algebraic root-terms,
position!“ The design principles and intended
are stimulated to account for the methods they
effects of such problems are described in Kaune
used. Pupils dispose of mathematical objects
(2001, p. 44). This type of problem encourages
with the help of names. But the question, if the
pupils to exercise the metacognitive activity
used symbols are truly names for existing ob-
“Reflection” that Kilpatrick (1986, p. 8) de-
jects or just meaningless words is not answered
scribes as follows:
until some calculation steps are done.
Nonetheless, the image of reflecting on an idea, turn-
ing it over in one’s mind, is a powerful device for
Problem: thinking about thinking, and for thinking about one’s
Four pupils are discussing the solution of the follow- own thought.
ing problem:
Linguistically and logically complex, Silke’s
Simplify the following term if possible:
comments decompose into different parts: If
18 − 4,5 ⋅ 18 + 4,5 . “This doesn’t work” is interpreted such that a
Silke: “First I thought, the result would not work. But now,
term rewriting is not possible, one can agree
with her first sentence. A separate calculation of
I know, it has to be − 2, 25 and that is − 1,5 .”
( 18 − 4,5)⋅ ( 18 + 4,5) results in − 2,25 . The
Eva: “That is not possible, because the solution is syntacti-
cally wrong.” number − 2,25 is correctly shown without
Michaela: “Not only the solution, but also the first line root. The design of Silke’s second sentence only
must be wrong.” permits to agree with the last term equality.
Ariane: “Every line is wrong. I think we should not even Part ‚b’ serves to focus the pupils to the problem
have started calculating … “ of sense-emptiness of certain formal written fig-
a) Which of Silke’s comments do you agree with? ures. The word choice of the fictive pupil Eva is
b) Why does Eva think that the solution is syntacti- intended to show that the pupils also know how
cally wrong? to differentiate between incorrect semantics and
c) Do you agree with Michaela? syntax, when working on the problem.
d) Please evaluate Ariane’s comment.
Problem parts ‚c’ and ‚d’ are meant to teach the
7
pupils to reflect more precisely about the signifi-
MNU: association of teachers for mathematics and cance of term rewriting. Also, they must exactly
natural sciences localize where the problem first occurs.
8
http://home.zugang.net/mnu-sachsen/sek1.htm,
[17.3.2006]
9
MUMAS-scene 54_01
354
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

Interpretation of a pupil’s solution suitable rule. Here she practices reflection as


Marion’s10 solution to ‚a’: described by Kilpatrick (1986) on page 8.
It is not surprising that, after having handled part
‚a’ of the task, she appropriately solves parts ‚b’
and ‚c’:
The first line and the one in between have to be incor-
rect, too, because we always concluded something
starting at the first line and there are equals signs and
every line is explained by a paragraph.

It is striking that she does not use the word


“name of a number“ anymore – as she did in
problem part a. Instead, she calls the written fig-
ure “line”. The equals signs explained by para-
graphs convey a feeling of correctness to her.
She is assured that she did not do any mistakes
in the single calculation steps.
It would have been desirable for her to legiti-
mate her calculation “subject to changes” in the
Marion’s answer to question a: beginning. She expresses in her comments to ‘b’
Silke’s first assumption is correct since − 2, 25 is not and ‘c’ that there is no true mathematical term in
the name of a number. There is no number that results any of her calculating lines. A clarification is not
in -2,25 when multiplied with itself. given until she comments part ‚d’:
You are not allowed to simply write the algebraic sign You are allowed to start calculating, because it cannot
in front of the square root symbol. be seen immediately that the term is syntactically
Marion’s term rewritings clearly show methodi- wrong. This is not possible until you finish calculat-
ing.
cal procedures which support the monitoring of
term rewritings. In class, it has been established
The availability of Computer Algebra Systems
to specify names above the equals signs to indi-
(CAS) can provide new occasions for a reflec-
cate the basic logical rule used for this calculat-
tion on the results of the used tool. This can be
ing step (e.g. ∗ is the name for a term replace-
seen in the following problem11 from an exami-
ment rule) or the proved theorems (SBF3 stands
nation in 11th grade. Pupils seem to reflect on an
for the third binomial formula, SWM for a theo-
output of a CAS, but really they reflect on their
rem that regulates the multiplication of numbers
understanding of recursive or inductive defini-
of a square root). As the concrete formulation of
tions.
the problem does not explicitly demand this pro-
cedure, it is evident that it has become a compo- Assignment:
nent of the pupil’s “cognitive operating system”. − ( n −1)
To define the sequence u1 with u1 (n) = 10
All of her term rewritings refer to the inner func-
tional term. They have been carried out accord- recursively, Marc enters the following lines into his
CAS:
ing to the rules, in case they were applicable.
Marion formulates a differentiated answer to
Silke’s statement: She agrees with the first part
and supports this by an explanation that indi-
cates that she knows the definition of a number
in root notation She interprets the appearance of
the term − 2, 25 as a careless use of the alge-
braic sign (“You are not allowed to simply ...“),
i.e. as a term rewriting that is not justified by a
The following error message is displayed as he wants
10 to draw the graph of the sequence:
Analyses of other pupils’ solutions of these parts of
problem can be found in Cohors-Fresenborg &
11
Kaune (2005b). MUMAS-scene 652_03
355
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

terms. It was supposed to test if an adequate


comprehension of the concept “explicit defini-
tion” was existent. The calculation of the func-
tion term could be assigned to the CAS.
However, if you read the definition recursively
and ask, for example, for the sequence member
u1 (3) , this can be calculated with the help of
the definition by going back to u1 (1) . This holds
After he deleted the error message, the following for all other odd arguments as well.
graph appears:
In order to “enforce” an examination of the
types of definition of u1 , the scale of the coordi-
nate system in the third display was not chosen
equidistant. Consequently, a pupil’s solution to
problem part ,c’ reveals, if the coordinates of a
point have simply been read – under the assump-
tion of standard settings of the display – or, if a
relationship between definition and graph could
be established.
a) Calculate u1(2) by means of both, the definition
given in the display and the explicit definition. Interpretation of a pupil’s solution
b) Explain why the CAS displays an error message. Vera’s work on problem part ‚a’ shows that she
c) Explain why the graph consists of one dot only. can both, explicitly and recursively calculate
State its coordinates. sequence members:

Starting Position and Analysis of the Problem


In this learning group, where every pupil was
familiar with the use of a CAS, the CAS was
used to “convey a well-balanced image of
mathematics and not only to practice to handle
mathematics.“ (Herget 1991, p. 147).
The first display shows a definition of a se-


quence in CAS-notation that corresponds to

n∈Ν
(u (n) = u (n − 2) ⋅ 10
1 1
−1
∧ u1 (1) = 1)
∧ n >1

The sequence only provides sequence members


for odd arguments. Thus, it only corresponds to She does not use the x as a name for u1 (0) , as
the explicitly defined sequence for a subset of can be seen in her solution to problem part ‚b’.
the domain. If you try to inductively determine Here, it rather has to be interpreted as something
further sequence members starting from u1 (1) , unknown:
The CAS probably displays an error message because
such as u1 (2) for example, it fails. This also be- you don’t know what u1(2 -2) is. This would actually be
comes clear through the error message “se- called u1(0), but before, only u1(1) was stated.”
quence setup”, as shown by the second display,
She can specify the coordinates of the point in
and through the graph of the sequence, which
( )
problem part ,c’ without mistake.
only contains the point P 11 in the third dis-
play. Problem part ,a’ focuses the pupils on that
problem in several steps: The determination of 3.2. Reflection on the relevance of a concept
u1 (2) on the basis of the explicit definition was in the mathematical system of concepts
not meant to check whether they could calculate Cohors-Fresenborg & Kaune (2005b) analyzed a
scene of a lesson that was based on a discussion
356
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

about the question „Is there a difference between but for those that formulated the problem as
proving and calculating?“ At first glance, it is Kind (1994, p. 62) puts it: “The plurality is a
hard to understand why this question is at all guarantor for an intensive reflection on formula-
asked, because obviously nobody associates tions and other possible solutions.” Only the fol-
“calculating” with the word “proving”. The lowing request during the lesson12, which was
analysis of the pupils’ discussion reveals a spe- added to the original setting of the problem,
cial point of view, whereby the pupils consider challenged to reflect on the nature of mathemati-
calculating as a progressive term rewriting based cal concepts:
on rules. From a cognitive point of view, they
have experienced algebraic proofs as a similar T: Part b of the problem asked: “Outline a deduction
2 of the „formula“ to calculate the rotational vol-
procedure. In the course of their reflection on ume.” We have reflected a lot on these mathe-
both concepts, the pupils discover themselves 4 matical concept systems (…), but we hardly
that the use of the word „calculating” also in- used the notion „formula”.
volves term rewritings without variables. On the 6 Could you try to explain the word „formula“
other hand, with the word “proving”, they asso- and to describe it with the concepts we used?
ciate the occurrence of variables in terms.
Every pupil on high school level has got a for-
Here and also in the following, possibilities of mulary. It contains, amongst other things, axi-
reflection in mathematics education and the oms, interpreted axiom systems, definitions and
conditions and possibilities for them to become theorems. However, the concept “formula” is
effective, are only taken into consideration on mostly not used in a reflected manner. The use
the basis of German mathematics education on of the word „formulary“ alone does not contrib-
grammar school level. It is specific for this kind ute to solve the problem that was raised. Gener-
of education that pupils gain an understanding of ally, formulas are (syntactic) written figures
the typically mathematical conception and preci- which can be deduced from a given formula cal-
sion process. This process is based on an axio- culus. In the given problem, the concept “for-
matic understanding of concepts with appropri- mula” is used in the sense of an equation that
ate definition and proof concepts. In addition, only permits numbers, variables and functional
the understanding of the processes by which signs. The case at hand gives a meaning to the
such specifications come about, the handling of concept “Volume of a rotational body during
usual techniques to use the concept of a function rotation around the argument axis“, i.e. the con-
and the well-founded handling of equation sys- cept is defined. The “binomial formulas”, how-
tems are supposed to be learnt by the pupils. ever, which are well-known to the pupils, are
The following scene of a lesson is taken from an considered mathematical theorems.
intensive math course with increased demands The concepts mentioned by the teacher in line 7
after the following problem had been worked on: („the concepts we used”) are obviously concepts
such as “theorem”, “definition”, “axiom“ or
How much fits into the barrel?
“fundamental term“.
a) Show that the volume is at any
rate smaller than 400,000 cm3. 8 Anne: Well, I would say, in this case you could
maybe use the concept „definition“ instead of
b) Outline a deduction of the 10 „formula“.
formula to calculate the We didn’t call this „theorem“, I think somebody
rotational volume 12 mentioned this before, but actually this is a defi-
nition, because we stipulated that this is the case
b
V = π ⋅ ∫ [ f ( x)] 2 dx
14 and that this cannot be proved now or (…) and
therefore I would say you can also … (...).
a 16 Else: Oh yes, this can be proved!
c) Compute the volume of the T: Please, let her finish her sentence. Yes, Kira?
barrel as exact as possible.
18 Kira: Yes, actually I would say this is a theorem
because it is a .... we had ...well .... It is not a
A group of didacts formulated this problem as 20 definition.
an example for a divergent problem format. It T: Jochen!
already prompted reflection in its developing
phase, however, not for the pupils working on it, 12
MUMAS-scene 012_02
357
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

22 Jochen: Yes, at least we derived it from other, hum, 58 that, that, I cannot deduce it any more in a dif-
areas, equations, hum, from integral calculus for ferent way, from other deviations.
24 example, and, hum, therefore you cannot really 60 Else: Not volume as such. But volume of a rota-
call it, I would say, not really call it definition, tional body. That’s what it’s about. It is no
26 as a definition …. 62 longer some arbitrary volume.
It could be said, yes with this equation it can be
28 said, yes, according to what we know, it can be Maret: Yes. But then it is more a definition of rota-
deduced from what we have had before, which 64 tional body than that of a volume, which means
30 means you can …. In any case, it turned out (...).
quite reasonably; the definition actually de- 66 Else: Yes, yes. And I, hum. If you have a definition,
32 scribes something new. And this is actually not then it is the case that you define this word – if
really something new, it has only been, yes, 68 you like, here it is ‘volume of a rotational body’,
34 found out from other areas, so to speak. you define it using other already defined con-
T: Else! 70 cepts and that, for example, would be the con-
cept “volume”.
36 Else: Well, I would anyhow say this is a definition in 72 You would use this concept, that is, one that has
so far as it is about a volume of a rotational hopefully been defined before. And you would
38 body, and we defined this with the help of, yes, 74 have to use it somehow (actually in that way).
other concepts or, yes, in this case it is the inte-
40 gral that helped to describe the volume of the ro-
tational body or, yes, we defined it. Maret presumably imagines a heuristic volume
42 The point is: The definition that now introduces that she describes pictorially by means of a Lego
such a new concept, with, and explains it with brick, which is simply there, and that she differ-
44 old concepts, which means with concepts al-
ready known. entiates clearly from the naming of things by
(16 seconds)
means of a definition. In her opinion, fundamen-
tal terms are simply there and cannot be ex-
At this stage, the teacher is content with the role plained by other concepts. In her reply, Else
of a moderator: she calls up single pupils with- clearly differentiates „Volume of a rotational
out giving own factual comments. Obviously, body“, a concept that needs to be defined (which
her intention is that the pupils develop the com- is possibly done with the formula), from the
prehension of the concept “formula” together. fundamental term “volume”. One can infer from
her comment that she agrees with Maret that
In Anne’s and Else’s opinion, a formula is a „volume“ cannot be explained more precisely,
definition, because it is a stipulation: „ ... we but that she considers the case “volume of a ro-
stipulated that this is the case“ (line 13). An un- tational body” differently. Maret’s answer to this
known concept is given a meaning by something shows that she does not differentiate between
already known (lines 42-45). In Jochen’s opin- „volume“ and „volume of a rotational body”, but
ion, however, the deduction of the formula from between “volume” (fundamental term) and “ro-
something known is a characteristic for the fact tational body” (concept to be defined). Even
that it is not a definition. though Else starts with twice a „yes”, she does
At this stage – after an interval of 20 seconds – not support Maret’s point of view, she only
Maret introduces a completely different train of agrees in parts. She talks about volume as a con-
thoughts by explaining her point of view on the cept („ ... one that has hopefully been defined
concept “volume” as a fundamental term. This before”, line 72 f). This contradicts Maret’s un-
gives rise to a spontaneous dialogue with Else derstanding of a fundamental term.
who feels challenged to defend her point of The statements clearly indicate that all pupils
view: that were involved in the discussion are awake
to the meaning of definition, theorem and fun-
46 Maret: But isn’t that, isn’t that a bit stupid, to simply
say that this is a definition, because a volume,
damental term. In their descriptions they do,
48 for me that is still something like a fundamental however, place emphasis on different things:
term which ..., which you cannot just, … it is Anne and Maret (lines 14 and 54f) stress the na-
50 like a Lego brick, it does exist and it is, I don’t ture of stipulations as regards definitions, Else
know.. and Jochen point out that something new is
52 It is certainly not a definition, because then
you’d stipulate – I’ll call this a rotational body added (lines 33 and 44). Both views are con-
54 now and I’ll explain it that way. formable. They disagree, however, concerning
Just as I say: this is a pencil case, it could also the question whether something new has been
56 be a banana, if I said: „This is a banana”. And described or deduced. The answer depends on
volume, that is the fundamental term, somehow,

358
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

what is new and what is not new. This will then richt. [Teaching quality: The role of discursiv-
be discussed in the second part of the lesson, ity for a „good“ mathematics education on
which is not further analyzed here. grammar school level.] In Beiträge zum
Mathematikunterricht 2003 (pp. 173-180).
Hildesheim: Franzbecker.
4. Relevance of a discursive teaching cul- Cohors-Fresenborg, E. & Kaune, C. (2005a).
ture Kategoriensystem für metakognitive Aktivitä-
ten bei schrittweise kontrolliertem Argumentie-
In the pupils’ contributions presented thus far, it
ren im Mathematikunterricht. [Category sys-
is striking that reflection is often associated with
tem for metacognitive activities in stepwisely
the capability to linguistically differentiate ex-
controlled arguing in mathematics education.]
actly between things that were said, written and
Arbeitsbericht Nr. 44. Osnabrück: Forschungs-
meant. In every day education, this is supported
institut für Mathematikdidaktik.
by a discursive teaching culture. It is vital to
Cohors-Fresenborg, E. & Kaune, C. (2005b).
form a concept system in which the difference
The Metaphor “Contracts to deal with Num-
between signs and their meanings, between
bers” as a Structuring Tool in Algebra. Pro-
names and variables, the description of general
ceedings of CERME 4.
regularities and special examples, are deliber-
http://cerme4.crm.es/Papers%20definitius/3/
ately put at the pupils’ disposal. The fact that
Cohors_Kaune.pdf
reflection is naturally appreciated forms the pre-
De Corte, E. (1995). Fostering Cognitive
condition for realizing and appreciating reflec-
Growth: A Perspective from Research on
tion and is indispensable for learners and teach-
Mathematics Learning and Instruction. Educa-
ers.
tional Psychologist, 30(1), 37-46.
„If pupils learn to express themselves appropri- Dubinsky, E. (1991a). The Constructive Aspects
ately, to reflect on language, if the teacher pays of Reflective Abstraction in Advanced
attention to a correct grammar, performances are Mathematics. In L.P. Steffe (Ed.), Epistemo-
increased.” This statement by Klieme (2006), logical Foundations in Mathematical Experi-
formulated as a result of the DESI-study, refers ences. New York: Springer.
to German and English lessons, but the addition Dubinsky, E. (1991b): Reflective Abstraction in
„And if all teachers support these aims, school Advanced Mathematical Thinking. In D. Tall
as a whole will achieve better results” also im- (Ed.), Advanced Mathematical Thinking (pp.
poses this responsibility on math teachers. 95-123). Kluwer.
Flawell, J. (1979). Metacognition and cognitive
monitoring. A new area of cognitive-
References developmental inquiry. American Psychologist
Boekaerts, M. (1996). Teaching Students Self- 34, 906-911.
Regulated Learning: A Major Success in Ap- Herget, W. (1991). Mathematikunterricht – Wie
plied Research. In J. Georgas et al. (Eds.), geht es weiter? [Mathematics Education: How
Contemporary Psychology in Europe, 245- to proceed?] In H. Hischer (Ed.), Mathematik-
259. Seattle: Hogrefe & Huber Publishers. unterricht im Umbruch (pp. 139-148), Hildes-
Bundesministerium für Bildung und Forschung heim: Franzbecker.
[German Federal Ministry of education and re- Kaune, C. (2001). Weiterentwicklung des Ma-
search], BMBF (Ed.) (2001). TIMSS - Impulse thematikunterrichts: Die kognitions-orientierte
für Schule und Unterricht [Impulses for Aufgabe ist mehr als „die etwas andere Aufga-
School and Instruction]. Bonn. be“ [Advancements in mathematics education:
Cohors-Fresenborg, E. (2001). Mathematik als The cognition-oriented problem is more than
Werkzeug zur Wissensrepräsentation: Das Os- „a somewhat different problem“]. Der Mathe-
nabrücker Curriculum. [Mathematics as a tool matikunterricht 47(1), 35-46.
for knowledge representation: The curriculum Kaune, C. (2005). Acht Jahre MUMAS - Eine
of Osnabrueck.] Der Mathematikunterricht Recherche in 1000 Unterrichtsszenen zum Va-
47(1), 5-13. riablenverständnis von Gymnasiasten. [Eight
Cohors-Fresenborg, E. & Kaune, C. (2003). Un- years of MUMAS: Research on 1000 scenes of
terrichtsqualität: Die Rolle von Diskursivität lessons on variable comprehension in high
für „guten“ gymnasialen Mathematikunter- school] In C. Kaune, I. Schwank & J. Sjuts

359
Analyses ZDM 2006 Vol. 38 (4)

(Eds.), Mathematikdidaktik im Wissenschafts- conceptual differentiation and interpretative


gefüge. Zum Verstehen und Unterrichten ma- analysis of a cognitively and constructivistly
thematischen Denkens (pp. 131-151). Os- theoretical mathematics education.] Os-
nabrück: Forschungsinstitut für Mathematik- nabrück: Forschungsinstitut für Mathematik-
didaktik. didaktik.
Kilpatrick, J. (1986). Reflection and Recursion. Sjuts, J. (1999b). ‘Metacognition in Mathemat-
In M. Carss (Ed.), Proceedings of the Fifth In- ics Lessons’. In Developments in Mathematics
ternational Congress on Mathematical Educa- Education in German-speaking Countries. Se-
tion (pp. 7-29). Boston: Birkhäuser. lected Papers from the Annual Conference on
Kind, R. (2004). Bericht der Sektion 8. In Nie- Didactics of Mathematics (pp. 76-87). Bern.
dersächsisches Kultusministerium (Ed.) [Re- http://webdoc.sub.gwdg.de/ebook/e/gdm/1999/
port of Section 8 of the lower Saxony state index.html
ministry for education and cultural affairs], Wang, M. C., Haertel, G.. D. & Walberg, H. J.
Ziele und Inhalte eines künftigen Mathematik- (1993). Toward a Knowledge Base for School
unterrichts an Gymnasien, Fachgymnasien Learning. Review of Educational Research
und Gesamtschulen (pp. 61-62). 63(3), 249-294.
Klieme, E. & Helmke, A. (2005). „Oft sind die
Lehrer zu ungeduldig“. [„Teachers are often
too impatient.“] Die Zeit vom 9.3.2006, 75.
Konrad, K. (2005). Förderung und Analyse von Author
selbstgesteuertem Lernen in kooperativen Christa Kaune, Apl. Prof. Dr.
Lernumgebungen: Bedingungen, Prozesse und Institute for Cognitive Mathematics
Bedeutung kognitiver sowie metakognitiver Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science
Strategien für den Erwerb und Transfer kon- University of Osnabrück
zeptuellen Wissens [Promotion and analysis of D-49069 Osnabrueck
self-directed learning in cooperative learning Email: ckaune@mathematik.uni-osnabrueck.de
environments: Stipulations, processes and re-
levance of cognitive as well as metacognitive
strategies for the acquisition and transfer of
conceptual knowledge.]. Lengerich: Papst Sci-
ence Publishers.
MNU: Deutscher Verein zur Förderung des ma-
thematischen und naturwissenschaftlichen Un-
terrichts e.V. (1997). Forderungen an einen
Mathematikunterricht der nichtgymnasialen
Schulformen in der Sekundarstufe I.
[German association to enhance mathematics
and scientific education (incorporated society).
Requirements for mathematics education in
non-grammar secondary schools.]
http://home.zugang.net/mnu-sachsen/sek1.htm
Schoenfeld, A.H. (1992). Learning to think
mathematically: problem solving, metacogni-
tion and sense making in mathematics. In D.
A. Groues (Ed.), Handbook of research on
mathematics teaching and learning 334-370.
New York: Macmillan.
Sjuts, J. (1999a). Mathematik als Werkzeug zur
Wissensrepräsentation. Theoretische Einord-
nung, konzeptionelle Abgrenzung und inter-
pretative Auswertung eines kognitions- und
konstruktivismustheoretischen Mathematik-
unterrichts. [Mathematics as a tool for knowl-
edge representation. Theoretical classification,

360

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi