Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 181

T H E B A C K G R O U N D TO

Although the scientific and mattic-


matical manuscripts of the Ports- NEWTON’S P R IN C IPIA
mouth Collection have been available
to scholats for almost a centuryj it b
only comparatively recently that they
have begun to be used for the study
of the development of Newton’s
thought in Physics and Mathematics.
The present i»ok is thus ilie firs: to
be devoted exclusively to the develop^
ment ofNewton^s dynamical thought
leading up to the composition of the
FriTidpia. Part T contains studies of
various aspects of this development*
Part II the text of the manuicripts
from the Portsmouth Collection on
which these studies are based. Cer­
tain of these manuscripts, especially
the ver^^early ones on ci rc ular mo lion*
provide an insight into the nature of
Newton’s genius in dynamics W'hich
it would he impossible to guess at
from the finished form of the
Frini:tfija itself.
,: r . THE BACKGROUND TO
NEWTON’S PK/NC/PM
X

» A ^ Study of Newton's Dynamical Researches


in the Years 1664-84
\ nuxl-'tt^ ^
|^lW
i^■ i^lllgi■i ^4 f '*J

I'Ji^aii. On.lA /■ *«/»»«/ #« i»4(n fftn/^t ».. .* '{^, ..fvJinr* ■\


*pu§fm.
BY
•'Tf r »■;•» . S M . i nrit r t i t m itm -n r r i'( E f :« m n*4> m ............................ .

JOHN H E R I V E L

y - / ■ ,/./ ^/. ^’ ■ / ' ■ ^ '-

f e « * » » - C ‘» fd o ti ••■(^^'*^ */*»■» ,

ft : f - f d f ih. «#»■>/,J».' »<■«/>,-/••I* / f f. t/> I f r'm. y- ■.

4 1 :ft f t / e t d ' f fy jfd tr r ff ,


»v,-- ^ * /f • ■' . "^.
^ d ** f ■ ■ ■ ‘ r^rf S" r t 0 *~

H f ■#jif ^NMI ^ < ■!•* / y // .f^ . rtf />’ f d f t t / ’. / '

,.y,„
><-r r. / /<^/.«'ie; fr^ 4 f„^y,.,^
»9 : f '-jd /wtJhyfi t'X ’f'f y.-,pf:.,/'X
')t*ift:^'/f.>tf( ( e>ft^ tt >t ( /» ^)f .i / ¥ e />t f / ( > / ^ ”’ f ^ y •f

> «. « | { « I m W !1 * • : « « ; / ■ « A i itf j f / «• r < ^ / ^ r T fp'Ptfe^'S I ,.

-J'f/^ t / 'Ityfff. (*<»•■ >'I'* d^ef /^ ^

r r f.fM f^4yX .'^ trv ,.

>.f L i» S * l‘ '*/ / • ■. ✓ Z^V A«^^vy

3^^ v4 » V.
OXFORD
lui^A^rMEl ^e-4t f t /■ *"»T~^*f A T T EI E C L A R E N D O N PRESS

1 965
I. T h e first page o f the so-called lectures ife M o tii, 1684
Oxford University Press, Ely House, London W . t
(GLASGOW NKW YORK TORONTO MELBOURNE WELLINGTON

CAPE TOW N SALISBURY IBADAN NAIROBI LUSAKA ADDIS ABABA PREFACE


BOMBAY CALCUTTA MADRAS KARACHI LAHORE DACCA

KUALA LUMPUR HONG KONG


I n the summer of 1958, while preparing a course of lectures on the his­
tory of dynamics from Copernicus to Newton, I was struck by how little
Oxford University Press 1965 seemed known of the grozvth of Newton’s dynamical thought. It was
surprising, for example, to find that almost more seemed to be known of
the growth of dynamical thought among Newton’s precursors in Oxford
P R IN T E D TN G R F. A T B R I TA 1 N
and Paris than in the case of Newton himself. Although this first im­
pression was somewhat modified on reading Rouse Ball’s Essay on
Newton's Principia, I was left with the impression that much still
remained to be found. In particular, I noticed how seldom Ball referred
to aetual documents in the Portsmouth Collection, and this despite
the fact that the collection had been catalogued some years previously,
and the mathematieal and physical papers deposited in the University
Library, Cambridge. For example, while I was struck with Ball’s sugges­
tion that the proof given at the end of the Scholium to Prop. 4, Theor. 4, of
the represented Newton’s first discovery o{ the law of centrifugal
force, I was surprised he made no mention of having searched for the
original document in the University Library. At the first opportunity,
then, in April 1959, I visited Cambridge to search for this and other
early documents.
A study of the dynamical papers among the early mathematical docu­
ments sufficed to confirm the correctness of my original impression, and
this was then greatly strengthened by an examination of the Waste
Book Feb. i66p. Here was a wealth of documentary evidence far beyond
anything hinted at in Rouse Ball’s Essay, and it seemed to me then that if
one could interpret and order this evidence it might be possible to pre­
sent some sort of connected account of the growth of Newton’s dyna­
mical thought prior to the composition of the Principia and thus help
fill up one of the large gaps in the history of dynamics. The reader may
judge to what extent this aim has now been realized.
I should like to express my indebtedness to those who in one way and
another have made this work possible. To E. Ashby, D. R. Bates,
and W. B. Gallie for enabling me to enter the field of the History of
Science professionally in the first place. And to W. B. Gallie again and
G. Davie for their encouragement during my first year as Lecturer
in the History and Philosophy of Science at Queen’s University. T o the
late H. W. Turnbull for forbearing to tell me that Newton’s Vellum
PREFACE
MS had been already deciphered, thus enabling me to get to grips
with Newton’s earliest researches in dynamics. Also for Turnbull’s
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
criticisms of my own provisional solution to this manuscript, and to those
of a referee in the journal Isis which taught me the necessity of inter­
I AM grateful to the Librarian of the University of Cam­
preting Newton in terms of his own approach to dynamics as opposed
bridge for permission to reproduce pages from manu­
to the present-day reformulation of that subject.
scripts in the Portsmouth Collection, to Flermann et
In common with other historians of science I have been indebted to
C ‘°, Paris, for permission to quote in extenso from my
the late Alexandre Koyre for the inspiration of his writings. I was also
article ‘Galileo’s Influence on Newton in Dynamics’
very fortunate to enjoy his friendship and encouragement, especially
in Melanges Alexandre Koyre (Paris, 1963), and to the
the opportunity of lecturing under his auspices on Newton in Paris in
Editors of Isis and the Archives Internationales de
1961. I am particularly indebted to two other colleagues; to I. B, Cohen
VHistoire des Sciences for permission to use articles
for first suggesting that I write this book, and for his continued interest
from their respective journals.
in its composition; and to A. C. Crombie for reading an early draft and J. FI.
encouraging me to persist with others. Also to E. S. de Beer for criticism
and advice on the reproduction of texts and to E. W. Bower for help
with translations from Latin.
The research on which this book is based would have been impossible
without generous grants from the late Research Committee of the
Senate and the present Research Committee of the Council of the
Queen’s University, Belfast. Thanks are due too for typing assistance to
Margaret Sheridan, Freda Silcock, Rosemary Clarke, and particularly
Ann Greer who bore the brunt of the many typings and retypings of
earlier drafts.
I must finally acknowledge my indebtedness to the staff of the Anderson
Room of the Cambridge University Library, especially F. J, Gautrey, for
their unfailing courtesy and assistance, and to the Clarendon Press for
much sound advice and for their skill in printing a difficult text.
Most of all to my wife and children for their continued forbearance over
a book which would never be finished.
J. H.

Department of History and Philosophy of Science


The Queen's University
Belfast
September, ig6j
CONTENTS

List of Plates XI

General Introduction

Short Titles and Abbreviations XV I

PART I
newton’s dyn am ical researches, 1664-1684

1. The main line of development of Newton’s dynamical thought


1.1 Newton’s first steps in dynamics
1.2 Newton before the problem of circular motion 7
1.3 The solution to the problem of Kepler-motion 14
1.4 The final synthesis of Newton’s dynamical system 22

2. The influence of Galileo and Descartes on Newton’s dynamics 35


2.1 The influence of Galileo 35
2.2 The influence of Descartes 42

3. Newton’s concept of conatiis 54


4. Tests of the Law of Gravitation against the moon’s motion 65

5. The motion of extended bodies 77


5.1 Kinematical aspects 77
5.2 Centre of motion in the dynamical sense 78
5.3 Dynamics of a single rotating body 81
5.4 Collision between two rotating bodies 82
5.5 Discussion in later researches 84

6. Order of composition and dating of manuscripts 87


6.1 Order of composition of earliest manuscripts 87
6.2 Dating of earliest manuscripts 91
6.3 Order of composition of later manuscripts 93
6.4 Dating of later manuscripts 96
6.5 Paget’s propositions 102
6.6 The status of manuscript VIII 108
CONTENT'S

PART II
L I S T OF P L A T E S
NEWTON D Y NA MI C A L MANUS CRI PTS , 1664-1684

Introduction 119 I.
I. Extracts from early notebook 121
2. facing p. 12
II. Dynamical writings in the Waste Book 128
III. The Vellum Manuscript 183 3- ition 13
IV a. On circular motion 192
4- 184
ivb. On motion in a cycloid 198
V. The Laws of Motion paper 208 5- 292
VI. Extracts from MS. Add. 4003 219
VII. Extracts from correspondence prior to 1684 236
VIII . The Kepler-motion papers 246
IX. The tract de Motu 257
xa. Drafts of definitions and laws of motion 304
xb. Drafts of definitions 315
XI. The lectures de Motu of 1684 321

Note regarding Previous Publication ot Newton Dynamical


Manuscripts 327

Bibliography 328

Index 331
GENERAL INTRODUCTION

W i t h certain notable exceptions,^ the whole history of dynamics from


Newton to Einstein can be thought of as an exploitation, albeit in­
finitely ingenious and resourceful, of the definitions, principles, and
propositions in the Principia. It is hardly surprising, therefore, that
We shall, I think, in this as in other subjects, get Newton’s achievement in dynamics has largely been equated with the
the best view of the matter if we look at the natural Principia itself, an opinion reinforced by Newton’s own claim^ to have
growth of things from the beginning.
composed the whole work within the space of a year and a half apart
Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, Chapter 2 , Section 2 from a handful of propositions discovered in 1679 and 1684. Admittedly,
Translated b y T . a . S i n c l a i r some indication of much earlier work in dynamics epitomized by the
story of the applet has come down to us through the accounts of Pem-
berton^ and Whiston,5 and Newton’s own account^ of his researches in
mathematics and ‘philosophy’ during the Plague Years. But this early
work in dynamics, if such there were,^ and whatever its exact nature and
extent, was inevitably so dwarfed by the towering achievement of the
Principia that it has seemed till recently of quite negligible interest and
importance.
In the nineteenth century a certain shift in this attitude towards the
Principia first became noticeable. Rigaud’s Essay on the Publication of
Newton^s Principia,^ though largely concerned with the events im­
mediately preceding the appearance of the great work, touched also on
some earlier researches of Newton, especially the important tracts de
Motu published for the first time in an Appendix to Rigaud’s Essay.
Edleston, in his Correspondence of Newton and C o t e s , added some
further important details, notably the presence in the University Library,
* For example, the theory of rotating bodies. Curiously, when Newton came to write
Book III of the Principia he either ignored, or had forgotten, the early, and particu­
larly brilliant work on rotating bodies found in M S . V.
^ Quoted in Brewster, D . [i], vol. i, p. 471.
3 See for example Stukeley, W . [i], p. 19. Attention seems first to have been drawn
to this very important account of the story of the apple by Pelseneer, J. [2]. T h e relevant
passage is reproduced below on p. 65, n. 7, Chapter 4.
* Pemberton, H. [i]. Preface. T h e relevant passage is reproduced below at Chapter
4. P- 6 5 .
^ Whiston, W . [i], pp. 35-38. T h e relevant passage is reproduced below at Chap­
ter 4, p. 65.
^ Portsmouth D raft Memorandum, Portsmouth Collection, Section i, division X I,
number 41, as reproduced below at Chapter 4, p. 66.
’’ e.g. Patterson, L. D ., [i], [2] has questioned the veracity of N ew ton’s account.
* Rigaud, S. P. [i].
'' A term first used, apparently, by Rigaud. Edleston, J. [i].
xiv GENERAL IN T R O D U C T I O N GENERAL I N T R O D U C T I O N xv
Cambridge, of the original texts of all Newton’s university lectures be­ late medieval dynamics, increasing emphasis has been placed on the
tween 1669 and 1687,' especially those apparently read in the Michael­ filiation and growth of dynamical thought as opposed to the final pro­
mas term 1684 under the title de Motu Corporum. Brewster, in his duct of such thought. So that today the importance of the study of the
Memoirs of Newton,^ though concerned with the whole sweep of New ­ growth of Newton’s dynamical thought would no longer be questioned.
ton’s life and work, and not only his researches in mathematics and In the absence of original manuscripts, however, this study would in­
dynamics, drew attention to some important new material relating to evitably be largely a matter of speculation eked out by the few meagre
dynamics.^ Finally, in Ball’s Essay on Newton’s Principia'^ the whole details supplied by the above-mentioned accounts of Pemberton,
question of Newton’s researches in dynamics prior to the composition Whiston, and Newton himself. Fortunately there are a considerable
of the Principia came much more to the fore. Admittedly, Ball’s most number of ‘early’^ Newton dynamical manuscripts in that part of the
important contribution was his discovery of the greater parts of the original Portsmouth Collection now lodged in the Cambridge Univer­
correspondence of 1679 between Hooke and Newton. But apart from sity Library. Although many of these manuscripts have already been
invaluable chapters on this correspondence, and on the tract de Motu, published in part or in whole, almost half Newton’s early dynamical
Ball also had a chapter devoted to Newton’s earliest dynamical researches. writings, especially those in the Waste Book, have remained unpublished.
Since Ball’s Essay various studies of Newton have appeared, notably These latter writings are now made available in company with those
the biographies of More,^ Sullivan,^ and Andrade,^ and Cohen’s study of previously published, so that Newton scholars and others interested in
Newton and Frankl i n. None of these works, however, is exclusively, the early development of Newton’s dynamical thought have here before
or even predominantly, concerned with Newton’s researches in dynamics, them what is to my knowledge the whole extant corpus of Newton dyna­
so that up to date Ball’s Essay represents the only study of this aspect of mical manuscripts prior to the composition of the Principia.
Newton’s intellectual genius. Ball’s Essay, however, in spite of its unique Some explanation is called for on the structure of the present work.
status and many valuable features, suffered from one serious defect: Part I consists of an extended commentary on the manuscripts repro­
although composed after the cataloguing of the Portsmouth Collection, duced in Part II. In the first chapter an attempt is made to give a con­
it contained surprisingly few references to original documents, especially nected account of the main line of development of Newton’s dynamical
the earliest ones. This defect may well have been due not to any de­ thought up to the final draft of Book I of the Principia. The remaining
ficiency in Ball qua historian of science but simply to lack of time.^® On chapters of Part I are devoted to detailed studies of various topics which
the other hand, there are certain indications that Ball had not entirely could not be incorporated directly in Chapter i, including a final chapter
freed himself from the prevailing attitude towards the Principia. For on the order of composition and dating of manuscripts. The method
example, he finally dismissed one important question relating to the followed in the reproduction of texts is explained in the introduction to
early researches as being ‘mainly a matter of antiquarian interest’ ." Part II, especially the division of footnotes into critical and exegetical.
Since the publication of Ball’s Essay there has been something Exegetical footnotes relating to matters allowing of a potentially wide
approaching a revolution in the attitude of historians of science towards variation of opinion, such as those relating to the growth of Newton’s
dynamics. Beginning, perhaps, with Duhem’s celebrated researches into dynamical thought, have been mostly restricted to a direct reference
to the appropriate section of Part I, or to such a reference preceded
' Apart from those for 1686 which appear to he missing. See below, Chapter 6.4,
pp. 98-102. by a brief, unsupported expression of opinion. In this way it is hoped
^ Brewster, D . [i]. that other scholars anxious to form their own opinions on the many un­
3 For example, the document referred to on p. xiii, n. 2.
^ Ball, W . W . R. [t].
certain questions raised by these manuscripts will be free to do so un­
5 T h e remainder of the correspondence has since been discovered by Pelseneer and biased by the arguments advanced in Part I.
Koyre. See especially Koyre, A . [2].
More, L . T . [i]. ’ Sullivan, J. W. N . [i]. * i.e. prior to the composition of the Principia.
® Andrade, E. N . da C . [i]. ^ Cohen, I. B. [i].
See the remarks at the end of first paragraph on p. i of Ball, W. W. R. [i].
” Ibid., p. 17, end of top paragraph.
PART I
SHORT T I T L E S AND ABBREVIATIONS
NEWTON’S DYNAMICAL RESEARCHES
(a) P U B L I S H E D W O R K S
1664-1684
Correspondence The Correspondence of Isaac Newton (Cambridge Univer­
sity Press, for the Royal Society of London, vols. 1-3,
19 59 , i9 6 0 , 19 6 1).

Descartes, (Euvres (Euvres de Descartes publiees par Charles Adam et


Paul Tannery, 13 vols. (Paris, 1897-1913).
Galileo, Dialogue Dialogo Sopra i Due Massimi Sistemi Del Mondo
(Florence, 1632).
1
Galileo, Discorsi Discorsi e Dimonstrazioni Mathematiche Intorno a Due T H E M A I N L I N E OF D E V E L O P M E N T OF
Nuove Scienze (Leyden, 1638).
Galileo, Ed. Naz. Le opere di Galileo Galilei, Edizione Nazionale, 20 vols. NEW TON’S D YN AM ICAL THOUGHT
(Florence, 1890-1909).
Huygens, Horologium Christiani Hugenii Zulichemii, Const. F. Horologium
Oscillatorium (Paris, 1673). 1.1. N e’WTon ’s F irs t S teps in D ynamics
Huygens, (Euvres (Euvres completes de Christiaan Huygens, 22 vols. (The N e w t o n ’ s interest in dynamics would inevitably have awakened very
Hague, 1888-1950).
early, and the boy who constructed a mill turned by the wind or the
{b) M A N U S C R I P T S force of a mouse, or a water clock to measure the time,^ or the youth who
C.U.L. Cambridge University Library. attempted by jumping to gauge the force of the great storm of 1658^
Vellum MS. Newton MS. (C.U.L. MS. Add. 3958, folio 45). would already have begun to ponder the two basic concepts of dynamics
Waste Book Newton MS. (C.U.L. MS. Add. 4004). — force and movement— ^though it is improbable that he would have
had any contact with the subject on the theoretical side before his entry
to Cambridge in 1661.^ At some stage in his undergraduate studies
Newton would inevitably have encountered Aristotle’s theory of local
motion directly or at second hand through a work such as that of
Magirus [i] from which extracts are found in one of the early notebooks.
In any case the passage ‘On Violent Motion’ in the same notebook^
proves that he had already begun to free himself from any such Aristote­
lian or scholastic influences by the second half of 1664.5 For in spite of
the unmistakably medieval flavour of the writing, the upshot of the
argument was to reject the possibility of the motion of a projectile as
due either to the surrounding air (Aristotle), or to a force impresst (im­
petus school), and to And the cause of the continued motion of the body
in its natural gravity, that is, presumably, in its inertia. References to
Galileo^ and Descartes'^ close to this passage ‘On Violent Motion’ suggest
that it was under their influence that Newton began to develop his own
• See Brewster [i], vol. i, p. 9. ^ Ibid., p. 15.
3 Ibid., p. 17. M S . I, § 2.
5 See below, Chapter 6.2, for question of dating of earliest manuscripts.
* M S . I, § 6. ’’ See, for example, M S. I, § 3.
8i)S205 B
MAIN LINE OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.1 1.1 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 3
views on dynamics.^ This development was evidently very rapid, for petal force for circular motion in Prop. 4, Theor. 4, of the Principia.
an entry in the Waste Book^ dated 20 January 1664 (O.S.) discloses a The unique exception to this comparison rule is found in the note to
recognizably modern quantitative approach to the problem of the inelastic Axiom 26 of the Waste Book.^ There Newton considers a single body,
collision of two bodies. and after noting that in the case of uniform motion the distance and time
This entry, like others in the Waste Book and elsewhere among the may be represented by two of the sides of a right-angled triangle, he
earliest dynamical manuscripts, is remarkable for the confident way it proceeds to state that in the general case of non-uniform motion a
deals with the kinematical side of the problem. It is probably impossible crooked line will result from plotting space against time, the (instanta­
to disentangle the various influences which went to shape Newton’s neous) velocity at any point being given by the inverse gradient of the
approach to kinematics. He could well have been influenced by Aristotle space-time curve. This brief note must be regarded as representing,
himself, or by certain of the late medieval thinkers of the Oxford school simultaneously, the hidden culmination^ of the train of thought which
such as Calculator ,3 or by Galileo directly, or indirectly through Torri­ went back to the definition of instantaneous velocity by the Merton
celli or Barrow. Also his interest in kinematics (and later in dynamics) College school in the first half of the fourteenth century,^ and, for New­
could have arisen out of his researches in fluxions or vice versa .4 In any ton, the dividing of the ways: if he had followed the line indicated in this
case, kinematics evidently presented no problem to Newton from the note it would inevitably have led him to the construction of a dynamics
Waste Book onwards, and at various points in the earliest dynamical based on analytical geometry and the method of fluxions as opposed to
manuscripts we find clear definitions of movement as the passage of a the actual development based on synthetic geometry and the method of
body from one point of extension to another, or change of place, velocity prime and ultimate quantities expounded in Section I of Book I of the
being the intensity of motion and proportional to the distance covered in Principia. The long and difficult process of ‘transformation’ and reformu­
a given time. lation of the results and methods of the Principia in the first half of the
With one exception the measurement of velocity always involved eighteenth century might then have been avoided.
comparisons between the velocities of two different bodies, or of different Almost inevitably the problem of collisions would have been that to
velocities in the same body, thus avoiding the ‘forbidden’ division between which Newton first applied his exact, quantitative definition of velocity.
the two dissimilar quantities space and time.^ This was equally true of It is probable, too, that his first ideas on this problem were based on the
other quantities such as momentum or force, a typical example at a discussion given in Part 2 of Descartes’s Principia Philosophiae including
much later stage being provided by the enunciation of the law of centri­ the fundamental definition of the motion of a body as jointly propor­
tional to its size and speed.^^ If so, Newton must have very soon corrected
* See below, Chapter 2, for the influence of Galileo and Descartes on Newton in
the error in Descartes’ law of conservation of motion. For in the dis­
dynamics.
2 See M S . Ilb . cussion of inelastic collisions in the Waste Book^ we find that for Newton,
3 Boyer [i], p. 194, notes that the terms fluxion and fluent employed by Newton had unlike Descartes, the unchanging total quantity of motion was the alge­
appeared earlier in the work of Calculator.
C f., for example, Prop, i and 2 of the paper ‘T o Resolve Problems by M otion ’ braic sum of the separate motions taking account of the directions or
{Correspondence, vol. iii, no. 348) with §§ 2, 3, respectively, of M S . V. determinations^ of the movements of the individual bodies.
^ T h e notion of a proportion between dissimilar quantities was unthinkable to both
Greek and medieval philosophers. For example, Bradwardine defines proportion as
In the case of inelastic collisions all that was required for a complete
‘the mutual relationship of two things of the same kind’, Clagett [i], p. 465. And solution was the size of each body and the magnitudes and directions
although the Merton College kinematicists ultimately achieved a perfect definition of
of their respective velocities before the collision. To find the magnitude
instantaneous velocity in the case of non-uniform motion, it is evident that they still
thought of this velocity not as a ratio but as representing the distance which would have and direction of the velocity of the composite body after collision was
been covered by the body in a certain time, ibid., p. 167. T h e notion of velocity as a
separate quantity is evident in the section on ‘Uniform M otion’ in the Third D ay of ‘ M S . Ild .
Galileo’s Discorsi, where he goes so far as to represent individual speeds by lines of ^ Assuming, of course, that Newton was not forestalled in this definition of velocity
as a ratio by some previous writer such as Barrow.
diflferent lengths. But it is still a question always of comparing speeds, and neither in
^ See, for example, Clagett [i], Chapter 4, especially §§4, 5.
this section nor elsewhere in the Discorsi does one find a definition of an individual
♦ Op. cit.. Art. 36. 5 See M S . Ilb . * See M S . lie , Def. 4.
speed as a ratio o f distance to time.
M A I N L I N E OF D E V E L O P M E N T O F 1.1
1.1 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T
then a matter of elementary algebra. Noteworthy, however, and very
head the various inconclusive discussions of previous years by inviting
characteristic, is the systematic way in which Newton allows for all
papers on the subject from Wren, Wallis, and Huygens.^
possible cases.
The true importance of the problem of collisions was very different
Of greater interest is the discussion in the Waste Book of the direct from that which would have been imagined by the Scientific Establish­
collision of two elastic spheres.^ There the mutual reflection of the ment of the day. It was, in fact, twofold: it provided material for the pro­
spheres was due to some ‘springing motion’ in the bodies or the matter longed controversy between the supporters of Leibniz’s measure of
crowded between them. And as the spring was more dull or vigorous so motion, the vis viva, on the one hand, and the supporters of the Cartesian
the bodies would be reflected more or less vigorously. During the actual measure on the other.^ Even more important, perhaps, it provided an
process of collision the spheres would ‘relent’ from their spherical ideal testing ground for the earliest formal development of Newton’s
shapes and be pressed into ‘sphaeroidicall’ figures up to the point where concept of force. It is this latter aspect which concerns us here.
they momentarily came to rest when the pressure between them would There were, as we have seen, three basic elements in Newton’s treat­
be greatest.2 But if the bodies were ‘absolutely solid’ the collision would ment of the problem of collisions in the Waste Book. First the assump­
take place instantaneously, no relenting from the spherical shape being tion (following Descartes) that the proper measure of the quantity of
possible.2 motion in a body was proportional jointly to its size and speed. Next
In the direct collision of two equal, perfectly clastic spheres moving Descartes’s law of conservation of total quantity of motion suitably
with equal speeds in opposite directions the relative velocity of separa­ emended as regards direction of motion. Lastly a perfect understanding
tion would necessarily equal that of approach.^ This would still re­ of the physical process of elastic collisions with its momentary distortion
main true for all sizes and velocities of the bodies.^ No indication of of the colliding bodies. It was this last, physical, aspect of the collision
the proof of the general result was given. Evidently it corresponded process which figured in Newton’s first definition of force in the Waste
to Newton’s experimental law of collisions for the special case in which Book as ‘the pressure or crowding of one body on another’.^ We can
the coefficient of restitution equalled unity. Later it was employed in thus assume that the pressure between colliding bodies was one of the
the remarkable solution to the problem of the collision of two rotating first kinds of force seriously considered by Newton. This pressure,
bodies.5 however, had the grave disadvantage that it was impossible to assign
By the middle of the seventeenth century the centre of interest in any numerical quantity to mirror its extremely rapid variation from zero
dynamics in continental Europe had shifted from the problem of motion, up to a maximum and down to zero again. In fact, in the extreme case
to which it must have seemed that Galileo had provided the definitive of ‘absolutely solid’ bodies the process of collision was instantaneous.^
solution in his Discorsi, to the problem of collisions, a topic to which Newton’s powerful drive towards a quantitative treatment of dynamics
Galileo had contributed little. Attention had been focused on this latter would then have led him to search for a new quantitative definition of
problem by its treatment in Part 2 of Descartes’s Principia Philosophiae. force. Hence the various Axioms in the Waste Book^ equivalent to the
In England any previous interest in this problem would have been single definition/orre oc change in quantity of motion produced.
stimulated by Huygens’s successful application of his own theory of We cannot be sure how Newton arrived at this fundamental definition
collisions before various members of the Royal Society, including of force. But it seems probable that it had some close connexion with
Laurence Rooke, Wallis, and Wren, at the time of his visit to London in the immediately preceding enunciation of the principle of inertia:^
i66i.^ This theory, as we now know, had been fully worked out as * See Birch [i], vol. ii, pp. 315, 320.
Huygens’s paper, transmitted to the Royal Society early in January 1669, was un­
early as 1656.7 Finally, in 1668, the Royal Society sought to bring to a
accountably, and much to H uygens’s annoyance, not published in the Transactions like
* See M S . lid . Ax. 7-10 . ^ M S . I Id, Ax. Q. those of Wren and Wallis. Hence the paper ‘Regies du Mouvement dans la Rencontre
3 Ibid., at end. M S . I Id, Ax. 10. des Corps’ appearing in thQ Journal des Scavans in March 1669.
5 See M S . V , §§ 9, 10. ^ For various aspects of this controversy see Costabel [i], Chapter 2; Dugas [i],
* See Huygens’s CEuvres, vol. xvi, pp. 172-3, 181. Chapter 14, § 7; Dugas [2], Part III, Chapter 2. ^ M S . lie , Def. 9.
7 Ibid., pp. 10, 137, n. I.
M S. Ild , Ax. 9. 5 Ibid., A x. 4, 5, 6, 23. ^ Ibid. Ax. i, 2.
M AI N LIN E OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.1 1.2 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L TH O U G H T
(1) If a quantity once move it will never rest unless hindered by some 1.2. N ew ton before the P roblem of C ircular M otion
external cause.
(2) A quantity will always move on in the same straight line (not changing It is worth pausing for a moment to consider how fortunate the exis­
the determination nor celerity of its motion) unless some external cause tence of uniform circular motion was for Newton, and how important
divert it. his successful treatment of it for the whole future development of
From this enunciation it followed that any change in the state of rest or his dynamics. Apart from motion in a circle, the only relatively simple
motion of a body was due to some external cause. If this external cause kinds of movement available for study by Newton were rectilinear,
were identified with force then force would be that which produced parabolic, and elliptical. The first two occurred in motion under gravity
change in a body’s state of motion or rest. This is precisely the identifica­ at the Earth’s surface, and had already been fully explored, at least in
tion found later in the Waste Book where force is said to be the power their kinematical aspects, by Galileo. Both bulked large in the growth of
of the cause which changes a body’s motion.* Newton’s dynamical thought, especially uniformly accelerated rectilinear
But the measure of the force corresponding to a given change in motion, the paradigm case for all other more complicated motions. But
velocity had still to he assigned. The simplest assumption would have neither of these motions admitted of any development of the concept of
been to measure it in terms of actual change of velocity. This, however, force. On the other hand, the elliptical motion discerned by Kepler in the
would have ignored the role of a body’s bulk epitomized by the fact unruly movements of the planet Mars was far too difficult and complex
that it is more difficult to induce a given change in the velocity of a large a case for Newton to treat first. In contrast, the problem of uniform
than a small body. Given the role of quantity of motion in collision pro­ circular motion was at once not impossibly difficult and yet of sufficient
complexity to call for a real advance in his concept of force and his
cesses, Newton would inevitably have assumed that the measure of force
method of applying it to motion in a curved path.
depended in some way on the change in quantity of motion produced.
The first known discussion by Newton of the problem of circular
The simplest assumption— force directly proportional to change in
motion is found at Axiom 20 of the Waste BookJ The case considered is
quantity of motion— would have been tried first, and would then have
that of a ball moving on the interior of a hollow spherical surface. Accord­
been found to possess the signal merit of ensuring conservation of
ing to the principle of inertia there is a constant tendency for the ball to
quantity of motion in collision processes on the assumption that the
continue on in the instantaneous direction of its motion at any point, i.e.
forces between the colliding bodies were equal and opposite.^
along the tangent to the circle. And the fact that it does not so continue
In some such way Newton was led to his fundamental, quantitative
but moves instead in a circle argues the continuous action on it of a force.
definition of force. It represented the first important step towards his
This force can only arise from pressure between the ball and the surface.
final achievement in dynamics. But at this point a formidable difficulty
But if the surface presses the ball, the ball itself must press the surface.
seemed to bar the way to any further progress: how to relate forces thus
From which it follows^
defined with the actual, physical forces encountered in Nature, such as
the pressure between bodies, or the tension in a rotating sling. Newton’s that all bodies moved circularly have an endeavour from the centre about
which they move.
ability to surmount this difficulty in the case of centrifugal force marked
his first decisive breakthrough in dynamics and one which lifted him to This first discussion of the physical origin of centrifugal force bears
a new plane of achievement in the subject only attained by Huygens^ evidence of Descartes’ treatment of the same subject in Part 2 of his
besides. Principia Philosophiae.^ Having thus attained to a clear physical under­
* M S . He, A x. 104. 2 M S . Ild , A x. 7, 8.
standing of the problem Newton was now faced with the task of provid­
^ In the treatise D e V i Centrifuga, written by 1659. This, however, was first pub­ ing it with an exact, quantitative treatment. His first tentative steps
lished in 1703 among the Opuscula Posthuma. Various results based on the law of
toward such a treatment are found at Axiom 22 of the Waste Book.^ There
centrifugal force were published without proof in the Appendix to the Horologium Oscil-
latorium of 1673. See section on centrifugal force in Huygens’s (Euvres, vol. xvi, » M S . Ild . ® Ibid., A x. 21.
pp. 237-328. A detailed comparison between the respective approaches of Huygens 3 See below. Chapter 2, § 2, section on circular motion. M S . Ild , A x. 22.
and Newton to the problem of circular motion would be very valuable.
MAIN LINE OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.2 1.2 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L THOUGFIT
he notes that the whole force hy which a body co endeavours from the At each corner it would be reflected from one side into the next and so on
centre m in half a revolution is more than double the force that is able to ad infinitum. In this particular case an exact relation could be deduced
destroy or create its motion, that is the quantity of its motion. For in involving the magnitude of the shock encountered by the ball at each
moving from any point of the circle to the diametrically opposite point corner of the square, namely:
the ‘resistance’ of the surrounding surface (equal to the contrary pressure
total sum of shocks at 4 corners sum of sides of square
exerted by the body on the surface) is able to destroy the original quantity
force of movement of ball radius of circle
of the body’s motion along the tangent at the first point and create an
equal quantity of motion in exactly the opposite sense at the second point. The same argument could be applied to regular inscribed polygons of
Two things are noteworthy here: first a small point of capital im­ any order invariably leading to the result:
portance. If a complete revolution of the circle had been considered no total sum of shocks at all corners sum of all sides
conclusion could have been drawn since the final state of the body force of movement of ball radius of circle
would then have been the same as its original one. On the other hand,
Newton then continued:
for half a revolution the position is entirely different. The line of action
and so if [the] body were reflected by the sides of an equilateral circumscribed
of the motion remains the same, certainly, but not its sense, and New­
polygon of an infinite number of sides (that is by the circle itself) the force of
ton, unlike Descartes, was well aware of the importance of sense or de­
all the reflections are to the force of the body’s motion as all those sides {id est
termination in defining the motion of a body. Next there is the phrase the perimeter) to the radius.
‘whole force . . . in half a revolution’. The exact sense of this phrase will
The last proportion was evidently ztt thus explaining the cancellation
become clear later. At present it need only be noted that it is a matter of
of a 4-F elsewhere in the Waste Book^ and its replacement by a 6 + , that
the effect of a continuous force during an extended interval of time. In
is to say ztt. In addition, it is evident now that the expression force of all
fact, without understanding the exact meaning of the argument its
reflections meant sum of all the forces of reflection in a complete revolu­
general drift is sufficiently clear, namely, that the whole effect of the
tion, thus explaining the earlier phrase of doubtful meaning the whole
force on the hall during half a revolution is exactly to reverse its sense of
force . . . hi half a revolution.
movement and consequently to change its motion by an amount equal
This replacement of an inequality by an exact result was a brilliant
to double its original quantity. Equally clear is the attempt to effect a
achievement. Nevertheless the result obtained in the form given is not
connexion between force in the physical sense on the one hand, and
very useful. For example, the sum of all the forces of reflection during a
force in the sense of change of quantity of motion on the other.
complete revolution is considered but no mention is made of the centri­
In this ingenious way Newton was able to introduce number into his
fugal force itself. Again, and even more serious, although the sum of the
treatment of circular motion. Admittedly the result obtained was no
forces of reflection remains finite in passing to the limit of an inscribed
more than approximate. It was a question not of an equality but of an
polygon with an infinite number of sides all the individual forces tend
inequality. The problem now was to improve on this inequality and
towards zero! In addition these forces of reflection continually change
replace it, if possible, by an exact result. As long as the circle itself was
their direction, so that it is rather doubtful if any valid physical sense
retained further progress was impossible. It was necessary, like Des­ can be attributed to their sum. These difficulties may explain the exis­
cartes, but in a very different sense, to escape from the tyranny of the tence of another paragraph immediately preceding the above proof
circle only to return to it again later. And that Newton was able so to where one finds in essence the following result:
escape was entirely due to the fact that he had replaced the stone in the
If a ball moves in a circle, then the force by which it tends away from the
Cartesian sling by a ball moving on an inner spherical surface. For now
centre acting on some other body in a straight line (like the force of gravity)
it was possible to imagine the body moving along a square inscribed in will create in this other body, in the time for motion in the circle through
the circle as opposed to the circle itself, as on folio i of the Waste Book.^
‘ M S . I Id, Ax. 24.
I M S . Ila, § 2.
10 M A I N L I N E OF D E V E L O P M E N T OF 1.2 1.2 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 11
a distance equal to the radius of the circle, motion equal to the quantity of relating to the motion of vertical and horizontal pendulums. He thus
motion of the ball.
arrived at the excellent figure of 196 inches of fall in one second.
The equivalence of this result referring to movement in a straight line to The assumption that the distances moved in a given time were pro­
the result obtained for movement in a circle follows without difficulty, portional to the forces, and the extension of Galileo’s V law from the
and doubtless Newton would have divined it immediately. special case of motion under gravity to that under any constant force,
Thus Newton obtained a quantitative result concerning the motion of would both have appeared self-evident to Newton, requiring no justi­
a body in a straight line under the action of a constant force equal to the fication. Later they played a central role in his treatment of motion in an
centrifugal force for a given circular motion. Noteworthy is the fact that ellipse where he extended them still further to a case where the forces
up to this point he had not obtained a formula giving the dependence of acting were no longer constant. ^
centrifugal force on the speed and the radius of the circle. This com­ Having learnt how to calculate the ratio of weight to centrifugal force,
pletes the treatment of the problem of circular motion in the Waste Book. Newton then discovered that the centrifugal force of a body at the
The scene now shifts to MS. I ll, devoted, for the most part, to calcula­ equator due to the diurnal motion could be safely neglected compared
tion of the ratios of the force of gravity to the centrifugal forces of the with its weight. This was his first great practical discovery in dynamics.
diurnal and annual movements of the Earth. These calculations are all The ancient arguments of Ptolemy against the rotation of the Earth
based implicitly, nevertheless certainly,^ on the following formula: were theoretically sound but in practice the effect was negligible and
A body moves from rest in a straight line under the action of a force equal would have none of the catastrophic consequences imagined by Ptolemy.
to that acting on an equal body moving in a circle, radius R, with speed V. Then This was a result of great importance and must have powerfully
in the time of movement in the circle through a distance R the other equal reinforced Newton’s belief in the Copernican system. Yet it in no way
body will move from rest in a straight line through a distance \R.
implied a knowledge of the dependence of centrifugal force on radius and
To consider Newton’s probable derivation of this formula we must speed. One calculation in MS. I I P indeed proves that Newton had
return to the result immediately above his exact quantitative ‘polygonal’ reached this result sometime after his first calculations on that manu­
treatment of circular motion on folio i on the Waste Book. The known script, and it is even possible that he first derived this result by the
behaviour of a body in this case then leads to the ‘\R! formula. For if jR following proof found at the end of the Scholium to Prop. 4, Theor. 4,
be the radius of the circle, and V the speed of the ball, the result given of the Principia.^
by Newton implies that the second body acquires motion M V in time In any circle suppose a polygon to be described of any number of sides.
RjV, M being the bulk of the ball. If, as in MS. I ll , the second body And if a body, moved with a given velocity along the sides of the polygon, is
happens to have the same bulk as the ball, it will clearly acquire speed V reflected from the circle at the several angular points, the force, with which
in time RjV, and by the Merton^ Rule the distance moved in this time will at every reflection it strikes the circle, will be as its velocity: and therefore the
sum of the forces, in a given time, will be as the product of that velocity and
be (^-R/V)V = \R— precisely the result used by Newton in MS. I ll,
the number of reflections; that is (if the species of the polygon be given), as
and most probably derived by him in the manner just indicated. T o cal­
the length described in that given time, and increased or diminished in the
culate the ratio of the weight of a body to any given centrifugal force it ratio of the same length to the radius of the circle; that is, as the square of
was then only necessary to compare the distances moved by the body that length divided by the radius; and therefore the polygon, by having its sides
under the action of the two forces in the same interval of time. At first the diminished in infinitum coincides with the circle, as the square of the arc de­
value assumed for the rate of fall due to gravity was based on a result scribed in a given time divided by the radius. This is the centrifugal force,
given by Galileo in the Dialogue.^ Later becoming dissatisfied with this with which the body impels the circle; and to which the contrary force, where­
with the circle continually repels the body towards the centre, is equal.
result, perhaps as the result of some crude experiment, he redetermined
The approach to the problem of circular motion in this proof is
the rate of fall due to gravity by a very ingenious use of certain results
evidently the same as that found in the Waste Book. And the possibility'^
* See § 2 o f Commentary and Interpretation to M S . III.
' See below, § 3 of present chapter. ^ See M S . I l l , Appendix B, § 2.
* Familiar to Newton if only through Galileo’s Dialogue or Discorsi.
3 As first suggested by Ball. See Ball [i], p. 13. ^ See Ball [i], p. 13.
^ See M S . I, § 6; M S . I l l , Appendix A .
PLATE 2
12 M A I N L I N E OF D E V E L O P M E N T OF 1.2
that it represents the actual culmination of the discussion in that manu­
script is strengthened by Newton’s statement in his letter of 14 July 1686
to Halley that he came across it when ‘turning over some old papers’.
However, the first undoubtedly early proof of the law of centrifugal
force is that given in MS. IVa.
Once again, as in the polygonal treatment, there is the basic Cartesian ' si ^I V
notion of the natural tendency of the body to follow the inertial path
along the tangent. But whereas the ‘polygonal’ treatment was based on -1 4 : 2 t .
: 5
the idea of replacing the circle by an inscribed polygon, and the con­ * ^
. - i
■ ^
tinuous force by a series of sharp impulsive ‘forces of reflection’, the
circle is now retained throughout, the outward conatus or endeavour
from the centre being measured by the deviation it would produce be­ tS I . V
tween the actual and inertial paths in a given small interval of time.
This deviation, D B (MS. IVa, Fig. i), is thus the distance through
which the conatus would impel the body if free to act in the absence of
o
o
any constraining force. By Galileo’s F law it then follows that the same cq
conatus acting on the body in a straight line, like the force of gravity,
would move it through a distance 2tt^R in the time of a complete revolu­ I
tion in the circle. That this result is equivalent to the ‘ l-R’ formula of
MS. HI follows immediately by a second application of the F law. So
the two treatments, the polygonal and the deviational, agree. But where­
as the derivation of the law of centrifugal force by the polygonal method
is, as we have seen, rather difficult, it follows easily from the deviational
treatment. For if the given conatus moves the body through a distance
2tt^R in the time T of a complete revolution, it will move the body
through a distance 27 t^Rx {i ITY in unit time. From the proportionality
arguments for constant forces it follows that the conati of divers circular
• I O - ;■ ^
motions will vary with the result given by Newton at §2 of MS. IVa.
In this deviational treatment of circular motion we thus find renewed
use of the paradigm case of motion under gravity, including application
of the extension of Galileo’s F law; in addition there is the first intro­ “I
u ^
I i I■ 1 V- I ' ?c '
duction of the important notion of measuring force or conatus in terms " ^ .N , . ,ir ‘ >^ r • V - A-j 11-
- c1 nI .
of the deviation DB in a given time.
5t t I . -
Two things are noteworthy: first, Newton’s apparent belief in conatus
■ v ‘ -I
i t ^ T-1
^ it- ; ' •
as a real species of potential force; z/the body were free then the conatus L fA " *‘ J-JkJf _.^ 4
t| •> ^<- i ' ' -V - f 3 '
would impel it through the distance DB in the given small interval of i S V w ^ ’V ' C - t*
time. This is precisely the same notion of conatus found in Def. 6 of MS. i V.
VI, where it is said to be ‘an impeded force or a force in so far as it is ^ ..:r Cl- t f' ^ ¥
. : '4 ^ ^d <. Ii ^
F '• "K
** i" ‘ ^ ' N V t
resisted’. In the case of circular motion this is an entirely false notion
plate 3

1.2 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L TH O U G H T 13
dynamically, the only true tendency being that along the tangent. That
I iS hfm A H 0 Qiuniuf ^ Newton ultimately came to realize the illusory nature of centrifugal, as
4. ^aAvw h.*Juf Sf#>~j u ^ L i Uk, (f^ opposed to centripetal, force would seem* to follow from his treatment
|0t.J «. *9 of orbital motion from the tract de Motu onwards. For now it is a devia­
£<i«n fi ht-^OVL, tion BD equal to the original one, but in the opposite sense, in terms
of which he compares the centripetal forces for different circular motions.
*** In the second place, it is noteworthy that Newton does not set the
^ <Xt J,
conatus proportional to the distance DB. He states only that the conatus
itO ih«./ 9 C ^ n i t h < t ^
is of such a quantity that it would impel the body through a distance D B
f„^V f u./- n^fciur- M
.
? in the time corresponding to AD . Such an identification would, of course,
*: ' ' T V ’T have been false, since the conatus is finite while the deviation D B is very
% uf- juJArv-u*^ Ai0lA / r </)T,
small. Nor was there any call to consider the actual relation between the
deviation and the conatus, since the constancy of the latter made it
a.1 34 T«; /M' jk .;„■ «» C-t«
possible to deduce the distance moved in any finite time given the dis­
^ e . 0A'--»/4 -
tance moved in the ‘time’ AD . This was sufficient for comparing the
;^ at.O . 2/tf ^ .2 ^ ) ' /l3£/( ’ ..I w " ^
/• #<4-^iCii*, (rr%»jlfii«.^^ 4 . . 4» . ft...
magnitude of the conatus to that of any other constant force, such as the
/V^ \ ' s.v^Mi-swrf - V , ' ^%n4u^ force of gravity, or the conatus of some other circular motion. But this
* ‘1 ^f.r-
fTi'fc'% ■ f Ca^Oi-ivtf WtWi^Pt' O. Ci«.i^ method of comparing forces by the distances moved in a finite interval
3'WlHfi*P^-Hf. of time no longer applied in the problem of Kepler-motion owing to the
variation in the magnitude of the force acting on the body.
Wct^«4 ; ^ The derivation of the law of centrifugal force represented the most
a. «*Jrr 4 »Ut 4 w i ^ ; #* 9tx important achievement of Newton’s early researches in dynamics. It
^vn.0<u0 JUH,‘9!o4»*Ufff A'/^ff'Ujt Am pW b<^<^SJ^
was particularly important in two respects; in the first place it made
^y». ^vr- |XC» tf’ i«t Ht *mAc ^r\A^ f*^
possible his derivation of the inverse square law of gravitation via
plliS^S 1 ^ -it^ :-t*t . ft^u»,'ii! ■ifck
Kepler’s third law and its test against the moon’s motion. Lacking any
i'lif **A pTAM-im. 9 c4>t3M»i. p\APg4'
direct documentary evidence of this test one cannot be entirely certain
\ficCA»*t ^»^*“# **‘ that it did take place, but there is a considerable amount of indirect
i <- v4 - ci>kUt *C 4 rmL evidence largely consistent with this possibility.^ In the second place,
•\i,\‘ fjrrpYPL »•» ' tL «* «<tvts prte>9^^’<n. . ^ the long process leading from the first tentative approach to the problem
^ , ^#itC '**. <jjt4n.*i^ A. u.l~ i|rt. “# • of circular motion to the final derivation of the law of centrifugal force
must have provided Newton with invaluable experience in the dynamical
*A oMiWy t\4 npfi^ , .!,< .CM^m
treatment of motion in a curved path. Lacking this experience of
/k !-> "*'” 7 <f^ «i* / z y SVA' ffi ^4 ^x 5
)«#/*f. <9 i g0 S s ^ 'if^ M k v r^ k 4 i a tv v r i ^ circular motion at the time of Hooke’s intervention in 1679, is per­
iSfi t J J^C 0 i j 4 ikmk'a^ J*tf^/r^Sk i i K et^ l^ haps rather unlikely that he would then have been able to solve the
• • .i l I iA jk c ktUkg pnffirrL'0n.^ »^ *) * vastly more difficult problem of motion in an ellipse.^

A page from an early Newton manuscript on circular motion (MS. IVa) ' But see below, Chapter 3, p. 62. ^ See below, Chapter 4.
^ Assuming that Newton first solved the problem o f Kepler-motion synthetically
rather than analytically. See n. 2, p. 17, below for a discussion of the possibility of an
original analytic?.! solution.
14 M AIN LINE OF DEVEL OPM EN T OF 1.3 1.3 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 15
torium in 1673. In his letter of thanks to Huygens he refers* to the use­
1.3. T he S olution to the P roblem of K epler- M otion
fulness of the formulae relating to centrifugal force given (without
The precise dating of the various elements of the early researches will proof) at the end of that work, instancing a notion of his own that the
probably always remain a matter of speculation. But it seems likely that invariable aspect of the moon from the Earth was due to the greater
the first test of the law of gravitation against the moon’s motion took conatus of its motion relative to the Earth compared with that relative
place at Woolsthorpe in the summer or autumn of i666d and that New­ to the sun. This revival of interest, however, must have been at most
ton’s return to Cambridge in the following spring marked the end of the short-lived, and if any more extensive work in dynamics was contem­
first period of his creative work in dynamics. There follows a long break plated it remained unfulfilled. Newton, as we know, was at this time
in the story from 1667 to 1679 during which there is no evidence of any heavily engaged in defending his publication in optics against Hooke
further development in Newton’s dynamical thought.^ Brewster sup­ and others.2 And the animosity, ill will, and misunderstanding to which
posed that this apparent loss of interest in the subject resulted from his the controversy on light gave rise left him with a strong, almost patholo­
gical, aversion to ever publishing anything in ‘philosophy’ again and even
disappointment at the failure of the first test,3 but it seems more prob­
with some aversion to the subject itself. For example, in 1675 we find
able that it was due simply to the renewal of his optical researches and
Collins complaining in a letter^ to a friend that Barrow and Newton were
the consequent total absorption even of all Newton’s creative scientific
so busy with chemical experiments that they had no time for mathematics
energy. In any case, it is hardly surprising that these early researches in
(and, by implication, philosophy). So that Newton’s statement^ that for
dynamics should have been followed by a long gap of years during which
some years previous to 1679 he had been endeavouring ‘to bend himself
his interest in the subject lay almost entirely dormant. For one can
from philosophy to other studies’ may have been very close to the truth.
regard it as the inevitable working of a mind so deeply intuitive as
If Newton had died before December 1679 he would have held today
Newton’s, an infallible index of genius of the rarest kind, that this in­
a very high place in science for his researches in light and mathematics.
tensely difficult and creative work in dynamics should have been fol­
But the researches into dynamics and gravitation on which his popular
lowed by a long fallow period during which the experience gained in the
fame largely (and perhaps justly) rests would never have been made, and
early researches could be quietly and unhurriedly absorbed and assimi­
his early researches in dynamics would have been either entirely ignored
lated. So that when the time was ripe, at the height of his powers, with
or regarded today as of antiquarian interest only. On the 27 November
a mind purged by the most intense emotional experience of his life,
1679 he returned to Cambridge after an absence of almost six months,
he could turn, at Hooke’s prompting, to the supreme problem of
much the longest since his return in 1667 after the plague. His mother
elliptical motion and find ready to hand just those tools needed to carry
had died in the preceding May or June.s She had caught a fever when
the work through to a final conclusion.
nursing her other son Benjamin Smith at Stamford Bridge and Newton
It is possible, however, that Newton’s interest in dynamics revived
had hurried to her side to nurse her him self.After his mother’s death the
temporarily some years before Hooke’s intervention in 1679 following
‘ See relevant extract of New ton’s letter of 23 June 1673 to Huygens at M S . V ila .
the receipt of his presentation copy of Huygens’s Horologium Oscilla- ^ See More [i], Chapter 4.
3 See para. 4 of Collins’s letter of 19 October 1675 to James Gregory reproduced in
Rigaud [2], vol. ii, p. 280.
’ See below, Chapter 6.2.
In his letter of 28 November 1679 to Hooke.
2 M S . V may well have been completed in this period. But it contains no new
5 According to the records of Colsterworth Parish (as reported by T u m o r [i]) a Mrs.
developments important for New ton’s later researches in dynamics apart from the
Hannah Smith was buried there on 4 June 1679. In all probability this was New ton’s
separation of the law for composition of motions from that for resolution of velocity. mother, nee Hannah Ayscough, who married (secondly) Barnabas Smith in 1645.
Also the treatment of the problem of the collision of two rotating bodies in §§9, 10 ^ Conduitt (K M S 130(8) Library, K in g ’s College, Cambridge) describes how
must be regarded as the natural completion of the study of collisions in the Waste Book. Newton ‘ attended her with a true filial pity, sate up whole nights with her, gave her all
T h is problem played no part in New ton’s later researches in dynamics. Its importance her physick himself, dressed all her blisters with his own hands, and made use of that
lies rather in the brilliant example it provides of his genius in dynamics. manual dexterity for which he was so remarkable to lessen the pain which always
^ Brewster [i], vol. i, p. 26, no doubt on the authority of Whiston and Pemberton who accompanied the dressing (the torturing remedy usually applied in that distemper) with
both state that this was the reason for Newton laying aside his researches on gravitation as much readiness as he ever had employed it in the most delightful experiments’.
at this time.
16 M AIN LINE OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.3 1.3 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 17
whole business of winding up and settling her estate devolved on Newton towards the sun, varying inversely as the square of the distance there­
who had thus no time ‘to entertain philosophical meditations, or so from. In this respect, if in no other, our sympathies are entirely with
much as to study or mind any thing else but country affairs’.^ Fortunate Newton in his cri de coeur to Halley:
Newton, that he could thus escape all creative intellectual thought for Now is this not very fine ? Mathematicians, that find out, settle, and do all
so long a period and return to Cambridge with a mind entirely refreshed. the business, must content themselves with being nothing but dry calculators
For soon after his return he was to be faced by the decisive challenge of and drudges. . . .'
his career. This came about, as it were by chance, as a result of the cele­ What is possibly Newton’s first solution to the problem of Kepler-
brated letter of the 24 November from Robert Hooke. motion is found in Prop, i and 3 of MS. VIH.^ Before attempting to
The ensuing correspondence between Newton and Hooke is well estimate the magnitude of the force he would need to have known its
known thanks to the fortunate recovery of all the letters and to the writ­ direction, so that he probably discovered Prop, i first. Dynamically the
ings of Rouse Ball,2 Pelseneer,^ and Koyre.^ Here we are concerned only proof of this proposition rests on the notion of replacing the actual
with Newton’s famous ‘imagination’ of an experiment to discover the * Postscript to New ton’s letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley.
2 See below, Chapter 6.6, for a discussion of the status of this manuscript.
diurnal motion of the Earth.s In the light of other evidence^ it then seems Account must also be taken of the possibility that New ton’s first solution to the prob­
certain that it was Hooke’s criticism of the spiral path proposed by lem of Kepler-motion was analytic rather than synthetic. This would seem to be implied
by the well-known passage in the Portsmouth D raft Memorandum : ‘By this M ethod I in­
Newton for the falling body which revived Newton’s interest in dyna­ vented the Demonstration of K epler’s Proposition in the year 1679, and almost all the
mics, and this time so thoroughly that he went on to construct the two rest of the Difficulter Propositions of the Book of Principles in the years 1684, 1685,
and part of the year 1686.’ T h e M ethod in question has usually been assumed to be that
propositions corresponding to Kepler’s first and second laws, probably
of the fluxions, for example by Rouse Ball (Ball [i], p. 7). But it must be remembered
before the end of December 1679. that the Portsmouth D raft Memorandum was most probably written after the outbreak
When Newton first gave his entire attention to the problem of motion of the controversy with Leibniz over the Calculus, so that any references in it to the
Method of Fluxions have to be taken with some reserve. T h e potentially most reliable
in an ellipse one thing, at least, would have been clear to him; a body, a indication of the actual method employed b y Newton is contained in his letter of 14 July
planet, could only trace out so unnatural, non-inertial a path as an 1686 to Halley. There he states: ‘T h is is true, that his letters occasioned m y finding the
method of determining figures, which when I had tried in the ellipsis, I threw the calcu­
ellipse under the constant action of a force. What was so difficult was to lation by, being upon other studies; and so it rested for about five years, till upon your
determine the direction and magnitude of this force at every point of request I sought for that paper; and not finding it, did it again, and reduced it into the
propositions shewed you by M r. Paget.’ Unfortunately the first vital part of this passage
the ellipse. He may, of course, have had some preliminary notions of the is ambiguous. I f the method referred to was the analytical method for determining
answers to these questions. He may have believed, or guessed, that the figures sketched out in principle in Prop. 41 of Book I of the Principia, then he should
have stated that he tried it on the inverse square law instead of the ellipse. On the other
force on a planet was entirely directed to the sun. He may also have hand, if he was referring to Prop. 6, Theor. 5, by means of -which given the figure the cen­
expected that the magnitude of the force would vary inversely with the tripetal force for any curve (including the ellipse) may be calculated in principle, then he
should have used the phrase method of determining forces. Lacking any documentary
square of the distance.'^' But there w^as a world of difference between
evidence we can therefore only surmise the actual method employed. I think it is
guessing the answers to these questions and proving them. T o Newton entirely possible that Newton did develop the method of determining figures in 1679.
was given the privilege of proving that on the basis of Kepler’s laws On the other hand, there is no reliable evidence that he either then or later proved in
detail that an inverse square law would lead to a conic, with an ellipse as one particular
it necessarily followed that the force on any planet was entirely directed case. A nd in fact if he had done so, then it is rather surprising that he did not give this
case as a corollary to Prop. 41, Book I, Principia. It is possibly significant that in the
* Letter of 28 November 1679 to Hooke.
much simpler case of an inverse cube force referred to in Corollary 3 of that proposition
2 Ball [i], Chapter 3. 3 Pelseneer [i]. ^ Koyre [2].
no details are given of the actual orbit. And this remains true for the justification pro­
3 T h e relevant passage from New ton’s letter of 28 November 1679 to Hooke is
vided for that corollary by Newton to David Gregory at the time of the latter’s visit to
reproduced at M S . V H c.
Cambridge in 1694. See Correspondence, vol. iii, pp. 348-9. Possibly relevant too is
^ Especially New ton’s statement in his letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley: ‘This is true,
the well-known detail in Conduitt (see Ball [i], p. 26) that New ton’s failure to reproduce
that his [Hooke’s] letters occasioned m y finding the method of determining figures,
his original proof after H alley’s departure was due to his having drawn the axes of
which when I had tried in the ellipsis, I threw the calculation b}", being upon other
an ellipse ‘instead of two conjugate diameters somewhat inclined to one another’. This
studies.’
must surely have referred to a synthetic proof. So that whether or not he achieved
7 A possibility suggested by Bullialdus, and referred to specifically by Newton in the
an analytic proof in 1679, he would seem at least to have achieved a synthetic one.f
postscript of his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley. For the passage on the inverse square
law see Bullialdus [i], p. 23. f See additional note, on p. 34.
18 MAIN LINE OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.3 1.3 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H l ' 19
continuously varying force by a series of equally spaced sharp impulses. the impulses which turns its motion into the chord P F , Y being the
The actual path is then replaced by a polygon made up of the rectilinear, point on the ellipse reached in time A^. The distance X F , having been
inertial, motions of the body between successive impulses. Given the generated by the impulse at P, must therefore be proportional, and
initial velocity of the body the first impulse will turn it sharply into a parallel, thereto. The same will be true for any other set of points^, x, y.
determinate new direction, and the position at the end of the first inter­ From this it follows that the force at P ; force at p ~ X Y : xy. By
val of time is then given by the beautiful construction based implicitly application of certain geometrical properties of the ellipse together with
on the law of composition of independent motions enunciated in Hypo­ the fact that the rate of description of area is constant, so that A P Y F =
thesis 3. The position of the body at successive instants then follows in ApyF, it follows that the ratio of the forces at P and p will be inversely
precisely the same way and the proof is completed by the passage to the as PF^ to pF-.
limit of vanishingly small intervals of time. From the dynamical point of view the new element in Prop. 3 com­
The development of the law of composition of motions is considered pared with Prop. I rests in the assumption that the deviation gives a
elsewhere^ and nothing need be said of the use of the principle of direct measure of the varying force of attraction. It will be convenient to
inertia— this could confidently have been predicted a priori. But the examine this assumption later in the light of the slightly different use of
replacement of the continuously acting force by a series of equally spaced the deviation in the tract de Motu, the lectures de Motu, and the first
impulses calls for comment. At first sight this recalls the original poly­ edition of the Principia. One other feature of the proof calls for com­
gonal treatment of circular motion,^ the impulses in the present treat­ ment: the peculiar mixture of tangents and chords. In reality this invali­
ment corresponding to the discrete ‘forces of reflection’ in the former. dates the claim that the motions will be along the chord P F , and then
In reality, there is a great difference between the two problems. In the along the next chord, and so on. For the motion along P F resulted from
first it was the circle which was given, the ‘forces of reflection’ arising the impulse at P acting on the inertial motion along the tangent at that
from the impacts at the corners of the inscribed polygon. Now it was point. Whereas when the body reaches F it will be moving along the
the force (and therefore the impulses) which was given as a function of chord. Of course, the difference between the tangent and the chord is
the time, the polygonal approximation to the actual path being then very small and ultimately disappears in the limit. But to remove this
determined in terms of the initial position and velocity of the body. In difference beforehand would abolish the deviation X Y and with it the
fact, this step-wise development of the approximate path given the force proof itself. The process envisaged by Newton can therefore only be
as a function of the time represents the first example of the determinacy applied, if at all, to individual points of the ellipse. So that the analogy
of Newtonian dynamics. between the method adopted in this proposition and that in the first is
From Kepler’s second law and the converse of Prop, i it then followed more apparent than real. Newton could have followed another more
that the force on the planet was entirely directed towards the sun. New­ consistent method based on a thoroughgoing use of a polygonal approxi­
ton was thus free to take up the problem of the motion of a body in an mation. This will be discussed later when considering the whole
ellipse under the action of a force directed to one of the foci. His solution question of his use of deviation as a measure of force.
to this problem is contained in Prop. 3 of MS. V III. As in Prop, i he In the first and later versions of the tract de Motu^ the propositions
replaces the continuous force of attraction to the focus by a series of corresponding to Kepler’s second and first laws of planetary motion
focally directed sharp impulses separated by a constant interval of time reappear as Prop, i and Prob. 3, Prop. 3, respectively. The proof of
A^, the corresponding positions of the body on the ellipse being P, Y Prop. I follows on exactly the same lines as Prop, i of MS. V III. As to
(MS. V III, Fig. 6) etc. If the force of attraction were suddenly to cease the inverse square law for motion in an ellipse under a force directed to
when the body is at P, it would continue its inertial path along the one focus, Newton now derives it as a special case of the general formula
tangent reaching a point X in time Af. Instead it is acted on by one of for centripetal force for motion in any curved path given in Prop. 3. Only
this proposition need be considered since it contains all the dynamical
* See below, § 4 of present chapter, section on Corollary i to laws of motion,
2 See above, § 2 of present chapter. I M S . IX .
20 MAIN LINE OF DEVEL OPM EN T OF 1.3 1.3 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 21
arguments, the special mathematical arguments appropriate to an P equal to the corresponding impulse will be FpAt so that the correct
ellipse being concentrated in Prob. 3. equation should read
Once again the force at any point P of the curve is calculated in terms X Y j A t oc FpAt,
of the deviation. But now both the curve and the force are regarded as
i.e. X Y oc Fp{At)\
continuous throughout and the deviation found by drawing a line parallel
to S P (MS. IX, Fig. 3) through a point O close to P cutting at R the However, since the interval At is everywhere the same, a comparison
tangent to the curve at P. RQ is then the deviation. For a given small between any two points of the ellipse gives
interval of time between P and O, R Q will be proportional to the
XY _Fp
magnitude of the actual force, Pp, at P ; and for a given force it will be
xy ~ F p '
proportional to AP. S o that altogether
Fp{Aty, Newton’s measure of the impulse in terms of the deviation thus in­
evitably led him to the correct result for the force. By removing the
i.e. oc RQ/(Aty.
double use of chords and tangents the whole proof can then be placed
The actual result given then follows in the limit assuming the constancy on an entirely satisfactory basis. Imagine the given ellipse divided up by
of description of area about the centre of force S. a large but finite number of points reached at equal small intervals of
In the lectures de Motu^ and the first edition of the Principia the time. It may then be asked; what set of focally directed impulses at these
derivation of the inverse square law exactly follows those in the various points will enable the body to describe this polygon ? The process is now
versions of the tract de Motu apart from a marginal reference to the similar to that considered in the ‘polygonal’ treatment of circular motion;
second law of motion in justification of the assumption that the deviation but whereas in the latter case the body can obviously follow a regular
is proportional to the force acting. inscribed polygon indefinitely as a result of continued reflections at the
The central role of deviation in Newton’s treatment of force for corners, now the motion in the polygon will only persist if the impulses
motion in a curved path is now sufficiently evident. He first used it in his at the corners are arranged so as to be of exactly the right magnitude and
second, deviational, treatment of circular motion, and then modified it to direction— there is no question of the body being reflected naturally at
derive the inverse square law for Kepler-motion. Thereafter it reappeared the surface of the containing ellipse. T o find the magnitude of these
in his rather different derivation of the same result in the tract de Motu, impulses— corresponding to the ‘forces of reflection’ in the case of the
the lectures de Motu, and the first edition of the Principia. In each case circle— it is then only necessary to calculate the change in velocity at
Newton’s handling of the deviation was superb and always led to the each corner; and it follows easily that for a given point P this is propor­
right result. But the arguments advanced in its support seemed less tional to X Y j A t , thus leading to the same result as before though now
compelling and call for a critical examination. by an entirely unobjectionable method.
There were two unsatisfactory elements in Prop. 3 of MS. V III. The Viewed in this light Newton’s own proof appears as a peculiar mixture
first was the simultaneous use of chords and tangents. This invalidated of the polygonal (the chord) and deviational (the tangent) methods used
the continuous process envisaged and really necessitated a new argument in his two early treatments of circular motion. It likewise contains a
at each point of the ellipse. Next there was the assumption that the devia­ peculiar mixture of the discrete (the impulses) and the continuous (the
tion, being generated by the force (impulse) at P, would be proportional, accelerative force). Though it appears to be a deviational proof, it is in
and parallel, to the force. This was justified by an appeal to Hypothesis 2 fact much closer to a polygonal treatment in terms of which it derives its
that ‘the alteration of motion is ever proportional to the force by which true justification. The success of this proof in spite of its deficiencies
it is altered’. But the motion generated by the impulse at P is propor­ could be regarded as an indication that Newton was confident beforehand
tional to the velocity generated rather than the displacement, that is to what the correct result should be; but it could also be regarded as one of
X Y j A t as opposed to X Y . If then we set the actual accelerative force at the best examples of his intuitive grasp of dynamical processes.
> M S . X I.
22 MAIN LINE OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.3 1.4 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 23
Newton’s use of deviation in Prop. 3 of the tract de Motu and the cor­ his first successful test of the law of gravitation against the moon’s
responding propositions of the lectures de Motu and the first edition of motion is possibly relevant here. If this was made in 1679, as stated by
the Principia remains to be considered. Here there is no trace of impulses Pemberton, I then his loss of interest at this point would almost seem to
and polygons. Both the path and the force are regarded as continuous argue an inability to appreciate the importance and significance of his
throughout. The assumption deviation oc (A^)^ for a given force is en­ own discoveries. On the other hand, the fact that Pemberton’s account
tirely justified. The deviation is now the distance moved away from the is probably erroneous in another respect^ gives us leave to doubt the
inertial path under the action of a force effectively constant in the given veracity of his account in regard to the date of the test of the inverse
small interval of time. Likewise the assumption that the deviation will be square law. And if this test actually took place later, most probably in
proportional to the magnitude of the force given the small interval of 1684,3 the lull between 1679 and 1684, though still puzzling, becomes
time This is obviously true, being the same proportionality argu­ much less incomprehensible. Another possibility to be considered is
ment used in the early researches though now extended to the action of that Newton was held up in 1679 through an inability to prove that a
variable forces in very small intervals of time. But the justification of this gravitating sphere attracts external particles as though all its mass were
assumption in the lectures de Motu and the first edition of the Principia by concentrated at its centre. But against this we know that he certainly
an appeal to the second law is less satisfactory. For the second law of was not prevented from composing the tract de Motu in 1684 by the lack
motion concerns the motive force and the change in motion, whereas of the same proposition.^
now it is a matter of the accelerative force and the distance moved. This The remainder of the traditional account is well known.s How Halley
epitomizes a certain confusion in Newton’s thought between the two kinds visited Newton at Cambridge in August 1684 to inquire what figure a
of force, motive and accelerative. It was unfortunate that his second body would describe under an inverse square law of force. How he was
law referred to the former while his calculations always concerned the overjoyed to learn that Newton knew the answer and had dXxQzdyproved
latter. The use of the versed sine in place of the deviation in the second it. And how Newton, being unable to find the original proof, promised
and third editions of the Principia may possibly indicate that he himself to rework the solution and send it to Halley at the Royal Society, which
felt a certain dissatisfaction with his use of the latter concept, especially promise was then fulfilled in November of the same year when Paget
in the crucial theorem on the general expression for force for motion in carried the proposition or propositions in question from Cambridge to
a curved path. Curiously, however, his justification of versed sine as a London. Finally, the registration at the Royal Society, some time before
measure of force appears in Coroll. IV of Prop, i, and therefore depends February 1685, of Newton’s Propositiones de Motu followed by the pub­
on a polygonal rather than a continuous treatment, that is on the im­ lication of the Principia in 1687.
pulse rather than the actual force. From this impasse there was no escape So much has generally been agreed to. Opinions, however, have
except through a thoroughgoing application of the differential calculus. differed on the exact nature of the propositions carried by Paget to
London, and on their connexion with the tract de Motu, the lectures de
1.4. T he F inal S ynthesis of N e w t o n ’s D ynam ical Motu of the Michaelmas term 1684, and the propositions de Motu regis­
S ystem tered at the Royal Society. There is also the possibility that the marginal
Newton’s construction of the propositions corresponding to Kepler’s entry ‘Octob 1684/Lect. i ’ in MS. X I was added considerably later
first two laws of planetary motion represented his most important single and should have read ‘Octob 1685/Lect. i ’,^ and that the actual contents
achievement in dynamics and the very cornerstone of the Principia. ' Pemberton [i], Preface. ^ See below, Chapter 4, p. 75.
How then explain his apparent loss of interest in dynamics again until ^ A s suggested below, Chapter 4, p. 75.
* In his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley Newton stated: ‘ I never extended the
1684? Later he said himself that ‘he threw the calculations by being on duplicate proportion lower than to the superficies of the earth, and before a certain
other studies’ I and certainly there must have been much else to claim demonstration I found the last year, have suspected it did not reach accurately down so
low'.’ T h e demonstration in question was presumably the proposition referred to here.
his attention after so long an absence from Cambridge. The question of 5 See, for example. Ball [i]. Chapter 4.
' New ton’s letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley. See below'. Chapter 6.4, pp. 98-102.
24 M AIN LINE OF DEV ELOPMENT OF 1.4 1.4 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 25
of these lectures were considerably different from the text given in bulk, or size.^ At this stage no consideration is given to bodies of equal
M S .X I.i size but different mass. So that it is tacitly assumed that all the bodies
However, the available evidence seems to point fairly unambiguously considered are of the same material. Earlier drafts of the enunciation of
to the following course of events in 1684 and early 1685. After Halley’s this definition are found in Def. i of MS. Xb and in Def. i of the original
first visit to Newton at Cambridge, most probably in May 1684,2 and not and revised versions of MS. XI. These are all essentially the same as the
in August as generally supposed, Newton reconstructed the two missing final enunciation, the differences between the total definitions residing
propositions and then added a number of new ones. The result was largely in the explanatory passages following the enunciations. Here we
Version I of the tract de Motu probably composed by the end of July find a smooth progress towards the final definition, the first references
1684.^ Version II of this tract, a fair copy of Version I, was later sent to to the possibility of freely pervading medium and to the experimentally
Halley in fulfilment of Newton’s original promise of May.^ But for confirmed proportionality between weight and quantity of matter
some reason or other, possibly connected with his fear of Hooke’s re­ occurring in the revised version of MS. X I. A brief discussion of the
actions, he at first held it up. Instead he pushed on with his researches, the use of pendulum experiments to prove this proportionality oecurs at
result being Version III of the tract. Following Halley’s second (or third) Def. II of MS. Xa, followed by a much fuller discussion at Def. 7 of
visit in November he sent Version II of the tract to London via Paget. MS. Xb where the use oipondus as an alternative to quantity of matter
The Propositiones de Motu entered in the Register Book of the Royal or mass, even in the absence of any gravitational effects, is brought out
Society some time before 23 February 1685 were copied from this paper. much more elearly than in the Principia. Rather surprisingly a clear
There seems some doubt whether the so-called lectures de Motu of indication of weight-mass proportionality is found already at § 5 of
1684 were actually read in the Michaelmas term 1684 as opposed to MS. I.
1685; but what is in any case certain is that up to the beginning of Newton’s definition of mass or quantity of matter has occasioned con­
Section I of Book I of the Principia these lectures (MS. XI) contain an siderable controversy.2 Mach ,3 for example, found the definition un­
original version which, as emended in the manuscript itself, agrees almost fortunate in that it involved a circular argument, density itself being
exactly with the first edition of the Principia of which it must be re­ defined by the mass per unit of volume. Crew,^ on the other hand, main­
garded as the final draft. Also that Versions I and III of the tract de tained that in Newton’s age density was synonymous with specific
Motu and M SS. Xa, b^ enable us to follow in very considerable detail the gravity, so that it was reasonable for Newton to define quantity of matter
creation of this part of the original version of the lectures de Motu, and in terms of it. In this case, however, the proportionality between quantity
thus of the corresponding part of the Principia. In other words they enable of matter and weight would necessarily follow, whereas in Def. i of the
us to follow the creation of the final synthesis of Newton's dynamical system. Principia Newton asserts that this proportionality has been proved by
This process will now be studied in detail following the actual order in experiment. Mach’s criticism was therefore justified; there was an essen­
the Principia itself. Wherever possible reference will be made to the appear­ tial circularity involved in Newton’s definition of quantity of matter in
ance of particular concepts in the earlier manuscripts, thus stressing the terms of density, and this is fully borne out by Def. 6 of MS. Xb where
striking element of continuity between the earlier and later researches. density is said to be proportional to the quantity of matter and the
volume conjointly. Further confirmation for this view is provided by the
D efinitions
passage towards the end of the second paragraph of Def. 13 of MS. VI
1. Quantity of matter where Newton sets the weight (gravitas) of a body equal to its size (molis)
In the early manuscripts, especially in the Waste Book, the term multiplied by its specific gravity.
quantity or body refers indiscriminately both to a body and its magnitude, However, this flaw in the definition of quantity of matter in no way
* A s suggested in a private communication by D . T. Whiteside.
’ See, for example, M S . lie , Def. 1-3.
2 See below, Chapter 6.4, p. 97. ^ Ibid., p. 97.
^ See, for example, Cajori [2], p. 638, n. i i .
* See below. Chapter 6.5, pp. 105-8.
^ M ach [i], p. 188. * Crew [i], p. 124.
® For the order of composition of these manuscripts see below, Chapter 6.3.
26 MAIN LIN E OF DEVEL OPMENT OF 1.4 1.4 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L TH O U G H T 27
interfered with the development of Newton’s thought in the Principia, Identical definitions are given in the other Versions of the tract,
for when he had to compare the quantities of matter of two bodies he
MS. Xa, Def. 12
did so by making an appeal to his second law of motion. ^It is this law,
Corporis vis insita innata et essentialis est potentia qua id perseverat in statu
therefore, rather than Def. i, which must be regarded as giving the real,
suo quiescendi vel movendi uniformiter in linea recta, estque corporis quantitati
operational definition of mass in Newton’s dynamics. proportionalis, exercetur vero proportionaliter mutationem status et quatenus
As to the original development of the concept, we can be confident that exercetur did potest corporis vis exercita . . . una species est vis centrifuga gyran-
the obvious fact of inertia, or Vis Insita, would inevitably have led tium.
Newton to attach a measure to it. For example, collision experiments Ibid., Def. 13, cancelled
with bodies of equal size, but of different material, revealed that the
Vis motus seu corpori ex motu sua adventitia est qua corpus quantitatem totam
inertias of such bodies were not entirely determined by their sizes. Two
sui motus conservare conatur. Ea vulgo dicitur impetus estque motuiproportionalis,
bodies of equal size could have quite different capacities to sustain their et pro genere motus vel ahsoluta est vel relativa.
states of rest or motion. That he then attempted to give a definition of
MS. Xb, Def. 3
mass independently of the second law was understandable, though per­
haps a trifle unfortunate. Materiae vis insita est potentia resistendi qua corpus unumquodque quantum in
se est perseverat in statu suo vel quiescendi vel movendi uniformiter in directum:
2 . Quantity of motion estque corpori suo proportionalis neque dijfert quicquam ah inertia massae nisi in
modo conceptus nostri. Exercet vero corpus hanc vim solummodo in mutatione
An equivalent definition is found first in Defs. 2, 3 of the Waste Book status sui facta per vim aliam in se impressam. . . .
(MS. lie), where the same explanation is given in terms of the motions
MS. X I (Original Version), Def, 5
of the separate parts of the body. Earlier drafts of the definition in the
This version differs from that immediately above only in the replace­
Principia are found at Def. i i of MS. Xa, Def. 2 of MS. Xb, and Def. 4
ment of conceptus nostri by concipiendi at the end of the first sentence,
of the original version of MS. XI.
and the introduction of the following two sentences immediately after­
3 . Innate force or inertia of a body wards :
Per inertiam materiae fit ut corpus omne de statu suo vel quiescendi vel movendi
The origin of this concept went back at least to MS. VI, where it is difficultate deturhetur. Unde etiam vis insita nomine significantissimo vis inertiae
clearly referred to under the heading of force in Def. 5 as ‘motus et did possit.
quietis causale principium' or
The version in the first edition of the Principia differs in no important
internum principium quo motus vel quies corpori insita conservatur, et quodlibet respect from that in the lectures de Motu.
ens in suo statu perseverare conatur et impeditum reluctatur A cursory examination of these definitions reveals nothing of par­
or in Def. 8 of the same work as ticular interest beyond the obvious identity of the various terms vis
insita, vis corporis, vis inertiae, or inertia. Admittedly, there is the quali­
Inertia est vis interna corporis ne status ejus externa vi illata facile mutetur. fication of this force from MS. Xa onwards as a power by which the
inertial state of rest or motion is maintained, and from MS. Xb onwards
The first formal definition of Vis Insita occurs in Version I of the
this power becomes a power of resistance. But a closer examination
tract de Motu. This and later definitions are listed below:
of Newton’s description of the circumstances under which this power is
MS. IXa, Def. 2 exercised reveals a remarkable transition in his view of vis insita or
Et vim corporis seu corpori insitam [appello] qua id conatur perseverare in motii inertia. Up to and including MS. Xa this is the force or power by virtue
suo secundum lineam rectam. of which a body maintains its inertial state of rest or motion; in vulgar
‘ See, for example, Principia, Book III, Section V I, Prop. 24, Theor. 18. parlance, the impetus of the body, as noted in Def. 13 of MS. Xa.
28 M AIN LINE OF DEV ELOPMENT OF 1.4 1.4 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 29
That this was Newton’s actual belief is confirmed by the corresponding Scholium to definitions
enunciations of the principle of inertia, each of which contains a refer­ The first reference to space in the later manuscripts occurs at Law 3
ence to vis insita. In MS. Xa occurs the first hint of an impending of Version III of the tract de Motu. Another reference in the same work
transition in his thought. There he states that the vis insita is exercised is found in the addendum (compared with Version I) to the Scholium to
in proportion to the change in state. In MS. Xb the transition is com­ Theorem 4. The first formal definitions of absolute and relative space
plete. Now the vis insita is exercised only (solummodo) in changes of and time occur in Def. 1-4 of MS. Xa. In Def. 7, 9 of the same manu­
state. It would seem, therefore, to have been relegated to a species of script occur rudimentary drafts of the definitions of place and absolute
potential force, having no effect as long as the state of rest or of uniform motion in MS. XI. Definition 9 above also contains the germ of the
motion continued, being called into action only in changes of state. That methods for distinguishing between relative and absolute motions in­
this was indeed Newton’s new view of the matter is proved conclusively cluding that depending on centrifugal effects. There is no indication of
by the absence of any reference to vis insita in the enunciation of the later expansions of these early drafts, the version in the original of
principle of inertia from M S. Xb onwards. In these manuscripts we there­ MS. X I being effectively identical with that in the Principia.
fore have before us the record of how Newton, on reflection, freed himself Much has been written of the metaphysieal views on absolute space
from what was apparently his previous, essentially medieval belief in (and time) expressed in the Scholium to the Definitions of Book I of
the necessity of some interior force or impetus to maintain an inertial the Principia^ especially in the light of the Leibniz-Clarke controversy.^
state of uniform motion. From now on such a state of motion (or rest) A beginning has also been made by Fiersz^ to the study of the influences
was a true state in the Cartesian sense, entirely self-sufficient, and the which went to shape these views. The discovery of MS. Add. 4003
principle of inertia a true principle, something which had to be regarded provides important material which will make possible a new approach to
as given, a natural fact, having no explanation and requiring none. the question of the early influences on Newton’s metaphysical outlook
in general, and those on space in particular. This study, however, will
4 . Impressed force only be possible in the light of a detailed commentary of MS. Add.
Earlier drafts of this definition are found at Def. 15 of MS. Xa, Def. 4003 against the total philosophical background about the period
4 of MS. Xb, and Def. VI of MS. XI. The qualification that the impressed 1660-70.3
force consists in the action only appears first in MS. Xb, and the refer­ Laws of motion
ence to the force of motion in MS. XI. First law. This law, inherited by Newton from Galileo and Descartes,-^
formed the central element of his dynamical thought and method.
5-8 Centripetal force Fortunately it is well documented, appearing in some form or other in
Significantly, the term centripetal as opposed to centrifugal is not most of the major documents throughout the period 1664-84. The
found in the early dynamical manuscripts. It occurs first at Def. i of various expressions given to the principle by Newton in these manuscripts
Version I of the tract de Motu, and in identical form at Def. i of Version are listed below.
III of the same work. Thereafter it recurs in identical form at Def. 16 MS. II, Ax. I , 2.
of MS. Xa apart from the addition of the examples of this force given If a quantity once moves it will never rest unless hindered by some external
in Def. 5 of the Principia. At Def. 5 of MS. Xb the division into three cause
distinct quantities absolute, accelerative and motive first occurs, while in and
MS. X I (original and final versions) these different quantities are assigned a quantity will always move on in the same straight line (not changing the
to separate definitions. ' For a summary account see Alexander [i]. For a more recent discussion see
The definition in the Principia is effectively identical with that in the Toulmin [i]. ^ Fiersz [i].
^ A n excellent beginning to this has now been made by Hall and Hall [i]. See pp. 7 6 -
original version of M S. X I apart from one rather large emendation in 85 of their introduction to text and translation of M S . 4003.
Def. 10 of that manuscript (Def. 8 of Principia). * See below, Chapter 2.
30 MAIN LINE OF DEVELOPMENT OF 1.4 1.4 N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L TH O U G H T 31
celerity or determination of its motion) unless some external cause divert Curiously, there is no reference to the second law in MS. V apart from
it. the statement at the end of § i ‘that the force is equivalent to that motion
MS. II, Ax. 100. which it is able to beget or destroy’. It first reappears as Hypothesis
A body once moved will always keep the same celerity, quantity and deter­ 2 of MS. V III:
mination of its motion.
The alteration of motion is ever proportional to the force by which it is
MS. VI, § 4. altered.
et multo magis quod corporis sine impedimentis nioti velocitas non did potest The presence of this hypothesis is accounted for by Newton’s explicit
uniformis, neque linea recta in qua motus perficitur. use of it in justification of his assumption of proportionality between
MS. V III, Hyp. I. ‘force’ and deviation.
Bodies move uniformly in straight lines unless so far as they are retarded There is no trace of the second law in the first two versions of the
by the resistance of the medium or disturbed by some other force. tract de Motu. But in the third version we find it enunciated in Law 2
MS. IXa, Hyp. 2. as follows:
Corpus omne sola vi insita uniformiter secundum rectam lineam in infinitum Mutationem status movendi vel quiescendi proportionalem esse vi impressae et
progredi nisi aliqiiid extrinsecus impediat. fieri secundum lineam rectam qua vis ilia imprimitur.
MS. IXc, Lex I. It is employed there in the proof of Lemma i, and in Theorem 4 where
Sola vi insita corpus uniformiter in linea recta semper pergere si nil impediat. it ensures that equal forces produce equal deviations (in equal times).
MS. Xa, Lex i. In MS. Xa (Law 2) the enunciation is identical with that given above
Vis insita corpus omne perseverare in statu suo quiescendi vel movendi uni­ apart from the replacement of status movendi vel quiescendi by motus.
formiter in linea recta nisi quatenus viribus impressis cogitur statum ilium mutare. In the same manuscript a reference is added to the use of the first and
MS. XI, Lex I. second laws by Galileo in his derivation of the vertical and parabolic
Corpus omne perseverare in statu suo quiescendi vel movendi uniformiter in motions of bodies under gravity.
directum, nisi quatenus a viribus impressis cogitur statum suum mutare. In the lectures de Motu the law retains the same form as in MS. Xa apart
A noteworthy feature of these enunciations is the absence of any from the introduction of motrici between vi and impressae, and there is
reference to a state of rest as opposed to that of motion until MS. Xa no further change in the Principia.
immediately preceding the lectures de Motii. This represented a closer Third law. The assumption of the equality of action and reaction in
approach to Descartes’s formulation of the principle. The only previous the direct collision between two bodies is found in Def. 7, 8 of the Waste
reference to rest occurs in Def. 5 of MS. VI where force is said to be Book (MS. Hd), and for oblique collisions in Ax. 119, 121 of the same
‘the causal principle of motion or rest’. work (MS. He).
Interesting, too, is the reference to Vis Insita appearing in Versions I There is no trace of this law after its early indication in the Waste
and HI of the tract de Motu and in MS. Xa but absent from later enun­ Book before M S. Xa where it is enunciated as Law 3 in the form:
ciations. A possible explanation of this has already been given above in Corpus omne tantum pati reactione quantum agit in alterum.
the discussion of the genesis of the definition of inertia. Both in MS. X I and in the first edition of the Principia it appears in the
Second law. The germ of this law is found in the early researches. For form:
the definition of force as change in momentum in the Waste Book corre­ Actioni contrariam semper et aequalem esse reactionem: sive, corporum duorum
sponds to the first part of the second law, and the second part corresponds actiones in se mutuo semper esse aequales et in partes contrarias dirigi.
to the statement in the same manuscript that ‘A body must move that The most important use of this law, and undoubtedly one of the rea­
way which it is pressed’.^ sons for its explicit formulation in the lectures de Motu and the Principia,
^ M S . lie , Ax. 120. was its role in the proof of Corollary 3 to the laws of motion.
32 M AIN LINE OF DEVEL O PME NT OF 1.4
1.4 N E W T O N ’ S D Y N A M I C A L TH O U G H T 33
Corollaries to laws of motion
the solar system in the addendum (compared with Version I) to the
Corollary i. It is easy to confuse the dynamical rule for composition Scholium to Theorem 4.
of motions with the kinematical rule for combining two relative velocities The same result appears as Law 5 in MS. Xa, and as Corollary 4 to
or for finding the components of a given velocity in two oblique the laws of motion in MS. X L The proof given in this latter manuscript
directions. Newton himself seems to have fallen into this confusion in the is essentially the same as that in the Principia. In the first part of this
Waste Book where he gives the correct rule for the composition of two proof, that relating to the purely kinematical case in which there are
motions as a corollary (without proof) to an apparently incorrect rule for no collisions between the bodies, an appeal is made to Lemma X X III.
resolving velocity.^ In MS. V this confusion has disappeared. In § 2 of This is the result first proved by Newton at Ax.-Prop. 28 of the Waste
that manuscript he gives a perfectly correct rule for finding the re­ Book (MS. Ilf) for the special case of motion in a plane.
solved part of a given velocity in any oblique direction, followed in § 3 The immediately following Ax.-Prop. 29 provides justification for the
by the rule for composition of motions. His formulation of this rule in claim in the Principia that the result may also be proved in loco solido.
MS. V is potentially of great interest. As suggested in Chapter 2.1 it Corollary 5. This appears first as Law 3 in Version III of the tract de
affords a possible indication of Galileo’s influence on Newton. Motu and then in identical form as Law 4 of MS. Xa apart from the
The same rule appears as Hypothesis 3 of MS. VIII. Now the two addition of the example of motion relative to a ship. In MS. X I and the
motions are on an equal footing— the possible indication of Galileo’s Principia the enunciation is the same as before but now the law has become
influence contained in MS. V having disappeared— and the same is a corollary.
true of the rather obscure formulation in Hypothesis 3 of Version I of the Corollary 6. This first appears in MS. X I and then in identical form
tract de Motu. In Version III of the same work the status of the rule in the Principia.
suddenly changes. Previously it had been a hypothesis, now it has be­
come a lemma (Lemma i) furnished with a proof based implicitly on the Scholium to laws of motion
second law of motion. In MS. Xa it reappears as Lemma i, the enuncia­ The version of this in MS. X I is effectively identical with that in the
tion and proof being effectively identical with those in Version III of Principia. No trace of earlier drafts has been found apart from the inter­
the tract de Motu. The same is true of MS. X I and the Principia apart esting reference to Galileo and the first two laws of motion at the end of
from the change of title from Lemma to Corollary. Law 2 in MS. Xa.
Corollary 2. There is no trace of this corollary before MS. X L Subject
to a substantial emendation of the last three paragraphs this agrees with Method of prime and ultimate ratios
Corollary 2 of the Principia. This method, given immediately after the scholium to the laws of
Corollary 3. This represents Newton’s emended form of Descartes’s motion, formed the final element of Newton’s formal dynamical system
law of conservation of motion. Its probable role in the early develop­ in the Principia. With one important exception to be noted presently
ment of Newton’s dynamical thought has already been noticed in § i of there appear to be no earlier drafts of this section before MS. XI, of
the present chapter. The first formal enunciation occurs in MS. X I which the original version differs substantially from that in the Principia
and is effectively identical with that in the Principia. The outline in the only in the absence of the two corollaries to Lemma X and the final
last paragraph of the method of treatment of the problem of the collision paragraph to the scholium. However, this absence of earlier drafts is
of two non-spherical bodies, with the possibility of rotation arising from of no importance dynamically since the whole section is of purely
the collision, must be read in the light of the detailed solution to this mathematical interest apart from Newton’s generalization of Galileo’s
problem provided by Newton in MS. V. law of falling bodies at Lemma X. In Newton’s early dynamical in­
Corollary 4. This appears first as Law 4 of Version HI of the tract de vestigations this law played a vital role in M SS. I l l and IV. The first
Motu, being employed in the remarkable discussion of the motion of formal enunciation of the generalization of the law to curvilinear motion
I M S. Ilg .
occurs at Hypothesis 4 of Version II of the tract de Motu. In Version HI
858205 D
34 DEV ELOPMEN T OF D Y N A M I C A L T H O U G H T 1.4
of the same work its status has changed from a hypothesis to a Lemma
(Lemma 2), the proof being based on an application of the result that the
area under a velocity-time graph equals the space described. For a proof
T H E I N F L U E N C E OF G A L I L E O A N D
of this result Newton appeals to the authority of Galileo. In MS. Xa
the same enunciation is given at Lemma 2, but the proof has not been D E S C A R T E S ON N E W T O N ’ S D Y N A M I C S
preserved beyond the first few lines. In Lemma X of MS. X I and the
rrincipia the proof is contained largely in the preceding Lemma apart 2.1. T he Influence of G alileo

from the result relating to the space described which is now unsupported I t has always been assumed that Newton was indebted in dynamics
by a reference to the authority of Galileo.’' to Galileo, and this would remain highly probable even in the absence
of any corroborative evidence. For by 1661, the year of Newton’s entry
' Curiously, Newton himself supplies no proof of the result. Since Galileo’s proofs in
the Dialogue and the Discorsi were both defective, being based on the method of in ­ to Cambridge, Galileo’s writings, especially in dynamics, were widely
divisibles, the foundation of the Principia was at this point insecure. It would be in­ known throughout Europe including England, witness the translation
teresting to know when the first published correct proof of the result was given. T h at
given by Beeckman was almost certainly the first in point of time, but it remained un­ of his Dialogue in Tome I of Salusbury’s Mathematical Collections pub­
published till the rediscovery and publication of his Journal by de Waard. P'or Beeck- lished in the same year.
man’s proof see Beeckman [i], vol. i, p. 262.
To my knowledge, the only explicit indication of such an influence
Additional note f to p. l y : in the Principia occurs in the celebrated passage at the beginning of the
Since writing note 2 on p. 17 I have become aware through Lohne [i] of two other Scholium to the laws of motion. There Newton states:
relevant passages in Newton manuscripts. T h e first passage occurs in M S . Add. 3968 b,
fol. l o i : after referring to the correspondence of 1679/80 with Hooke, Newton con­ Per leges duas primas & Corollaria duo prima adinvenit Galilaeus descensum
tinues: ‘Whereupon I computed what would be the Orb described by the Planets for graviumesseinduplicata ratione temporis, & motumprojectiliumfieri in Parabola,
I had found before by the sesquialterate proportion of the tempora periodica of the conspirante experientia, nisi quatenus motus illi per aeris resistentiam aliquan-
Planets with respect to their distances from the sun that the forces which kept them in
their Orbs about the Sun were as the squares of their mean distances from the Sun
tulum retardantur.
reciprocally, and I found now that whatsoever was the law of the forces w'hich kept the In certain respects this statement is entirely clear and unexceptionable.
Planets in their Orbs the areas described by a Radius drawn from them to the Sun
would be proportional to the times in which they were described. And by the help of
Galileo did discover both the law of falling bodies and the parabolic path
these Propositions I found that their Orbs would be such Ellipses as Kepler had of a projectile, basing his derivations of them on an inertial principle
described.’
T his would seem to point unequivocally to New ton’s discovery o f the proposition
and a method of compounding motions identical with that found in the
corresponding to Prop, i of the tract de M otii in the winter o f 1679/80. But it could first corollary to Newton’s laws of motion. To what extent, however,
imply equally well a direct (analytic) or converse (synthetic) proof of the proposition did Galileo’s inertial principle agree with Newton’s principle of
corresponding to Kepler’s first law (motion in an ellipse).
In the other passage (M S. Add. 3968 b, fol. 405) Newton states unequivocally: ‘By inertia, and how far if at all did Galileo either recognize or use the
the inverse M ethod of fluxions I found in the year 1677 [ = 1679/80] the demon­ second law of motion? Finally, are we to understand from this state­
stration of Kepler’s Astronomical Proposition viz. that the Planets move in Ellipses,
which is the eleventh proposition of the first book of the Principles.’ Nevertheless, I am
ment of Newton’s that he felt himself indebted to Galileo for all these
still inclined to agree with Lohne [i] and Whiteside {History o f Science, i (1962), p. 20) elements of his dynamics ? Before attempting to answer these questions
that Newton never possessed an analytic proof that an inverse square centripetal force
two things are necessary: one must first decide what were Galileo’s
implied motion in a conic, including an ellipse as a special case.
original contributions to dynamics; and one must then look for documen­
tary evidence of the influence of these contributions on Newton.
There can be no doubt that Galileo was the first to derive the para­
bolic path of a projectile. His derivation' was based on the combination
of two independent and non-interfering motions, the one uniform and
horizontal, appropriate to a ball moving freely on a horizontal plane, the
‘ Discorsi, Fourth Day, Theor. i. Prop. 1.
36 I NF LU EN C E OF GALILEO AND D E S C A R T E S 2.1 2.1 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 37
other vertical and uniformly accelerated, appropriate to free fall under Discorsi, in the well-known passage elaborated by Viviani at Galileo’s
gravity. It likewise seems certain that although Galileo may not have request.^ In this passage, which contains a derivation of the theorem
been the first to derive the fundamental formula soc for uniformly that the velocity acquired from rest on an inclined plane depends only
accelerated motion, having been possibly anticipated by Beeckman,' on the vertical height fallen, there is certainly an assumption which could
yet he was the first to publish it and to realize its true physical signifi­ be interpreted^ as implying that the distance moved in given time on
cance.^ an inclined plane will vary with the component of the weight of the body
It is equally certain that Galileo never enunciated the principle of along the line of greatest slope. But whether or not Galileo’s use of this
inertia,3 and indeed could not have done so correctly, since ‘horizontal’ assumption should be regarded as an indication that he possessed an
motion was for him always at the surface of the earth, equidistant from inkling of the second law of motion seems to me a very moot question.
its centre, and therefore in reality circular and not rectilinear. This was In any case it would still have to be decided whether Newton knew of,
clearly his belief in the Dialogue, and although there is no indication of or was influenced by, this particular passage in the Discorsi at the time
a continuing belief in ‘circularity’ for the greater part of the kinematical of his earliest researches in dynamics.
and dynamical writing in the Discorsi, a passage towards the end'^ makes Among the dynamical problems touched on by Galileo in the Dialogue
it evident that he had in no way modified this particular belief in the was that of circular motion.^ His treatment of this was rather uneven.
interval between the composition of the two works. Nevertheless, al­ For although he believed that a stone on a revolving wheel tended to be
though Galileo’s principle of inertia was thus restricted to a very special thrown off along the tangent, yet his argument for supposing it might be
terrestrial case, this restriction did not obtrude itself in his vivid physical prevented from doing so because of its weight was unconvincing. In
discussion of inertial motion on a horizontal plane, especially in his any case, his failure to reach a true understanding of inertial movement,
discussion of the motion of a projectile. And Newton would have been to separate it completely from terrestrial phenomena and imagine it
powerfully impressed and influenced by this discussion. taking place in empty space, inevitably precluded him from attaining
It is not at all clear how far, if at all, Galileo’s understanding of force that clarity of conception of circular motion found in Descartes’s treat­
had progressed along the road leading to the second law of motion. New­ ment in Part II of the Principia Philosophiae. Against this, however, we
ton himself, as we have seen, seems to imply that this law was known to have to set Galileo’s suggestive argument, in favour of the centrifugal
Galileo, and various historians of science, including Whewell,s Dugas,^ tendency decreasing with increase of radius for a given rate of rota-
and Singer,^ have all to differing extents adopted the same point of view. tion.+
Koyre, however, is rightly very guarded in his estimation of Galileo’s Apart from the topics already considered mention must be made of
views on force.® In particular, there seems to be only one passage in Galileo’s realization that the efficacy of a body’s motion varied directly
Galileo which gives any hint of the second law. This occurs in the with its bulk and velocity. This notion is found both in the Dialogue^
and in the Discourse on Bodies in Water.^ But although, as is well known,
^ For Beeckman’s derivation, and the part played in it by Descartes, see Duhem [3],
pp. 570-4; Koyre [i]. Part II, pp. 25-40.
Galileo had given much thought to the problem of percussion, and even
^ For Galileo’s treatment of the law of falling bodies, see especially Koyre [1], promised a treatment of it in the Discorsi,"^ he never published anything
Part II.
3 In this connexion see particularly Koyr^ [i]. Part III, Appendix A.
* See Ed. N a z., t. viii, p. 214 et seq. (Crew and Salvio [i], p. 180 et seq.).
^ Could be interpreted because in the key phrase ‘since the forces are in the same ratio
* See Salviati’s statement found in Ed. N a z ., t. viii, p. 274.
as these distances’ (Crew and Salvio [i], p. 184) the term employed by Galileo (or
5 Whewell, W ., [i], vol. ii, p. 29: ‘T o see that a transverse force would produce a
Viviani) for ‘force’ was ‘ momenti' which may or may not have implied the same thing as
curve was one step; to determine what the curve is, was another step, which involved
the discoverj'^ of the second law of motion. T h is step was made by Galileo.’
‘Vimpeto’— the force impelling a body to fall— which in turn may or may not have
had the same significance as force for Newton or for us.
* Dugas, R., [2], p. 206, where New ton’s statement at the beginning of the Scholium
^ See pp. 200 et seq. of Salusbury’s translation of the Dialogue in Santillana [i].
to the laws of motion is reproduced and interpreted as New ton’s homage to his prede­
Ibid., pp. 231 et seq.
cessors.
^ Ibid., pp. 229-30.
’ Singer, C ., [i], p. 236: ‘New ton’s second law . . . is involved in Galileo’s theory of
^ A t Def. 5, A x. 2, 3. See Salusbury’s translation of this work in Drake [i].
projectiles.’ What he means by ‘involved’ is not clear.
^ See Ed. N a z., t. viii, p. 293 (Crew and Salvio [i], p. 271).
* See especially Koyr^ [i]. Part III, Chapter 3.
38 IN F LU E N C E OF GALILEO AND D E S C A R T E S 2.1 2.1 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 39
on the subject,^ and his projected treatment of it must remain a matter of In MS. II Newton gives a correct statement of the law of composition
speculation. of independent motions as a corollary to what appears to be an incorrect
Bearing in mind these achievements, and limitations, of Galileo in rule for resolving velocityP Later, in MS. V, this connexion between the
dynamics, let us now consider what evidence there is for his influence on kinematical rule for resolving velocity and the dynamical rule for com­
Newton’s earliest researches in the subject. First there is the reference pounding motions has disappeared. Now they are given separately, and
to Galileo in MS. I. This comes after a critical discussion of Aristotle’s correctly, in succeeding sections. Only the dynamical rule need concern
theory of projectiles in the same manuscript and must date close to the us. This Newton formulates as follows:
beginning of Newton’s study of dynamics. Next there are two references If a body move towards B with the velocity R, and by the way hath some
to Galileo in MS. I l l of which the original data must in any case have new force done to it which had the body rested would have propelled it to­
been taken by Newton from the Dialogue.^ Here is indisputable evidence wards C with the velocity S. Then making AB : A C : : R : S, and com­
of Galileo’s influence on Newton in dynamics at a very early stage. And pleting the parallelogram BC the body shall move in the diagonal AD and
although Newton was probably little indebted to Galileo, if at all, for his arrive at the point D with this compound motion in the same time it would
have arrived at the point B, with its single motion.
first clear realization of the concept of centrifugal force, it seems very
probable that the peculiar formula on which the calculations in At first sight this enunciation of the parallelogram law seems to differ
MS. I l l are based was derived by Newton from the formula given on from later ones, such as that found in Corollary i to the laws of motion
folio I of MS. II by application of the Merton Rule.3 In that case, assum­ in the Principia, only in its relative verbosity— which in turn could be
ing that he was not already familiar with this rule through a study of accounted for by the superior conciseness of Latin over English. But
medieval works,^ it is possible that he took it either from the Dialogue a closer inspection reveals one small, yet possibly significant, difference
or the Discorsi. Some independent support for this view is provided by between this enunciation and all later ones: namely, in all later enuncia­
Version III of the tract de Motu of 1684 (MS. IXc). For although his tions both motions are treated on precisely the same footing, whereas
proof of Lemma 2^ of that work uses the fact that the distance travelled here one motion is regarded as prior to the other. Initially the body was
equals the area under the s-t graph, he gives no proof of the result moving from A to B with velocity R when some ‘new force’ was done
himself, appealing instead to that given by Galileo— ut exposuit Galilaeus. to it. Immediately there comes to mind Galileo’s marvellous derivation
Apart from this possible indication of a debt of Newton to Galileo in (in the Fourth Day of the Discorsi) of the parabolic path of a projectile.
respect of the Merton Rule, MS. I l l contains repeated applications of There, too, there was initially a certain motion of the body, along the
Galileo’s law, the first, but by no means the last, occasion on which table, to which was added at the moment of its reaching the edge a ‘new^
Newton made use of this fundamental result.^ force’, that due to the weight of the body downwards. And to find the
* W ith the exception of the short section entitled ‘O f the Force of Percussion’ at the
subsequent movement of the body thereafter it was necessary to com­
end of the early treatise ‘On Mechanics’ (see pp. 179-82 of the translation of this work pound the two motions, the one horizontal and inertial, the other vertical
in Drake and Drabkin [i]). This, however, in no way advances the problem of per­ and accelerated. Admittedly, there was a fundamental difference be­
cussion or collision from the dynamical point of view. See, however, the unpublished
dialogue ‘Della forza della percossa’ intended by Galileo to supply the treatment of the tween the ‘forces’ considered by Newton and those implicit in Galileo’s
subject promised in the Discorsi. For a French translation of this dialogue together with problem. In the latter case there was no force in the horizontal direction,
an illuminating discussion of its content and historical significance see the article
Remarques sur le dialogue de Galilee ‘D e la force de la percussion' by S. Moscovici, Revue and the vertical force w^as constant, producing acceleration, whereas here
d'Histoire des Sciences, 16, 7 -1 3 7 (1963), ^ See M S . I l l , Appendix A. the forces considered by Newton were really impulses producing
•'* See above. Chapter 1.2, p. lO.
* A possibility by no means to be ruled out, though one of the certain sources
(almost) instantaneous changes in motion. Nevertheless, I think that
of New ton’s knowledge of Aristotelian physics, Magirus [i], while it contains an
interesting commentary on the problem of projectiles, at no point goes so far as a dis­ * See M S . Ilg .
cussion of uniformly accelerated motion. * See Fig. 2 of M S . V.
3 Notice here New ton’s use of the word ‘new ’. It affords a good illustration of the
^ T o appear later as Lemma X in the Principia.
peculiar exactness and completeness of his dynamical thought. Another force had acted
^ See, for example, New ton’s generalization of Galileo’s law in 'I’heor. 3 of the tract
de M otu (M S. TX). on the body previously to produce the original motion in the direction A B .
40 I NF LU EN CE OF GALILEO AND D E S C A R T E S 2.1 2.1 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 41
this difference between the present enunciation and all later ones acting on it— ‘a body must move that way which it is pressed’. But this
provides a precious indication of a possible, if not probable, influence definition of force, its connexion with motion, and its effect on direction
of Galileo on Newton in his formulation of the parallelogram law based arose directly out of his discussion of the problem of collisions. The
on the compounding of independent motions: given that Galileo was the influence, if any, was therefore from Descartes, not from Galileo, and
first to make real use of this novel and entirely un-Aristotelian notion will be discussed in the immediately succeeding section.
there would always have been a strong a priori possibility of its having T o summarize, the one ingredient of his early dynamical researches
influenced Newton, and this possibility must now be somewhat streng­ which Newton undoubtedly owed to Galileo was the latter’s t^ law of
thened. I falling bodies. This continued to play a vital role in the growth of New­
MS. II contains what are undoubtedly the earliest of Newton’s extant ton’s dynamics up to and including the composition of the Principia.
researches in dynamics. There we find an enunciation of the principle of It is enshrined in Newton’s generalization of the law in Lemma X of that
inertia which could only have been taken by Newton from Part II of Des­ work. In the same Lemma he implicitly assumes the Merton Rule the
cartes’s Further strong indications of Descartes’s influence are proof of which he had previously attributed to Galileo. In all probability
found in Newton’s concept of centrifugal force in the same manuscript, he took this originally from the Dialogue or the Discorsi sometime prior
and in his treatment of momentum and collisions. On the other hand, to the composition of the Vellum MS.
there is no indication whatsoever in the earliest^ dynamical writings in Probably, if not certainly, Newton owed to Galileo the notion of com­
the Waste Book of any Galilean influence: no treatment, for example, of pounding non-interfering independent motions as first used by the
uniformly accelerated motion, or of motion on an inclined plane. All latter in his proof of the parabolic path of a projectile in the Discorsi.
the indications^ therefore, point towards a predominant prior influence Without this notion Newton could not have formulated his parallelogram
of Descartes on Newton in respect both of the principle of inertia and law for the composition of independent motions. A possible indication
the concept of centrifugal force. And this, of course, is just what one of such an influence is provided by the peculiar nature of an early formu­
would expect given the great superiority in respect of both completeness lation of the parallelogram law. This law, too, played a vital role in the
and clarity of Descartes’s treatment of these two topics compared with growth of Newton’s dynamical thought— ^without it, for example, the
that of Galileo. On the other hand, Newton’s treatment of centrifugal original proof of the proposition corresponding to Kepler’s second law of
force in MS. IVa where he first derives the law of centrifugal force by a planetary motion would have been impossible.
method entirely different from that which he had followed in MS. II, Finally, there is no indication in the earliest researches of any influence
shows traces of a possible influence of Galileo. Like Galileo’s argument of Galileo on Newton in respect of the principle of inertia, centrifugal
in favour of the centrifugal tendency decreasing with the ratio it is force, or the genesis of the second law of motion. In the last case the
based on the notions of measuring this tendency by the deviation be­ possibility of any influence is effectively ruled out by the actual form of
tween the actual circular path and the inertial path along the tangent.^ the law and its undoubted origin in Newton’s study of momentum and
It remains to consider the second law of motion. Unmistakable collisions, whereas some influence in the case of centrifugal force is
traces of the genesis of this law are found in MS. II. There Newton possible at a later stage.
defines force as the change in motion produced. Likewise the change in As to the total impact of Galileo on Newton in science in general and
direction of motion produced in a body is in the direction of the force in dynamics in particular, this is something which goes beyond the
‘ Assuming, of course, that Newton had access to the Discorsi at an early date. present volume and for which there is no evidence in the purely dyna­
^ T h e reasons for this are given in the immediately following section on Descartes’s mical manuscripts. In all probability it was profound. Certainly the
influence on Newton.
^ A s opposed, that is, to the somewhat later writings such as those on fol. i of the
whole cast of Newton’s thought, his humility before Nature, his drive
same manuscript where there is a reference to Galileo in connexion with the synchron­ towards exact quantitative results, his delight in experiment, was alto­
ism of the simple pendulum. See M S . Ila, § 4.
gether Galilean, and if he recognized any master in science apart from
On the other hand a rather similar kind of deviation figures in Descartes’s dis­
cussion of centrifugal force in Art. 58, Part 3, o f his Principia Philosophiae. Archimedes it could only have been Galileo.
42 IN F LU EN CE OF GALILEO AND DE S C A R T E S 2.2 2.2 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 43
2.2 T he Influence of D escartes set his face against Descartes at the time of composing this manu­
script.
Newton’s aversion to certain elements of Descartes’s physics has long
At first sight this seems a very promising start. Parts II and III of
been recognized. For example, the Principia was evidently intended to
Descartes’s Principia contain effectively all his published^ writings on
provide not only a new ‘explanation’ of the solar system based on
dynamics, and MS. V I bears every indication of being an early work.
Kepler’s laws and Newton’s own dynamical principles, but also a rebut­
Newton must therefore have been familiar at an early stage with Des­
tal of Descartes’s theory of vortices. Moreover, as Koyre has demon­
cartes’s dynamics, thus improving the prior odds in favour of his having
strated, ^a careful reading of the Principia, especially between the lines,
been influenced by them. But not very much, for we know that Newton’s
proves how strong was Newton’s aversion to certain elements of Des­
knowledge of dynamics was growing rapidly around the beginning of the
cartes’s I n fact it would not be too strong to say that Newton
year 1665, ^so that to provide any real help towards determining Descartes ’ s
eventually came to detest Descartes both as a physicist and a philosopher,
influence MS. V I would need to be dated about the same time. In fact,
his aversion to Descartes even extending to mathematics with his well-
no date is given, and some internal indications of date point towards the
known belief that a geometrical proof could only be regarded as well
second half of 1666 rather than the beginning of 1665.3 Apart from MS.
founded if presented in synthetic rather than analytic form. And yet in
VI, the only other early references by Newton to Descartes’s Principia
spite of Newton’s strong, one might almost say passionate, dislike of
occur in MS. I. These were probably entered sometime in the second
Descartes and all his works, there has always been a strong possibility
half of 1664, about the beginning of Newton’s work in dynamics,^ so
that Newton was largely indebted to Descartes for the most important
that once again the probability of an influence by Descartes on Newton
single element of his dynamics, the principle of inertia! In questions of
in dynamics becomes somewhat strengthened.
the influence of one thinker on another, however, possibilities are rarely
At this point we can summarize the position as follows: given that
of much help. Other possibilities are almost always equally open. Here,
Descartes’s enunciation of the principle of inertia in Articles 37 and
for example, apart from the possible, even probable, influence on
39 of his Principia Philosophiae was the first to be published apart from
Newton of Galileo’s imperfect, ytt physically very powerful, discussion
that of Gassendi, there would always be a distinct possibility of Newton
of inertial movement, there is also the possibility of his having taken the having been indebted to Descartes for at least this element of his dyna­
true and complete notion of this concept from Gassendi.^ Failing other mics; and the likelihood of such an influence is increased by the fact
evidence beyond the fact of Descartes’s memorable enunciation of the that Newton did make a study of Descartes’s Principia, a study, more­
principle of inertia in Part II of his Principia Philosophiae further pro­ over, which began very early and was ultimately of a profoundly detailed
gress towards establishing Newton’s debt to Descartes in respect of this nature— as MS. Add. 4003 proves. Nevertheless, to proceed further, to
element of his dynamics is therefore impossible. render Descartes’s influence on Newton in dynamics seem not only
Additional evidence, however, is fortunately available. First there is possible but probable, some much more definite evidence is needed.
MS. VI in which Newton displays a most intimate acquaintance with This is fortunately provided in MS. II. On the basis of the new evidence
Parts II and III of Descartes’s Principia. And since he was then already supplied by the dynamical writings in this manuscript, certainly among
interested in dynamics— witness his statement of the principle of the earliest of Newton’s which we possess, and in any case very close to
inertia on p. 19 of that manuscript^— he could hardly have failed to notice the actual beginning of his researches in dynamics,® it first becomes
the specifically dynamical articles in Descartes’s work. So that the fact
* But by no means all his thought on dynamics, of which much valuable evidence is
that he pointedly omits any reference to these articles is then of no sig­ supplied by the Correspondence. See G abbey [i], for the first comprehensive account
nificance apart from the indication it affords of how absolutely he had of Descartes’s dynamical thought as a whole.
^ One of the earliest dvnamical entries in the Waste Book is dated 20 January 1664
^ See Koyre [6]. (O.S.). S e e M S . Ilb .
* Petri Gassendi, D e motu impresso a motore translato, Paris, 1642. See especially 2 See below, Chapter 6.2, p. 93. * Ibid., p. 91.
5 A t various points between p. 92 and p. 121 of M S . Add. 4003 there are entries
Chapter 15, p. 59, and Chapter 16, p. 62. Translations of the two relevant passages are
relating to motion, gravity and levity, violent motion, and Aristotle’s theory of
given by Koyre [i]. Part III, pp. 152, 153. See M S . V I, § 4.
44 IN F LU E N CE OF GALILEO AND D ES C A R T ES 2.2
2.2 ON N E W T O N ’S D Y N A M I C S 45
possible to attempt a serious assessment of the actual influence of Des­
if it is moved, why we should think that it would ever of its own accord, and
cartes on Newton in dynamics. unimpeded by anything else, interrupt this motion.
A word of explanation is called for on the method of treatment followed.
To this inertial tendency of rest and motion Descartes then adds in
The dynamical topics in Parts II and III of Descartes’s Principia are
Art. 39 the supremely important qualification that
considered in three separate sub-sections, the first two devoted to the
III. Any particular part of matter, regarded in itself, is never inclined to
principle of inertia and circular motion, respectively, and the third to
prosecute motion in any curved lines, but only in straight lines.
topics other than these two. In each section an account is first given of
Descartes’s method of treatment followed by Newton’s treatment of the Which law, states Descartes, follows like the preceding one from the
immutability and simplicity of the operation by which God conserves
same topic, or topics, in MS. II. No attempt is made in any of these
motion in matter. Namely, not as it was at some previous instant, but as
subsections to draw any conclusions relative to Descartes’s influence on
it is at the very instant itself. So that although the movement of a body
Newton, since it seemed best to separate the evidence from the argu­
takes place in time and not instantaneously,' and may in fact be curved
ment based upon it; in any case, although it is convenient to consider
and not rectilinear, nevertheless at each instant the determination^ of
the various dynamical topics separately in the first place, the question of
its motion is never in a curved line but always along a straight line—
Descartes’s influence on Newton in dynamics must ultimately be con­
the tangent to the curved path at the instant in question. And this law
sidered as a whole, in the light of all the available evidence, as in the
is supported by the fact that a stone loosed from a sling moves always
final subsection.
along the tangent line to its original circular path.
Principle of Inertia Newton. Newton’s first enunciation of the principle of inertia in MS.
Descartes. In Art. 37 of Part II of his Principia Descartes introduces II occurs at Axioms i and 2. There he states:
the first part of the principle of inertia, not casually, in an ad hoc manner, IV. If a quantity once move it will never rest unless hindered by some
but as a special case of a general philosophical principle mirroring the external cause. [Ax. i]
immutability of God, namely: and
I. Any particular thing, in so far as it is simple and undivided, remains V. A quantity will always move on in the same straight line (not changing
always to the best of its ability in the same state, nor is ever changed [from this the determination nor celerity of its motion) unless some external cause divert
state] unless by external causes.^ it. [Ax. 2]
For example, a square-shaped piece of matter always remains square Later, at Ax. 100, we find the statement of the following general philo­
unless something intervenes to change its shape, and sophical principle:
II. If [a body] is at rest we do not believe it is ever set in motion, unless it is VI. Every thing doth naturally persevere in that state in which it is unless
impelled thereto by some [external] cause. Nor that there is any more reason it be interrupted by some external cause.
projectiles. On p. 9 3 V , the same page on which occurs a reference to Descartes’s Principia, ‘Hence’ he adds ‘Axiom ist & 2nd’, and
there is a cometary observation dated 17 December 1664. T his would seem to point
towards the beginning of a serious interest by Newton in dynamics around the second VII. A body once moved will always keep the same celerity, quantity and
half of 1664, not long before the dynamical entry on fob 10 of the Waste Book dated determination of its motion.
20 January 1664 (O.S.). See below’, Chapter 6.2.
^ A ll translations of passages from the Principia have been made direct from the
Circular motion
(first) Latin edition as given in Adam and Tannery, v. viir. We cannot be sure which
edition Newton used, though it may well have been that found in his library, the third. Descartes. In Art. 38 of Part II of his Principia Descartes cites the
But he would presumably have used a Latin version, given his avowed ignorance of
case of the circular motion of a stone in a sling as an example of the
French. It is worth noting that there are certain important differences between the first
Latin edition and Picot’s French translation. For example, the enunciation of the first ' In this connexion see the discussion in Koyre [i]. Part 3, Appendix B.
part of the principle of inertia in the Latin version contains no explicit reference to the * In Art. 39, Part II, Principia Descartes states; ‘ omne id quod movetur . . . determina-
uniformity of the motion, whereas in Art. 37, Part II, of the Picot translation the motion tum esse ad motum suum continuandimi versus aliquam partem, secundum lineam rectani’ .
is explicitly stated to be ‘de meme force’. Newton, in the Waste Book, uses the term determination in the same sense.
46 IN F LU EN CE OF GALILEO AND D E S CA R T E S 2.2 2.2 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 47
instantaneous tendency of a body to move rectilinearly along the tangent then we say that the stone at every instant has a tendency to recede
to its actual curved path. From which it follows that: along the radius from the centre of the circle.
Descartes therefore definitely gives the impression that he believes in
VIII. Every body which is moved circularly tends perpetually to recede
from the centre of the circle which it describes.^ two separate conati: one along the tangent due to the motive force in
the stone itself, and one along the radius away from the centre. Both
This is something, moreover, which we actually sense with our hand tendencies remain potential only, their realization being prevented by
when we whirl a stone in a sling. the sling. But this, as he wfisely notes, does not prevent the existence of
If this were the only discussion of circular motion given by Descartes, the tendencies themselves. This interpretation of Descartes’s views is
one would be inclined to assume that he did not believe in a centrifugal then confirmed by his discussion of the motion of an ant on a rotating
tendency in circular motion distinct from the inertial tendency along the ruler in Art. 58, and of a ball in a rotating tube in Art. 59. In each case
tangent. After all he specifically states that the second tendency follows he clearly believes both in a tangential and a centrifugal tendency or
from the first. And this deduction is entirely just: motion along the endeavour. One can surmise that any doubts he may have had of the
tangent is necessarily motion away from the centre, something which reality of the centrifugal conatus would have been removed by the second,
Galileo, too, was well aware of. However, it is clear from the more de­ characteristically ingenious, example of the ball in the rotating tube. For
tailed discussion of circular motion in Art. 57, 58, 59 of Part III of the how can the ball move away from the centre of rotation in the absence of
Principia that Descartes really believed in two separate tendencies, the some centrifugal tendency or conatus} His discussion of the ensuing
one centrifugal, the other along the tangent. accelerated centrifugal motion from the centre also gives the impression
He opens this discussion in Art. 56 by noting that the attempt of that he looked on this conatus very much in the nature of a force. This
second-class matter to escape from the centre of its vortex due to its is confirmed when he returns to the example of a stone in the sling at
circular motion does not imply any conscious striving, but only a the end of Art. 59:
tendency so to move which may be impeded by other causes. In fact, X. atque ista tensio, a sola vi qua lapis recedere conatur a centro sui
as he notes in Art. 57, the simultaneous action of various causes is the motus exorta, exhibet nobis istius vis quantitatem.
rule rather than the exception, so that one can talk of a body simulta­ As to the ‘quantity’ of this ‘force’ Descartes makes no attempt to calcu­
neously having divers tendencies or conatus in different directions. It is late it beyond noting that it increases with the speed of rotation.
at this point that he specifically instances the case of the motion of a Newton. In Axioms and Propositions 20, 21 of MS. II we have what
stone in a sling. Under the combined effect of all the causes acting on the must represent something very close to Newton’s first thoughts on circular
stone it moves in a circle. But if one thinks only of the motive force in motion. There he considers a sphere moving within a spherical or
the stone itself— Descartes is clearly identifying this as one of the causes cylindrical surface:
acting on the stone— the corresponding tendency to motion is always XI. Axiom 20. If a sphere Oc move within the concave spherical or
along the tangent to the circle. And although the sling prevents the cylindrical surface of the body circularly about the centre m, it shall press
stone from following this tendency it cannot prevent the tendency upon the body def, for when it is in c (supposing the circle hhc to be described by
itself— its centre of motion, and the line eg a tangent to that at 0) it moves towards g
or the determination of its motion is towards g, therefore if at that moment
IX. ac quamvis funda hunc effectum impediat, non tamen impedit cona- the body ed/should cease to check it it would continually move in the line eg
tum. (ax. I, 2) obliquely from the centre m, but if the body de/oppose itself to this
Again, if we do not consider the whole motive force of the stone along endeavour keeping it equidistant from m, that is done by a continued checking
or reflection of it from the tangent line in every point of the circle chh, but the
the circle, something wFich he obviously distinguishes from the motive
body def cannot check and curb the determination of the body co unless they
force in the stone itself, but consider only that part prevented by the sling, continually press upon one another. The same may be understood if the body
adb be restrained into circular motion by the thread. . . .
^ Loc. cit., towards end of article.
48 IN F LU EN CE OF GALILEO AND D E S C A R T E S 2.2
2.2 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 49
XII. Axiom 21. Hence it appears that all bodies moved circularly have an
endeavour from the centre about which they move, otherwise the body Oc followed immediately by its generalization:
would not continually press upon edf. So much force as is required to destroy any quantity of motion in a body
so much is required to generate it; and so much as is required to generate it
Notice that for Newton the sphere is at any instant moving in the
so much is also required to destroy it.
direction of the tangent line; this is its determination or endeavour,
Although Descartes believed that the motion conferred on a body by
which endeavour is only prevented by the continual check exerted by
the action of some external agent or force resided entirely in the body
the surrounding surface. And this check can only be exerted by the
not as a substance, but as a mode or state of the body, yet this state of
surface on the sphere if the two press upon each other. Hence there must
motion had a certain attribute consisting in a tendency to maintain it­
always be an opposite endeavour of the sphere away from the centre.
self, as followed, of course, from the principle of inertia. This tendency
Thus for Newton at the time of composing these two axioms a body
of a body to persevere in its motion— adpergendum secundum lineam
moving circularly had two endeavours, one along the tangent, one away
rectarrC^— ^was to be compared with the analogous tendency to remain
from the centre along the radius. In the somewhat later MS. IVa we
at rest which revealed itself in the form of a resistance to motion. The
still find the same belief in an endeavour or conatus away from the centre
process of collision between two bodies, one in motion and one at rest,
in circular motion.
could then be thought of as a contest between the force of motion of the
Other topics moving body and the force of resistance of the other.
The remaining dynamical topics considered in Descartes’s Principia In MS. II Newton develops his discussion of colliding bodies in two
come under the general heading of force, resistance, momentum, and ways. One is based on the motion of the elastic forces brought into play
conservation of momentum. All these enter into his treatment of colli­ by the deformation of the colliding bodies, while the other makes use of
sions between two bodies. the term perseverance of bodies in their state*^ (of motion or rest) and
From our childhood, states Descartes, we labour under the delusion regards the collision process as a mutual intervention or hindrance
that more action is required for motion than rest. This, he suggests, between these powers.
springs from the fact that various forces, including gravity, oppose the In the case of a collision between a moving and a stationary body
motions of our limbs causing fatigue, whereas we are not aware of the Descartes supposed that the ‘resistance’ of the latter could exceed the
action of gravity responsible for rest in our own and other bodies. In force of motion of the former.3 In this case, if the two bodies were soft
fact, no more action^ is required to produce motion in a body than is the moving body would be brought to rest, its motion being absorbed
required to bring it to rest again by destroying this motion. For example, in some unspecified manner; whereas if the bodies were hard it would
the action required to set a boat in still water in motion will be the same be reflected without loss of motion. On the other hand, if the force of
as that required to bring it to rest ;2 apart, that is, from a small diflFerence motion of the moving body exceeded the resistance of the stationary one
due to that portion of the original action used to set the surrounding water the two would move on together the total quantity of motion being con­
in motion. served, the quantity of motion in a body being proportional to the mag­
It is not clear in what sense Descartes believed this last result would nitude of the body and its velocity. As for the conservation, this was
help to remove the original prejudice in favour of motion rather than rest. necessary to ensure that the total quantity of motion in the universe was
Nor does it seem to play any further part in his Principia. But it is per­ unaffected by such encounters between bodies in accordance with the
haps important for the connexion it implies between action and move­ general law of conservation derived from the immutability of God’s
ment, between force and momentum. working in the universe.^
At Axiom 3 of MS. II we find the following statement: In MS. II the quantity of motion, or simply the motion, of a body was
There is exactly required so much and no more force to reduce a body to likewise proportional to its bulk or magnitude and its velocity. Unlike
rest as there was to put it upon motion: et e contra. * Ibid., Art. 40. 2 M S . lie . A x. 104.
' T h e term used by Descartes i s ‘flcn’o’. ^ See Art. 26, Part II, Principia. 3 See Art. 40, Part II, Principia. * Ibid., Art. 36, 42.
8G8205 E
50 IN F LU EN CE OF GALILEO AND D E S CA R T E S 2.2 2.2 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 51
Descartes, however, Newton realized that the total momentum in a precisely the argument used by Descartes to derive the first part of his
collision must be calculated algebraically, paying due regard to determina­ principle of inertia.
tion as well as to magnitude. So that it was now impossible that the I conclude, therefore, that Newton took his first known enunciation
moving body should be reflected from a stationary one which itself con­ of the principle of inertia in Axioms i and 2 of MS. II directly from
tinued at rest. Articles 37 and 39 of Part II of Descartes’s Principia. The evidence for
this as it stands, without any further support, seems to me quite con­
A comparison between Descartes’s and Newton’s treatment of these clusive, the probability of Newton having reproduced by chance the
topics at once reveals a most remarkable similarity in the case of the peculiar features of Descartes’s enunciation vanishingly small. On the
principle of inertia. There were two peculiar, and quite characteristic, basis of this evidence, for example, I deduce that Descartes’s Principia
features of Descartes’s enunciation of this principle: in the first place, must have been available to Newton around the beginning of the year
he enunciated it not as a single principle, but in two separate parts, the 1665. Nevertheless, it is comforting to have the reference to the Principia
first affirming the inertial property of motion or rest in the absence of Philosophiae in M S. I, and to find a copy of Descartes’s work in Newton’s
external disturbances, the second the tendency of motion always to take library.
place in straight lines. Secondly, Descartes deduced both parts of the Knowing that Newton’s first enunciation of the principle of inertia
principle from the nature of God and His working in the universe; in MS. II was modelled on that given in Part II of Descartes’s Principia,
the first as a special case of a more general philosophical principle we can now confidently look for further indications of a like influence
mirroring the immutability of God, the second from the immutability in the other topics. First there is Newton’s approach to the problem
and simplicity of the operation by which God conserved motion. of circular motion in Axiom 20 of the same manuscript. As with Des­
Both these peculiar features figure in Newton’s presentation of the cartes, the treatment is entirely qualitative, only later does he begin to feel
principle: he too divides the principle into two parts, the first affirming his way towards an exact quantitative result. Here he is concerned with
the inertial property of motion in the absence of external disturbances, the basic physical approach to the problem, and this approach exactly
the second its rectilinearity. Given that Descartes was the first, and follows that of Descartes resting on a double tendency, or endeavour,
apparently the only, person to enunciate the principle of inertia in of the body, the first along the tangent to the circle at any point, the second
two parts, then the fact that Newton does likewise, and that his parts away from the centre. This second endeavour away from the centre is
closely follow those of Descartes, must make it at least probable that he evidenced by the pressure of the ball on the spherical containing surface,
modelled his enunciation on that of Descartes. Admittedly, there are corresponding to the tension in the string in the case of motion in a sling. ^
certain differences between Newton’s enunciation and Descartes’s: Given that Descartes’s treatment of circular motion differed from all
Newton omits any references to rest as a state of a body^ in Axiom i, previous treatments by his very clear and explicit insistence on tw^o
whereas he refers both to determination and celerity^ in Axiom 2. How­ tendencies, the one tangential, the other centrifugal, and knowing that
ever, any residual doubt as to Descartes’s influence is removed by Newton must have been familiar with this treatment when composing
Axiom 100. For the general philosophical principle in that axiom is Ax.-Prop. 20, then the fact that Newton bases his appreciation of circular
nothing less than a faithful English paraphrase of the principle given in motion on the same two tendencies points strongly to his having modelled
Latin at Article 37 of Part II of Descartes’s Principia. For good measure, his approach on that of Descartes. This conclusion, already probable, is
to make assurance doubly sure, there is New ton’s laconic note following then strengthened by the fact that Newton does not content himself with
his enunciation of the philosophical principle ‘Hence Axiom ist and 2nd’, merely stating the tendency for motion along the tangent, but justifies
* Whereas in Def. 5 of M S . V I we find: 'vis . . . est internum principium quo motus vel
it, like Descartes, by an appeal to the principle of inertia: it was pre­
quies corpori insita conservatur'. cisely this appeal which constituted Descartes’s supreme contribution
^ T h e fact that celerity is inserted in the text is just possibly significant. .\s already
to the problem of circular motion, which enabled him to make a clean
noted in n. i, p. 44, there is no reference to uniformity of motion in Art. 37 of Part
II of the first Latin edition of the Principia. * T h e last sentence of M S . Ild , .\x.-Prop. 20, obviously refers to this case.
52 IN F LU EN CE OF GALILEO AND D E S C A R T E S 2.2 2.2 ON N E W TO N ’ S D Y N A M I C S 53
break with the tyranny of the Platonic circle, ^ and which provided the the concept of momentum itself directly from Descartes must remain
sole basis for its further treatment by Newton. uncertain— for this was a commonly accepted notion which went back
Illuminating also is the comparison between Newton’s use of the at least to Buridan and which is found, for example, in Galileo’s Dia­
concept endeavour^ with Descartes’s use of the term conatus. For Des­ logue. In any case it seems probable that Newton took the idea of using
cartes the conatus away from the centre remained potential only, being momentum (and its conservation) in collision processes directly from
prevented from taking effect owing to the action of the sling. Compare Descartes.
this notion with Newton’s definition of conatus in Def. 6 of MS. V I: The arguments here advanced, if sound, point to a very important
influence of Descartes on Newton in dynamics, direct in the case of
Conatus est vis impedita sive vis quatenus resistitur.
the principle of inertia, circular motion, and collisions, indirect in the
That the conatus here defined is the same as the endeavour used in Ax. case of Newton’s concept of force. Newton’s ‘homage’ to Galileo at the
20 of MS. II is evident from the treatment of centrifugal force in MS. beginning of the Scholium to the laws of motion would then need to be
IV based on the use of the ‘deviation’ between the actual, circular path taken with considerable reserve. We would feel that at this point he
and the natural, inertial one along the tangent. There Newton states should also have made an honest avowal of his debt to Descartes. That
that if the conatus a centra were not impeded (as it actually is) the body he did not do so would then provide one more example of the depth and
would move freely along the tangent. intensity of his aversion to Descartes.
The laws of collision given by Descartes in Part II of his Principia
were notoriously full of error. 3 Nevertheless they represented the first
widely known published attack^ on the problem based on the notion
of momentum and its conservation, and as such would inevitably have
influenced Newton’s approach, if only indirectly. But Newton’s treat­
ment of collisions in MS. II certainly antedated the celebrated papers
of Wren, Wallis, and Huygens,^ so we are entitled to assume that any
influence of Descartes on Newton in that manuscript was direct. In the
light of what we already know of Descartes’s influence in MS. II,
effectively certain in the case of the principle of inertia, highly probable
in that of circular motion, we are justified in looking for an influence also
in the case of collisions. An independent indication of such an influence
is provided by the close similarity between Descartes’s explanation of
the collision process as a contest between the persistence of motion of one
body and the resistance to motion of the other, and one of the explana­
tions put forward by Newton in MS. II.^ Whether or not Newton took
* A s opposed, for example, to Galileo, and even more strikingly to Beeckman, with
his belief that both rectilinear and circular motions could be inertial.
^ For a discussion of New ton’s concept of conatus see below. Chapter 3.
3 See, G abbey [i]. Chapters 3, 4, for an exhaustive and sympathetic account of these
rules.
* A s opposed to that of J. Marcus Marci whose treatment of collisions in his De/)ro/)or-
tione motus seu regula sphygmica (Prague, 1639) seems largely to have escaped notice.
* T h e papers of Wren and Wallis appeared in 1669, that of Huygens (in French) in
1670; whereas some o f New ton’s work on collisions in M S I lb is dated 20 January
1664 (O.S.).
See the section Other topics above.
N EW TO N’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS 55
sling.^ That Newton, like Descartes, regarded the centrifugal tendency as
a species of impeded force, normally potential, yet capable on occasion
N E W T O N ’ S C O N C E P T OF C O N A T U S of being imagined as active, is likewise clear. In Def. 6, MS. V I, he actually
defines endeavour as an ‘impeded force, or a force in so far as it is
I t seems likely that Newton’s first views on conatus or endeavour^ resisted’ in MSS. I l l and IV he employs the terms vis a centra and
resulted from his study of Parts 2 and 3 of Descartes’s Principia Philo- conatus a centra^ respectively, when referring to the centrifugal endeavour
sophiae.^ In Art. 39, Part 2, of the Principia Descartes discusses the or tendency resulting from circular motion; and on folio i of MS. II he
motion of a stone in a sling in the light of the principle of inertia ad­ derives an exact relation involving the centrifugal endeavour for uniform
vanced in Art, 37, explaining the constant endeavour of the stone to circular motion by calculating the momentum acquired in a certain
escape from the centre, as evidenced by the tension in the string, in terms interval of time by a body constantly impelled in a straight line by
of its continuous inertial tendency to escape along the tangent at every a force equal to the given centrifugal endeavour.^ A similar procedure is
point of its path. Descartes thus seems to imply that the centrifugal imagined in MS. IVa,'^ and both there and on folio i of MS. II he com­
endeavour derives entirely from the inertial tendency along the tangent, pares the resulting rectilinear motion to that under gravity. There can
whereas in his later, and more detailed, discussion of circular motion in be little doubt, therefore, that Newton, like Descartes, originally
Arts. 57-59 of Part 3 of the Principia he appears to believe in two separate regarded conatus a centra as a species of force very much on a par with
endeavours, the one along the tangent as before, and another, indepen­ the force of gravity.
dent, endeavour away from the centre along the outward radius. This The situation is quite different in Newton’s treatment of orbital
centrifugal endeavour, like the tangential one, is normally potential motion in Book I of the Principia., and in his discussion of the motion
only. Nevertheless, Descartes seems to have supposed it capable of of the moon in Book III. Now the notion of centrifugal endeavour so
having the effects of a force, for example, in his ingenious example of a prominent in the early treatment of circular motion has been replaced
particle free to slide in a rotating tube.^ There the particle acquires an by that of centripetal force. A striking example of this change in outlook,
increasing outward motion along the tube, and how can this possibly of this shift from centrifugal to centripetal force, is provided by the
occur in the absence of some cause or force ? So that when he returns at treatment of uniform circular motion in Prop. IV, Theor. IV, of Book I.
the end of Art. 59 to the original case of a stone in a sling it is not sur­ Once again, as in MS. IV, the central notion is that of deviation, but
prising to find him employing the term vis in reference to the centrifugal whereas this was formerly measured outwards between the circle and
endeavour: ^atque ista tensio, a sola vi qua lapis recedere conatur a centra the tangent, now it is measured inwards between the tangent and the
sui motus exorta, exhihet nobis istius vis quafititatem’ . circle.
There is a striking, and I believe significant, similarity between In the absence of any reference to centrifugal force in the treatment
Descartes’s ultimate views on endeavour and circular motion, and those of orbital motion in the Principia one might be tempted to assume that
first advanced by Newton in MS. II.C onsidering the motion of a ball Newton had simply seen the error of his ways, had given up the old,
within a spherical surface, he postulates, like Descartes, both a constant false notion of a centrifugal endeavour separated from, and independent
endeavour to escape along the tangent, and a centrifugal endeavour along of, the inertial, tangential endeavour, and replaced it by the true notion
the outward radius. This latter, centrifugal tendency is evidenced by the of an impressed centripetal force. After all, one might argue, there is no
pressure of the surface on the ball, equal and opposite to that of the ball on such thing as a true centrifugal force within the framework of dynamics
* A case referred to by Newton at the end of A x. 20, M S . Ild ; ‘the same may be
the surface, and corresponds to the tension of the string for motion in a
understood if the body adb be restrained into circular motion by the thread . . .’ .
‘ Endeavour will consistently be used in place of conatus apart from the phrase ^ ‘ Conatus est vis inipedita sive vis quatenus resistitur.’
conatus a centra. ^ 'the force by which it endeavours from the centre n would bepet so much motion in a body'
^ T h e best evidence for this is supplied by M S . Add. 4003 from which the extracts (italics mine).
in M S . V I are taken. * 'hie conatus corpora, si modo in directujn ad modum gravitatis continuo urgeret, im-
Principia Pliilosophiae, Part 3, Art. 59. Especially in AIS. Ild, Ax. 20, 21. pelleret per spatia . . . .’ M S . IVa, second para., beginning.
56 N E W T O N ’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS
3 N E W T O N ’S C O N C E P T OF CONATUS 57

presented in the Principia where the only unambiguous measures of line (along the tangent) is not at all clear. The absence of any reference
both motions and forces are relative to absolute space, motion in a to centrifugal force in the preliminary definitions of the lectures de Motu
straight line with uniform speed relative to this space being likewise the and the Principia is perhaps an indication that Newton himself was not
one true type of inertial motion. O f course, relative to a rotating frame of altogether happy about the above definitions in terms of the ‘force of a
reference centrifugal forces will make their appearance and bodies will body’.
appear to tend to move outwards away from the centre of rotation. But The other reference to centrifugal force, at Def. 9 of M S. Xa, is
such forces and motions are not real, are merely engendered by measur­ evidently a preliminary draft of the well-known passage relating to
ing them relative to the rotating frame, and are in reality no more than rotary motion in the Scholium to the Definitions preceding Book I of
disguised manifestations of inertial motion relative to absolute space. the Principia. T o distinguish, says Newton, between relative and abso­
Unfortunately for this simple attitude there is a great deal of evidence lute rotation, it is necessary to examine the effects, if any, of the rotation.
pointing towards a continued belief by Newton in centrifugal force In the case of relative rotation, such as that between the water and the
right up to and possibly beyond the Principia. bucket, there are no effects. In the case of absolute motion there is
The first indication of such a continued belief in centrifugal force or always some real effect, such as the curved surface of the water, or the
conatus a centra is provided by the well-known letter of 23 June 1673 from tension in the string connecting the two rotating globes. And in all
Newton to Oldenburg (for Huygens). In the first paragraph of this cases these real effects bear witness to an endeavour to recede from the
letter^ Newton draws attention to the formulae for centrifugal force axis of rotation. As Newton expresses it:
given (without proof) at the end of Huygens’s Horologium Oscillatorium,
instancing a notion of his own to explain the invariable aspect of the moon This ascent of the water shows its endeavour to recede from the axis of
its motion; and the true and absolute circular motion of the water, which is
from the earth on the grounds of her greater endeavour from the earth
here directly contrary to the relative, becomes known, and may be measured
compared with her endeavour from the sun. There can be no doubt^
by this endeavour.
that Newton is here referring to MS. IVa, and he gives no indication
that he has in any way altered the view of conatus a centra found in that Soon after the Principia was presented to the Royal Society in June
manuscript. 1686 a bitter controversy broke out over Hooke’s claim that Newton
There are no references to centrifugal, as opposed to centripetal, owed him the notion of the inverse square dependence of gravitation as
force in any of the versions of the tract de Motu. Hardly surprising, applied to the motion of the planets.^ In the ensuing correspondence
since this tract evidently represents a first draft of Newton’s treatment between Newton and Halley^ there are a certain number of references
of orbital motion in the lectures de Motu and the Principia. However, to centrifugal force. With one exception, these all originate in Newton’s
several references to centrifugal force occur in MSS. X probably com­ reference, in his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley, to the first paragraph
posed just prior to the lectures de Motu. In Def. 14 of MS. Xb centri­ of his letter of 23 June 1673 to Oldenburg, and to the original paper
fugal force is instanced as one species of the ‘force of a body’ to perse­ (MS. IVa) from which was taken the example of the usefulness of centri­
vere in its state of movement or rest. It is not stated whether the motion fugal force quoted in the first paragraph of the 1673 letter. Nowhere in
in question is rectilinear or not. But that this is intended is evident from his description of this paragraph from the letter to Oldenburg, nor in
a rather more detailed definition of the ‘force of a body’ in Def. 12 of his resume of the principal results of the original paper, does Newton
MS. Xa, where centrifugal force is now instanced as a species of the give any indication of having changed his view of centrifugal force from
‘force of a body’ to persevere in its state of rest or of motion in a straight that expressed in this letter and paper.
line with uniform speed. Why Newton should thus have instanced cen­ A second reference to the 1673 letter occurs in Newton’s letter of
trifugal force as an example of the ‘force of a body’, i.e. its inertia, as 27 July 1686 to Halley. After reporting the discovery of a copy of the
opposed to a force derived from the tendency to persevere in a straight
* T h e best general account of this controversy is that given in Koyr^ [2].
' See M S . V ila . ^ As first pointed out by Hall [2]. ^ See Correspondence, vol. ii, Letters 285-91.
58 N E W T O N ’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS
NE W TO N ’ S CONCEPT OF C O N A T U S 59
letter in question, backed up by a quotation of the first paragraph in assumption would be that centrifugal force played no role at all; in
extensOy he continues:
which case this test would have marked the transition from a belief in
Thus far this letter concerned the Vis Centrifuga. . . . Now from these centrifugal to one in centripetal force, at least in the case of orbital
words it’s evident, that I was at that time versed in the theory of the force motion.^ But how then explain the references to centrifugal force in the
arising from circular motion, and had an eye upon the forces of the planets, letter of 23 June 1673 to Oldenburg, especially that to the endeavour of
knowing how to compare them by the proportions of their periodical revolu­
the Moon from the Earth? It is natural to regard these references as
tions and distances from the centre they move about: an instance of which you
evidence of a continued belief by Newton in centrifugal force for
have here in the comparison of the forces of the moon arising from her men­
strual motion about the earth, and annual about the sun. So then in this theory circular orbital motion; in which case one seems forced to assume that
I am plainly before Mr. Hooke. there was either no test of the law of gravitation during the Plague Years,
or that it involved the notion of centrifugal force. This latter assumption
The remaining reference to centrifugal force occurs in Newton’s
is entirely plausible: Newton could well have regarded the stability of
letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley. Writing of Halley’s experiment of a
the Moon in her orbit about the Earth, and of the planets in their orbits
pendulum clock at St. Helena to demonstrate the diminution of gravity
about the Sun, as the direct result of a balance between a centripetal pull
at the equator due to the diurnal motion he says:
of the Earth, or the Sun, inwards, and a centrifugal force of the Moon,
The experiment was new to me, but not the notion; for in that very paper or the planets, outwards. This was the manner in which Borelli^ attempted
which I told you was written some time above 15 years ago and to the best of to explain the stability of circular orbits, and Newton could possibly
my memory was written 18 or 19 years ago, I calculated the force of ascent
have been influenced by Borelli’s discussion prior to his first test— cer­
at the Equator arising from the earth’s diurnal motion in order to know what
would be the diminution of gravity thereby. tainly he had read it by 1686.2 In any case, apart from any possible
influence of Borelli,'^ it would have been fairly natural for Newton to
In the light of the evidence so far presented what answer is to be
approach the stability of a circular orbit in this way, especially if we
given to the question of whether Newton continued to believe in the
assume, as seems plausible, that his derivation of the inverse square law
physical reality of centrifugal force up to and beyond the composition
of gravitation immediately prior to the first test was based on considera­
of the Principia ? On the one hand we have the striking absence of any
tion of the force of a globe rotating within a spherical surface. For in
reference to centrifugal force in the treatment of orbital motion in the
this case the centrifugal force of the globe, as evidenced by its pressure
Principia'y on the other hand we have the repeated references to this on the spherical surface, was exactly balanced by an equal and opposite
concept in the discussion of rotation in the Scholium to the Definitions, pressure of the sphere on the globe, and this could have suggested a
and in the correspondence of 1686 with Halley. Perhaps the best approach similar balance between the conatus a centra terrae of the Moon and the
to some sort of understanding, and explanation, of this apparent para­
dox is to attempt to trace through the development of Newton’s views on ' T his was originally my own view.
conatus a centra from the beginning, paying special attention to a pos­ ^ Borelli [i]. For a discussion of Borelli’s views see Koyre [3].
3 And probably much earlier. There was a copy of Borelli’s work in New ton’s
sible transition from the concept of centrifugal to that of centripetal library. He refers to it in the unfortunate postscript to his letter of 20 June 1686 to
force. Halley; ‘he has published Borell’s hypothesis in his own name; and the asserting of this
to himself, and completing it as his own, seems to me the ground of all the stir he makes.
There can be no doubt, as already indicated, that Newton’s treatment Borel did something in it; and wrote modestly.’
of circular motion in the earliest researches was firmly based on the ^ Or of Descartes, who in Art. 140 of Part 3 of his Principia explains the stability of a
planet’s (circular) orbit by a balance between two opposing conati, one outward due
notion of conatus a centro, or centrifugal force. The question then to the circular motion of the planet about the sun, and the other inward due to the
naturally arises; if he carried out a test of the inverse square law of action of the surrounding vortex material. Replace the latter conatus by a natural inward
tendency to the sun and there results Borelli’s hypothesis. Descartes’s view of the
gravitation during the Plague Years, ^more probably in 1666, what part, matter is referred to by Newton at the foot of p. 3 of M S . Add. 4003: ‘ S ed postea
if any, did the notion of centrifugal force then play? One plausible tamen in Terra et Planetis ponit conatum recedendi a sole tanquam a centro circa quod
moventur, quo per consimilem conatum Vorticis gyrantis in suis a sole distantijs librantur
’ For a discussion of this question see below, Chapter 4. Art. 140 part 3.’ See M S . V I, § 2.
60 N E W T O N ’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS 3 N E W TO N ’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS 61
inward pull of the Earth. A plausible explanation could then also be that his attention would soon have become directed to centripetal
given of Newton’s peculiar suggestion (in his letter of 23 June 1673 to rather than centrifugal forces. In the case of motion in a uniform circular
Oldenburg for Huygens) that the invariable aspect of the Moon from the orbit, as in the Moon about the Earth, or the approximate orbits of the
Earth was due to her much greater endeavour from the Earth compared planets about the Sun, it is natural to attach equal importance to the in­
with that from the Sun. At first glance this theory seems absurd, for if the ward pull towards the centre and the centrifugal force outwards. But
endeavour of the Moon from the Earth is greater than from the Sun, this the situation is vastly different in the case of the elliptical motion of a
would seem a good reason for the Moon to depart from the Earth rather planet about the Sun at one focus. Now the problem of paramount in­
than the Sun. But if we assume that Newton measured the inward pull terest, one to which Kepler had tried in vain to give an answer, is the
of the Earth on the Moon by the outward endeavour of the Moon from the nature of the force exerted by the Sun on the planet. Having first proved
Earth, then the greater value of this endeavour compared with that from the astounding result that this force must be directed solely towards* the
the Sun would now be a measure of the much stronger hold of the Earth focus, it remained to find the variation in its magnitude at different
on the Moon compared with that of the Sun. And this in turn could points of the ellipse. In some such way we must suppose Newton’s treat­
conceivably explain the invariable aspect of the Moon from the Earth. ment of motion in an ellipse, and then general orbital motion, became
A similar interpretation applied to the original argument in MS. IVa dominated by the notion of centripetal force directed to a point. It would,
would then tend to show that this manuscript was composed after the of course, have been possible for him to have introduced . fictitious cen­
3

first test, the notion of universal gravitation being present in Newton’s trifugal force equal and opposite to the centripetal force. But this would
mind when he composed it though absent from the manuscript itself— have been entirely gratuitous. For it was now clear that the whole
perhaps for reasons of secrecy, or because the agreement between process of orbital motion under central forces could be looked on as a
theory and experiment in the first test, and in the test implicitly con­ continual drawing away of the body from its natural, inertial path along
tained in this manuscript, still left him in considerable doubt of the the tangent into its actual curved path. The problem therefore was:
adequacy of the inverse square law of universal gravitation as an explana­ given the orbit to determine the force, and vice versa. As Newton him­
tion of the stability of the lunar and planetary orbits.* self expressed it:
Given Newton’s familiarity with the notion of centrifugal force, his for the whole burden of philosophy seems to consist in this— from the pheno­
possible use of it to explain the stability of circular orbits, and his mena of motions to investigate the forces of nature, and then from these forces
definite reference to it in the letter of 23 June 1673, it would have been to demonstrate the other phenomena.^
natural for him to attempt to use it when he first seriously turned his Given the dominant role of centripetal force in the treatment of orbital
attention to the problem of Kepler-motion in December 1679. There is motion in Book I of the Principia, and the expected absence of any use
even some evidence that he had actually contemplated applying the of, or reference to, the notion of centrifugal force, I think we need not
idea of centrifugal force to the problem of motion in an ellipse at a very regard the references to centrifugal force and planetary motion in the
early stage. For beneath his discussion of circular motion on folio i of 1686 correspondence with Halley as evidence for Newton’s real views on
the Waste Book occurs the following entry: this subject at that time. These are surely to be found in the Principia.
If a body be moved in an Ellipse that its force in each point (if its motion in And there is really no paradox here since Newton in his correspondence
that point be given) would [ ?] be found by a tangent circle of equal crooked­ with Halley was not concerned to state his actual views on the subject,
ness with that point of the Ellipse. but only to describe his views of 1673 and earlier, and to attempt to con­
There is no evidence, however, that he succeeded in solving the prob­ vince Halley that these proved his understanding of the problem of
lem of Kepler-motion by this method in 1679. Instead it seems certain planetary motion, including a knowledge of the inverse square law of

* Remember W histon’s statement that N ew ton’s disappointment over the first test * T h e force could equally well have heen directed away from the focus, but in that
made him suspect ‘that this Power [that restrained the moon in her orbit] was partly case the orbits would have been hyperbolic rather than elliptic.
that of Gravity, and partly that of Cartesius’ vortices’. ^ Preface to first edition of Principia.
62 NE W T O N ’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS 3 N EW TO N’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS 63
gravitation, prior to that of Hooke. Opinions will differ on whether or not force, something which can be seen most clearly by following the apparent
Newton was justified in citing these views as evidence of such an under­ development of such forces from a state of rest. For example, if a stone
standing, and whether there was not a certain element of special plead­ is attached to a slightly elastic spring whose other end is fixed, and is
ing in his argument.^ It is also a moot point how' far so acute a mind as suddenly set in motion by a blow at right angles to the length of the
Halley, and one so well versed in the Principia, would have been persuaded spring, then the ensuing motion of the stone, and the resulting tension in
by Newton’s case. Certainly it would have been most interesting to know the spring, can both be explained in terms of the laws of motion and the
how Newton would have replied to a request from Halley for an explana­ elastic properties of the spring. No introduction of centrifugal force is
tion of his references to centrifugal force in the light of the treatment of necessary here any more than in the discussion of the oscillatory motion
orbital motion in the Principia. Nevertheless, although we can thus resulting from the projection of the stone along, instead of at right angles
easily dispose of the apparent paradox posed by these references to to, the spring; nor is the ensuing tension in the spring any more (or less)
centrifugal force in connexion with planetary and lunar motion in the mysterious in the first case than in the second. It is only when we imagine
1686 correspondence with Halley, there still remains the other reference a rotary motion as pre-existing from eternity^ rather than having been
(in the letter of 14 July 1686) to the centrifugal force arising from the created at some instant of time, that there is any mystery about the
earth’s diurnal motion, and the various uses of the term in the discussion resulting forces in the rotating body.
of rotary motion in the Scholium to the Definitions of the Principia. It can be argued, of course, that centrifugal forces make their appear­
In the Scholium to the Definitions preceding Book I of the Principia ance relative to rotating frames of reference. For example, a body
Newton discusses the causes and ejfects which distinguish true from attached to a rotating plate experiences a ‘force’ outwards; if released
relative motions. The causes are the forces impressed to produce true it will move along the outward radius relative to the plate. But this is
motion ; whereas true motion in a body can only be generated by the only to say that when released the body will move uniformly in a straight
action of such forces, motion relative to a given body may be produced line along the instantaneous tangent to its original path relative to
by forces impressed on other bodies, or may even be absent in spite of the absolute space; from which its observed motion relative to the plate can
action of impressed forces, as when equal bodies are acted on simul­ immediately be deduced. So that it is true to say that the body has a
taneously by equal forces. As to the effects which distinguish real from centrifugal endeavour relative to the rotating plate. But the ‘results’ of
relative motion, these are ‘the forces of receding from the axis of circular the rotation, for example, the pressure of the body on its support, will
motion’. Evidently, then, he has in mind the conatus or ‘endeavour of be the same whether we look at the plate from the standpoint of the
receding from a centre or axis of rotation’, a phrase actually used in the rotating frame or from that of absolute space, it is only their explanation
same passage. These centrifugal forces are in turn demonstrated by which is different: relative to absolute space their origin and presence is
certain observable effects, such as the concave surface of the rotating explained in terms of the laws of motion in precisely the same way as
mass of water in the bucket, or the tension in the string between the two the tension produced in a slightly elastic spring by a body moving
rotating globes. Or, he might have added, by the diminution in the force (approximately) in a circle. Relative to the rotating frame their presence
of gravity at the equator due to the Earth’s supposed diurnal motion, (but not their origin) can be explained in terms of supposed centrifugal
as referred to in the letter to Elalley of 14 July 1686. forces corresponding to the undoubted centrifugal endeavours.
I do not propose to enter here into the question of the proof supplied If it is accepted that centrifugal forces have no place within the New­
by these and other observable effects for the existence of absolute rota­ tonian framework of absolute space and time, being no more necessary
tion. The point at issue is the existence of centrifugal forces arising from for an explanation of the effects of rotation than in the case of orbital
the rotation of extended bodies. Once again, as in the case of orbital motion, it has still to be asked why Newton retained these forces for
motion, especially circular motion, there can be no doubt of the answer: rotating bodies while dispensing with them for orbital motion. Initially,
relative to Newton's own system of dynamics there is no need for centrifugal of course, the notion of introducing centrifugal force in rotating bodies
would have been a perfectly natural one. For we know that Newton
' For a discussion of this see below, Chapter 4, pp. 72-73.
64 N E W T O N ’ S CONCEPT OF CONATUS

originally believed in the existence of centrifugal forces for single bodies


or particles describing uniform circular motions, and in the case of the
uniform rotation of an extended body all its component parts describe T E S T S OF T H E L A W OF G R A V I T A T I O N
uniform circular motions about centres lying on the axis of rotation. But A G A IN S T THE M O O N ’S MOTIO N
whereas the study of orbital motion after the solution of the problem of
Kepler-motion revealed no properties which could not be accounted for
R e f e r e n c e s to a test of the law of gravitation during the Plague Years
purely in terms of centripetal forces, this was apparently not the case
occur in the following accounts of Whiston,^ Pemberton,^ and Newton^
for the effects produced in the rotation of extended bodies. It was
himself:
therefore natural, though as we have seen inconsistent, for Newton to
Whiston: What the Occasion of Sir Isaac Newton’s leaving the Cartesian
continue to employ the concept of centrifugal force in the latter case while
Philosophy, and of discovering his amazing Theory of Gravity was, I have
dispensing with it in the first. heard him long ago, soon after my first Acquaintance with him, which was
A word finally about the case of centrifugal force instanced by Newton 1694, thus relate, and of which Dr Pemberton gives the like Account, and
in the 1686 correspondence with Halley, that referring to the diminution somewhat more fully, in the Preface to his Explication of his Philosophy:
of gravity to be expected at the equator due to ‘the force of ascent at the It was this. An Inclination came into Sir Isaac’s Mind to try, whether the
equator arising from the Earth’s diurnal motion’. Newton’s first calcula­ same Power did not keep the Moon in her Orbit, notwithstanding her pro­
tion of this force of ascent is to be found in MS. III. It was therefore one jectile Velocity, which he knew always tended to go along a strait Line the
Tangent of that Orbit, which makes Stones and all heavy Bodies with us
of the earliest problems in circular motion to be treated by him. It was
fall downward, and which we call Gravity} Taking this Postulatum, which
likewise the only one in which the notion of conatus a centro was entirely
had been thought of before, that such Power might decrease, in a duplicate
justified, since he would undoubtedly have thought of the problem from Proportion of the Distances from the Earth’s Center,^ Upon Sir Isaac’s First
the point of view of an observer on the Earth’s surface. For such an Trial, when he took a Degree of a great Circle on the Earth’s Surface,
observer the conatus a centro could become a real phenomenon provided whence a Degree at the Distance of the Moon was to be determined also,
the rotation of the Earth were sufficiently large, or the gravity of the to be 60 measured Miles only, according to the gross Measures then in
Earth sufficiently small. Things would then fly off the surface as envis­ Use. He was, in some Degree, disappointed, and the Power that restrained
aged by Ptolemy, but upwards, towards the sky! It would be interesting the Moon in her Orbit, measured by the versed Sines of that Orbit,® appeared
not to be quite the same that was to be expected, had it been the Power of
to know if Newton had this example of conatus a centro in mind when
Gravity alone, by which the Moon was there influenc’d. Upon this Dis­
developing his exact theory of circular motion in MS. IVa. appointment, which made Sir Isaac suspect that this Power was partly that
of Gravity, and partly that of Cartesius’s Vortices,^ he threw aside the
Paper of his Calculation and went to other Studies.
Pemberton: The first thoughts, which gave rise to his Principia, he had, when
he retired from Cambridge in 1666 on account of the plague. As he sat
alone in a garden,7 he fell into a speculation on the power of gravity; that as
* Whiston [i], vol. i, pp. 35-36. ^ Pemberton [i]. Preface.
^ Catalogue of Portsmouth Collection (Cambridge, 1888), Section i, Division xi,
number 41. Ball [i], p. 6, was of the opinion that this was written some years after the
1686 correspondence with Halley, ‘perhaps about 1714 ’.
See, for example, Bullialdus [i], p. 23.
* Implying, rightly or not, that Newton measured the force on the moon in terms of
her ‘fall’ towards the Earth in a given interval of time.
* Various references to Descartes’s vortex theory in M S . I prove New ton’s familiarity
with the theory at an early date.
7 W e are reminded here of the incident of the falling apple of which the most cir­
cumstantial account is that given by Stukeley [i], p. 19;
66 T E S T S OF THE LAW OF G R A VI T AT IO N
A G A I N S T THE MOON’ S MOTION 67
this power is not found sensibly diminished at the remotest distance from
the center of the earth, to which we can rise, neither at the tops of the next year in January had the Theory of colours, and in May following I had
loftiest buildings, nor even on the summits of the highest mountains; it entrance into the inverse method of fluxions. And the same year’ I began
appeared to him reasonable to conclude, that this power must extend much to think of gravity extending to the orb of the Moon, and having found out
farther than was usually thought; why not as high as the moon, said he to how to estimate the force with which [a] globe revolving within a sphere
himself? and if so, her motion must be influenced by it; perhaps she is presses the surface of the sphere, from Kepler’s Rule of the periodical
retained in her orbit thereby. However, though the power of gravity is not times of the Planets being in a sesquialterate proportion of their distances
sensibly weakened in the little change of distance, at which we can place from the centers of their Orbs I deduced that the forces which keep the
ourselves from the center of the earth, yet it is very possible that, so high as Planets in their Orbs must [be] reciprocally as the squares of their dis­
the moon this power may differ much in strength from what it is here. To tances from the centers about which they revolve: and thereby compared
make an estimate, what might be the degree of this diminution, he con­ the force requisite to keep the Moon in her Orb with the force of gravity at
sidered with himself, that if the moon be retained in her orbit by the force the surface of the earth, and found them answer pretty nearly. All this was
of gravity, no doubt the primary planets are carried round the sun by the in the two plague years of 1665 and 1666, for in those days I was in the
like power. And by comparing the periods of the several planets with their prime of my age for invention, and minded Mathematicks and Philosophy
distances from the sun,’ he found, that if any power like gravity held them more than at any time since.
in their courses, its strength must decrease in the duplicate proportion of Whiston stated that he had his account from Newton soon after
the increase of distance. This he concluded by supposing them to move in
making his acquaintance in 1694, and it is possible, if not probable, that
perfect circles concentrical to the sun, from which the orbits of the greatest
he made a note of it at the time. But since Whiston refers to the ‘like
part of them do not much differ. Supposing therefore the power of gravity,
when extended to the moon, to decrease in the same manner, he computed account’ of Pemberton it would be dangerous to regard the two accounts
whether that force would be sufficient to keep the moon in her orbit. In as entirely independent, and since Pemberton’s account was derived
this computation, being absent from books, he took the common estimate in from Newton towards the end of the latter’s life^ it is natural to regard
use among geographers and our seamen, before Norwood had measured Newton’s own earlier^ account as the most reliable of the three.
the earth, that 6o English miles were contained in one degree of latitude on Nevertheless, the accounts of both Whiston and Pemberton contain
the surface of the earth. But as this is a very faulty supposition, each degree certain circumstantial details having an authentic ring difficult to resist.'^
containing about 69J of our miles,^ his computation did not answer For example, Whiston’s account gives a strong impression that Newton’s
expectation; whence he concluded, that some other caused must at least
recollection of his first test of the law of universal gravitation arose from
join with the action of the power of gravity on the moon. On this account
he laid aside for that time any farther thoughts upon this matter. a chance reference by Whiston to the ‘Cartesian philosophy’ he was
Newton: I found the method [of fluxions] by degrees in the years 1665 and then studying at Cambridge.s Newton possibly replied that he too had
1666. In the beginning of the year 1665 I found the method of approximat­ formerly studied the same philsophy,^ and then proceeded to describe
ing Series and the Rule for reducing any dignity of any Binomial into such the occasion of his leaving that philosophy and discovering his own
a series. The same year in May I found the method of tangents of Gregory
’ T h is could refer either to 1665 or 1666. From the context 1666 would seem to be
and Slusius, and in November had the direct method of fluxions, and the the more probable year. It is also the one given by Pemberton.
^ ‘For it was in the very last years of Sir Isaac’s life, that I had the honour of his
‘A fter dinner on 15th April 1726 the weather being warm we went into the garden acquaintance’ ; Pemberton [i], Preface, p. 2.
and drank thea under the shade of some apple trees, only he and myself. Am idst other 3 See n. 3, p. 65 above.

discourse, he told me, he was just in the same situation, as when formerly, the notion Against the view that Pemberton’s account is worthless, having been taken from
of gravitation came into his mind. It was occasioned by the fall of an apple, as he sat in a Newton in extreme old age, it could be argued that memories of childhood and youth
contemplative mood.’ are sometimes much more vivid in old age than in middle life. O n this view it is just
* B y means of Kepler’s T hird Law of Planetary Motion. conceivable, though perhaps improbable, that Newton remembered his first test of the
^ Cajori [i], p. 150, points out that this implies i mile == 5280 ft whereas it seems law of gravitation in his old age having previously forgotten it in 1686 at the time of the
more probable that Newton would have taken i mile = 5000 ft. See n. 3, p. 68, below. controversy with Hooke.
5 ‘We at Cambridge, poor Wretches, were ignominously studying the fictitious H ypo­
3 For example, that of ‘Cartesius’s Vortices’ as remarked by Whiston. A t this point
theses of the Cartesian, which Sir Isaac Newton had also himself done formerly, as I
Whiston is therefore more detailed than Pemberton, thus strengthening the possibility
of his account having been independent o f the latter’s. have heard him say’ : Whiston [i], immediately before quotation on p. 65 above.
^ As proved conclusively by M S . Add. 4003.
68 T E S T S OF THE L AW OF G R A V I T A T I O N 4 A G A I N S T THE MOON’ S MOTION 69

theory of gravitation. Of particular interest here is the reference to minute.^ This has to be compared with the true figure of approximately
Newton’s disappointment at the failure of his test having lead him to 16 feet in one minute, corresponding to a fall of the same distance in
one second at the surface of the Earth, a figure derived by Newton in
suspect that
MS. III."
This power [by which the moon was influenced] was partly that of Gravity, It seems probable, therefore, that in this particular respect the accounts
and partly that of Cartesius’s Vortices. of Pemberton and Whiston are rather more reliable than that of Newton
himself. Nevertheless, in spite of this discrepancy, and in the absence of
Evidently he had not entirely freed himself from the persuasive argu­ any further evidence, there would seem no very good reason to doubt
ments of Part 3 of Descartes’s Principia Philosophiae\ Equally telling is that Newton carried out a test of the inverse square law of gravitation
Pemberton’s statement that Newton took the common measure of 6o during the Plague Years, more probably in 1666, the year mentioned
miles to a degree of latitude at the surface of the earth ‘being absent from by Pemberton, and likewise the more probable year from Newton’s own
books’. account.3 Some further items of evidence must now be considered, some
One discrepancy between Newton’s account and those of Whiston and of which support, while some oppose, the supposition of a test during
Pemberton has been the subject of much discussion, namely Newton’s the Plague Years.
statement that he found the force necessary to keep the moon in her orbit One item of evidence supporting the bare possibility of some test or
to answer ‘pretty nearly’ to the force of gravity, as opposed to Whiston’s other of the law of gravitation at an early period is supplied by Newton’s
statement that Newton was ‘in some degree disappointed’, and Pember­ treatment of the problem of circular motion in the early dynamical
ton’s statement that ‘his computation did not answer expectation’. The manuscripts.'^ This, as we have seen, commences in the Waste Book and
extent of this discrepancy obviously hinges on the meaning to be attached culminates in MS. IVa devoted to circular motion and containing an
to Newton’s phrase ‘pretty nearly’, and this in turn depends on the actual explicit statement of the law of centrifugal force. Without this law
value derived by Newton for the ratio of the force of gravity at the Newton could not have derived the inverse square law of gravitation by
distance of the moon’s orbit to the same force at the surface of the Earth, way of Kepler’s third law of planetary motion. Whereas the certain
or of the corresponding figure for the ‘fall’ of the moon in her orbit in knowledge that he was in possession of this law at an early period,s
one minute of time. Assuming that he took the period of the moon in her possibly as early as 1665 or 1666, must necessarily increase our confi­
orbit as approximately 27 days 8 hours, ^the radius of the moon’s orbit dence in the account in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum. One striking
as sixty times that of the radius of the Earth,^ and the figure of 60 miles detail of this account increases our confidence still further, namely, New­
to a degree of latitude at the surface of the Earth mentioned by both ton’s reference to his
Whiston and Pemberton, the fall of the moon in her orbit in one minute having found out how to estimate the force with which [a] globe revolving
would have come out at approximately 13*9 or 13-2 feet, according as he within a sphere presses the surface of the sphere.
set one mile equal to 5280 or 5000 feet. After a thorough investigation of
This was exactly the situation considered by Newton in his first re­
contemporary evidence Cajori concluded that Newton was more likely
connaissance of the problem of circular motion in the Waste Book.^
to have set one mile equal to 5000 rather than to 5280 feet.^ Since this
finding is confirmed by Newton’s use of 5000 feet to a mile in M SS. I l l * Assuming, of course, that he was thinking in terms of such a ‘fall’ produced by the
pull of the Earth’s gravitation as opposed to a balance between this latter force and an
and IVa, whereas he nowhere in the early manuscripts uses the figure of
outward centrifugal conatus. In the latter case 13-2 would represent the distance out­
5280, it seems most probable that the actual figure arrived at by Newton ward through w hich the moon would have moved in one minute under the action of this
for the ‘fair of the moon in her orbit was approximately 13*2 feet in one conatus. See Chapter 3 above for New ton’s concept of conatus.
^ T h e original figure employed in that manuscript, about half the figure finally de­
duced, would have led to an intolerably large discrepancy between theory and observa­
* In M S . IV a it is taken as 27 days, 7 hours, 43 minutes. tion for the motion of the moon.
^ T h e figure adopted in M S . IVa. ^ See n. i, p. 67 above. * See above, Chapter 1.2.
^ See Cajori [i], pp. 150-6. Cajori could only find one author prior to 1666 (Oiigh- 5 See below. Chapter 6.2. * See M S . Ild , Ax.-Prop. 20.
tred) using 1° = 60 miles of 5280 ft.
70 T E S T S OF THE LA W OF GR A VI T AT IO N
A G A I N S T THE MOON’ S MOTION 71
Nevertheless, although he went on to derive an exact result involving the
he was indebted to Hooke for at least the initial impetus which led to his
centrifugal force or conatus at folio i of that manuscript, there is appa­
thorough investigation of the problem of Kepler-motion in the winter
rently no trace of his having completed this line of approach by deriving
of 1679-80. Evidently he would dearly have loved to have been able
the actual dependence of the centrifugal force on the radius and the speed
to present Halley (and the Royal Society) with incontrovertible dated
as implied by the account in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum. At this
evidence of his knowledge of the inverse square law long prior to any
point a suggestion of Rouse Ball’s^ comes to the rescue, namely, that the
public or private statement of it by Hooke. But he was unable to do so,
proof of the law of centrifugal force at the end of the Scholium to Prop,
having to content himself with two items of evidence, neither of them
IV, Theor. IV, of Book I of the Principia^ was possibly the actual one
very impressive. The first, and much less important, item is contained in
employed by Newton to calculate the force exerted by the globe on the
the postscript of his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley. There Newton
sphere. That this proof corresponds to the situation referred to by New­
quotes the following passage from his letter of 7 December 1675 to
ton in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum is at once evident: equally
Oldenburg:
evident is the similarity between the method here employed— replace­
And as the earth, so perhaps may the sun imbibe this spirit copiously to con­
ment of the actual circular path by an inscribed polygon, and the actual
serve his shining, and keep the planets from receding further from him; and
continuous force by a series of sharp forces of reflection at the corners of
they that will may also suppose that this spirit affords or carries with it thither
the polygon— and the method followed by Newton in his treatment of the solary fuel and material principle of light.. . .
circular motion on folio i of the Waste Book. One further item of evidence
Newton himself made no large claim on the basis of this passage, con­
is supplied by Newton at the end of the letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley
tenting himself with noting that it proved his concern with the problem
in which he enclosed the proof in question with instructions to insert it
of planetary motions at this time; as for the inverse square dependence
after the Scholium to Prop. IV, Theor. IV, of Book I of the Principia\^
of the force of gravity supposedly implicit in the passage, it was ‘But an
there he mentions that he met with this proof ‘in turning over some old
hypothesis, and so to be looked on only as one of my guesses’.
papers’.
The other, and much more important, item is found in the following
In the light of this mutually interlocking evidence it seems reasonable
passage in the body of the same letter to Halley:
to suppose that a test of the law of gravitation did take place during the
That in one of my papers writ (I cannot say in what year, but I am sure some
Plague Years, being based on a derivation of the law of centrifugal force
time before I had any correspondence with Mr Oldenburg, and that’s above
by the ‘polygonal’ method, and in all probability also on the figure of
fifteen years ago)^ the proportion of the forces of the planets from the sun, reci­
60 miles of 5000 feet to a degree of latitude at the equator. Otherwise procally duplicate to their distances from him, is expressed, and the propor­
one seems forced to conclude that Newton not only misinformed both tion of our gravity to the moon’s conatus recedendi a centra terrae is calculated,
Whiston and Pemberton, but also fabricated the very circumstantial though not accurately enough. That when Hugenius put out his Horol. Oscil.,
account in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum, presumably after re­ a copy being presented to me, in my letter of thanks to him, I gave those rules
freshing his memory of his early researches in dynamics by referring to in the end thereof a particular commendation for their usefulness in Philo­
the Waste Book. sophy, and added out of my aforesaid paper an instance of their usefulness, in
comparing the forces of the moon from the earth, and earth from the sun; in
Let us turn now to the evidence provided by the Newton-Halley
determining a problem about the moon’s phase, and putting a limit to the
correspondence of 1686+ arising out of Hooke’s claim that Newton was
sun’s parallax, which shows that I had then my eye upon comparing the forces
indebted to him for the notion of the inverse square law of gravitation of the planets arising from their circular motion, and understood it.
as applied to the motions of the planets. Hooke’s claim stung Newton
Newton was later to substantiate his claim to have written this letter
to the quick, more especially, one feels, because he was well aware that
to Oldenburg by discovering a copy in the hand of his friend John
' See Ball, [1], p. 13. * Reproduced above, at Chapter 1.2, p. i i . Wickins, quoting the first paragraph, that relating to centrifugal force, in
^ A nd thus conveniently ‘compass’, as Neii'ton thought, the dispute between him­
self and Hooke. * In his letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley Newton refers again to this paper, stating
See especially Koyre [2]. ‘to the best of my memory [it] was w’rit 18 or 19 years ago’.
72 T E S T S OF THE L A W OF G R A VI T AT IO N 4 A G A I N S T THE MOON ’ S MOTION 73
his letter of 27 July 1686 to Halley. The existence of the paper referred to meaning of the phrase elsewhere in the same and other letters of the
by Newton is likewise certain, since it may be identified with MS. IVa.^ correspondence. ^
Given Newton’s very detailed and accurate synopsis of this paper Admittedly, the fact that this paper contains no trace of the concept of
in the above passage it seems likely that he had the actual paper before universal gravitation does not prove that Newton had not entertained
him when composing his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley. In any case it such a notion prior to its composition. As Hall rightly remarks: ‘With
is evident that nowhere in this letter does he go beyond the actual con­ Newton, however, the argument from silence is never s tr o n g ,O n the
tents of the paper. In particular, he is very careful to refer always to the other hand, the continual reference to endeavour from the centre in
forces of the planets from the sun, or of the moon from the Earth. Like­ circular motion, and the absence of any reference to centripetal force is
wise he nowhere explicitly claims that this paper proved his familiarity in striking, and I think significant, contrast to the position in the
with the inverse square law of gravitation as opposed to the inverse square Principia. For there the terms centrifugal force, conatus, or endeavour
dependence of the forces of the planets from the sun. Such a claim would, from the centre, nowhere appear in Newton’s treatment of orbital
in fact, have been entirely unjustified, since an examination of the paper motion in Books I and III .3 Instead the emphasis throughout is on
reveals that although he compares the ratio of the force of gravity at centripetal force in its capacity of drawing a body away from its natural,
the Earth to the moon’s endeavour to recede from the sun, and proves inertial path along the tangent, and forcing it to follow its actual curved
that the endeavours of the planets vary inversely as the squares of their orbit about the centre of force. This approach to the problem of orbital
distances from the sun, yet he makes no mention of the forces on the motion is particularly evident in the discussion of gravitation in terms of
planets towards the sun, or of the force on the moon towards the Earth, the moon’s motion about the Earth at the beginning of Book III. One
so that there is apparently no indication whatsoever of the notion of seems forced to conclude that if Newton really intended to give Halley
universal gravitation.2 And this is particularly evident in the omission the impression that this paper implied not only an interest in the prob­
of any comment on the discrepancy between the calculated ratio of lem of planetary motions, as it certainly did, but also an understanding
gravity at the surface of the Earth to the moon’s endeavour to recede of that problem including a knowledge of the ‘duplicate proportion’
from the Earth, and the ratio to be expected on the basis of the inverse of universal gravitation and its application to the motion of the moon,
square law of gravitation. Nevertheless, whether intentionally or not, then he was apparently following a line of argument quite different from
Newton’s references to the ‘duplicate proportion’ of the forces of the that found in the Principia presented to the Royal Society a short time
planets from the sun, and his note that the ratio of the force of gravity previously.'^
to the moon’s endeavour to recede from the Earth was not calculated Given that this paper contained no explicit evidence for a knowledge
‘accurately enough’, would inevitably have given Halley the impression of the inverse square law of gravitation, and that Newton seems scarcely
that Newton thought this paper proved his early familiarity with the to have been justified in giving the impression that it implied such a
‘duplicate proportion’ of universal gravitation. For this was the invariable* knowledge, why then did he make no mention of the early test of the
law of gravitation referred to in the accounts of Whiston, Pemberton,
* As first pointed out by Hall [2].
and Newton himself? One possible explanation, of course, would be that
^ Though David Gregory evidently formed a different impression on his visit to
Newton at Cambridge in M ay 1694: there was no such test apart from the somewhat inaccurate comparison of
‘I saw a manuscript [written] before the year 1669 (the year when its author M r
Newton was made Lucasian Professor of Mathematics) where all the foundations of his ' For example, in the letter of 27 M ay (twice), of 20 June (three times), 14 July
philosophy are laid: namely the gravity of the M oon to the Earth, and of the planets to (once), 27 July (once).
the Sun. And in fact all these even then are subjected to calculation. I also saw in that 2 Hall [2].
manuscript the principle of equal times of a pendulum suspended between cycloids, 2 This, however, unfortunately does not prove that Newton had entirely given up the
before the publication of H uygens’ Horologium Oscillatorium.' (University Library, concept of conatus. There are the references to this concept in New ton’s discussion of
Edinburgh, Gregory C43, quoted in translation, Correspondence, vol. iii, p. 332.) absolute motion in the Scholium to the laws of motion. See above. Chapter 3, p. 62.
Since there » a paper on cycloidal pendulums in the Portsmouth Collection (M S. IVb) * But it must be remembered that the first test of the law of gravitation was
written in the same hand, and on the same size of paper as M S . IVa, it seems very prob­ possibly based on the notion of a balance between the inward pull of the Earth and an
able that the latter was the manuscript referred to by Gregory in the above passage. equal and opposite outward conatus of the moon. See above. Chapter 3, p. 59.
74 T E S T S OF THE LA W OF G R A VI T AT IO N 4 A G A I N S T THE MOON’ S MOTION 75
the force of gravity at the surface of the Earth to the moon’s endeavour hand, it seems possible, even probable, that Newton was guilty of some
to recede from the Earth contained in MS. IVa. In that case one has doubtful pleading in his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley, reminding us
to assume that both the reported use of 6o miles to a degree at the surface forcibly of Hooke’s bitter entry in his diary on 15 February 1688/9:
of the Earth, and the method of determining the law of centrifugal At Halys met Newton— ^vainly pretended claim yet acknowledged my
force referred to in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum were figments of information. Interest has no conscience. . . .
Newton’s imagination. For the measure of the Earth’s radius employed On the basis of Pemberton’s account it has generally been assumed
in MS. IVa was the same as that employed in MS. I ll, in turn derived that Newton made his first successful test of the law of gravitation based
by Newton from Galileo’s Dialogue^ and though it happens to differ on Picard’s figure for the dimensions of the earth in 1679, following
little from 6o miles of 5000 feet to a degree at the surface of the Earth,* Hooke’s intervention. In that case, given his successful solution to the
this seems no reason for supposing that Newton would have confused the problems posed by Kepler’s first two laws of planetary motion, it is
two measures. Likewise the method of deriving the law of centrifugal certainly extraordinary that he should have lost interest in dynamics
force in MS. IVa, based on the use of the ‘deviation’ as a measure of the again till the time of Halley’s first visit to Cambridge in May 1684.*
endeavour to recede from the centre together with an application of There is, however, one aspect of Pemberton’s account in flat contra­
Newton’s extension of Galileo’s P law of falling bodies, could never be diction with other, more trustworthy evidence, namely his statement
confused with the polygonal approach to the same problem begun in the that having discovered the proposition relating to motion in an ellipse
Waste Book and completed in the proof at the end of the Scholium to Newton went on to compose nearly a dozen propositions relating to the
Prop. IV, Theor. IV, of the Principia. motion of the primary planets about the sun, the Principia being com­
On the other hand, if we reject this possibility, and assume that there posed from scarce any other material than those few propositions in the
was a true test of the inverse square law during the Plague Years, it is space of one year and a half. For elsewhere Newton himself stated that
then hardly surprising that Newton made no mention of it in his cor­ the Principia was entirely composed between December 1684 and May
respondence with Halley. For it is evident he was looking for dated 1686 apart from two propositions discovered in December 1679, and
evidence— ^witness his emphasis on the letter of 23 June 1673 to Olden­ twelve discovered in June and July 1684. The twelve propositions in
burg— and the original calculations of the first test, even if still extant in question fit remarkably well with the contents of the tract de Motu^
1686, would probably have been undated— like almost all early Newton which was thus most probably composed by Newton around June and
dynamical manuscripts including MS. IVa— and therefore of no help in July 1684 following Halley’s first visit in May of that year. The likeli­
establishing a watertight case against Hooke. hood of an error in Pemberton’s account at this point thus makes it
In the absence of further evidence, especially of any documentary permissible to doubt his assertion that Newton made his successful test
evidence of the calculations of the first test, or of the original of the proof of the law of gravitation in 1679. In that case the most probable alterna­
given at the end of the Scholium to Prop. IV, Theor. IV, of the Principia, tive date would be in 1684 or 1685, at some time following Halley’s
it is impossible to make a definite choice between these two possibilities. visit in May 1684. In fact, from Conduit’s account^ we know that
On the one hand, the assumption that there was no true test of the law Newton was unable to find the proposition of 1679 on the occasion of
of gravitation during the Plague Years argues for a degree of duplicity Halley’s visit. After Halley had left he would very probably have made a
on Newton’s part, both in casual conversations with Whiston and further careful search through all his old papers in dynamics for the
Pemberton (in the latter case long after Hooke’s death), and in his missing proposition, and it may have been in the course of this search
unpublished account in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum, difficult to that he came across the paper containing the calculations of his first test
credit even allowing for a continued desire to establish his indepen­ of the law of gravitation during the Plague Years. If he had reworked
dence of Hooke in the matter of universal gravitation. On the other these using Picard’s figure the resulting excellent agreement between
* A radius for the Earth of 3500 Italian miles of 5000 feet gives one degree at the ' A s opposed to August. See below, Chapter 6.4, p. 97.
equator equal to 6 1 -i miles. ^ See below, Chapter 6.4, p. 96. ^ Given in Brewster [i] vol. i, p. 297.
76 T E S T S OF THE LAW OF GR A V I T A T I O N
theory and observation would have given him just the stimulus he needed
to rework the 1679 proposition, and then carry his dynamics through to
their final completion— as we know he did.
T H E M O T I O N OF E X T E N D E D B O D I E S
In any case, it seems reasonably certain that the successful test was
carried out before the summer of 1685^ at the latest, for in Version III
5.1. K inem atical A spects
of the tract de Motu, in the penultimate paragraph of the Scholium to
Prob. 5 we find the following: T he first dynamical entries in the Waste Book deal only with the move­
ment, in modern parlance, of a mass-point or particle, or an extended
Nam virium centripetarum species una est gravitas: et computanti mihi prodijt
body devoid of rotation. But knowing Newton’s powerful drive to­
vis centripeta qua luna nostra detinetur in motu suo menstrua circa terram, ad vim
gravitatis his in superficie terrae, reciproce ut quadrata distantiarum a centra wards greater generality it is not surprising to find that he soon turns
terrae quamproxime. his attention to the general motion of extended bodies. His first recon­
naissance into this new territory is based on the concept of centre of
* See below, Chapter 6.4, pp. 97-102, for a discussion of the date of composition of
motion (or rotation) as a point ‘which rests when a body is moved with
Version II I of the tract de M otu (M S. IXc).
any circular but not progressive motion’h and on a peculiar criterion for
determining whether one body can be said to move towards another,
namely, that a body is said to move towards another body either when
all its parts move towards it, or else when some of its parts have more
movement towards it than others have from it.^ This criterion is but an
ansatz, and soon exhausts its usefulness, though its free creation by
Newton reminds us that his genius comprised both that of the pure and
the applied mathematician, whereas the concept of centre of motion
continues to play a central role until it finally coalesces with the other,
dynamical centre of motion in his treatment of the collision of two
rotating bodies. ^
From this criterion it follows that a line rotating about its mid-point
has no progressive motion, for the movement of any point of it towards
any fixed line is exactly balanced by the opposite motion of the mirror
points away from the same.'^ It follows likewise that when the centre of
motion (or rotation) is not at the mid-point ‘the whole line moves the
same way which the longest part doth’.s Also that if a line rotates but
has no progressive motion (in the sense of Def. 12) its centre of motion
must coincide with its middle point.^ And ‘by the same reason the middle
point of a parallelogram, parallelipiped, prism, cylinder, etc. (are at the)
centre of their motion’.
Having made a beginning of the study of the pure rotation of an
extended body he next considers the translational motion of such a body.
The simplest case is that in which the body is moved parallel to itself
J M S . lie , Def. 10. ^ Ibid., Def. 12. 3 M S . V . §§ 9, 10.
4 M S . Ild , A x. ir. 5 Ibid., Ax. 12. ^ Ibid., A x. 13.
’ Ibid., Ax. 14a.
78 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 5.1 5.2 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 79
(pure translation) when all its points describe parallel lines each with the centre of motion is first defined as a point such that if the body be
same determination and velocity as that of the body as a whole. * But if rotating about an axis through it there will be the same quantity of
the body moves both ‘straightly forward and circularly’ its centre of motion on both sides of any plane through this axis.^ It is probable that
motion has the same determination and velocity as the body.’ For this definition dated from a period when Newton still measured circular
example, any motion of a line (in a plane) may be compounded of a movement in terms of quantity of motion, not having developed the
certain pure translation of the line parallel to itself followed by a rotation concept of endeavour away from the centre on which the following,
about its middle point. In the first movement the determination of the final definition of centre of motion in the dynamical sense is based:
motion coincides with that of the mid-point, i.e. the centre of motion. ‘in every body there is a certain point called its centre of motion about
In the second there is no progressive motion (by Ax. 11). A reference to which if the body be anyway circulated the endeavours of its parts every
Ax. 17 and the corresponding diagram will show that Newton’s proof of way from the centre are exactly counter poised by opposite endeavours’.2
the result is identical with the modern proof. He has therefore introduced a notion of dynamical balance similar to
In the general case where the progressive part of the motion is no that found in practical applications of the theory of rotating bodies. In
longer restricted to be rectilinear but is in any ‘crooked line’ the centre fact, if one slightly amends Newton’s definition to read ‘the endeavours
of motion has the same determination and velocity as the body.^ For of its parts every way from the axis of rotation’ then it easily follows that
this has been proved true in the special case (Ax. 17), and a ‘crooked line’ the point in question must coincide with the centre of mass or gravity
may be thought of as made up of an infinite number of straight lines. of the body in question,^ a result well known to be necessary if the bear­
Alternatively, at any point of the ‘crooked line’ the motion may be con­ ings are to be free of periodic forces due to the rotation of the body. It
ceived to be along the tangent line. is interesting to note that on occasion Newton first uses the term centre
Unlike the case of translational velocity, for which a quantitative of gravity replacing it later by centre of motion.^ It is as if he had divined
measure has been given, his treatment of circular movement has so far that the two points are identical. And as usual his physical intuition is
been entirely qualitative. A quantitative measure of the concept of circular correct.
movement remains to be given; this is found in MS. V where he states On the other hand, it is possible that both this interchangeable use of
that ‘the angular quantity of a body’s circular motion and velocity is more the terms centre of motion and centre of gravity and the final definition
or less accordingly as the body makes one revolution in more [or] less of centre of motion originally arose from his consideration of the centre of
time . . .’.5 The rule for resolving angular velocity is also given in the motion of a pair of bodies. This he defines as a point so placed between
same paper.^ Another kinematical result relating to rotational motion is the bodies that if it be thought to rest and the bodies circulate around
found in Prop. 38 of the Waste Book. it any way they shall have equal quantities of motion.^ This is clearly
based on the definition of centre of motion given in the immediately
5 .2 . C entre of M otion in the D ynam ical S ense preceding paragraph. But he later ‘proves’ that the centre of motion for
We have already noticed Newton’s definition of centre of motion in the pair of bodies as thus defined is at a point dividing the line joining
the kinematical sense as a point ‘which rests when a body is moved with their respective centres of motion in the inverse proportion of their
any circular but not progressive motion’. Elsewhere in the Waste Book quantities (i.e. their masses).^ For if the bodies circulate around this
he uses the same term in another quite distinct, dynamical sense. This point always keeping opposite one another, they will have equal
motions, and consequently equal endeavours from a\ so that if they be
’ M S . Ild , A x. 14b. ^ Ibid., A x. 17. ^ Ibid., A x. 18.
* Evidently the (Archimedean) notion of approximating to a curve by a set of broken
joined to a ‘the one hinders the other from forcing the centre any way
lines was second nature to Newton. It was also one of the most powerful instruments of so that it shall stand in equilibrio between them and (by Def. 10) is
his dynamical method as used, for example, in his earliest treatment of centrifugal
force or in his proof of the proposition corresponding to Kepler’s second law. Charac­ * M S . lie , Def. 10. 2 M S . V , § 4. 2 See M S . V , n. 8.
teristic too is his method of proceeding from the simple (motion in a straight line) to * For example, in Def. 10 of M S . lie . 5 Ibid., Def. i i .
the complex (motion in a curved line). ^ M S . Ild , A x. 25. ’ See Fig. lo to M S . Ild .
5 Loc. cit., § 5. * Ibid., § 6.
80 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 5.2 5.3 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 81
therefore their centre of motion’. The reference to Def. lo implies that pair of bodies ends with the case in which the two bodies are attached
he is here thinking of the centre of motion more in the kinematical sense to a weightless rod lying perpendicular to the direction of motion of a
as a point ‘which rests when a body is moved with any circular but not third, impinging body.^ In this case although the attached bodies them­
progressive motion’. selves will no longer describe straight lines, but will check one another
Thus in this proof of the equivalence of the centre of gravity of two and thus describe ‘crooked lines (perhaps Troichoides)’, yet their
bodies and their common centre of motion we have at once a peculiar centre of motion will continue serenely to describe a straight line as
mixture of centres of motion in the kinematical and dynamical senses, when the bodies simply rested on the rod, and with the same speed.
and also what seems to be a bridge between the original dynamical defi­ It is clear, then, that at this early stage Newton had already divined
nition in terms of quantity of motion and the final definition in terms of the dynamical importance of the centre of motion ( = centre of gravity)
endeavour. of a pair of bodies moving under some sort of mutual interaction. So that
But although his thinking on the question is obviously still provisional we see shadowed forth, as it were, the role which the centre of mass of
and heuristic yet his thought is always extraordinarily clear. Like good the Solar System will play later in the Principia.
philosophy it is meaningful and persuasive even where one cannot follow
every detail of the argument. And always his dynamical intuition is 5.3 . D ynam ics of a S ingle R otating B ody
leading him towards the right goal, that final identification of the kine­ We have already noticed Newton’s semi-quantitative definition of the
matical and dynamical centres of motion found in MS. V. angular velocity of a rotating body.^ Now we are concerned with the
Having thus defined the centre of motion of a pair of bodies Newton dynamical aspect of such motion. One must, says Newton, distinguish
proceeds to prove a number of theorems relating to the motion of this between the angular quantity of a body’s circular motion and velocity,
point. These theorems provide a remarkable example of his drive to­ and the real quantity of such motion which is ‘more or less accordingly
wards ever-increasing generalization. First he proves that the centre of as the body has more or less power and force to persevere in that motion’.^
motion of a pair of non-colliding bodies moving uniformly in one plane Which real quantity of circular motion divided by the body’s bulk (i.e.
itself describes a straight line, ^and with uniform velocity.^ Then he proves mass) is the real quantity of its circular velocity. But how can a quantita­
that the same result holds when the lines of motion of the two bodies tive measure be assigned to this real quantity of circular motion? By the
are no longer coplanar.^ Finally he shows that the result is unaffected following method whose beauty is matched only by its inevitability.
by collision.4 The proof of the last theorem assumes that the quantities Suppose, says Newton, that the body is rotating about an axis E F (MS.
of motion of two bodies relative to their centre of gravity are equal and V, Fig. 3) and let it strike a second, spherical body of equal bulk so
opposite, a generalization^ of the special case where the centre of motion placed that it captures all the motion of the rotating body. ‘Then hath
is stationary,6 the globe gotten the same quantity of progressive motion and velocity
After this final result he characteristically notes^ that he is now able which the other had of circular.’ Newton attaches special importance to
to find the position of the centre of motion of the two bodies at any time, the distance between the axis of rotation E F and the line of motion of
and since their distance apart is also known the two spheres on which the centre of the sphere, terming it the ‘radius of circulation’. A simple
the bodies must lie at any instant are known, so that ‘there wants there­ analysis'^ based on application of conservation of momentum, angular
fore only their determination to be known that their places in the sphere momentum about the point of contact, and energy reveals that Newton’s
be found’.^ A good example of Newton’s tendency to give an exact for­ ‘radius of circulation’ equals the radius of gyration, k, of the rotating body
mulation of the solution in principle to some general problem. about EF, and that the real quantity of circular velocity, equal by defini­
Newton’s discussion in the Waste Book of the centre of motion of a tion to the velocity of the sphere, is kw where co was the original angular
velocity of the rotating body.
M S . Ilf, Prop. 28. ^ Ibid., Prop. 30. Ibid., Prop. 29.
Ibid., Prop. 31 , 2. 5 Given without proof. ' M S Ilf, Prop. 37. See above, end of § i of present chapter.
M S . Ilf, Prop. 27, ’ Immediately after Prop. 32. 8 Ibid. 3 M S . V , § 5. See M S . V , n. 16.
8.'^820r>
82 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 5.3 5.4 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 83
These three quantities, real quantities of circular motion and velocity, the dynamical writings in the Waste Book, represented Newton’s first
and radius of circulation later play a vital role in Newton’s solution to orientation towards the much more difficult general problem.
the problem of the collision between two rotating bodies. ^
One body immobile
Combination of circular motions
A spherical body colliding at right angles with an immobile plane will
Imagine a body rotating with angular velocity^ R about an axis A C
be reflected back along its original path, the pressures on each side of the
acted on by a new force which if applied alone would cause the body to
vertical through the centre being equal and so producing no tendency
rotate about another axis CB with angular velocity S. Newton then gives
to motion on one side or the other of the vertical.^
a rule for finding the new axis of rotation of the body and its angular
If a body collides at one corner with an immovable plane its motion
velocity about it. Although the rule only holds if the moments of inertia
parallel to the plane will be unaffected by the collision.^ From the dis­
of the body about the three axes in question are equal, it is interesting
cussion it is clear Newton had in mind a smooth plane such that a body
for the indication it affords of Newton’s realization of the vector nature
‘might slide upon it without losing any motion’.
of angular momentum.
In the case just considered all the points in the body in the line Op
Free rotation of an extended body perpendicular to the plane through the point of contact O shall move
away from the plane immediately after impact with the same velocity
In § 8 of the same MS. V Newton gives a wonderfully just physical
they had before impact.^ This result follows from the facH that in rotary
appreciation of the free rotation of an extended body. In the first place
motion all the points of any line (and in particular Op) have the same
every such body keeps the same real quantity of circular motion so
velocity in the direction of this line, together with the assumption that
long as it remains undisturbed. This is the principle of inertia for rota­
the velocity of the point of contact from the plane immediately after
ting bodies. Moreover, it continues to rotate about the same axis which
impact is the same as that towards the plane immediately before.
always remains parallel to itself provided the endeavours of its four
quarters away from the axis of rotation balance. This condition is
obviously necessary though apparently not sufficient. But if this balance Both bodies rotating
does not obtain then although there will be a tendency for the body to Owing to the unfamiliar manner of his approach Newton’s treatment
draw ever nearer to such a balance it will never actually attain to it. of this problem in §§ 9 and 10 of MS. V is at first sight incomprehensible.
And as the actual axis of rotation moves continually in the body, so it will However, by solving the problem by modern methods and then expressing
also move continually space some kind of ‘spiral motion’, always everything in terms of the parameters used by Newton in § 5 of the
drawing nearer and nearer to a ‘centre of parallelism with itself’ but same manuscript his solution may be shown to be correct.^ It remains,
never attaining it. ‘Nay ’tis so far from ever keeping parallel to itself therefore, to consider the method by which he arrived at it. Here there
that it shall never be twice in the same position.’ are two distinct factors, his assumption that the relative velocity of the
It is to be regretted that Newton did not proceed to give a quantitative two points of contact merely changes its sign as a result of the collision,
treatment of this problem. It is clear that his unerring intuition had led and his method of distributing the resulting change in relative velocity
him to an almost perfect physical appreciation of the problem. among the translational and real angular velocity components of the two
points of contact.
5 .4 . C ollision b e t w e e n T wo R otating B odies There is no indication of the origin of the first assumption. But know­
We consider next Newton’s treatment of the problem of the collision ing Newton’s invariable habit of passing from the simple to the complex
of two rotating bodies, beginning with the special case where one body we can be fairly confident that he derived it by direct generalization
is immobile. It is likely that this special case, found towards the end of
' M S . Ilf, Prop. 33. * Ibid., Prop. 39. ^ Ibid., Prop. 40.
' In §§ 9, l o of M S . V . ^ See Fig. 5 to M S . V. * Proved in Prop. 38. 5 See M S . V , n. 22.
84 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 5.4 5.5 THE MOTION OF EXTENDED BODIES 85
from the case of the head-on collision of two elastic spheres considered bodies.^ We have also noticed Newton’s development of the concept of
in the Waste Book.^ centre of motion in the dynamical sense culminating in his use of this
No indication is given either of the origin of his method of distri­ concept in his solution to the problem of the collision of two rotating
bution based on factors of easiness or difficulty of change of the four bodies. Moreover, his interehangeable use of the two terms, and his proof
distinct velocities in question. As to the factors themselves, for a given of their equivalence in the case of two bodies, would seem to indicate
impulse P acting on the body of quantity (— mass) A the change in that he had divined that they were identical in the case of a single body
translational velocity will be also.
p
8F = _^, After the early researches there is no trace of either concept before
Version 3 of the tract de Motu (MS. IXc). In Law 4 of that work he states
SO that for given P, SF is proportional to ijA. that the communal centre of gravity of a set of mutually interacting bodies
Again, the same impulse P acting at the point B will produce a change maintains its state of rest or motion with uniform velocity in a straight
in angular velocity SQ given by line. In the lectures de Motu this law becomes Corollary 4 to the laws of
P F = AG^ SQ, motion, the proof supplied being based on a generalization of the result
so that the real quantity of angular velocity D — GO. will change by an for two bodies previously derived in the Waste Book. But whereas there
amount it was presumably derived by Newton with no particular aim in view,
8D = but simply as an application of his new-found facility in dynamics, in
AG'
Version 3 of the tract de Motu we have a clear indication of the physical
For given P the change in D is therefore proportional to FjAG.
motivation behind its introduction. For in the Scholium to Theorem 4
These are the factors given by Newton. He could well have arrived
of that paper Newton notes that the centre of gravity of the solar system
at the first factor in much the same way as given here, but failing a
will either be at rest or move uniformly in a straight line, thus providing
knowledge of the principle of angular momentum he must have derived
a proof a priori of the Copernican system.
the second factor by some general argument: clearly the greater F the
The concept of centre of motion in the dynamical sense found in
greater the change produced in the angular velocity, and so on. . . .
Newton’s treatment of rotating bodies in MS. V plays no part in the
Given the various resistance factors it remains to decide on the proper
Principia. But very remarkably, and significantly, it appears in the
distribution formula. The one given by Newton has the double advantage
original Definition 3 of MS. X L There Newton defines the centrum
of being not only the simplest formula imaginable, but also the correct
materiae as the intersection of two axes of the body, an axis having
one. Having provided this impressive proof of his dynamical genius,
previously been defined (Def. 2) as a line about which the body can
Newton proceeds to draw on all the preceding sections of the paper
revolve in free space maintaining always the same position relative to
(apart from the first) to present the solution in principle to the problem
the parts of the body. This axis is clearly the same as that referred to in
of the collision of two rotating bodies.
§ 8 of MS. V, and the centre the same as the centre of motion defined in
The next section entitled ‘Some Observations about Motion’ is in the
§ 4 of that work. Moreover, Newton notes that the centre of matter as
hand of Newton’s friend John Wickins. Newton, however, was almost
thus defined will coincide with the centre of gravity provided the latter
certainly the author. It shows how clearly he had understood the con­
is calculated according to the masses rather than the magnitude of the
ditions actually governing collisions between rotating bodies in practice
various parts of the body.
as opposed to the ideal conditions assumed in §§ 9 and 10.
Thus Newton explicitly confirms in MS. X I that identification of the
5 .5 . D iscussion in L ater R esearches two points, centre of motion and centre of gravity, previously hinted at
Among the early researches we have noticed the remarkable set of in MS. V and in the Waste Book. The presence of these two Definitions
theorems relating to the motion of the centre of gravity of a pair of moving 2 and 3 in the original version of MS. X I thus provides a remarkable
^ See M S . lid , A x. lo. * See § 2 above.
86 THE MOTIO N OF EXTENDED BODIES 5.5
example of the continuity and persistence of Newton’s thought in dyna­
mics between the early and later researches.
Apart from the reference to axes and centre of matter in Definitions O R D E R OF C O M P O S I T I O N A N D D A T I N G
2 and 3 there is no further reference to rotating bodies in the lectures OF M A N U S C R I P T S
de Motu. Nor is there any indication of any further development of
Newton’s thought on this topic in the Principia itself. On the contrary, T he relative degree of certainty attainable in the following discussion is
his erroneous treatment of the precession of the equinoxes^ would seem inevitably subject to great variation; at some points the true order of
to point to a definite retrogression in his thought on this subject com­ composition of the manuscripts is unmistakable, at others no more than
pared with the original treatment of it in the problem of the collision of probable, while the almost total lack of dated entries renders the question
two rotating bodies. There is, however, a very interesting reference to of dating much more uncertain than the order of composition. Thus it is
rotation at the end of his enunciation of the principle of inertia in MS. not claimed that the order of composition and dating here suggested is
Xa: there he continues other than uncertain, though I think it is the most probable one in the
Motus autem uniformis hie est duplex^ progresswus secundum lineam rectam light of the evidence considered. If further evidence becomes available
quam corpus centro suo aequabilite lato descrihit et circularis circa axem suum it may, of course, at some points invalidate, or perhaps strengthen, the
quemvis qui vel quiescit vel motu uniformi latus semper manet positionibus suis order here suggested.
prioribus parallelus. Newton’s dynamical manuscripts prior to the composition of the
It would seem, therefore, that originally Newton had in mind a prin­ Principia fall into two distinct sets; the first set comprises the earliest
ciple of inertial rotatory motion besides that of translatory motion. manuscripts, all most probably composed before Newton’s letter of
23 lune 1673 to Huygens, and the majority almost certainly much earlier;
' See Book 3, Prop. 39, Prob. 20, Principia (3rd ed.).
the second set comprises the remaining manuscripts, one possibly
dating from the winter of 1679-80, and the remainder all probably
written between May 1684 and the summer of 1685. Given the gap be­
tween these two sets, nothing is lost by regarding them as independent,
and they will therefore be treated separately in sections 6.1, 6.2 and
6.3, 6.4 respectively. The topics treated in the last two sections also
refer to the later manuscripts but could not conveniently be included
in sections 6.3, 6.4.

6.1. O rder of C om position of E arliest M anuscripts

Given its unmistakable medieval flavour, and the serious qualitative


discussion of the old problem 'a quo moveantur projecta\ there can be
no doubt that the passage ‘On Violent Motion’ in MS. I preceded all
the dynamical writings in MS. II with their recognizably ‘modern’
approach to dynamics firmly based on the principle of inertia and quanti­
tative measures for motion and force. The same is then presumably true
of the small number of other dynamical entries in MS. I.
Internal evidence^ points unmistakably towards the following order
• See para. 3 of general introduction to M S . II. It is reproduced here for complete­
ness’ sake.
88 ORDER OF CO M P O S IT I O N AND 6.1 6.1 DA TI N G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 89
of composition in MS. II; Def. 1-14, Ax.-Prop. 1-26, Ax. 100-122, MS. IVa is particularly memorable for its explicit statement of the
Ax.-Prop. 27-40. Given that the order of composition for these entries dependence of centrifugal force on the radius and period of revolution
corresponds to their order of entering in the Waste Book, it is then of the motion— that is, for the law of centrifugal force. Although MS.
natural to assume this is true also for the remaining entries on folios 1,10, IVa as a whole must have been composed after MS. I ll, there is good
and 38 respectively. No internal contradiction results from this assump­ evidence that the law of centrifugal force was discovered by Newton
tion for the last pair of entries; in fact in both cases there is some sup­ sometime between the calculations of centrifugal force on the left-hand
porting evidence. P'or the calculations on folio 10 are restricted to the side of MS. I ll, and the calculations of the rate of fall due to gravity
specially simple case of totally inelastic collisions, whereas the physical on the right-hand side. In the first place, it seems very unlikely that if
discussion in Ax.-Prop. 7-10 deals with the much more difficult case Newton had already been in possession of the law of centrifugal force
of perfectly or partly elastic collisions. Again, the entries on resolution of he would have based his calculations of centrifugal force on the left-
velocity and composition of motions on folio 38 are the first to treat hand side of the manuscript exclusively on the formula. At least
of these topics in the Waste Book, and follow the preceding dynamical one application of the '^R', or equivalent, formula is certainly necessary
entries on folio 15 after a considerable gap. Lacking further evidence it is to compare the force of gravity with a given centrifugal force; there­
therefore reasonable to assume that the most probable order of com­ after, however, the law of centrifugal force provides a far more con­
position of the entries on folios 10 and 38 is given by their position of entry venient method of comparing other centrifugal forces with the original
in the Waste Book. A similar assumption, however, cannot be made for the one and thus with the force of gravity. This is precisely the method em­
treatment of circular motion on folio i which evidently came after the first ployed in MS. IVa. It seems probable, therefore, that the discovery of
tentative discussion of the problem in Ax.-Prop. 20. Striking confirma­ the law of centrifugal force followed the calculations on the left-hand side
tion of this is provided by the alteration of the figures 4-]- in Ax.-Prop. of MS. III. That it preceded the calculations on the right-hand side of
24 to 6 - f , corresponding to the exact result 2 tt obtained in folio i. the same manuscript is made probable by the use of this law (at 2.4) to
As noted previously,^ the peculiar formula of MS. I l l may be compare the centrifugal forces due to the annual and diurnal motions
derived from a result obtained on folio i by an immediate application of of the Earth. This single use of the law of centrifugal force in MS. I l l
the Merton Rule. Even if it cannot be absolutely certain that this w^as may well point to its first employment by Newton. His subsequent use
the actual method of derivation employed by Newton, nevertheless the of the result obtained for the above ratio is equally interesting. He com­
fact of the derivation itself can scarcely be in doubt. In particular, it bines it with the figure 144 for the ratio of the force of gravity to the
seems inconceivable that Newton would have accidentally directed centrifugal force due to the diurnal motion. This figure, however, is
attention in both cases to so ‘odd’ a time as that for circular motion based on the original, erroneous value for the rate of fall under gravity.
through a distance equal to the radius. MS. I l l must therefore be It would thus seem probable that this particular application of the law
placed after folio i of MS. II. of centrifugal force was made not only after the original calculations on
The position of MS. IVa after MS. I l l is likewise certain. This rests the left-hand side but before the calculations on the right-hand side. The
on the values employed in these manuscripts for the rate of fall under actual position of the calculation itself, in the ‘middle’ of the manu­
gravity. Originally, on the left-hand side of MS. I ll, Newton employed script, ‘between’ the two sets of calculations, supports this interpretation.
a wildly erroneous figure about half the true value. Later, on the right- The position of Newton’s first test of the law of gravitation relative
hand side of the same manuscript, he recalculated the rate of fall arriv­ to M SS. HI and IVa must now be considered. This test must have been
ing at a figure of 196 inches of fall from rest in one second. This agrees based on a figure of around 16 ft of fall per second under gravity as
almost exactly with the figure of 16 ft of fall in one second employed in opposed to the figure about half that value employed originally in MS.
MS. IVa, so that we can be certain that MS. IV followed the completion I ll ; otherwise the disagreement between theory and observation would
of MS. III. have been intolerably large. So that we can be certain that if there were
‘ See above, Chapter 1.2, p. 10. a test it must have taken place after the commencement of MS. III.
90 ORDER OF CO M P O S IT I O N AND 6.1 6.1 DATING OF M A N U S C R I P T S 91
While its position relative to MS. IVa is less certain it is perhaps rather the completely general collision problem. MS. V must therefore be placed
more likely to have taken place after the composition of that manuscript. after Ax.-Prop. 39 of MS. II.
For although MS. IVa contains a comparison between the force of gravity MS. V I remains to be considered. Given its largely philosophical,
and the conatm recedendi of the moon from the Earth, and a deduction non-technical nature, it is not surprising that there is little or no indica­
via Kepler’s Third Law of the inverse square dependence of the conati tion of its order of composition relative to the other manuscripts. There
of the planets from the sun, any reference to a force of gravity on the are, perhaps, some indications that it was composed, in part at least,
moon towards the Earth, or on the planets towards the sun, or of universal before MS. V ; for example the definition of place in § i of that manu­
gravitation, is conspicuously absent. It is as if the one thing absent from script—
a stage entirely set for its reception w^ere the notion of universal gravita­ There is an uniform extension, space, or expansion continued every way
tion itself. On the other hand, as Hall has rightly remarked in discussing without bounds: in which all bodies are, each in several parts of it: which parts
this curious absence of any reference to universal gravitation in MS. IV a : of space possessed & adequately filled by them are their places [italics mine]
‘With Newton the argument from silence is never strong’, and it could
is reminiscent of Def. i of MS. V I :
well be that MS. IVa was composed after the test, any reference to
universal gravitation having been intentionally suppressed in a paper Place is that part of space which a thing entirely fills.
quite possibly originally intended for publication. On the other hand, Nevertheless, the only really firm indication of the early nature of this
the chances of MS. IVa having been composed after the first test are manuscript is provided by the handwriting which places it definitely
somewhat improved if we allow for the possibility that this test may have among M SS. II-V , and certainly before 1673.
been based on the notion of a balance between a centrifugal force out­
wards and a gravitational pull inwards. ^ If MS. IVa were composed
6.2 . D ating of E arliest M anuscripts

before the test, then the original discovery of the law of centrifugal The following indications of date for the earliest manuscripts are
force in the ‘middle’ of MS. I l l would most probably have resulted available:
from the treatment of circular motion in MS. IVa, as opposed to its 1. The various cometary observations between 4 December 1664 and
presumably distinct derivation by the ‘polygonal’^ method just prior to I April 1665 found among the ‘original’ * entries in MS. I including the
the test itself. dynamical entries, especially the passage ‘On Violent Motion’. This
Just as M SS. I l l and IVa must be regarded as the continuation of would seem to point towards a date of composition for this passage to­
the original discussion of circular motion in MS. II, so MS. V must wards the second half of 1664, and in any case before 20 January 1665
be regarded as both a resume and extension of certain other subjects given the much more advanced nature of the discussion of collisions in
treated in the same manuscript. For example, the true method of resolu­ MS. Ilb.
tion of velocity in § 2 of MS. V must be compared with the erroneous 2. The marginal entry 20 January 1664 [= 1665 N.S.] on folio 10 of
method given at folio 38 of MS. I I ; the law of composition of independent MS. II.
motions in § 3 corresponds to the first enunciation of the same law on 3. //the dependence of the period of a simple pendulum on the square
folio 38; the definition of centre of motion in § 4 is a final form of the root of its length, expressed at § 5 of MS. Ila, was taken by Newton
earlier drafts in Ax.-Prop. 11-18. Finally, the solution to the problem from Galileo’s Discorsi,^ the entries on folio i of MS. II would have
of the collision of two extended, rotating bodies in §§ 9, 10, represents been composed after 1665, the year of publication of Tome II of
the culmination of the discussion of collisions at various points of MS. Salusbury’s Mathematical Collections, of which Part I contains an English
II, especially that of the collision between one moving and one stationary, translation of the Discorsi.^
extended body in Ax.-Prop. 39; this proposition gives every indication * A s opposed to abstracts of books.
^ It is found at p. 139 of the Discorsi (ed. Naz.) but not in the Dialogue.
of representing Newton’s first orientation towards his treatment of
^ T o my knowledge there was no Latin version of the Discorsi prior to Salusbury’s
' See above, Chapter 3, p. 59. ^ See above, Chapter 1.2, pp. 8 - 1 1. English translation.
92 ORDER OF C O M P O S IT I O N AND 6.2 6.2 D A TI N G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 93
4. Certain indications of the place and date of the first test of the law profound study of that work on which MS. VI is based was under way
of gravitation. First there is the statement in Pemberton’s account* that towards the second half of 1664. {b) Newton’s proud, but rather juvenile­
The first thoughts, which gave rise to his [Newton’s] Principia, he had sounding claim at p. 16:
when he retired from Cambridge in 1666 on account of the plague. As he sat Et sic plurimorum solidorum turn longitudine turn latitudine infinitorum quanti­
alone in a garden, he fell into a speculation on the power of gravity. tates solidas positive et exacte determinare possum.
Also that Newton took the figure of 60 miles to a degree at the surface would seem to refer to his inverse method of fluxions possibly dis­
of the earth ‘being absent from books’. The statement that Newton was covered in May 1666.* In which case this part of the manuscript would
sitting in a garden when the notion of universal gravitation first entered have been composed after that date.
his head agrees with the various accounts of the story of the falling apple The results obtained for the probable order of composition and dating
of whieh the most circumstantial and compelling is that of Stukeley.^ of the earliest manuscripts are displayed in the following chart.
Aceording to this account Newton was sitting in the shade of the apple MS. I Second half 1664
tree, so that the falling of the apple w'ould seem to point towards late MS. Ilb c. January 1665
summer or autumn. MS. lie.
Again, Newton’s account in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum^
asserts that the first test took place during the Plague Years. The actual
year intended, 1665 1666, is not absolutely clear, but in the context
of the whole account 1666 seems the more probable candidate. This is
also the year given in the above passage by Pemberton.
MS. Ila MS. Ild-g 1665-6?
On the basis of this evidence it would seem that if a test of the law of
I
gravitation took place during the Plague Years it was certainly away from MS. Ill 1665-6?: < 1669
Cambridge, and probably in the summer or late autumn of 1666 rather I
MS. IVa . . . b MS. V <1669?
than 1665.
MS. VI c. 1665-9?
5. Indications of the date of composition of M SS. IVa, b. According
to Gregory these manuscripts were composed sometime before Newton’s 6.3. O rder of C om position of L ater M anuscripts
election to the Lucasian Chair,^ that is sometime before 1669; while to
Given the uncertainty regarding its early status it will be best to
the best of Newton’s memory MS. IVa was composed eighteen or
consider MS. V III separately.^ The remaining manuscripts^ are then
nineteen years prior to 1686, that is in 1668 or 1667.5
all apparently ‘early’ (i.e. prior to the Principia) and their true order
6. There are no explicit indications of the date of MS. V. But in
of composition can be established with certainty apart from a small
view of what has been said of its order of composition in the preceding
element of doubt in the case of M SS. Xa and Xb.
section it must have been composed after Ax.-Prop. 39 of MS. II, and it
It will be convenient to express certain relations of order between the
seems not improbable that it was composed like M SS. IV before 1669.
manuscripts in equation form by means of the symbols < and = signi­
7. Indications of the dates of composition of MS. VI. {a) Various
fying ‘composed earlier than’ and ‘identical with’ respectively. We then
references to Descartes’s Principia in MS. D make it probable that the
have:
* Given above at Chapter 4, p. 65.
M S. IXa < M S. IXc. (0
^ Given above at Chapter 4, p. 65, n. 7. * See Portsmouth D raft Memorandum reproduced above at Chapter 4, p. 66.
^ Given above at Chapter 4, p. 66. ^ In § 6 of present chapter.
* See Correspondence, vol. iii, p. 332. T h e passage in question is given above in n. 2, 3 Apart from M S . IX b which might have been copied from IXa after the Principia.

p. 72 of Chapter 4. However, there are good reasons for identifying this manuscript with the original of the
See his letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley. propositions carried by Paget from Cambridge to London in 1684. See § 5 of present
See, for example, that at M S . I, § 3. chapter.
94 ORDER OF C OM P OS IT IO N AND 6.3 6.3 DATIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 95
This is almost inevitable given the more advanced state of dynamical that no explanation was required for the principle of inertia.' Also,
thought in the second manuscript. It is proved conclusively by a compari­ there is no law in MS. IXc corresponding to the third law in MS. X I
son of the texts of Prob. 3 in the two manuscripts. These are found to be Orig. Finally, and perhaps most conclusive evidence of all against
identical apart from a certain number of emendations in M S. IX c; in Hyp. I, there is the identity between Lemma i of MS. IXc and that in
almost all cases the original text is legible, and is then identical with that MS. Xa. Since MS. Xa was undoubtedly composed before MS. XI
in MS. IXa: Orig., we are forced to assume that although Prob. 3 of MS. IXc was
M SS. Xa, b < MS. X I Orig. (2 )
emended in the light of the corresponding proposition in M S. X I Orig.,
There can be no doubt of this; for example, Def. 1-4 and Def. 9 of nevertheless Lemma i was taken not from the very similar version in
MS. Xa constitute what is evidently a rough preliminary draft of the the same manuscript, but from a fragmentary document preceding MS.
finished, and much more detailed, discussion of absolute and relative X I ! There can therefore be no doubt that Hypothesis i is false, so that
space and time in the Scholium to the Definitions at the beginning of
MS. IXc < MS. IX Orig. (5)
MS. X I Orig., and Def. 5 of MS. Xb is evidently a preliminary draft
of Def. 7-10 of MS. XI Orig. This latter equation seems to fit all the evidence.^
The order of MSS. Xa, b relative to each other and to MS. IXc
Prob. 3 MS. IXc = Prob. 3 MS. XI Orig. (3) remains to be considered.
Lemma i MS. IXc = Lemma i MS. Xa. The relative order of M SS. Xa, b cannot be established with certainty.
(4 )
But what indications there are point towards MS. Xa < MS. Xb. For
Consider next the hypothesis example, whereas in (a) there are definitions of locus (7), quies (8), motus
MS. X I Orig. < MS. IXc. (Hypothesis i) (9), and velocitas (lo), in (b) only the headings are given, as if Newton
were referring to the definitions already given in the other manuscript.
In that case given equation (3), and the relationship between Prob. 3 in
Again Def. 17-19 of (a) reappear neither in (b) nor in M S. X L Finally,
M SS. IXa and IXc used to establish equation (i), it has to be assumed
the actual order of the definitions in (b) follows that in MS. XI Orig.
that Prob. 3 of MS. IXc was first copied from MS. IXa and then emended
much more closely than does the order in (a). The equation
so as to agree with the text of MS. X I Orig. This emendation, though
of course not the original copying from MS. IXa, must necessarily have MS. Xa < MS. Xb (6)
been carried out between the date of composition of MS. XI Orig. and its therefore seems probable.
emendation— that is, sometime before the presentation of the Principia Next, given that the definitions in MS. IXc are less detailed than the
to the Royal Society in April 1686. So that the possibility of a date of corresponding ones in both MS. Xa, b, and less numerous, and that
composition and emendation of MS. IXc as late as 1694 can definitely MS. Xa contains one law^ not found in MS. IXc, the equation
be ruled out. This is important, given that M S. IXc may possibly be in MS. IXc < MS. X (7)
the hand of David Gregory who is known to have visited Newton at seems again probable.
Cambridge in 1694. Finally a comparison of MS. X I (Emended) with the First Edition of
If Prob. 3 of MS. IXa was emended in the light of MS. X I Orig., the Principia proves conclusively that
then one would have expected all the addenda in MS. IXc compared
with MS. IXa to have been taken from MS. X I Orig. But this is not the MS. X I Orig. < First Edition Principia. (8)
case either for the definitions, laws, or lemmas. On the contrary, both * See above, Chapter 1.4, p. 28.
the definitions and the laws give every sign of being rather distant drafts * T h e fact that M S . IXc, unlike M S . X I, contains applications of the results obtained
for elliptical motion to the problem of planetary motion provides a good indication that
of those in MS. X I Orig. For example, there is a reference to vis insita M S . X I was always intended as the beginning of a larger work in which the motion of
in Law 2 which is missing from the version in MS. XI Orig. It can be the planets would find its proper place, as in Book III of the Principia.
^ T h at numbered 3, corresponding to the third law of motion in the Principia.
argued that this omission corresponds to Newton’s ultimate realization
96 ORDER OF C O M P O S IT I O N AND 6.3 6.4 DATING OF M A N U S C R I P T S 97
This latter equation, in company with equations (i), (2), and (5), having discovered in June and July 1684 makes it not improbable that
establishes the ‘early’ status of all the manuscripts so far, the probable MS. IXa was composed about that time. But in that case what of the
order of composition being: belief that Newton took up his researches in dynamics following
IXa < IXc < Xa < Xb < XI Orig, < First Edition Principia. Halley’s visit to him at Cambridge in August 1684?^ Not that there is
any reason to doubt that Halley was responsible for renewing Newton’s
6 .4 . D ating of L ater M anuscripts interest in dynamics. But whether or not he paid a visit to Newton in
Newton’s letter of 23 February 1685 to Aston contains the following August 1684,2 there is some evidence that his first, decisive visit took
well-known passage: place in May of that year. This is the month referred to in Conduitt’s
account,3 while Newton himself refers to Halley visiting him in ‘Spring
I thank you for entering in your Register my notions about motion. I de­
1684’.4 Again, Halley relates^ that his interest in the subject was aroused
signed them for you before now, but the examining several things has taken a
greater part of my time than I expected, and a great deal of it to no purpose. by a discussion with Wren and Hooke in January 1684, and that Wren
And now I am to go into Lincolnshire for a month or six weeks. Afterwards promised either of them a book if they found a solution to the problem
I intend to finish it as soon as I can conveniently. of motion in an ellipse within two months. Why then did Halley, having
failed to win the book by March, wait till the following August before
The ‘notions about motion’ referred to in this passage must be those
paying his visit to Newton ? It seems more likely that he would have
contained in the paper Isaaci Newtoni Propositiones de Motu, apart from
tried to visit him earlier, for example in May.
the Principia the only work of Newton’s on dynamics in the Archives
T o summarize, in the light of the available evidence it seems most
of the Royal Society. Since this paper represents an emended version
probable that MS. IXa was composed around June and July 1684
of MS. IXa the latter must have been composed before February 1685,
following Halley’s first visit to Newton at Cambridge in May of the
and possibly considerably earlier, judging by Newton’s statement ‘I
same year.
designed them for you before now’.
Given that MS. IXc was composed before MS. X I Orig.,^ and that the
A possible indication of the actual date of composition is provided by
emended version of the latter manuscript is effectively identical,^ as
a document^ originally forming part of the Portsmouth Collection in far as it goes, with the corresponding part of Book I of the Principia, there
which Newton states that the propositions in the Principia were all can be no doubt that M S. IXc was composed some considerable time
composed after the end of December 1684 apart from the ist and n th before the presentation of the Principia to the Royal Society in April
of Book I, in December 1679, and the 6th, 7th, 9th, loth, 12th, 13th, 1686, and even possibly before October 1684, the date given on folio i
and 17th of Book I, and the ist, 2nd, 3rd, and 4th of Book II, in June of MS. XI. Without further investigation, however, it would be dan­
and July 1684. Disregarding the order, this list tallies with the problems gerous to assume October 1684 preceded the actual date of composition
and propositions in MS. IXa, apart from Theor. 4 of MS. IXa and of MS. X I, as we shall now see.
Props. 8, 9, 12, and 13 of Book I. However, Props. 8 and 9 are no more
* A s implied, apparently, by H alley’s letter of 29 June 1686: ‘T h e August following
than special applications of Prop. 6, on the law of force to a given point when I did myself the honour to visit you, I then learnt the good news that you had
under which a body describes a given orbit (— Prop. 3, MS. IXa); and brought this demonstration to perfection.’
^ It is just possible that Halley paid three visits to Newton in Cambridge. T h e first
Props. 12, 13 extend to the case of the hyperbola and parabola what has in M ay, the second in August, the third in November. It seems unlikely that Newton
already been proved for the case of an ellipse in Prop, i i ( = Prob. 3, would have given the impression that he had ‘brought the demonstration to perfection’
at the time of the first visit, especially considering he could not then find the original
MS. IXa). paper. But he could have given this impression in August after the composition of
The fact that apart from Theor. 4, and the two propositions discovered Version I of the tract de M otu.
^ Reproduced in Brewster [i], p. 297.
by Newton in December 1679, the remaining theorems and problems
* M S . Add. 3968b, fol. l oi .
of MS. IXa are included among the propositions Newton admitted to ® In his letter of 29 June 1686 to Newton.
^ See preceding discussion of order of composition of later manuscripts.
* Reproduced in Brewster [i], vol. i, p. 471. Present whereabouts unknown. ’ Apart, that is, from a number of emendations and insertions, none of great moment.
858205 II
98 ORDER OF CO M P O S IT I O N AND 6.4 6.4 DA TIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 99
MS. X I of the present work forms part of MS. Dd-9-46 C.U .L. The consisted of only two sets of fourteen and sixteen lectures respec­
latter manuscript consists of 102 folios written recto only apart from a tively.*
small number of addenda on the verso of certain folios. The folios them­ Then there is the reference in a. Coroll. 4, to the laws of motion to
selves are in a state of great disorder, but after rearrangement they may Lemma 21. In the Principia the reference at this point is to Lemma 23,
be grouped in four sections a, y, each consisting of a number of and there is no doubt this was the lemma Newton had in mind. But when
propositions, &c., following in unbroken sequence without gaps. MS. we examine y we find that although the lemma in question is actually
XI consists of a only. and ^2 ^^e at first identical but then diverge. numbered 23 there is some indication that it was originally numbered
Either or ^2 could have been the original continuation of a, but the 21. This is supported by traces of corresponding changes in the numbers
writing, which is the same in a and and different in points to of the three following lemmas, and is then confirmed absolutely by a
having followed a. This is confirmed by the division of a and jSj into a reference to Lemma 21 (instead of 23) in Lemma 25. Evidently Lemma
number of ‘lectures’ by marginal entries not found in ^2- Oo the other 23 in y was originally numbered 21, probably due to a simple error over
hand, there is no doubt that y followed though like and unlike the number of the immediately preceding lemma which happens to
^2, it is divided up into a number of ‘lectures’ by marginal entries. occur in jSj. So it seems that Newton was referring in a. Coroll. 4 of the
Folios I of a and y are dated Octob. 1684 and 1685 respectively. Finally, laws, to a lemma appearing in section y. This is difficult to understand,
the emended version of a^2 is effectively identical with the correspond­ for a comparison of the common beginning of and ^2 reveals that jSg
ing part of Book I of the First Edition of the Principia of which it must must have been composed after and y, which follows ^2y would have
have provided a final draft. been composed still later. Since a would certainly have been composed
A regulation relating to the Lucasian Chair of Mathematics required before jSj, we have to assume a reference in a to a lemma in y composed
Newton to give a course of public lectures each year.* Those from after oc. It will be argued later that y was composed some considerable
January 1669 to October 1683 are extant, the number of lectures in time after a, thus making the forward reference to Lemma 23 (alias 21)
different years varying between three and ten, with ten the most fre­ even more difficult to understand. I shall return to this problem presently.
quent number. So that given the division of and y by marginal A possible explanation of the significance of the two continuations
entries into a number of lectures, nine in the first case, ten in the jSj, ^2 fo a, and the faet that y follows ^2 ^rid not is provided by the
second,^ there seems no reason to doubt that each represents one course following passage from Newton’s letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley.
of Newton’s public lectures. Also considering that the lectures up to The Proof you sent me I like very well. I designed the whole to consist of
October 1683 are complete, and that there is a set dated September three books, the second was finished last summer being short and only wants
1687,3 the dates actually given on and y, namely October 1684 and transcribing and drawing the cuts fairly. Some new Propositions I have since
October 1685, must be regarded as plausible. Nevertheless, two awk­ thought on which I can as well let alone. The third wants the Theory of
ward facts bar the way to an easy acceptanee of the correctness of these Comets. In Autumn last I spent two months in calculations to no purpose for
want of a good method, which made me afterwards return to the first Book
dates.
and enlarge it with divers Propositions some relating to Comets, others to other
First, as already noted, the presumed set of lectures y follows ^2 things found out last Winter. The third I now design to suppress.
rather than /Sj, and this in spite of the fact that the second set was
Judging by this passage the original version of Book I of the Principia
evidently numbered 10, i i , 12, . . . originally in place of i, 2, . . ., thus
was finished some time before the summer of 1685 but was later altered
giving the impression that Newton regarded the two sets as forming
to incorporate certain new material, some of it ‘relating to comets’ and
a single whole, as was the case for the four courses of Optics Lectures
some found out the ‘last winter’— in the context necessarily the winter
from January 1669 to October 1672 which are numbered as if they
of 1685-6. The actual incorporation of this new material may have pro­
' See Edleston [i], pp. xci-xcviii, for a useful synopsis of these lectures. ceeded in stages, but it evidently did not begin till after the two fruitless
- In each case the last lecture is incomplete.
^ See Edleston [i], pp. xcviii and 209. Also the footnote to p. 27 of Ball [i]. * See Edleston [i], loc. cit. - jSa is at first identical with as amended.
100 ORDER OF C OM P OS IT IO N AND 6.4
6.4 DATIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 101
months devoted to the problem of comets in the autumn of 1685, and possible exception of the numeral X X L This gives the appearance of
it possibly took place early in the year 1686. being written slightly more heavily than the surrounding text. Not
In the light of this passage, of the fact that oc^2y represents a final only so, there is a noticeably large gap between the right-hand side of
draft of part of Book I of the First Edition of the Principia^ and of the X X I and the extreme left of the immediately following word. In fact,
existence of the two alternative continuations jSj, ^2 to the following by measuring the intervals between successive words it appears that
hypothesis naturally suggests itself: the gap immediately to the right of X X I is the largest in the body of the
Hypothesis. corresponds to the ‘original’ draft, and ajSgy to the ‘revised’ text of a. The supposition of an insertion as required originally by the
draft of part of Book I of the Principia. hypothesis thus gains powerful backing from the text itself.
A comparison of with appears to support this hypothesis. For We are now in a position to re-examine the problem of the dates of the
contains only three propositions and one lemma from Art. IV of Book I lectures represented by and y, especially that of the first set. The only
of the Principia, and nothing from Art. V. Instead, after Prop. 19 of jS^, plausible dates for the first lecture of are October 1684 or October
corresponding to Prop. 21 of there follows Prop. 20 corresponding to 1685, for October 1686 is ruled out as being after the transition from
Prop. 30, Prob. 22, of jSg, that is the first proposition of Art. V I of Book I ajSj to ajSay. If the lectures were given in October 1684 they would
of the Principia. In other words, if we suppose represented the begin­ need to have been composed between that date and the preceding May.^
ning of the original version of Book I of the Principia, then it was lacking Assuming MS. IXa was composed around June and July this seems just
most of Art. IV and all of Art. V of the final version. But Art. V is devoted possible, since all the most difficult theorems of are already found
to the problem of determining conics from various sets of given data in the earlier manuscript.
excluding a knowledge of foci or axes, precisely the problem posed by Relevant also is the following passage from the minutes of a meeting
cometary orbits. In fact, although there appear to be no direct references of the Royal Society on 10 December 1684:
to Art. V in the treatment of cometary orbits in Part III of the First Mr. Halley gave an account that he had lately seen Mr. Newton at Cam­
Edition of the Principia, Lemma 5 there corresponds to Prop. 22, Prob. bridge who had shewed him a curious treatise de Motu\ which upon Mr.
14, of Art. V, Book I. Halley’s desire, was, he said, promised to be sent to the Society to be entered
Returning now to ajSj, y regarded as two sets of lectures, this same upon their register. Mr. Halley was desired to put Mr. Newton in mind of his
hypothesis provides an explanation of why y follows ^2 instead of jSj. promise for the securing of his invention to himself till such time as he could
at leisure publish it.
For we need only suppose that the additions to found in ^2 were
made after the lectures a^i had been read, in which case it is not par­ Since the propositions carried by Paget to Halley in November 1684
ticularly surprising that Newton should not have continued with the were almost certainly those contained in Version I of the tract de Motu,
original continuation of (of which the manuscript appears not to have it is a little difficult to believe that this was the work referred to here.
been preserved) but with part of the final continuation ^27 * 5 that he In which case he was presumably referring to part of the first draft of
started this second set of lectures at y and not earlier, in jSg, for example Book I of the Principia, i.e. to part or all of But this does not prove
at the beginning of Art. V, is perhaps a little surprising but raises no that what he had seen was already being given by Newton for his
insuperable difficulties. public lectures of the Michaelmas term 1684. In fact, there are various
Finally, if we hold to this hypothesis the section y must have been internal indications that was originally conceived as part of the
composed several months after the composition of oc. So that the full Principia, being used later as lecture material only as an afterthought.
reference to Lemma 21 could not possibly have been made at the time For example, there is the title itself De Motu Corporum Liber Primus,
of composing a. We are therefore forced to assume some insertion at the phrase unde caveat Lector . . . at the beginning of the last sentence
this point of a. On examination of the text it seems almost certain that the following the Definitions, and the sentence at the end of the succeeding
whole of the phrase ab Lemmate X X P was present originally with the Scholium: Hum enim in finem Tractatum sequentem composui. None of
* A t 1. 4, proof of Coroll. 4 to laws of motion, Principia (First Edition). ‘ August would have left an impossibly short time even for Newton.
102 ORDER OF C O M P O S IT IO N AND 6.4 6.5 DA TING OF M A N U S C R I P T S 103
these sound right in the text of a work originally intended as a set of in London at any given date between August 1684 and March 1685’.
public lectures as opposed to a book. In any case, they judged the matter to be ‘trivial’ since ‘comparison of the
On the whole, therefore, it seems rather more probable that the lec­ various pxQ-Principia drafts makes it perfectly clear from internal evi­
tures ajSj were given in the Michaelmas term 1685, beginning in October. dence that all of them precede the Michaelmas term lectures, which
This would leave open the actual date of commencement of ajSj though themselves are headed in Newton’s own hand ‘Octob 1684’.^
it would necessarily have been some considerable time before the sum­ Nevertheless, for completeness’ sake, and because of the unique
mer of 1685, and perhaps even as early as November 1684. As for the historical interest attaching to Newton’s first public announcement of
lectures y, it seems most likely that they were begun in October 1686; his decisive discoveries in dynamics, it seems worth while to re-examine
for October 1685 would have given very little time for the rather large the above and related questions in the light of all the available evidence,
insertions found in /S.^y compared with ^8^after the two fruitless months a thing so far apparently not attempted.-
spent on the problem of cometary motion in the autumn of that year. The first known public reference to Newton’s researches in dynamics
In any case, apart from the question of the actual texts of the lectures was made at a meeting of the Royal Society on 10 December 1684. At
delivered by Ne\Mon in the years 1684-6, there is good reason to be­ this meeting^
lieve that a represents the first part of the original draft of Book I of (A) Mr. Halley gave an account that he had lately seen Mr. Newton at
the Principia, in which case MS. X I would have been composed some Cambridge who had shewed him a curious treatise, de Motir, which upon Mr.
time before the summer of 1685. Halley’s desire, was, he said, promised to be sent to the Society to be entered
upon their register. Mr. Halley was desired to put Mr. Newton in mind of his
6 .5 . P a g e t ’s P r o p o s i t i o n s promise for the securing of his invention to himself till such time as he could
Opinions have differed on the nature of the propositions carried by at leisure publish it.
Paget from Newton to Plalley in November 1684.^ Brewster^ was of the Various references to certain ‘papers’, evidently on motion, are found
opinion that there was only one proposition, that corresponding to soon afterwards in letters between Newton and Flamsteed. On 27
Kepler’s first law of planetary motion, while Edleston^ thought it more December 1684 the latter wrote:
probable that the propositions in question corresponded to those entitled I am obliged by your kind concession of the perusal of your papers, tho I
Isaaci Newtoni Propositiones de Motu in the Register Book of the Royal believe I shall not get a sight of them till our common friend Mr. Hooke and
Society. Ball’s^ views on the nature of ‘Paget’s Propositions’ are not the rest of the town have been first satisfied.
very clear, though he presumably would not have equated them with the In his letter of 5 January 1685 to Newton, Flamsteed wrote again:
tract de Motu, since he believed that all three versions of this work were
If you will give me leave to guess at your design I believe you are endeavour­
composed in December or January 1685. Opinions have likewise dif­
ing to define the curve that the comet described in the aether from your Theory
fered on the identity of the ‘curious treatise de Motu' referred to by Halleys of Motion
at the meeting of the Royal Society of 10 December 1684. Rigaud^
and later in the same letter:
identified this work with the tract de Motu, whereas Edleston thought
Halley’s reference was to Newton’s Public Lectures of the Michaelmas Sir I have not had the happiness of Mr. Paget’s company this Christmas
term 1684. More recently Hall and HalL have given it as their opinion tho’ he promised it me; the hard weather perhaps prevented him as it did me
from going to London so I have not yet had the happiness of the perusal of
that it ‘is now impossible to decide which (if any) of the surviving drafts
your papers. I am very well pleased how^ever to hear that you intend to oblige
was intended and how much was communicated by Newton to his friends
us with the publication of them next term when I hope to have the use of
* As described in Extract C below. them [not] being obliged to any but your self for it.
^ Brewster [i], vol. i, pp. 298-9, esp. n. i, p. 299.
^ Edleston [i], p. Iv, n. 75. ■* Ball [i], pp. 30-32. * This, however, may be in error for Octob. 1685. See above, § 4.
^ See Extract A below. Rigaud [i], pp. 14-16. ^ Further evidence has come to hand since the account given in Herivel [2], [3].
’ Hall and Hall [i], p. 237. ^ Birch [i], vol. iv, p. 347.
104 ORDER OF CO M P O S IT IO N AND 6.5 6.5 DA TI N G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 105
In his letter of 12 January 1685 Newton excused the non-arrival of that the opposition is as the Velocity; which tis possible is not true: however
the papers by reason of Paget’s sickness but promised to instruct the I thought any thing of his might not be unacceptable to you, and I beg your
latter to transmit them to Flamsteed ‘as soon as he has a convenient opinion thereupon, if it might not be (especially the 7th problem) somewhat
opportunity’. Finally, from Flamsteed’s letter of 27 January 1685 we better illustrated.
learn of his safe reception of the papers in question from Paget. Finally there is the following passage in Newton’s letter of 13
The next relevant reference occurs in Newton’s letter of 23 February February 1687 to Halley:
1685 to Aston, one of the then Secretaries of the Royal Society;
(F) Dr. Wallis has sent up some things about projectiles pretty like those of
(B) I thank you for entering in your Register my notions about motion. I mine in the papers Mr. Paget first shewed you. . ..
designed them for you before now, but the examining several things has
taken a greater part of my time than I expected, and a great deal of it to no Since the version of the tract de Motu entitled Isaaci Newtoni Pro-
purpose. And now I am to go into Lincolnshire for a month or six weeks. positiones de Motu is the only dynamical work by Newton in the Register
Afterwards I intend to finish it as soon as I can conveniently. Book of the Royal Society, there can be no doubt that these propositions
In connexion with the above passage it is worth noting that the ver­ corresponded to the ‘notions on motion’ referred to in extract (B). This
sion of the tract de Motu in the Register Book of the Royal Society has version of the tract de Motu must then have been sent to London some
the date-line 10 December. time before 23 February 1685, and judging by Newton’s remark in
Next there is the following well-known passage in Halley’s letter of the same letter ‘I designed them for you before now’ they were possibly
29 June 1686 to Newton at the time of the controversy with Hooke on ‘composed’ considerably earlier. As for the statement ‘I intend to
the inverse square law of gravitation: finish it as soon as I can conveniently’, the ‘it’ in question presumably
referred to the Principia of which the second book was apparently com­
(C) The August following when I did myself the honour to visit you, I then
pleted in the summer of 1685.^
learnt the good news that you had brought this demonstration to perfection,
It appears that Newton sent certain propositions relating to motion in
and you were pleased, to promise me a copy thereof, which the November
following I received with a great deal of satisfaction from Mr. Paget; and a resisting medium to London ‘about 2 years’ before i i December
thereupon took another jour[ne]y down to Cambridge, on purpose to confer 1686, that is around the winter of 1684-5. According to Newton (F)
with you about it, since which time it has been entered upon the Register they were shown to Halley by Paget; whereas Halley stated (E) that they
Books of the Society. were given to him by Paget. Since the tract de Motu contains two pro­
And in Newton’s letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley: positions relating to motion in a resisting medium, and a version of this
tract was certainly sent by Newton to London before 23 February 1685,
(D) . . . and so it rested for about 5 years, till upon your request I sought it is possible that the propositions referred to in extracts (E) and (F)
for that paper; and not finding it, did it again, and reduced it into the pro­
were identical with those in the tract de Motu. This possibility is then
positions shewed you by Mr. Paget.
greatly strengthened by the reference in (E) to the ‘7th problem’. For
Relevant too is the following passage in Halley’s letter of 11 December the last ‘proposition’ in the tract de Motu, the second of two on motion
1686 to Wallis: in a resisting medium, appears in that work as ‘Prob. 7’. It seems very
(E) You were pleased to mention some thoughts you had of communicating probable, therefore, that both Newton and Halley were referring to the
your conclusions concerning the opposition of the Medium to projects moving two propositions on motion in a resisting medium at the end of the Royal
through it; the Society hopes you continue still inclined so to do, not Society copy of the tract de Motu, and that consequently the original
doubting but that your extraordinary talent in matters of this nature, will be of that copy was brought to London by Paget around the winter of
able to clear up this subject which hitherto seems to have been only mentioned 1684-5, either given to Halley or ‘first shewed’ him by Paget.
among Mathematicians, never yet fully diseussed. Mr. Isaac Newton about
2 years since gave me the inclosed propositions, touching the opposition of the ^ See passage at beginning of last paragraph of New ton’s letter of 20 June 1686 to
Medium to a direct impressed Motion, and to falling bodies, upon supposition Hallev.
106 ORDER OF C OM P OS IT IO N AND 6.5
6.5 DA TIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 107
Conclusive evidence in support of this hypothesis is supplied by Version possibility now inevitably suggests itself that Version II of the tract de
II of the tract de Motu in the Portsmouth Collection at Cambridge. Motu represents the actual papers carried by Paget from Cambridge to
At first sight this version of the tract de Motu appears to be little more London. And one further peculiarity of that version not so far alluded
than a fair copy of Version I. But a closer examination reveals a number to— the absence in it of the two last propositions— provides with (E)
of peculiar features: final confirmation of the correctness of this supposition.
1. Compared with Versions I and III Version II was composed with If extract (C) is omitted, the remaining evidence agrees internally and
extreme care as regards writing, punctuation, and Latin quantities. It with the conclusion arrived at above. There is now every reason to
also contains a list of contents not found in the other versions. identify the papers (on motion) referred to in the Flamsteed-Newton
2. Version II consists of a number of single sheets and one double correspondence of the winter 1684-5 with Version II of the tract de
sheet. If, as seems probable, the double sheet was originally used to Motu, in which case it probably reached London prior to 27 December
contain the others, on the cover sheet were part of the list of contents, 1684. Judging by extract (A) it would also seem to have reached London
and the back sheet was blank apart from the following note: ‘Letter, after 10 December, for there now seems every reason to identify the
Book No. 7, P. 234, Mr. Locke’s letter to Mr. Oldenburg le.’ The letter ‘curious treatise de Motu' referred to in Halley’s account with Version
referred to, on poisonous fishes, is in the Archives of the Royal Society. II of the tract de Motu: this latter work was entered in the Register Book
3. Where the Royal Society version of the tract de Motu differs sub­ of the Royal Society, and no other reason for this suggests itself than
stantially from Version I it agrees with Version II, namely: that given in (A), namely, to ‘secure’ Newton’s invention(s in dynamics)
{a) Both the Royal Society copy and Version II lack the Scholium to himself‘till such time as he could at leisure publish it’ ( = his invention)
to Prop. 2 found in Versions I and III. This Scholium notes that — as in fact he later did in the Principia. This pleasing picture, however,
the case considered in Coroll. 5, where the square of the periodic is somewhat marred by the evidence in extract (C). According to this
time is assumed proportional to the cube of the radius (leading to some proposition or propositions were brought by Paget to London in
an inverse square dependence of the force on the radius), holds November 1684, that is before the meeting of 10 December. And the
both for the revolutions of the major planets about the sun, and reference in extract (A) to Halley having ‘lately seen Mr. Newton in
for the satellites of Jupiter and Saturn. ^ Cambridge’ seems to tie up with Halley’s statement in (C) that he took
{h) At the end of the table of contents in Version II appear two another journey down to Cambridge after receiving the proposition(s)
lemmas numbered 3 and 4 and not found in Version I. The same from Paget in November.
lemmas now numbered 2 and i, respectively, appear in the Royal One possible solution to this apparent conflict of evidence is that there
Society copy. were two sets of propositions carried by Paget to London, the first
It appears, therefore, that Version II was copied from Version I with before 10 December 1684, probably in November, and the second set,
some particular end in view (i); that it passed at some time through the after 10 December, consisting of the complete Version II of the tract
hands of an official of the Royal Society (2); and that the Royal Society de Motu. But arguments can be advanced against this solution. For
copy of the tract de Motu w^as either taken from Version II, or from some example, Newton’s reference to his reduction of the demonstration of
other manuscript differing similarly from Version I (3). Since there is the inverse square law to the proposition showed Halley by Paget
already a very strong presumption that the proposition referred to in sounds more like the tract de Motu than a separate demonstration. Again,
(E) and (F) formed part of the original of the Royal Society copy, the Halley states in (C) that the copy of the demonstration of the inverse
square law which he had received ‘with a great deal of satisfaction from
'■ A modified form of the same Scholium was eventually introduced by Newton after
Prop. 4, Theor. 4, of the Principia to ‘compose’ the dispute between himself and Mr. Paget’ in November was later ‘entered upon the Register Books of
Hooke (see N ew ton’s letter of 14 July 1686 to Halley). T h e omission of this Scholium the Society’ and this was true only of the demonstration contained in
in the version of the tract de M otu sent to London in 1684 is therefore just possibly an
indication that Newton anticipated some reaction by Hooke in the matter of the inverse the Royal Society copy of the tract de Motu.
square law. On the other hand, if there was only one set of Paget’s propositions
108 ORDER OF C O M P O S IT I O N AND 6.5 6.6 D A TI N G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 109
(C) implies that it was sent to London before lo December 1684. And Newton could have dictated it extempore. This is confirmed by the
in that case the account in (A) would seem to be somewhat misleading presence of only two corrections in the whole copy, something again
— provided of course we continue to identify the ‘curious treatise de almost inconceivable in the extempore dictation of so long and difficult
Motu' with Version II of the tract de Motu. a paper. In fact, one of these corrections, the substitution of ‘times’ for
Lacking further evidence it is impossible to decide definitely between ‘lines’,! provides good support for the copy hypothesis; whereas this
the existence of one or two sets of Paget’s propositions. It seems seems a rather unlikely error in dictation, an examination of the other
certain, however, that if there was only one set then it must have con­ copy, in Newton’s handwriting, referred to hereafter as the ‘Newton
sisted of the propositions in the complete Version II of the tract de Motu, copy’, reveals how easy it would have been for an unwary copyist to
and this would likewise have been true of the second set in the other case. misread Newton’s ‘times’ as ‘lines’, an error even committed at one point
It also seems certain that in both cases these propositions were brought by Newton himself!^
by Paget to London before 23 February 1685, and probably before 27 The establishment of an original manuscript from which the Locke
December 1684, and shown to various people including Halley and Flam­ copy was taken has been laboured at some length because of its impor­
steed, and possibly Hooke; that they were later copied into the Register tance for the remainder of the argument. Hereafter this original manu­
Book of the Royal Society and then retained in London, probably by script, or manuscripts, since there may well have been several, will be
Halley, until the last two propositions were sent by him to Wallis with referred to as the ‘Original M S .’
his letter of i i December 1686; and that finally, at some later date, by Consider now the hypothesis that the Original MS. was composed
some unknown route, the remaining propositions found their way back specially for Locke’s benefit, probably around March 1690, but in any
into the Portsmouth Collection. case certainly after the composition and publication of the Principia.
The assumption then is that Locke had asked Newton for a more
6.6. T he S tatus of M anuscript VIII straightforward derivation of the inverse square law than that given in
As already noted, ^the existence of the Locke copy, with its endorse­ the Principia. Newton did supply such a proof. One can even agree with
ment ‘Mr. Newton Mar. 1689-90’ throws doubt on the early status of Brewster^ that it is somewhat more ‘popular’ than the one in the Principia.
the Newton copy. It is then natural to assume^ that the original (or Though of course, given the essential depth of the proposition in ques­
originals) of both copies was composed around March 1690 to provide tion, the great ‘distance’ between it and the axioms of dynamics, not
Locke with a more straightforward exposition of the two vital proposi­ even Newton could make the proof simple. It is also an entirely dijferent
tions from which followed the inverse square law of attraction on the kind of proof; whereas the proof in the Principia follows by application
basis of the known elliptical orbits of the planets about the sun. But there of Prop. 6, Theor. 5, Book I, applicable to any curve, to the special
are certain difficulties in the way of accepting this assumption of the case of motion in an ellipse under a force to one focus, the present proof
late status of the original MS. V III. These will now be considered. begins and ends with an ellipse, and, in particular, makes no use of
An examination of the copy in the Locke papers, hereafter referred to Newton’s beautiful generalization of Galileo’s law of falling bodies, as
as the ‘Locke copy’, makes it certain that this must have been taken in Prop. 6, Theor. 5. What is surprising, however, is that Newton felt
from some earlier manuscript.^ For the handwriting is certainly not any need after the publication of the Principia to supply Hypotheses
Newton’s,4 and the complicated and detailed nature of the argument, 1-3 and Prop. i. Why did he not simply refer at the appropriate places
especially the mathematical parts, makes it inconceivable that even in Prop. 2 to Laws i, 2, Coroll, i, of the Laws, and Prop, i, Theor.
I, Book I, of the Principia, to which Hypotheses 1-3 and Prop, i
' M S . V I I I , Introduction.
^ T his was the view taken by Brewster [i], vol. i, p. 339, and Ball [i], p. 116.
evidently correspond? He had, after all, a recent precedent for so
^ It will appear later that this earlier manuscript could not have been the Newton ’ A t Prop. 2, para. 4, word 15. A t the end of the enunciation of Prop, i the same
copy. error of ‘lines’ for ‘times’ occurs, this time uncorrected.
* According to Cranston [i], p. 337, the handwriting is that of Locke’s valet and ^ Six words from the end of the penultimate sentence of Prop, i .
amanuensis Brownover. ^ Brewster [i], vol. i, p. 340.
no ORDER OF C OM P OS IT IO N AND 6.6 6.6 DATIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 111
doing in his correspondence with Huygens of the previous autumn.^ Original MS. But another explanation suggests itself: that Newton not
Then he referred at need to the Principia, instead of working out every­ only had not a copy of the Principia available, but could not have had,
thing ab initio. that work not yet having been composed. It is the three hypotheses, the
Even if it is granted, however, that for some unknown reason Newton same in both the Locke and Newton copies, and therefore presumably in
now felt unwilling to quote references from the Principia,^ it would still the Original MS. also, which seem to point to this conclusion.
have been surprising if he had not consulted it when composing, at First, the very term ‘hypothesis’ itself is a little surprising. We know
Locke’s request, a new and more comprehensible version of two of the that as Newton grew older he increasingly tended to avoid use of this
propositions in that work. Yet such would appear to have been the case. term.^ An interesting example of this tendency is provided by the tract
First there is Prop, i : apart from the detailed justification of the con­ de Motu. In Version I of that work there are four hypotheses, of which
struction for the position of the body at the end of the second moment the first is the principle of inertia. In Version III there were also origi­
of time, the proof of this proposition in the Locke copy is essentially the nally a number of hypotheses, of which the first was again the principle
same as that in Prop, i, Theor. i, of Book I of the Principia. Yet it would of inertia. But later the term ‘hypothesis’ was cancelled and replaced by
be impossible to regard it as in any sense a translation of that proposi­ ‘Lex’, the term exclusively used thereafter. The use of the term ‘hypothe­
tion from Latin into English. This confers a unique status on Prop. sis’ as applied to the principle of inertia in the Original MS. (Hypothe­
I in the Locke (and Newton) copies. For example, a comparison of sis i) therefore represents a small reversion towards the more primitive
Theor. i of the tract de Motu with Prop, i, Theor. i, of Book I of the viewpoint of the summer of 1684.2
Principia reveals that apart from the transition to the limit at the end Newton, however, might have used the term ‘hypothesis’ in a paper
the proof in the Principia is an almost exact copy of that in the tract de intended to show how a certain result (the inverse square law) followed
Motu. This in itself is not surprising. The proof in the tract de Motu logically from certain initial assumptions or hypotheses. After all, it was
is well nigh perfect, unmatched in all Newton’s dynamical writings for precisely the strict deducibility of Newton’s system of the world which
its simplicity, elegance, and display of profound physical intuition. so impressed the philosopher Locke .3 Nevertheless, the actual form of
Little wonder that he felt no need to modify it in any essential detail the first two hypotheses, corresponding respectively to the first and
in the Principia. Yet we now have to assume that in March 1690 he second laws of motion, is rather surprising in the author of the Principia
had somehow become dissatisfied with this proof. Or, alternatively, that little more than two years after the publication of that work. Why,
he did not have a copy of the Principia available when composing the for example, does he omit any reference to rest as opposed to motion
Original MS., a rather improbable hypothesis, especially if the Original in Hypothesis i ? Once again this represents a small reversal to the
MS. was composed after Newton’s return to Cambridge in February level of the tract de Motu in no version of which is there a reference
1690^ following the dissolution of the Convention Parliament, as seems to the state of rest, although it could be countered that Newton makes
most probable. no use of the assumption of rest in the Original MS. But the omission
To explain the difference between the form of Prop, i in the in Hypothesis 2 of any reference to the change of motion being in the
Original MS. and that found in other versions of the same proposition, direction of the force cannot be disposed of so easily. For this part of the
it has been necessary to assume that Newton had either become tem­ second law is not only of great intrinsic importance but is actually used
porarily dissatisfied with the previous form of that proposition, or else at one point in Prop. 2.‘^ It is difficult to assess the improbability of
did not have a copy of the Principia available when composing the Newton making so serious an omission in the enunciation of the second
^ See the various references to the Principia in the two letters from Newton to ’ See especially Koyre [4].
Huygens reproduced as items 341, 2, of vol. iii of the Correspondence. ^ See § 4 above for a discussion of the date of composition of Version I of the tract de
^ One possible explanation, that Locke himself never possessed a copy of the Prin ­ M otu.
cipia, can be eliminated, since a copy of that work, with manuscript corrections in ^ See, for example, the quotation from Locke’s essay ‘On Education’ given in foot­
New ton’s own hand, was found among Locke’s possessions. It is of course not certain note 6 of p. 76 of vol. iii of the Correspondence.
that Locke was in possession of this copy in March 1690. * See reference to Hypothesis 2 towards the end of penultimate paragraph of this
See More [i], p. 356, foot. proposition in the Newton copy.
112 ORDER OF C O M P O S IT I O N AND 6.6 6.6 D A TI N G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 113
law of motion after his final synthesis of dynamics in the Principia. One In the first place, it is certain that the Locke copy could not have been
simply feels that it is not the sort of omission he would have made. taken from the Newton copy. If one examines the very small number
Finally, there is the evidence supplied by Hypothesis 3 against the of cancellations in the Newton copy then in two cases one finds that the
supposition that the Original MS. was composed around 1689-90. original versions, later cancelled, exactly agree with the Locke copy,i
This hypothesis is clearly a form of the parallelogram law for the com­ whereas in no case is the converse true. So that it seems certain that the
position of independent motions. In Version I of the tract de Motu it Newton copy was taken either from the Locke copy or the Original MS.,
occurs as Hypothesis 4. But in Version HI of that work it has suffered and not vice versa. As to the more substantial differences between the
a most important and significant change of status. From being an hypo­ two copies, these are as follows;
thesis, something ipso facto incapable of proof, it has become a lemma, 1. The detailed justification in the Locke copy for the ‘construction’
something derived from more primitive assumptions, in this case the in Prop. I is missing from the Newton copy.
second law of motion. Thereafter it naturally maintained its new status, 2. The proof of Lemma i in the Newton copy represents an emended
appearing as Coroll, i to the laws of motion in the lectures de Motu and improved version of that in the Locke copy: in particular, as
and the Principia, and as such was referred to in Newton’s correspon­ noted below (n. i), a small, yet nevertheless real, non-sequitur in the
dence with Huygens in the autumn of 1689. Once again, therefore, we Locke copy has been corrected in the Newton copy.
find a reversion in the level of Newton’s thought to that of Version I 3. The Newton copy contains an additional proposition, numbered
of the tract de Motu (or earlier). This time, however, the reversion be­ 2, not found in the Locke copy. This is a special case of the last propo­
comes far more difficult to account for: that the author of the Principia, sition.
a philosopher in his own right, always most punctilious about the exact 4. Certain parts of Prop. 3 in the Newton copy represent emended,
meaning of his terms, suspicious of hypotheses in general, and with and on the whole improved and clarified, versions compared with the
Ockham eschewing unnecessary multiplication of causes— Causas corresponding parts of Prop. 2 in the Locke copy.
rerum naturalium non plures admitti debere, quam quae et vera sint et earum In the light of these differences between the two copies, and bearing
Phaenomenis explicandis sufficiunt^— that Newton should have given as in mind that the Locke copy could not have been taken from the Newton
an hypothesis in 1689-90 what two years previously he had given as a copy, consider again the hypothesis that the Original MS. was com­
corollary in the Principia is surely difficult to accept. All the more so posed specially for Locke’s benefit at some time after the publication of
remembering that for Newton qua mathematician the reduction in the the Principia. There are then two mutually exclusive possibilities: either
number of independent axioms in his system of dynamics effected by Newton sent the Original M S., or one of the Original M SS., to Locke
the abrupt change in the status of this law would necessarily have been in the form of a letter to be retained by Locke, or not. If he did so, then
a most significant and memorable event. the existence of the Newton copy is at once explained as the copy
To summarize the argument so far: the presence and form of the ' T h e first, and more striking, o f these two cases is found in the last paragraph of
three hypotheses and Prop, i in both the Locke and Newton copies Lemma i. Originally Newton had begun this paragraph as follows: ‘For joyn i y and
d raw /F parallel to C D and because F f and F E are bisected in C and £)’ exactly as in the
raises certain difficulties for the supposition that the Original MS. was Locke copy (and presumably also in the original manuscript). Later he emended this
composed by Newton specially for Locke’s benefit, probably around to read: ‘ For joyn P f and d ra w /E parallel to C D and because F f is bisected in C , F E
shall be bisected in D , and therefore z P D shall be equal to the sum of P F and P E that is
March 1690, and in any case definitely after the publication of the
to the summ o f P F and P f , that is to A B , and therefore P D shall be equal to A C . '
Principia. Of these difficulties much the most serious are those raised by Clearly the Locke copy contained a small non-sequitur removed in the Newton copy.
Hypothesis 3: it is at this point one feels the onus most definitely rests on For the fact that P D is half the sum of P E and P F does not follow directly from the
fact that F E and F f are both bisected, as stated in the Locke copy, but from the bi­
the supporters of the 1689-90 hypothesis to defend their case. Never­ section of F E alone, itself derived of course from the bisection of F f, as stated in the
theless this hypothesis encounters further difficulties arising from Newton copy. T h e other case is found at the beginning of the last sentence of Lemma 3
where Newton had originally written: ‘But PX'^ was to G//® as . . .’ as in the Locke
certain differences between the Locke and Newton copies. copy, replacing it by: ‘But Y X I was to P X ^ as . . . ’. T his emendation, like the previous
one, results in a certain logical improvement in the presentation of the argument.
' Hypothesis i, Book III, Principia.
114 ORDER OF CO M P O S IT I O N AND 6.6 6.6 DATIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 115
retained by Newton. But in this case why was it not an exact copy, as from Cambridge to London in November 1684 in fulfilment of Newton’s
one would have expected ? Why the omission of the justification of the promise to Halley. To assess the relative probabilities of these two alter­
construction in Prop, i ? This justification, found nowhere else outside native explanations certain comparisons will now be made between the
the Locke copy, represents an important clarification of the proposition Newton copy and Version I of the tract de Motu. The sections of the
in question and was presumably introduced specially for Locke’s benefit. Newton copy involved in these comparisons are the same in the Locke
Why then omit it from the copy} Again, the improvements in the Newton copy, and thus presumably occurred in unchanged form in the Original
copy compared with the Locke copy are difficult to understand. Why MS.
not incorporate them in the manuscript sent to Locke One is almost 1. The form of the principle of inertia given in Hypothesis i com­
forced to assume there were two Original M SS., one of which was sent to pared with that given in Hypothesis 2 of Version I of the tract—
Locke, the other retained by Newton from which at some time after the Corpus omne sola vi insita uniformiter secundum lineam rectam in infini­
transmission of the first to Locke Newton made the new and improved tum progredi nisi aliquid extrinsecus impediat— throws no light on the
version represented by the Newton copy. Other small factors against the question of the relative order of composition of the two manuscripts.
supposition that Newton sent one of the Original MSS. to Locke are The reference here to the resistance of the medium is without signifi­
the absence of such a manuscript, or of any covering letter, or of a cance considering the reference to resisting mediums in Def. 3 of Ver­
letter of acknowledgement from Locke. Also that if Locke was in sion I of the tract, and the fact that Prob. 6 of that work deals with the
possession of an original manuscript in Newton’s hand why bother to actual motion of a body in a resisting medium.
have a copy made of it— remember the Locke copy is certainly not in 2. Hypothesis 2 of the present manuscript is clearly an early form of
Newton’s hand. the second law of motion. An equivalent and closely similar form of
Now consider the other possibility. In that case either the Locke copy this law first appears in Version III of the tract. The presence of this
was taken from the original ‘in Newton’s presence’, or else it was hypothesis could therefore be interpreted as evidence in favour of the
taken from the Original MS. which was later returned to Newton. In present manuscript post-dating Version I of the tract.
either case the Original MS. must have remained with Newton. In 3. The presence of Hypothesis 3 (the parallelogram law of compo­
which case one has to assume that Newton, after the publication of the sition of velocities) in the present manuscript also provides some slight
Principia, went to the trouble of copying out the manuscript again very evidence in favour of it post-dating Version I of the tract, since an
carefully, emending and improving it, and omitting the justification of equally clear formulation of the law first appears in Version III, the
the construction in Prop. i. form given in Hypothesis 3 of Version I— Corpus in dato tempore virihus
It seems, therefore, that either of these two mutually exclusive conjunctis eo ferri quo virihus divisis in temporibus aequalibus successive—
possibilities regarding the actual origin of the Locke copy are fraught being much more obscure. On the other hand one must remember the
with certain difficulties arising from the existence of the Newton copy very clear formulation of the same law in the much earlier MS. V.
and the peculiar differences between it and the Locke copy. 4. The proof here given in Prop, i of the result equivalent to Kepler’s
This completes the case against the assumption of late status for the second law of planetary motion differs in no important respect from
Original MS. V III. It remains to consider alternative explanations of the those given in the three versions of the tract de Motu. But the fact that
composition of the Original MS. and the Newton copy. Two such the reference to the planar nature of the motion in the present manu­
explanations suggest themselves: the Original MS. may have been script is absent from all three versions of the tract could be regarded as
composed in the winter of 1679-80 following Hooke’s intervention, thus evidence that the present manuscript post-dated these works.
containing Newton’s first proofs of the propositions in question: or it 5. The partial approximation to the ellipse by a broken line in
may have been composed in 1684 after Version I of the tract de Motu Prop. 2 and 3 shows unmistakable evidence of the influence of the
representing the original of 2i first set of propositions^ carried by Paget procedure adopted in Prop. i. No trace of such an influence is found
' Assuming that there were two sets. See § 5 above, p. 107.
in Version I of the tract. It seems difficult to account for this unless
116 ORDER OF C O M P O S IT I O N AND 6.6 6.6 DA TIN G OF M A N U S C R I P T S 117
one regards it as an indication of the way Newton first arrived at his solu­ the Newton copy was also composed before the Principia shortly after
tion to the problem of elliptical motion, and it is even more difficult the Original MS. of which it represented an emended and somewhat
to understand why he should have reproduced these details in a paper improved version. The omission in the Newton copy of the con­
written after Version I of the tract, unless, of course, one assumes that struction justification in Prop, i could then be explained in one of two
Newton was trying to make the proofs easier for Halley, as opposed to ways: either it was not in the Original MS., being introduced first in the
Locke, a rather improbable assumption. Locke copy as an aid to Locke’s understanding; or else it was in the
6. In Prob. 3 of Version I of the tract Newton derives the inverse Original MS. and was simply omitted as unnecessary in the Newton
square law for elliptical motion under a force to a focus by applying the copy. Finally, the existence of the additional proposition would have
general result of Theor. 3 to the special case of motion in an ellipse, been quite natural if the Newton copy had been composed in 1679, and
whereas here he concerns himself solely with the problem of motion in might or might not have been in the Original MS. It would perhaps
an ellipse. Again it is difficult to understand why Newton should have have been a little less natural in 1684. Whereas its presence in a paper
composed the present paper after Version I of the tract. composed in 1690 is difficult to credit.
The evidence supplied by the above comparison fails to decide de­ T o summarize, three explanations of the composition of the Original
finitely between the two explanations, though there is perhaps a slight MS. V III have been considered. It may have been composed:
balance of evidence in favour of the 1684 hypothesis. Against this we 1. In the winter of 1679-80 following Hooke’s intervention, thus
have the argument based on Prop, i already employed in consideration containing the original proofs of the proposition in question.
of the 1689-90 hypothesis. For if this proposition existed already in 2. In 1684 following Version I of the tract de Motu representing the
a perfectly acceptable form in Latin in Version I of the tract de Motu original of a first set of Paget propositions.
why did Newton not take it directly from that work? The same 3. After the Principia, around March 1690, specially for Locke’s
argument could even be applied to the last proposition, though perhaps benefit.
with less force, since the proof in the tract de Motu was given in the form The evidence for explanation 3 rested on Locke’s known interest in
of an application (Prob. 3) to elliptical motion of the general theorem Newton’s Principia, the existence of the Locke copy, and the admittedly
given in Theor. 3, whereas if there were two sets of Paget proposi­ more ‘popular’ nature of the propositions compared with the correspond­
tions the assumption is that the first set was devoted to motion in an ing ones in the Principia. But there were several items of internal evi­
ellipse. dence against this explanation all pointing towards the early status of the
The above comparison between M SS. V III and Version I of the Original MS. One of the strongest of these was the use of the term
tract de Motu was based on certain elements the two copies have in ‘hypothesis’ applied to the parallelogram law of composition of motion.
common. It remains to consider the substantial differences between As regards explanations i and 2, the relevant evidence failed to de­
them noted already in connexion with the 1690 hypothesis, namely; cide definitely in favour of one or the other, though there was perhaps
1. Certain improvements in the Newton copy compared with the a small balance in favour of the second explanation. The possibility of
Locke copy. other explanations must naturally be allowed for.^
2. The omission in the Newton copy of the justification of the con­ ^ T h e above interpretation of M S . V I I I follows closely that given in Archives
Internationale d ’Histoire des Sciences, 16 , 13-22 (1963). T h is interpretation has been
struction in Prop. I of the Locke copy. criticized by A . R. and M . B. Hall (ibid., pp. 23-28) who hold to the traditional inter­
3. The existence in the Newton copy of an additional proposition not pretation (previously advanced by Brewster and Ball) of this M S . as having originated
in the request from Locke for clarification of the corresponding proposition in the
found in the Locke copy. Principia. D . T . Whiteside has also drawn m y attention to a Latin translation o f the
These differences raised certain difficulties for the supposition that the same M S . in Whiston [2], Lecture X IV /X V . Whiston notes that he gives the
deduction ‘ Qualem nempe earn e charta M S . ipsius Newtoni olim acceperim'. T he
Locke and Newton copies were composed after the Principia. But these
fact that Newton apparently said nothing to Whiston about the origin of the M S .
difficulties no longer apply if it is assumed that the Original MS. was does not seem to tell much for or against the above interpretation.
composed before the Principia. For in each case it may be assumed that
PART II

NEWTON DYNAMICAL MANUSCRIPTS


1664-1684

INTRO D UCTIO N
T h e text aimed at throughout is a faithful ‘compromise’ reproduction
of the original manuscripts. Thus the use of capital letters, archaic forms
of spelling, and the punctuation follow the original manuscripts exactly,
whereas contractions such as ‘ye’ for ‘the’, ^ for par, &c., are every­
where extended as being a matter of handwriting and not of language.
All extensive, legible cancelled passages are given in full in critical foot­
notes, but certain cancellations of words and short phrases judged
unimportant have been omitted silently. Marginal entries in the original
manuscript other than footnotes are indicated in critical footnotes apart
from certain titles of sections entered in the text. Newton’s own footnotes
are given at the foot of the relevant page separated where necessary by
a rule from other footnotes. Alternatives in the manuscript are indicated
by a bar in the text. Everything within square brackets represent additions
to the text apart from [ ] representing a word or words missing from
the manuscript, or [?] representing a word or words illegible in the
manuscript. A word or words inserted within square brackets and suc­
ceeded by a ? indicate an editorial conjecture.
All manuscripts, or sections thereof, are supplied with an introductory
note giving details of location, probable order and date of composition
where possible, and a brief description of contents. Any indications of the
growth of the original texts are given at the end of these notes.
Other notes are of two kinds: critical notes, labelled alphabetically,
and given as footnotes; exegetical notes, labelled numerically, and given
together at the end of each manuscript or section of manuscript. These
latter notes fall under the following headings: (i) Cross-references to
the occurrence of the same or cognate topics elsewhere. For the most
part these have been restricted to the more important/omard' references,
a complete list of contents of manuscripts according to topic being given
in the Index. (2) References to the works listed in the Bibliography.
120 IN T R O D U C T IO N
(3) Comments not involving expressions of opinion, for example, those
referring to the modern equivalent of certain terms used by Newton.
I
(4) Non-controversial interpretations of certain technical dynamical or E X T R A C T S FRO M E A R L Y N O T E B O O K
mathematical questions, for example the majority of the notes to the
commentary to MS. III. MS. Add. 3996 consists of a small notebook of 140 leaves bound in worn
The remaining notes, for example those referring to the growth of leather bearing within the inscription ‘Isaac Newton Trin. Coll. Cant.
Newton’s dynamical thought, all relate to matters allowing of a poten­ 1661’. A careful general description of contents, together with a repro­
tially wide variation of personal opinion. For the reasons already given duction of certain passages, especially on optical subjects, has been given
in the General Introduction these latter notes are confined wherever by Hall [i]. Apart from extensive quotations from certain philosophical
possible either to a direct reference to the appropriate section of Part I, works, among which those from Magirus [i] seem of particular interest
or to such a reference followed by a brief unsupported expression of as one of the most likely sources of the scholastic background to Newton’s
physical thought, the book contains original entries by Newton covering
opinion.
a wide variety of topics listed at folios 87, 87V. With few exceptions,
With two possible exceptions, all the manuscripts here reproduced
largely of a psychological or physiological nature, such as ‘fantasy’,
certainly belong to the period 1664-84. The first of these exceptions, ‘soule’, or ‘sleepe’, these topics all treat of physical matters, the most
that represented by MS. XI, is comparatively unimportant. For even if substantial entries being on motion, optics, and properties of matter. It
that manuscript does not contain the text of public lectures given by seems likely that the majority of these entries were made in 1664 or early
Newton in the Michaelmas term 1684, it must still have been composed 1665 at the latest (among them are various cometary observations dated
by the autumn of 1685, and in any case it certainly represents the direct between 9 December 1664 and i April 1665) that the present manu­
continuation of the earlier drafts given by M SS. IX, Xa, and Xb. The script probably provides the best available evidence of Newton’s
other possible exception, that represented by MS. V III, is a much more preparation for his decisive discoveries in optics and dynamics during
serious one. For the existence of the Locke copy, with its endorsement the plague years. Another notebook (U .C.L. MS. Add. 4000) provides
‘Mr. Newton Mar 1689-90’, points to the possibility that it may have parallel evidence for his preparation for the mathematical discoveries
during the same period.
been composed after the Principia. Nevertheless, for the reasons given
The text is clean throughout apart from a small number of unimpor­
in Part I, Chapter 6.6, it seems to me on balance more probable that the
tant deletions. Unlike the later manuscripts, the punctuation in the long
original of both the Locke and Newton copies was composed either in passage on violent motion is very deficient and has been supplied and
December 1679 or in 1684. In any case, the treatment here afforded to emended where necessary to facilitate understanding of what is in any
MS. V III should help other interested scholars to decide for themselves case a rather difficult piece of writing.
on the status of this manuscript and its original.

Text
(1) * Note that the mean distances of the primary Planets from the Sunne
are in sesquialiter proportion to the periods of their revolutions in time. 2
(2)3 of violent motion
[i] Violent motion is continued either by the aire or by a force impresstor
by the natural gravity in the body moved. Not by the aire, since the aire
crowds more uppon the thing projected before, than behind, and must
therefore rather hinder it. For you may observe in water that a thing moved
in it doth carry the same water behind it along with it as in a cone, or at
least the water is moved from behind it with but a small forced as you may
122 E X T R A C T S FROM EARLY NOTEBOOK I I E X T R A C T S FROM EARLY NOTEBOOK 123
observe by the motes in the water. Suppose {a) [Fig. i] to be the body aire well be more compressed at (/) than at (b) and consequently when
moved, (b.d.i.f.) to be the water moved behind (a) to give it place, (r) let loose againe it will dilate it self and so begin a new motion. I answer
the water behind {a) following it and going along with it.s Then if the how comes the aire to be more crowded behind the ball than before it
water at (/) ran so violently against the backsid of [a) it would beate away since (a) will communicate as much force on (b) as it receives from (r),
the water at (r) with violence, but the water is moved very slowly from and the fore parte of the aire will croud no more on the latter parte than
behind (a) if it be moved away [at all]: as you may perceive by the motes the ball will croude on it. Againe whence is it that a piece of leade will
in the water. The like must hapen in aire. If you say no I answer must move farther and with more force than a piece of wood of the same
bignesse since the aire will have the same influence on both.*®
(2)** of violent motion
This motion is not continued by a force impresst because the force
must be communicated from the mover into the moved either by some
corporeall efflux or incorporeall one or nothing. If by corporeall attomes
we are still at a losse how those attomes must continue theire one motion.
If by an incorporeall efflux it must be by either spirit or some quality.
If by a spirit how comes the spirit to be so easly united to the body and
not to slip through it and when united to it how comes the spirits to
cease so soone and the spirit to leave it and hence every little attome must
have soules in store to cast away upon every body they meete with. If a
quality then qualitas transfigurat de subjecto in subjectum}^ and this quality
cannot be the motion of the mover since it and the mover are separated
at once from the thing moved. In a word how can that give a power of
moveing which it selfe hath not.
of violent motion
then move (a) forwards in water.^ So if hot leade drop into water that
parte which is behind will be pointed the fore parte round which would Therefore it must be moved after its separation from the mover by it
be otherwise if the aire pressed as much on it behind as before. Thirdly, one gravity. *3 Which will be cleare by seeing whether there can be motion
how can the aire continue the motion of a globe on it axis.7 Fourthly in in a vacuum and what that motion is and so comparing it with motion
the former figure the aire is supposed to have the same propensity* to in plena.
motion which the ball {a) is supposed to have, that is will move no That there may be motion in vacuo let us suppose (a, b) [Fig. 2] to be
longer than it is propelled on. Then I say the water at (r) cannot move a body as a piece of Aire, {c, d, e) to be three globes, (/, gy h, i) and all the
the ball unless the ball do not at the same time move {b), that {b) may space about the globes and that aire to be inane.*^ Now in the chapter de
[move] (g) and {h), and (g) may move (d), and (d) move (/), and (f) move vacuo we have shewed that these three globes would be really separate
(/), and (/) move (r), and force it to rush upon the ball. And consequently and not touch one another. You will grant that halfe the globes are in
at the same instant (r) must [move] the ball, and the ball move (r), which places, and consequently may move. Suppose then the halfe of (i:) in the
cannot be. But suppose the aire and the ball were detained from motion aire move towards {d) we aske whether that part in vacuo would move
by some outward agent, yet kept the same respect to one another in along with it or stay behind and be separated frome it. If the first we have
situation as they did in theire flight then as soone as they were both our desire, if the last wee ask what should separate it from it. Not the
let loose againe the aire would have as much power to move the ball as it vacuum since that is accounted nothing. But you may say that it is not
had when they were in theire former flight. If it be answered that the truly motion for the upper parte of (c) to be carried to {d). We answer that
124 E X T R A C T S FROM EARLY NOTEBOOK I I E X T R A C T S FROM EARLY NOTEBOOK 125
where there is action (for such is the passing of (c) to (d)) and where there the aire is uniforme. And we judge a thing to be moved when we see it
are new respects acquired to the same bodys there must be motion, but come nigher or goe farther from some thing which our senses can per­
the upper part of (c) hath neither the same respect to the aire nor to (d) ceive and so we judge not a thing to be moved in respect of the aire but
which it had before it began to pass towards d. If this going oi cto d be of the earth or something.
(3) ‘^ Cartes defines motion 2nd parte Pr to be the Transplantation
of one part of matter or one body from the vicinity of those bodys which
immediately touch it and seem to rest, to the vicinity of others.
(4) 21 How much longer will a pendulum move in the Receiver22 than in
the free aire. Hence may bee conjectured what bodys there bee in the
receiver to hinder the motion of the pendulum.
(5) 23 The gravity of bodys is as their solidity, because all bodys descend
equall spaces in equall times consideration being had to the Resistance
of the aire etc.
(6y^ ‘According to Galilaeus, a iron ball of 100 Florentine (that is 78 at
not motion I aske what is it, But this is onely to [strive ?] about termes London Adverdupois Weight) descends an 100 braces Florentine or
and if it please you not to call it motion call cubits (or 49,01 ells, perhaps 66 yds) in 5" of an hower.’

of motion 1. At fol. 2 9 . It is possible that Newton first encountered Kepler’s laws of


planetary motion through a reading of Streete [i]. For example, some astro­
it what you will but it is that which we aimed to prove and there is but
nomical entries on fol. 2 7 V are headed ‘Out of Streete’.
this difference twixt it and motion inpleno^ that the one is environed with 2. See Newton’s reference in the Portsmouth Draft Memorandum (repro­
such mater as is impenitrable and consequently the mater must be duced above at Part I, Chapter 4, p. 66) to ‘Kepler’s Rule of the Periodical
crouded out of the moving bodys way before or rather at the same time times of the Planets being in a sesquialterate proportion of their distances from
the centers of their Orbs’.
that the body moves, it must needs impede the motion and be continually 3. Beginning at fol. 98 and continuing (from the beginning of section 2) at
thrusting against and resisted by the body before it: but in vacuo it meets fol. 113. This considerable discussion of violent motion is memorable as being
with nothing impenitrable to stay it. Tis true God is as far as vacuum the earliest extant extended piece of writing by Newton on a dynamical subject.
It is also of great interest for the evidence it provides for the medieval background
extends but he being a spirit and penetrating all matter^^ can be noe to Newton’s thought. The tone of the whole passage is immistakably scholastic,
obstacle to the motion of matter noe more than if nothing were in its being cast almost in the form of a medieval disputation. Equally unmistakable,
way. Let me aske why one should be motion more than another since in however, is the extreme clarity of expression in striking contrast to that of many
of Newton’s contemporaries. Noteworthy, too, is the characteristically detailed
pleno [it] is so stopped by one body rubbing uppon another and in nature of his observations of the vortices produced in fluid motion, and especially
vacuum it hath its liberty. Can the same thing (viz. a being environed of the behaviour of small motes in the water at the ‘stagnation point’ immediately
with bodys) at the same time give a being to motion and yet destroy it, *7 behind the moving body.
At the top of fol. 88, before the first of the topics listed on fols. 87, 87a, Newton
wherefore to be in pleno cannot be essentiall to motion. And if it were, has written: 'Amicus Plato amicus Aristoteles magis arnica veritas.' In this passage
things would be more properly sade to move where there is most body on violent motion he has already parted company with the Aristotelian belief
or they find most resistance to theire motion and so more properly in that projectiles were moved by the circumambient air, though he is largely con­
cerned (in § [i]) with refuting the theory of antiperistasis which he may possibly
water than in aire etc. But if it is objected by A risto tleth a t a vacuum is
have confused with Aristotle’s own rather different theory of the motion of a
uniforme and everywhere alike and a body hath the same respects to a projectile. Just as Aristotle’s cosmological views became largely irrelevant after the
vacuum in all places alike but there is no motion with [out ] some mutation publication of Galileo’s Siderius Nuncius, so Aristotle’s theory of motion ceased
of circumstances. And so in vacuo no motion, I answer as to our senses to have any true scientific value after the publication of Newton’s Principia
126 E X T R A C T S FROM EARLY NOTEBOOK I I E X T R A C T S FROM EARLY NOTEBOOK 127
in 1687. Nevertheless it is gratifying to find Newton taking his place at the end 18. Physics, Book IV, Chapter 8.
of the long and distinguished line of critics of Aristotle’s theory of motion. 19. At fol. 117. Whereas Newton here gives Descartes’s definition of motion
At the beginning of the passage three distinct causes of the continuation of in the true and philosophical sense without comment, later, in MS. VI, he
violent motion are mentioned: the air, a ‘force impresst’, or the ‘natural gravity’ criticizes the same definition at length and to great effect, ultimately replacing it
of the body. The first section is devoted to a refutation of the first cause, the by his own definition of absolute motion relative to absolute space. There are a
second cause is rejected at the beginning of the second section, and the remainder number of other references to Descartes in the present notebook, including one
of the passage is devoted to a defence of the third and, in Newton’s view, correct to ‘page 54 Princip. Philos. 3rd’ at fol. 9 3 V in connexion with Descartes’s Vortex
cause. Theory. On the same folio occurs a cometary observation dated Sat. December,
4. This ‘small force’ (of the body’s motion) is clearly intended to be measured 4th 1664.
relative to the moving body. 20. That is, Descartes’s Principia Philosophiae first published in Amsterdam,
5. That is the region of the backward stagnation point relative to the moving 1644. There was a copy of the third (Latin) edition of this work in Newton’s
body. library. See de Villamil [i], p. 74.
6. The meaning of this sentence as it stands is obscure. Possibly Newton in­ 21. At fol. 117.
tended to supply ‘the water’ between ‘answer’ and ‘must’. 22. References to ‘Mr. Boyle’s Receiver’ occur at fols. 9 6 V , 9 9 .
2 3 . At fol. 1 2 1 V . This passage would seem to point towards a realization of the
7. An argument found, for example, in Buridan. See Duhem [3], p. 37. For
the best-documented and most detailed account of medieval dynamics see distinction between the concepts of mass and weight. Solidity would have to be
Clagett [i], and for the best brief account Crombie [i], vol. ii. Part I, § 3. equivalent to density in the sense of the quantity of matter per unit of volume.
8. This like propensity (towards cessation of motion) followed from the For a discussion of Newton’s concept of mass and density see above. Part I,
Aristotelian belief that all motion required a cause failing which it would im­ Chapter 1 . 4 , p. 2 5 .
2 4 . At fol. 1 2 1 V . The figure of 1 0 0 braces in 5" reappears in the Vellum
mediately cease.
9. The sense of this and the preceding passage is obscure. Most probably Manuscript (MS. Ill) and was taken by Newton from the Dialogue of Galileo.
Newton meant to imply that the air would have no more power to move the ball See MS. Ill, Appendix A, para. (i).
when they were released than when they were restrained.
10. This argument, based on the assumption that the same force (— influence)
will have the same effect on two different bodies, one heavy, one light, provides
a good indication of the primitive state of Newton’s dynamical thought at the
time of composing this passage. It should be compared with Buridan’s much
juster argument against the Aristotelian theory on the grounds that a feather
would then go further than a heavy body. See Duhem [3], p. 39.
11. The arguments in this section against the continuation of motion by a
‘force impresst’ do not seem so conclusive as those in the previous section.
12. One would have expected non migrat in place of transfigurat.
13. That is, the body’s natural gravity. An echo, perhaps, of the medieval
distinction between natural gravity = weight, and unnatural gravity = im­
petus or force. See, for example, Duhem [i], p. 114 et seq.
14. It appears later that Newton somehow intended the spheres to be partly
in vacuo and partly in air. Originally he had written earth throughout in place
of Aire which would have made the supposed arrangement more plausible.
15. As opposed, for example, to Descartes’s belief {Principia, Pt. 2, Art. 18)
that a vacuum in a vessel would be unthinkable since the walls of the vessel
would then necessarily touch. In the chapter de vacuo referred to (at fol. 8qv)
Newton bases his belief in the possibility of empty space between bodies on the
existence of atoms not infinitely divisible, so that if the bodies are nearer than
the least atom there would necessarily be empty space between them.
16. The view, for example, of Henry More: for a discussion of More’s views
on space, spirit, and matter see Koyre [5], especially Chapter 6. The influence
of More on Newton remains to be established. A beginning has been made by
Koyre and by Fiersz [i].
17. Reminiscent of Ockham’s argument against Aristotle based on the collision
of two stones, when one and the same portion of air would have simultaneously
to move the two stones in opposite directions
II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 129
II folio 15 after a considerable gap. Lacking further evidence it is therefore
reasonable to assume that the most probable order of composition of the
DYNAMICAL WRITINGS IN THE WASTE B O O K entries on folios 10 and 38 is given by their position of entry in the Waste
Book. A similar assumption, however, cannot be made for the treatment
of circular motion on folio i, for this must have come after the first tenta­
the religious commonplace book of Newton’s stepfather,
O r ig in a l l y
tive discussion of the problem in Ax.-Prop. 20. Striking confirmation of
the Rev. Barnabas Smith, whose signature, dated 12 May 1612, appears
this is supplied by the alteration of the figures 4 + in Ax.-Prop. 24 to 6 + ,
on the fly-leaf, the Waste Book (MS. Add. 4004) probably passed to
corresponding to the exaet result 2tt obtained in folio i.
Newton on the death of his stepfather {c. 1656) along with the latter’s
Given the date ‘Jan. 20th 1664’ [O.S.] oeeurring in the margin of
library. Some of the pages have theological entries followed by notes in
folio 10 it is probable that all the dynamieal entries in the Waste Book were
Smith’s handwriting, and the original index is also extant. When first
made on or after that date. On the other hand it is possible that some of
examined by the Syndics of the University of Cambridge appointed to
these entries represent final versions of earlier drafts composed earlier
catalogue the Portsmouth Collection the book was in a state of great
in January 1665 or towards the end of 1664.!
confusion with many folios missing. It has now been restored and appears
to be complete. It contains many entries by Newton apart from the I la
dynamical ones, those on mathematics being of particular importance. At folio I. The heading Dens on this folio in Barnabas Smith’s hand,
The dynamical entries occur as follows: against the normal alphabetical order, is confirmed by the index, and is
At folio I (Ila) explained by the original nature of the book. There can be no doubt that
At folio 10 (Ilb) the first two dynamical entries on this folio must have been made later
Definitions, at folio lov. (lie) than the discussion of circular motion beginning at Ax.-Prop. 20. It is
just possible that Newton originally left the first page blank either out
Ax.-Prop. 1-26 at folios iov-12 (Ud)
of a feeling of respect for his stepfather’s memory, or on religious grounds,
Ax. 100-22 at folios 12-13 (lie)
whereas the mathematical entry on the verso, bearing the date Septem­
Ax.-Prop. 27-40 at folios 13V-15, 39 (llf) ber 1664, the earliest in the Waste Book, could well have been the first
At folio 38 (Ilg) entry in the book.
The occurrence of references to the Definitions in both Ax.-Prop. Apart from a few unimportant erasures the text is clean and shows no
1-26 and Ax. 100-22 proves that lib was composed before lie and Ild. signs of being worked over. Given the rather complicated nature of the
Likewise references to certain of Ax.-Prop. 1-26 in Ax. 100-22 prove argument on circular motion it is perhaps unlikely that it was written in
that lie was composed before lid . Finally in He there are references to extempore.
all the preceding sections so that the order of composition of Ilc-e Text
follows the alphabetical order, that is, the order of entering in the Waste [i.]^ If the ball b [Fig. i] revolves about the center n the force by which it
Book. It is then natural to assume the same to be true for the remaining endeavours from the center n would beget soe much motion in a body as
entries on folios 1,10, and 38. No internal contradiction results from this there is in h in the time that the body h moves the length of the semidia-
assumption for the last pair of entries; in fact, in both cases there is some miter bn. (as if b is moved with one degree of motion through b7i in one
supporting evidence. For the calculations on folio 10 are restricted to the seacond of an hower then its force from the center n being continually
specially simple case of totally inelastic collisions, whereas the physical (like the force of gravity) impressed upon a body during one second it
discussion in Ax.-Prop. 7-10 deals with the much more difficult case of will generate one degree of motion in that body.) Or the force from n in
perfectly or partly elastic collisions. Again, the entries on resolution of one revolution is to the force of the bodys motion as : : periph : rad.
velocity and composition of motions on folio 38 are the first to treat of these t T h e dating of the earliest dynamical manuscripts is considered above in Part I,
topics in the Waste Book, and follow the preceding dynamical entries on Chapter 6.2.
130 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 131
Demonstration. [4.] If a body undulate in the circle bd all its undulations of any altitude
[2.]“ If e/ fg = g h ~ he — zfa — zfb = zgc = zed. And the globe move are performed in the same time with the same radius. Galileus.^
from a to b then zfa : ab : : ab : fa : : force or pression of b upon fg at [5.] As radius ab to radius : : so are the squares of there times in which
its reflecting : force of 6’s motion, therefore ^ab = ab be cd da : they undulate.5
fa : : force of the reflection in one round (viz: in b, c, d, and a) : force of [6.] If c circulate in the circle egef [Fig. 2], to whose diameter ce, ad = ab
being perpendicular then will the body b undulate in the same time that
c circulates.6
a

[7.] And those bodies circulate in the same time whose lines drawne
from the center a to the center d are equall.7
[8.] And ad : dc : : force of gravity to the force of c from its center d.^
[9.] Coroll : hence may the force of gravity of the motion of things falling
were they not hindered by the aire may very exactly [be] founds (viz.
Figure i. [}] cd : ad : : force from d : force from a.

Vs motion, by the same proceeding if the Globe b were reflected by each 1. For an interpretation of this and the following subsection see above,
side of a circumscribed polygon of 6, 8,12, 100, 1000 sides etc. the force Part I, Chapter 1.2, pp. 7-1 r. An equivalent result is derived by an entirely
different method in MS. IVa. It seems probable that Newton used this result to
of all the reflections is to the force of the bodys motion as the sume of derive the peculiar formula employed in the calculations of MS. III. See
those sides to the radius of the circle about which they are circumscribed. § 2 of the ‘Commentary and Interpretation’ to that manuscript.
And so if [the] body were reflected by the sides of an equilaterall circum­ 2. This demonstration must have followed Newton’s first estimate of the
fo r c e o f the body's endeavour fr o m the centre in h a lf a revolution given in Ax.-Prop.
scribed polygon of an infinite number of sides (i.e. by the circle it selfe)
22. Particularly interesting in this connexion is the cancellation of the figure 4 +
the force of all the reflections are to the force of the bodys motion as all in Ax.-Prop. 24 and its replacement by 6 + corresponding to the 2^ of the present
those sides {id est the perimiter) to the radius. section. For a similar ‘polygonal’ treatment of circular motion see the demon­
stration of the law of centrifugal force at the end of the S ch o liu m to Prop. 4,
[3.] If the body b moved in an Ellipsis^ that its force in each point (if its Theor. 4, Book, I, P rin cip ia . Ball ([i], p. 13) suggested that this latter demon­
motion in that point bee given) [will ?] bee found by a tangent circle of stration was the one employed by Newton to calculate ‘the force with which a
Equall crookednesse with that point of the Ellipsis. ball revolving within a sphere presses the surface of the sphere’ prior to his
132 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W A S T E B O O K 133
derivation and first test of the inverse square law of gravitation against the Text
moon’s motion during the Plague Years. See above, Part I, Chapter 1.2, especi­ Of Reflections.
ally pp. 8-11.
3. Although the results derived in the preceding subsections are exact, they [i.]'* Suppose that the bodys a, h, [Fig. i] have noe zis elastica to reflect
give no hint as yet of the dependence of centrifugal force on speed and radius: the one from the other but at theire occursion conjoine and keepe together
this dependence is first given (implicitly) in MS. IVa. Nevertheless Newton is
already pondering the more difficult problem of motion in an ellipse. Given the as if they were one body. Then
reference to Kepler’s third law of planetary motion noted in § i of MS. I, it is not first if Theire bulke and motion be
improbable that he had in mind the elliptical paths of the planets about the sun. equall then at theire meeting they
4. See, for example, the Dialogue (edit. Santillana [i], p. 246).
shall rest.
5. This result does not appear in Galileo’s Dialogue. It is found, however, in
his Discorsi (edit. Crew and Salvio [i], p. 96). See above. Part I, Chapter 6.2, (2). If {b) have more motion than
p. 91, for the possible indication of date thus provided. (fl) all the motion of {a) shall be lost
6. An early, if not the earliest, correct statement of this result appeared with­ Figure i.
and soe much of {b)s as (a) had and
out proof in Huygens’s Horologium Oscillatorium. See Theorem IX of the
appendix on centrifugal force at the end of Part 5 of that work. The problem of they shall both move towards c shareing the difference of the motion
the circular pendulum does not seem to have been considered by Galileo. There proportionally twixt them.
is a passing reference to it by Descartes in the Cogitationes Privatae (Qiuvres, Demon: Suppose the motion of ehf =■ motion of a
vol. X, p. 224) probably inspired by an entry in Beeckman’s Journal (Beeckman
[i], vol. i, pp. 256-7). The use of a conical pendulum as a regulator for clocks (2). If a rest and b hit it they shall both move towards c shareing the
was demonstrated by Hooke at meetings of the Royal Society at the beginning motion of b twixt them.
of the year 1667 (see Birch [i], vol. ii, pp. 150 et seq.). Later Huygens contested
Hooke’s claim to have been the first to employ such a method. It seems prob­ O f Reflection
able that Huygens had employed the circular pendulum in clock regulation as [2.]*^ Suppose the Bodys a, b [Fig. 2] doe not reflect one another but
early as 1658 (see Huygens, CEuvres, vol. vii, pp. 390-1). An important reference conjoyne*= at their meeting and soe
to the circular pendulum is also found in Hooke’s paper ‘Concerning the in­
flection of a direct motion into a curve by a supervening attractive principle’ move or rest together, a = the body
read before the Royal Society at their meeting of 23 May 1666. See Birch [i], a^\b = the body fee; c = body ced\
vol. ii, pp. 90-92. G
d = body fedc. m — motion of a, n
7. Horologium Oscillatorium, Theorem VII.
— motion of b, p = motion of c,
8. Ibid., Theorem X, for a special case of the result given by Newton. This
special case is the one employed in MS. HI. See § 3 of the ‘Commentary and q = motion of d — n-\~p, before re­
Figure 2.
Interpretation’ of that manuscript. flection. e = motion of a, f = motion
9. Characteristic of Newton’s invariable search for exact quantitative results. of b, g ^ motion of c, h = motion of d after reflection, r = swiftnesse
of a, ^ = swifness of b, c or d, before reflection, t — swiftness of a,
u =^swiftnes of b, c or d after occursion. 0 the point of theire occursion
I lb
Axiome first
At folio 10. The date, ‘Jan. 20th 1664’ (O.S.), in the margin is the only [3.] Two bodys {b, c) [Fig. 2] being alike swift the motion of b : motion of
one occurring among the dynamical entries in the Waste Book. This c : : b : c. for equall parts have equall motion. Therefore b : c : : a\\ the
whole section is devoted to the problem of collisions between two
parts of b : all such parts of c : : motion of b : the motion of c.
perfectly inelastic bodies. It is assumed throughout that the bodies move
together after collision the total directed motion (= momentum) being [4.] Prop: first. If before the occursion of a [Fig. 2] and d a rest then shall
conserved. Subsection 2 gives the impression of being a revised and more e^ h = q.~ and since t = v, tis alsoe e : q : : a : a-\-d.^ Or e ~ -also
far-reaching version of the cancelled subsection i. It is possible, there­ a-\-d
fore, that in spite of the small number of emendations the subsections h == f/— = -A -
2-8 were written in extempore. There are no errors in the calculations a-\-d a\ d
apart from the small slip indicated at note (f). [5.] Prop; 2*^1 If a meete d, and have lesse motion than it, then.
134 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 135
q— m = e-\-hA for suppose m — n. then should a and rest after cdm-\-bam dn-\-an j , , 7j , 7 1 cdmA-bam
---- ------ ~ — ----- or cdm^bam = bdn-\-ban and — — -— — n.
occursion did not p = q— ni force them towards k. ba a bd\--ba
[6.] Prop, 3: Suppose the center of gravity^ in d [Fig. 2], y i n a . z and bd-yba : cd^ba : : m n. tm vn : b : \ tbd-\-tba : vcd-\-vba.
/ the [points] in which the bodys a and d touch in theire meeting 0 the cdvA-abv , aetA-det
— e and v =
point of theire meeting, {a) the magnitude of the body («). (d) the magni­ td-\-ta obA-cd
tude of (d) m — motion of a before meeting, n = motion d before meet­ [8.i°] If a and d [Fig. 6] meete one another that c must be negative that is
ing. the time in which a or d<^ moves to 0 = time in which they both
move to y [Fig. 3]. p = motion oi a, q — motion of d after occursion ^ negative the pointy must be taken on the same

side of [0 as z]

Figure 3.

a. This sub-section deleted.


b. At this point there is a marginal entry, ‘Jan 20th/i664’.
c. Succeeded by either moving or resting together deleted.
d. See Diagram 2.
e. Immediately after this occurs the equation: zo x a ■ fo x d : :m : n equivalent to
the assumption motion proportional to magnitude of body X distance moved in given
time.
f. In error for m : p : : zo : oy.
1. Meaning a is the magnitude or bulk of the body a. From ‘Axiome first’ it
is clear that both bodies are assumed to be of the same material so that the
question of mass and density does not arise.
2. For the definitions of these and other terms in subsections 3-5 see sub­
section 2.
dm^dn 3. This assumes the motions of two equivelox bodies to be proportional to
m-^n = p+q- a : d :: p : q, or a-\-d :d : : m^n (= p + q ): q
CL-[- d their bulks. See MS. lie, Def. 3.
am-\-an am X zo-{-an X zo 4. The first indication that Newton had corrected Descartes’s law of conserva­
p. m [ p : zo : zy^. oy.
Q,-\- d am-\-dm tion of motion in respect of the direction of movement.
5. The reason for the division of the body d in Fig. 2 into two parts b and c
[7.]^ a = magnitude of the body a. [Figs. 4 and 5] = mag: of body d. now becomes evident.
0 = the point of concourse : z , f = the points of contact, at 0. zo — h, 6. Although the centre of gravity plays no part in the discussion its appear­
ance here indicates that Newton was thinking of extended bodies rather than
fo — c, op — e. t — time in which the bodys move from z and / to o. idealized particles.
V — time in which they move from 0 to p. m = motion of a before oc- 7. The calculations in this subsection, with their introduction of times and
cdnfi distances for measuring speed, may have been intended to serve as a basis for an
cursion. n = motion of it afterwards, ba : cd : : m = motion of experimental test of the law of conservation of motion.
ba 8. In conformity with MS. He, Def. 3, this assumes that motion is propor­
dn tional conjointly to bulk (magnitude or quantity) and distance moved in given
d before occursion. a : d motion of d after occursion.
time.
136 DYNAAIICAL W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II DY N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK 137
9. T h is is eq u ivalent to the assum ption speed proportional directly to distance Alsoe if the cube Inniqyz [Fig. 3] 8 move the length of op 5; and
and inversely to tim e. A lth o u g h N ew to n n orm ally com pares speeds b y the dis­ the piramis [Fig. 4] tvwx — 7 move the length of rs —- 3 in the same time;
tances m o ved in the same tim e, as in M S . l i e , D e f. 2, he does giv e the m ore
general expression in vo lvin g the ‘ fo rb id d en ’ division o f one kind o f ejuantity
then, as opxlmqyz : rsXtvwx : : 40 : 21 : : the motion of Imqyz to the
(distance) b y another (time) in the note to M S . I l d , A x .-P r o p . 26. H ere he is
careful on ly to com pare quantities o f the sam e kin d on each side o f the equation.
10. T h is su bsection again dem onstrates N e w to n ’s clear realization o f the
im portance o f direction. H is easy m astery o f the significance o f e n egative is also
striking.

lie
Commencing at folio lov. Four diagrams occur at the top margin
opposite Defs. i, 2 having no connexion with these definitions but
Figure i.
similar to the diagrams found at the foot of folio 10. Apart from the
substitution of ‘quantity’ for ‘body’, and the cancellations of the original
version of Def, 3 and the end of Def. 10, there are few alterations in the
text which could thus have been a write-out of an earlier draft. Some
support for this possibility is supplied by the absence of definitions
numbered 6 and 8, and by the fact that in Def. 3, of which the preceding
passage would seem to represent an earlier version, the term ‘quantity’
is used throughout in contrast to the original use of ‘body’ in the
immediately preceding and succeeding definitions.

Text
Definitions.
When a Quantity^ is translated/passeth from one parte of Extension^
to another it is saide to move^
2.3 One Quantity® is soe much swifter than another, as the distance
through which it passeth is greater than the distance through which the
other passeth in the same time.
One'^ Quantity® hath soe much more motion^ than another, as the summe
of the spaces through which each of its parts moveth is to the summe of
the spaces through which each of the parts of the other quantity® moveth'^ Figure 3.

in the same time, supposeing each of the parts in both Quantitys'^ to be


equall and alike to one another'' and moved in the same p osition .O r motion of tvwx. Or the motion of one quantity to another is as their
powers to persever in that state.s
3. One Quantity hath so much more motion than another, as the distance
4. Those Quantitys'i are said to have the same determination^ of their
through which it moveth drawne into its quantity, is to the distance
motion which move the same way, and those have divers which move
through which the other moveth in the same time, drawne into its
divers ways.
quantity. As if the line ah [Figs, i and 2] move the length of be and ef
the length of eh in the same time, the motion of ah is to the motion of cd, 5. ^'^A quantity® is reflected when meeting with another quantity it looseth
as abxbc — abed, to e fx eh — iehk. the determination of its motion by rebounding from it. As if the bodys
138 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE fiOOK II
II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 139
a [Fig. 5], h meete ones another in the point c they are parted either
on both sides any plaine with which [mn) is coincident**; also the line
by some springing motion in themselves or in the matter crouded
mn drawne through it is called an axis of motion.*
betwixt them, and as the spring is more dull or vigorous/quick soe the
11 .*3 The center of motion in 2 divers bodys is a point soe placed twixt
bodys will bee reflected with with [sic] more or lesse force: as if it
these bodys that (if it bee conceived to rest and) if the bodys bee moved
endeavour to get liberty to inlarge it selfe with as greate strength and
about it with circular motion they shall both have an equall quantity of
vigor as the bodys a, b, pressed it together, then the motion of the body a
motion, the line about which they move is the axis of motion.

Figure 5.

Figure 7.

12. ’^ A Body is said to move toward another body either when all its
parts move towars it or else when some of its parts have more motion
towards it than others have from it. Otherwise not.
13. * Bodys are more or lesse distant as the distances of their "^centers of
motion*" are more or lesse. or as their distances might bee acquired with
from b will bee as greate after as before that reflection, but if the spring more or less motion.
have but halfe that vigor, then the distance twixt a and b, at the minute
a. Replacing body deleted. Quantity, as appears from Def. 3, either means body,
after the reflection shall bee halfe as much as it was^’ at the minute
or its quantity, or bulk, a term sometimes used by Nezvton, as in M S. V, § i.
beefore the reflection. b. The succeeding passage dozen to position deleted. It is clearly an earlier version
7.9 Refraction is when the body ^passing obliquelythrough the surface ed of Def. 3.
c. Succeeded by supp deleted.
[Fig. 6] at the point b meets with more opposition on one side of the d. Replacing bodys deleted.
surface than on the other and soe looseth its determination; as if it turne e-e. Substituted for Or struck out and zvritten at the end of the line.
towards a. f. Marginal entry noe motion is lost in reflection. For then circular motion
being made by continuall reflection would decay.*
9.1° Force is the pressure or crouding of one body upon another. g. Succeeded on the left-hand side, as though at the beginning of a nezv definition,
by A quantity is said to bee refracted deleted.
10.^^ The center of motion* in the same body is such a point with in a h. Succeeded by before deleted.
quantity! which rests when a body is moved with any circular but not i. Replacing gravity deleted.
progressive motion!; **that'^ if it be conceived to rest as at a [Fig. 7] and j-j. Written in above the passage within a quantity.
k -k . Deleted.
some line as (nrn) be drawne through it, about which (as about an axis) 1. This definition entered in the margin.
the quantity (dklp) revolving there shall bee the same quantity of motion m-m. Replacing parts deleted.
140 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 141
1. See reference to extension, space, or expansion in MS. V, § i. Newton’s where the set is completed at Ax.-Prop. 40. The stop after ‘Axiornes’ in
metaphysical views on the nature of extension are given in MS. Add. 4003. the heading would seem to indicate that the original heading was ‘Axiomes’
Certain extracts from this manuscript are given in MS. VI.
2. Similar definitions of motion are given in MS. V, § i, and MS. VI, Def. 4. only. This is confirmed by various references to certain of Ax. 1-26 in
3. Cf. the definitions of velocity in MS. V, § i ; MS. VI, Defs. 13, 14. With Ax. 100-22, for example, those to Ax. i, 2 in Ax. 100. The term Propo­
one remarkable exception (see note to MS. I Id, Ax.-Prop. 26), Newton always sition first occurs in a reference to Prop. 28 in Ax.-Prop. 29. Again, there
compares either the velocity of one body with another, or two different velocities is a reference in the revised version of Ax.-Prop. 28, 30 to Prop. 25
in the same body. which had previously been referred to as Ax. 25 in Ax.-Prop. 27. It can
4. A more sophisticated definition of ‘motion’ is given in MS. V, § i, sent. 4.
Normally motion for Newton means quantity of motion momentum) but on
be assumed, therefore, that the original title of numbers 1-26 inclusive
occasion he uses it in the sense of movement, as in MS. V, § i, sent. 3. was ‘Axioms’, the term ‘Proposition’ having been added after the compo­
5. This statement refers back to that at the beginning of the Definition and sition of those following Ax. 100-22. The whole set of Axioms and
implies that for Newton the pow er o f a body to persevere in its state is proportional Propositions has therefore been divided into two sections Ild and Ilf,
to its motion. See MS. lie, Ax. 100. separated by Ax. 100-22 at lie .
6. Cf. Descartes, P r in cip ia Ph ilosop h iae, Art. 39, Part 2: omne id quod m ovetur
The members of the present set treat of the following topics:
. . . determ inatum esse a d motum suum continuanduni versus aliquam p artem ,
secundum lineam rectam . Principle of inertia (i, 2)
7. Notice how Newton follows his definition of reflection by a vivid illustra­
Force and motion (3-6, 23)
tion of the process as in certain of the definitions in P rin cip ia , Book I.
8. Cf. same notion in MS. I Id, Ax.-Prop. 20. Collision between two bodies (7-10)
9. Recalling, possibly, his early experiments in optics. Kinematics of an extended body (11-18)
10. The force here defined is force in the instantaneous, physical sense. Else­ Circular motion (19-22)
where, as in MS. I Id, Ax.-Prop. 3-6, he uses the term in the sense of an impulse Centre of motion of a pair of bodies (24-25)
measuring the total effect of a variable, physical force. It is this latter type of
Kinematics of a single particle (26)
m otive force which features in the second law of motion. For a discussion of
the development of Newton’s concept of force see above, Part I, Chapter i.i. Several inversions of number order point towards the original exis­
11. For a further discussion of the movement of extended bodies beyond that
tence of an earlier version. With the exception of a number of considerable
in Defs. 10-13, see MS. Ild, Ax.-Prop, i i et seq.
12. If the deletion of the remainder of the passage is ignored there results a deletions (all noted) the text is almost entirely clean.
definition of centre of motion in the dynam ical sense. Whereas on omitting the
cancelled section there results a definition of centre of motion in the kinem atical
sense. For a further discussion of this centre of motion see MS. Ild, Ax.-Prop.
2'ext
11-18, and for the centre of motion in the dynamical sense MS. V, § 4.
Newton’s kinematical centre of motion corresponds to, though it does not Axiomes. and Propositions
always coincide with, the modern instantaneous centre of motion, whereas his 1.1 If a quantity once move it will never rest unlesse hindered by some
dynamical centre of motion as defined in MS. V, § 4, may be shown to coincide
wdth the centre of mass or gravity of the body (see MS. V, n. 8), so that his externall caus.
alternative use of the term ‘gravity’ for ‘motion’ in the present definition was
2. A quantity will always move on in the same streight line (not changing
entirely just as applied to the dynamical centre of motion.
13. This gives the extension to two bodies of the immediately preceding the determination nor celerity of its motion) unlesse some externall cause
definition of the dynamical centre of motion for a single body. See MS. Ild, divert it.
Ax.-Prop. 25.
14. References to this definition occur in MS. Ild, Ax.-Prop, i i, 12. 3.2 There is exactly required so much and noe more force to reduce a
body to rest as there was to put it upon motion: et e contra.
I ld 4.3 Soe much force as is required to destroy any quantity of motion in a
The Axiom-Propositions commence at folio lov immediately after body, soe much is required to generate it; and soe much as is required to
Def. 12 and continue recto and verso to Ax. 100 at folio 12. They recom­ generate it soe much is alsoe required to destroy it.
mence with number 27 after Ax. 122 on folio 13V and continue recto and
verso to Ax.-Prop. 37 at foot of folio 15. 'I'here is then a break till folio 39 6. If the s[ame] force move 2 unequall bodys {a and h) the swiftnesse of
142 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 143
one body {a) is to the swiftnesse of [the ot]her as h is to and there­ and absolutely sollid'^ then at the period of theire motion towards one
fore the motion of both bodys shall bee equall. another (that is at the moment of theire meeting) theire pression is at
5. If two [equal ?] bodys [b, c) bee moved by uneqiiall forces, as the force the greatest, or rather ’tis done with the whole force by which theire
moveing (b) is to the force [movjing c, so is motion of b, to the motion of motion is stopt (for theire whole motion was stoped by the force of theire
c, so is the swiftnes of b, to that of c. pressure upon one another in this one moment, and there cannot bee/
succeede divers degrees of pressure twixt two bodys in one moment).
7. If two bodys [a and b moving?] against one another the same way
towards O [Fig. i], {a) overtaking {b) none of theire motion shall be lost, Now so long as neither of these 2 bodys yeild to one another they will
for {a), presses [(6) as much] as {b) presses {df^^ and therefore the motion retaine the same forcible pressure towards one another : that is soe much
force as deprived the bodys of their motion towards one another soe
of (i!)) shall increase [as much] as that of (<2) decreaseth.
much doth now urge them from one another and therefore^'^ they shall
move from one another as much as they did towards one another before
a h
d\ ct theire reflection.
10.5 There is the same reason when unequall and unequally moved
Figure i. Figure 2.
bodys reflect, that they should separate from one another with as much
8. ^ If two quantities [a and b) [Fig. 2] move towards one another and motion as they came together.
meete in O, Then the difference of theire motion shall not bee lost nor 11 If a line df [Fig. 4] bee moved not with d
loose its determination. For at their occursion they presse equally uppon a Progressive but onely a Circular motion its
one another and^P^ therefore one must loose noe more motion than the middle point (n) shall rest. For if it move let
other doth; soe that the difference of their motions cannot bee destroyed. it move towards r soe that, when the point (d)
If one body {a) overtake another body {b) they both moveing towards is in p and / in {q), then (w) shall be moved to
O then they shall always move together. If the body (c) move against {s).
an immoveable quantity {d) it shall not bee rebounded for c having 11. If aline {ce) [Fig. 5] be bisected in (a) about
urged d with which the line (ce) doth circulate and that
Figure 4.
9. *=If two equall and equally swift bodys {d and c) meete one another they point bee fixed. Then the whole line hath noe
shall bee reflected, soe as to move as swiftly frome one another after the progressive motion. For making ab = ad, bf, ag, and dh bee parallel, and
reflection as they did to one another before it. For perpendic to fh, then is vb = dp and vf-\~ph = bf-\-dh = zag. Wherefore
first suppose the sphaericall bodys e, f [Fig. 3] to the point c moveing towards n the point d shall move soe much towards
d f 1 ^ have a springing or elastic force soe that meeting one the line/A as the point b doth from it, and all the points in {a, c) or the line
another they will relent and be pressed into a ac move as much to the line fh as all the points in {ae) or the line (ae)
sphaeroidicall figure, and in that moment in which moves from it soe that the whole line ce stays in equilibrio neither
Figure 3.
there is a period put to theire motion towards one moveing to nor from//?, by the 12th Defin.
another theire figure will be most sphaeroidical and theire pression 12. Hence when the center of a line (a) is not in the midst of a line (/« e)
one upon the other is at the greatest, and if the endeavour to [Fig. 5] the whole line moves the same way which the longest parte doth,
restore theire sphaericall figure bee as much vigorous and forcible as for supposeing ca = ae then the line ce is in equilibria (par ax. ii) but if
theire pressure upon one another was to destroy it they will gaine as {m c) moves towards (fh) and be added to (c e) then (m e) moves towards
much motion from one another after their parting as they had towards ce (by def. 12).
one another before theire reflection. Secondly suppose they be sphaericall 13. When (ce) [Fig. 5] moves circularly but maketh noe progression its
Def. 3^^. Axiome 4th. Axiom 4th. axiome 3''.
144 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 145
midle point shall rest and is therefore the center of its motion, for if the determination from ac which d hath from h (for if ac be understood to
middle point move let it bee to r from a soe that the line ec bee moved move parallell to its selfe into the place ef, all its points describe parallel
into the place [w t) then let {w t) move about the fixed center r into the lines and therefore have the same determination one with another and
place xi’, then xs and wt are equally distant fromfh (by def. 13 and ax. 11) each with the whole body (by axiom 14) therefore gh hath the same
and alsoe (In) and [ce) are equally distant from the [line ?] f h : but xs and determination from ac which the point d hath from the point b.
In are not equally distant from/A: therefore neither are wt and ce equally 14(b). A Body being moved parallell to its selfe all its points describe
parallel lines and each of them have the same determination and velocity
with the body, for (by axiom 2)^ they must all bee streight ones which
if they intersect the body will not be moved parallel to its selfe. etc.
16.*’^ If a body move forward and circularly its center of motion shall
allways bee in the same streight line. For the body hath allways the same
determination (ax. 2) and the center of its motion hath the same deter­
mination with the body (ax. 15) therefore it hath always the same
determination, and soe will move continually in the same streight line.
If a body move streightly forward and circularly its center of
motion shall have the same determination and velocity that '4he body
hath'\ For suppos ac [Fig. 6] to be moved into the place and its center
of motion b into the place d, then let it turne about the center d into the
place ef parallel to ac soe that the point whieh was in {a) bee now in {e).
Now since [gh) by moveing into the place (/<?) makes noe progressive
motion (def. 10) it follows that’ the same quantity (or since
the same velocity (defin. 10)) and determination of motion in the same
distant from fh. and therefore the line ce had progressive motion when it time would translate ac parallell to it selfe into the place ef, that wold
passed into wt. translate it into the place had it both progressive and circular motion.
i4(a).^ By the same reason the middle point of a parallelogram paralleli- But the point d hath the same velocity and determination which the line
pipedon, prisme, cilinder, circle, sphaere, elipsis, sphaeroides [are at the ?] e/hath when moved parallel to its selfe^’’^ therefore the point d hath the
center of theire motion. same determination and velocity which the line gh hath when moved
with both eircular and progressive motion vide ax. 37.
15.'^ A Body hath the same determination of its motion which the center 18. If a body move progressively in some crooked line and alsoe circu­
« of its motion hath. As if the line ac larly its center of motion shall have the same determination and velocity
Q f .
^ [Fig. 6] move into the place the which the body hath. foH (ax. 17) this is trew when its motion is in a
center of its motion b moveing into streight line but a crooked line may bee conceived to consist of an infinite
the place d, then let gh move about number of streight lines.'" Or else in any point of the croked line the
the center d untill it be parallell to motion may bee conceived to be on in the tangent.”
ac, as into ef, soe that the point a fall
19. If 2 bodys make the same number of circulations with the same
into the point e. Now since gh by
distance from the center c [Fig. 7]: then as the Radij of the circles which
turning about the center d hath noe
their centers of motion describe are to one another soe are the perimeters
progressive motion (by Def. 10) tis
axiom 14.
plaine that gh and ef have determination from ac but ef hath the same 1,
146 DY N A M I CA L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 11
II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 147
call surface of the body edf circularly about the center m, it shall press
upon the body def for when it is in c (supposeing the circle bhc to be
described by its center of motion and the line eg a tangent to that circle
at 0) [it] moves towards g or the determination of its motion is towards
therefore if at that moment the body efd should cease to check it it
would continually move in the line eg (ax. i, 2) obliqly from the center m.

\
/ \
7/
a /
/ nv
\

\
\ /

but if the body def oppose it selfc to this endeavour keeping it equi­
distant from m, that is done by a continued checking or reflection of it
from the tangent line in every point of the circle ebh, but the body edf
cannot check and curbe the determination of the body eo unless they
continually presse upon one another. The same may be understood if
the body adb [Fig. 9] bee restrained into circular motion by the thread
{om)W
2 1. Hence it appeares that all bodys moved circularly have an endeavour
from the center about which they move, otherwise the body oe would not
/ continually presse upon edf.
Figure 8.
22. '^ The whole force by which a body eo indevours from the center m in
one to another soe are theire velocitys one to another (ax. lo, def. 2) and halfe a r e v o lu t io n is more than double to the force which is able to
their motions are to one another as theire bulkes drawne into the Radij generate or destroy its motion, that is to the force with which it is moved:
of those circle (which theire centers of motion describe) are to another for supposeing it have moved from (c) by {h) to {h) [Fig. 8]. Then the
(Def. 3). A s ; ec : CO : : velocity of eb : velocity of ao and eh xec \aoXco : : resistance of the body def (which is equall to its pressure upon def) is
motion eb : motion of ao. able to destroy its force of moveing from e to g and to generate in it as
20.^ If a sphaere or [Fig. 8] move within the concave shaeicall of cilindri- much force of moveing from [b) to {h) the quite contrary way.
148 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M IC A L W R IT IN G S IN TH E W A ST E B O O K 149

25.™ Having [the] cent[er] of motion of the 2 bodys ob and de [Fig. 10] to velocity of a is to the velocity oi e 2is, a b x d f to ed X be.^^ For supposeing
find the common center of both [their motions] draw a line oe from the 7 .1 • eb X ed * 1 / , 1 * r •
that gp — eb then is ep = — ^ — And (by def. 2) the velocity of a is to
centers of their motions o and e, and div[ide it at a ?] so that the body ob
is to the body de as the line ae to the line oa: that is so that obxoa = , r 7 . . eb Aed 7 7- 7 7 7 * 1 1
the velocity oi e : : ab : ep : : ab : ■— ^ - : : a b xfd : ebx ed. Alsoe the
ae X de.^^ For then if they move about the center a being always opposite fd
to one another they have equall motion (ax. 19) and consequently have" motion of a is to that motion of e (by def 3^) : : a xa b : eXcp : : aXab:
, eb Xed i n 7 7 • 1 .
eXep : : aXab : e x - : : a x a b x f d : eX eb xed : : a X its velocity :
e x its velocity.**^
a
Figure 10.

Figure 12.

an equall endeavour from the center a (ax. 24) soe that if they bee joyned
to center (a) by the lines ae and ao, the one hindereth the other from
forcing the centre a any way soe that it shall stand in equilibrio betwixt
them and (by def. 10)1^ is therefore theire center of motion.
24." If two bodies {cb and de) [Fig. ii] move about a center (a) then
making be ~ a, de — b, ac — c,ae — d, the time in which be makes halfe
a revolution call e, that in which de doth the same call /, the pressure of
cb from the center a in halfe a revolution call g, and that of de call h : the
motion of eb in halfe a revolution call k, and that of de call /, then k : I : :
24. If two bodys {eb and de) [Fig. 11] move about a center a thenP The Note^o that when the motion is uniforme that is when a body moves over
whole force by which the body eb tends from the center a in one revolu­ the same space in the same time (which will ever bee when the motion
tion (being equall to 6-f^7 times the force by which the body is moved of that body is neither helped nor hindred) then in a right angled
(ax. 22)^^ is to the motion of that body eb as the whole force by which the triangle ab may designe the space through which a body moveth in the
body de tends from the center a in one revolution (which is equall to time eb. Otherwise, when ’tis not uniforme the proportion of the time
6 + ^7 times the force by which the [body] de is moved, or which is able to in which a body moves to the distance through which it moves may be
stop its motion (ax. 22)) is to the motion of the body de. Vide Axioma 23""’. designed by lines drawne to a crooked line, as the time by [Fig. 13] or
26. If the body a [Fig. 12] move through the space ab =r- b m the time ih, the distance by gh or fi, the velocity by the proportion of nh to hi, ni
d = be, and the body e through the space cd — e in the time /. then the being tangent to the crooked line at i, etc.
150 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK II
II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 151
23.’' ®If the body bacd [Fig. 15] acquire the motion q by the force cT, and
result fo r ce oc change in m otion produced given later in A x .-P r o p . 23. A n alm ost
the body/the motion / by the force then d : q : ; ^ for suppose the identical expression o f the present n um ber occurs at M S . H e, A x . X14.
body rscb = / to acquire the motion w by the force d, then (ax. s) ^ S ■ '■ 3. See M S . H e, A x . 115.
4. N o tice for N e w to n absolutely solid m eant p erfectly elastic, whereas for
w : p. but q = zv (by ax. 4) therefore d : g : : q : p.
Descartes in his P rin cip ia P h ilosop h iae it im plied p erfectly inelastic. See, h o w ­
ever, G a b b e y [i]. C h a p ter 4.
5. T h e result given in this n um ber is true for a p erfectly elastic collision, as
follows, for exam ple, either from N e w to n ’s ow n law for relative velocities w ith
e =- I , or b y sim ultaneous application o f conservation o f m om en tu m and co n ­
servation o f energy. B u t it is not clear how N e w to n supposed that the general
result follow ed from the very special case considered in the p revious num ber.
T h e general result is em p loyed in M S . V , §§ 9, 10. N o tic e that the term ‘m o tio n ’
is here em p loyed in the sense o f m o vem en t rather than in the usual sense o f
cjuantity o f m otion ( — m om entum ).
6. In troduced to distin guish it from the later section o f the sam e num ber. T h is
latter section is clearly the ‘A x io m 14 ’ referred to in n u m ber 15, and therefore
presum ably bore the same n um ber in som e previous draft o f the present version.
7. T h e reference to A x . 2 is curious in this apparently kinem atical proposition.
F'igurc 15.
N e w to n m ay have had in m ind a b o d y m o vin g w ith o u t rotation un der the
action o f no forces.
a. F o l. I I begins.
8. N u m b e r 17 evid e n tly represents an im proved, com posite version o f the
b. D ele te d in fa v o u r o f the succeeding version.
present n um ber and the p revio u sly cancelled n um ber 15. In an y case the state­
c. E n title d in the margin O f the separation o f bo dys after reflection
m ent in the first sentence is u n tr u e : the centre o f m otion need n ot m o ve in a
d. D eleted in fa v o u r o f the succeeding version.
straight line b u t m ay describe instead som e ‘ crooked lin e’ , as in n um ber 18.
e. F o l. I I V begins. T h is zvhole section deleted.
9. N o tice the identical nature o f the dem onstration em p loyed to prove this
f. W hole section deleted.
proposition and that giv en in the ‘ m o dern ’ p ro o f that any m o vem en t o f a b o d y
g. E n title d in the margin T h e center o f m otions deter and velocity.
in a plane m ay be replaced b y a translation follow ed b y a rotation.
h-h. R ep lacin g It w o u ld have had did the b o d y m o ve parallel to it selfe deleted.
10. F o r exam ple, a circle, as in N e w to n ’s polygo n al treatm ent o f centrifugal
i. Su cceed ed by i f ac w o u ld be m oved parallel to it selfe into the place o f e f it
force at fol. i (M S . Ila ).
w ou ld keep the same determ ination and q u an tity o f m otion deleted.
1 1. A s in the case o f circular m otion. See n um ber 20.
j. S ucceed ed by in an y poin t o f the crooked line its determ ination is in the
12. T h e case considered b y D escartes in A rt. 38, Part 2, P rin cip ia Philosop hiae.
tan gen t deleted.
13. T h is first ten tative attem p t to introduce number into the treatm ent o f
k. E n title d in the margin O f endeavor from the center.
circular m otion is carried to a precise conclusion in fol. i (M S . H a).
l . I n error f o r g.
14. T h e exact m ean in g o f the p recedin g part first becom es evid en t in fol. i
m. E n title d in the margin T o find the center o f m otion in two bodys.
(M S . H a).
n. F o l. 12 begins.
15. S o that a is at the centre o f mass o f the tw o bodies.
o. D eleted in fa v o u r o f the succeeding version.
16. T h e reference is obscure. D e f. 10 refers to one b o d y only, whereas the
p. T h e r e follow s a n u m ber o f dashes in the m anuscript as if N e w to n were
dynam ical definition o f centre o f m otion o f a pair o f bodies in D e f. 11 contains
pon derin g the correct continuation.
no reference to equilibrium ( -- rest). N e w to n p ro b ab ly had in m ind the re­
q. S u cceeded b y a p artly illegible deleted portion containing a p ro of o f the
quirem ent that the centre o f m otion should be at rest, som eth ing w h ich fo l­
same result som ew hat less elegant than the final version.
low ed in this case from the equal and opposite endeavours o f the tw o bodies
r. M a r g in a l entry let this follow the s ' ax:
from the poin t under consideration. H ow ever, the im portan t th in g w as his
s. B en ea th I f 2 b o dys be m oved w ith equall or uneq deleted.
divination o f the special dyn am ical significance o f the poin t (centre o f mass) thus
1. N o tic e h o w in this and the su cceed ing n um ber N ew to n enunciates the defined. M a n y propositions relating to the m otion o f this p oin t are giv en in
p rinciple o f inertia in tw o separate parts. See A x . 100. See also above Part I, A x .-P r o p . 27 et seq. T h e s e propositions, in turn, m u st be regarded as the fore­
C h a p ter 2.2, for a discussion o f the evidence p rovid ed here and elsewhere in runners o f C o ro ll. 4 to the laws o f m otion in M S . X I and in the P rin cip ia .
the W aste B o o k for the influence of D escartes on N ew to n in dynam ics. A co m ­ 17. R ep la cin g a cancelled 4 k w h ich w o u ld correspond to the tentative
parison o f this and other enunciations o f the p rinciple o f inertia up to and in ­ approxim ation found in n um ber 22. W hereas 6 + corresponds to the exact result
clu d in g that in the P rin cip ia is given above in Part I, C h a p ter 1.4, p p. 29. 2TT derived at fol. i, good evidence that the present en try was originally m ade
2. T h is and the three follo w in g num bers are each special cases o f the general before those on fob i.
152 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 153
18. N o tic e in A x . 22 N e w to n equates the fo r c e by vAiich a body is m oved to this case the hindrance to the motion of one results from the pow er of
the force able to generate or destroy its m otion. B y A x .-P r o p . 23 (found out o f
the other to ‘persevere’ in its velocity or state. This power is usually
order at end o f the present set) this latter force w ill be proportional to the m otion
created or destroyed. T h is explains the final reference to A xio m a 2 3 ”” '.
called ‘the force of the body’. The endeavour of the force of one body to
19. T h e first occasion on w h ich qu a n tity o f m otion (as originally defined in hinder the progress of another is performed by pressure (Ax. 106). For
D e f. 3) is set jo in tly proportional to bu lk and velocity. two equivelox bodies, their forces (equal to the forces with lehich they are
20. W h a t follow s represents an extraordinary excep tion to N e w to n ’s cu sto ­ moved or their respective powers to persevere on their motion) are propor­
m ary m anner o f dealing w ith velocities b y com parison o f one w ith another
tional to the bodies (i.e. their sizes) (Ax. 107 via Ax. 102).
rather than directly, as here, as the gradien t o f the space-tim e graph. See above.
Part I, C h a p ter i . i , p. 3.
At this point a sharp distinction must be drawn between the force of
a body (as defined previously) and the force (acting) on a body. The
velocities acquired by equal bodies are proportional to the force acting on
lie
them (Ax. 108). The same is true for the destruction of velocity. For
At folio 12 immediately after Ax.-Prop. 23, and thereafter without a example, if the velocity of a is triple that of an equal body h, the force
break to folio 1 3 V. Several inversions of number order, especially in the required to deprive a of its velocity will be triple that required to deprive
last four axioms, point towards the existence of a previous version. b of its (Ax. 109). Hence the force of a ’s motion is triple that of A’s (Ax.
With the exception of the last four, the present set of axioms constitute 1 10 using the definition of force of a body’s motion in Ax. 106). The same
a closely interconnected whole whose significance and purpose is at first holds generally for equal bodies (Ax. i i i ) .
sight difficult to grasp. The clue to their interpretation is provided by The concept of a body’s motion (= momentum) is now introduced:
Ax. 1 18. This axiom is evidently equivalent to the general result relating ‘A body is said to have more or less motion as it is moved wdth more or
force and motion generated or destroyed given in Ax.-Prop. 23, itself less force, that is, as there is more or lessforce required to generate or destroy
the generalization of the special cases given in Ax.-Prop. 3-6. Now it can its whole motion' (Ax. 1 12). The motion of a body or the force of its motion
be proved that Ax. 1 18 is connected, directly or indirectly, to almost all is proportional jointly to its bulk and the distance it moves in a given
the results derived in the preceding axioms, and these results can in turn time (Ax. 1 13, via Ax. 107, 111). But if the same force acts on two bodies
ultimately be derived from a small number of basic assumptions regarded a, b, with a = 36, then the velocity generated in b is triple that generated
as self-evident by Newton. Ax. 100-18 therefore amount to an attempted in a (Ax. 1 16, via Ax. 108). And generally for equal forces as « is to 6 as
proof of the necessity of the result given as an axiom in Ax.-Prop. 23. In the velocity generated in b to the velocity generated in a (Ax. 117). Hence
addition, and quite independently, though in the same spirit, the the motion generated in any two bodies is proportional to the forces
principle of inertia enunciated previously at Ax.-Prop. i, 2, is derived acting on them. Likewise if motion is destroyed in both or generated in
from a certain more general philosophical principle at the beginning of one and destroyed in the other (Ax. 118, via Ax. 108, 113, 117).
Ax. 100. The total structure of the argument leading up to the demonstration
As an aid towards comprehension an outline of the argument cul­ of Ax. 1 18 is exhibited in the following chart. Only general results have
minating in the proof of Ax. 118 will now be given. At Ax. lo i, itself been included.
a revised draft of that part of Ax. 100 following the discussion of the
principle of inertia, Newton ‘proves’ that the ‘hindrance impediment, Text
resistance or opposition’ required to destroy the velocity of a given
Ax: 100. Every thing doth naturally persevere in that state in which it
body is double that required for an ‘equivelox’ (= equally fast) body of
is unlesse it bee interrupted by some externall cause, hence axiome ist
half the size. Or generally, that the resistance or hindrance required to
destroy a body’s velocity is proportional to its size (Ax. 102). Likewise and 2^ and [2?] A body once moved will alw^ays keepe the same
for the generation of velocity, the ‘power or efficacy vigor strength or celerity, quantity and determination of its motion.
virtue of the cause’ required to generate new velocity is proportional to IT two equall bodies {bepq and r) [Fig. i] meete one another wdth
the body acted on (Ax. 103). A particular type of hindrance to the motion equall celerity (unlesse they could pass through one the other by
of one body is provided by the motion of another, and two equal, equivelox penetration of dimensions) they must mutually hinder their perseverance
bodies offer equal and opposite hindrances to each other (Ax. 105). In in their states and (since the one hath noe advantage over the other they
154 DYNAAIICAL W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 155
must equally hinder the one the others perseverance in its State having which can onely deprive cbqp of its whole velocity and motion by hinder­
both of them an equall power to persever in their state, likewise if ing its perseverance in its state, can also only deprive aocb of its whole
the body aocb be = and equivelox with r they meeting would equally velocity and motion, for that cause hath the same advantage over both
the bodys. Now if I add the opposition {a) which can onely deprive
cbpq of its motion to the opposition {b) which can onely deprive aobc of
its motion the whole opposition {a^b = 2a = 2b) can onely deprive
both the bodys aobc~\-cbqp of their motion when they are joyned into
one {aopq) for a : cbpq : \ b : aobc : : a-\-b : cbqp-\-aobc : : 2a : aopq. Also
neither the opposition a nor b alone can deprive aopq of its motion for
then the parte*^ {a or b) would be equall to the whole {a-\ b — 2a — 2b).

///

Figure i.

By the same reason aopq and cbqp loosing equall velocity the impediment
of aopq must be double to the opposition of cbqp.
1 0 2 . Since^ because aopq [Fig. i] is double to cbqp and both of them
equivelox therefore the opposition which can deprive aopq of its motion
must be double to that which can deprive cbpq of its motion; by the same
reason^ it will follow that in equivelox bodys as one body {a) is to
another [b) soe must the resistance which can deprive that body (a) of
hinder or oppose the one the others progression or perseverance in
its velocity/motion bee to the resistance which can deprive {b) of its
their states and therefore the power of the body aopq (when tis equivelox
whole velocity/motion so is the resistance which can deprive («) of some
with r) is double to the power that r hath to persever in its state,
parte of its velocity, to the resistance which can deprive {b) of the same
that is the efficacy force or power of the cause which can reduce aopq
quantity of velocity, soe that a and b bee still equivelox.
to rest must bee double to the power and efficacy of the cause which
°Now it may be perceived how and why amongst bodys moved some
can reduce r to rest, or the power which can move the one must be
require a greater some a lesse opposition to deprive them of theire whole
double to the power which can move the other soe that they bee made
velocity or of some parte of it.*'
equivelox.'
Hence in equivelox bodies the powers of persevering in their states^ 103. By the same reason alsoe If two bodys rest or bee equivelox: then
are proportionall to their quantitys. as the body {a) is to the body {h) so must the power or efficacy vigor
Hence may bee perceived what is meant strength or virtue of the cause which begets new velocity in (a) bee to
the power virtue or efficacy of the cause which begets the same quantit\-
lo i. Supposing the bodies aobc and cbqp [Fig. i] to be equall and equi­
of velocity in {b), soe that a and b bee still equivelox.
velox; Then that cause hindrance impediment resistance or opposition
156 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOOK 157
104. Hence it appeares how and why amongst bodys move some require For let there be 2 other bodys a and d equivelox to them soe that a
a more potent or efficacious cause others a lesse to hinder or helpe their meeting b, and d meeting c they would equally hinder one anothers
velocity. And the power of this cause is usually called force. And as this progression then is, a = b, and c — d (ax. 105) and a { — b) \ d { = c) : :
cause useth or applieth its power or force to hinder or change the perse­ the force which can stop a (= to the force of b) to the force which can
verance of bodys in theire state, it is said to Indeavour to change their stop d (= to the force of c). [vide ax. == 102)^
perseverance. io 8.j’7 Tis knowne by the light of nature that equall forces shall effect an
105. ^ If the equall and equivelox bodys a [Fig. 2] and b meete (unlesse equall change in equall bodies. Therefore if the forces^, h, k, m be equall,
they could passe the one through the other by penetrating its dimentions) and the bodys a, b equall and rest, then let {a) bee moved by the force

a /
k b ■9
Figure 3. Figure 4.
d ct b c
g ; and b h y h ,a and b shall be equivelox: Also (since tis noe greater change
for (a) to acquire another part of motion now it hath one than for it to
Figure 2.
acquire that one when it had none)^ if {a) bee againe moved forward by
they must necessarily hinder the one the others progression, and since the force k, its velocity shall be double to the velocity of b, and if it bee
these bodys have noe advantage the one over the other the hindrance on againe moved forward by the force m its velocity shall be triple to that
both parts will be equall, likewise if the bodies d~\-a and b \-c bee equall of b, etc. Whence as the force moving (a) is to the force moving (b) soe is
and equivelox they must equally hinder one another’s progression. But the velocity acquired in (a) to the velocity acquired in (b) by that force.
the body {b) (being lesse than the body (6-fc)) and equivelox with [d-[-a) 109. By the same reason if a = b and the velocity of a be triple to the
cannot hinder the progression of the body d-\-a soe much as the body velocity of b, that force can deprive a of its velocity which is triple to the
(6+c) can; for then the power of [b) being part of the power of the body force which can deprive b of its velocity. Or in generall so is the lost
b-\-c would bee equall to the whole power of therefore that b-\-c velocity of a to the lost velocity of b as the force which deprives a of some
and d-\-a being equivelox doe equally hinder the one the others pro­ or all of its velocity, to the force which deprives b of some or all of its
gression tis required that they be equall. velocity.^
106. g Now if the bodys a and b meete one another the cause which hin- 112.6m body is saide to have more or lesse motion as it is moved with
dereth the progression of a is the power which b hath to persever in its more or lesse force, that is as there is more or lesse force required to
velocity or stated and is usually'^ called the force of the body b and as the generate or destroy its whole motion.
body b useth or applyeth this force to stop the progression of a it is said 1 13." If a body {a) [Fig. 3] move through the space ab = r in the time c,
to Indeavour to hinder the progression of a which endeavour in body and the body / [Fig. 4] through .§/ = v in the time h then, time c : time
is performed by pressure and by the same reason the body b may bee h X cib
said to endeavor to helpe the motion of a if it should apply its force to h : : line ab — r : - — = ak, and the body a would move through the
c
move it forward; soe that it is evident what the Force and indeavor in space ak in the same time {K) in which the body / moves through the
bodys are. space jg. Therefore the velocity of a is to the velocity of / as the line
107. ' If the bodys b and c be equivelox then as 6 : c : : the force with which b V nb
ak — : line fg : : h xa b : c x fg (def. 2). Then I ad the body r t o f
b is mov ed (or the power of b to persever in its velocity or [helpe ?] or
to hinder another body from persevering in its velocity) to the force of c. soe that/'+/=-:= a. Since/and rare equivelox, (ax. 107) as / : f ^ r ^ a :
158 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M IC A L W R IT IN G S IN TH E W A STE B O O K 159

am by that force. Tis axiome the 4th.^ And (by ax; 113) the bodys will have
m = force or motion of /, to -y = force o f/ + r. againe since a = /-|-r
equall motion.
(ax. i n ) as the velocity of a; to the velocity o f / + r : : h xa b : c x fg : : 1 18." If the body / be moved by the force q, and r by the force 5, (to find
n = the force or motion of a, to ~ = to the force of (t?) the celerity of / and {w) that of q). I add (f) to / , soe th a t/+ / — r,
hxab f and that (/) and (/+ /) are moved with equall force, then p-\-t ( = r)
f-[-r. Soe that n x f x c x f g = m x a x h x a b . Soe that haveing any 7 of
these the 8th may bee found, but suppose the bodys moved in equall : p : :v ; ^ t h e celerity of p-\-t (ax: 117) alsoe (ax: 108) ^ : q : :w :
times that is if c = h, then the rest of the termes may bee found by,
^ = or qrw = pvs. that is the celerity of / is to the celerity of r as qr
m x a x a b = n X fx fg etc. that is as f x fg is to a X ab soe is the motion
(m) of the body / to the motion (n) of the body a etc. VO
If the body (a and b) bee equall and the celerity of a triple to
that of b, then if the force d can deprive b of its motion the force can
deprive a of its motion. But if there bee less force {},d--p) it cannot de­
prive a of its motion for soe the parte (3<^—/) would be = to the whole
2,d; if there be more force (3<^+/>) it will doe more than deprive the body
a of its motion (i.e. move it the contrary way) otherwise the parte (3^/)
would be equall to the whole (3^^+^).'^ Therefore the force which can
deprive a of its motion must bee triple to the force which can deprive b
of its motion and consequently (def.’' 106) the force wherewith a is moved
is triple to the force wherewith b is moved is to ps. And by ax. 113 the motion of / is to the motion of r as the force
of / to the force of ^s r. And by the same reason if the motion of / and r bee
H I . By the same reason as the celerity of the body a ( = b) is to the
hindered by the force q and the motion lost in / is to the motion lost
celerity of b soe is the force wherewith a moveth to the force wherewith
in r, as q is to s. or if the motion of / be increased by the force q, but the
b moveth.
motion of r hindered by the force s] then as to ^ : : so is the increase
1 14. '! There is required soe much and noe more force to reduce a body to of motion in /, to the decrease of it in r (ax: i i i )
rest than there is to move it: et a contra. And
121.^ If 2 bodys / and r meet the one the other, the resistance in both is
1 15. Soe much force a[s] is required to generate any quantity of motion the same for soe much as / presseth upon r so much r presseth on / . ’<’
in a body, so much is required to destroy it, and e contra. For in loosing And therefore they must both suffer an equall mutation in their motion.
or to [«c] getting the same quantity of motion a body suffers the same
119. If r [Fig. 5] presse / towards zv then / presseth r towards i ’.’®Tis
quantity of mutation in its state, and in the same body equall forces will
evident without explication.
effect a equall change.
120. A body must move that way which it is pressed.*^
I i6.f If the bodys a — 36, and a and b are m o v e d w i t h the same force d
then the celerity of b is triple to the celerity of ap for 36 moved by 2>d is 122.2'’ Therefore if the body / come from c [Fig. 5] and the body r from
equivelox to b moved by dp^ but since 36 = a, therefore a moved by ^d d soe much as / ’s motion is changed towards w, so much the motion of
is equivelox to b moved by d. And (ax. 108) as the celerity of a moved r will be changed towards v. vide prop. [?]
by d to the celerity of a moved by 3 / soe is i to 3 soe is the celerity of a
a. T h e succeeding passages dozen to the beginning o f A x . 1 0 1 deleted.
moved by d to the celerity of b moved by d. b. F o l. I 2 v begins.
c. M a r g in a l entry referring to 1 0 2 , 1 0 j . W h a t force is required to beget or
I I 7. By the same reason. Any bodys / and g being moved by the same
destroy equall velo city in unequall bodys.
force, as (/) is to {g) soe is the celerity of {g) to the celerity of (/) acquired
160 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BO O K II II DYNAAdICAL W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 161
d. P reced ed B y th ey same reason that deleted. forces equal to the latter actin g sim idtaneously, the extension to a force n tim es
e -e . D eleted . another b ein g im m ediate. N o w he defines a force n tim es another as the latter
f. M a r g in a l entry. W h a t resistance in bodys. force actin g n tim es in succession. T h e result given finally is eq uivalent to that in
g. M a r g in a l entry. W h a t force In deavor and Pression is. A x .-P r o p . 5.
h. Com m encing above usu ally an d betzveen the lines occurs soe that a b o d y is 10. Im p licit here is the identification o f m otion (in the sense o f q u an tity o f
said to be m o ved w ith m ore or lesse force® w h ich m eetin g w ith another b o d y can m otion) and the fo r c e o f the body's m otion. T h is identification is also used at the
cause a greater or lesse m u tation in its state, or w h ich requireth m ore or less en d o f the su cceed in g axiom .
force® to destroy its m otion. 1 1 . N o tic e the inversion o f order at this point.
i. M a r g in a l entry. W h a t force or M o tio n is in E q u iv e lo x bodys. 12. T h e p recedin g sentence is really a parenthesis, the argum en t fo llo w in g on
j. M a r g in a l entry referring to i o 8 , l o g . W h a t v elo city acquired or lost in from the end o f the first sentence.
equall b o dys b y un equ all forces. 13. T h a t is a cted on by the sam e force.
k. S u cceed ed a fter tzvo d eleted an d largely illegible lines by the follozcing d eleted 14. T h e assertion 36 m o ved b y (the force) 3d eq u ivelo x to b m o ve d b y d im ­
passage. T h e force w h ich the b o d y (a) hath to preserve it selfe in its state shall plies that the force on b, that is d, is reproduced sim ultan eously on each o f
bee equall to the force w h ich p u t it in that s ta te ; n ot greater for the effect cannot b, b, b. T h is is his im plied definition o f an y force 3d.
exceede the [cause ?] for there can be n o th in g in the effect w h ich w as n ot in the 15. ‘ O f ’ in error for ‘ o n ’ . T h e reference to A x . 113 is e v id e n tly to the last
cause nor lesse for since the cause o n ly looseth its force aw ay b y co m m u n ica tin g equation m X a X a b = n x f x f g w h ich im plies that the force o f a b o d y ’s m otion,
it to its effect there is no reason w h y its [«c] should [not] be in the effect [w hat ?] that is its q u an tity o f m otion, or sim p ly its m otion, is proportional co n jo in tly to
is lost in the cause. H en ce appeares the tru th o f the 3"^^ and 4 “^axiom e. its b u lk and velo city.
l. F o l. 1 3 begins. 16. C o rrespo n din g to the third law o f m otion.
m . M a r g in a l entry. W h a t m otion in bo dys. 17. A ssu m in g force is m easured b y change o f m otion p roduced , as in A x . 1 18.
n. M a r g in a l entry. A generall theorem o f the p roportion o f v e lo city and 18. A c tio n and R eaction equal and opposite!
m otion o f g iv en b o d y m o vin g th rou gh g iv e n spaces in giv en tim es. 19. C o rrespo n d in g to that part o f the second law o f m otion w h ich states that
o. M a r g in a l entry referring to n o , i n . W h a t force required to bege t or des­ the change o f m otion is in the direction o f the force acting.
tro y u n equ all celerity in equall bodys. 20. T h is and A x . 1 19, 1 2 1 sho w that N e w to n had b egu n to thin k o f the m ore
p. I n error f o r A x . general problem o f oblique collisions to w h ich the com plete solution is given in
q. M a r g in a l entry referring to 1 1 4 , i i 5. O f hin derin g and help in g m otion. M S. V.
r. M a r g in a l entry referring to 1 1 6 , 1 1 7 . W h a t celerity acquired or lost b y
equall forces in u nequall bodys.
s. S u cceed ed by a p a r tly illegible deleted passage, evid en tly the beginning o f a
fir s t attem pt a t p roving the result in question. I lf
t. In error f o r
At folio 13V immediately after Ax. 122. The fact that there are no
u. M a rg in a l entry. W h a t velo city and m otion gotten or lost b y un equall forces
in u nequall b odys. A G en erall T h e o rem . inversions of order in this set of Axioms and Propositions, whereas such
V. M a r g in a l entry. O f the m utuall force in reflected bodys. inversions occur in Ax.-Prop. 1-26 and Ax. 100-22, is perhaps an indi­
cation that the present set were original having no previous draft. Some
1. N e w to n ’s conven ien t term for ‘eq u ally s w ift’ .
confirmation for this is afforded by the comparatively large number of
2. In A x . 106 this pow er o f p ersevering in its state is term ed the ‘force o f the
body’. cancellations, and the manner in which Ax.-Prop. 27 breaks off abruptly
3. T h e extension o f the previous definition for a - - zb to the case a ^ nb w ith in the middle of a calculation. Against this is the total absence of error
n integral is im m ediate, after w h ich it can be farther extended to the case p a --- in any of the algebraic calculations, some of which are extremely heavy,
qb w here p and q are integral. though this could simply be regarded as the algebraic counterpart of the
4. N o tic e here, as at the b eg in n in g o f A x . 100, how N e w to n follow s D escartes
impressive standard of arithmetical accuracy displayed in the calculations
in id en tifyin g m o vem en t as a state rather than a process.
5. N o tic e the different m eanings o f these tv'o kinds o f fo r ce. of MS. I l l which are certainly extempore.
6. W h ere he states that for eq u ivelo x bodies a, d, a - d = force w h ich can stop Ax-Prop. 27-30 deal with the motion of the centre of motion of
a : force w h ich can stop d. two non-colliding bodies, establishing that in all cases this motion is
7. W hereas A x . 10 0 -7 dealt w ith unequal, e q u iv e lo x bodies A x . 1 0 8 -1 1 w ill rectilinear and uniform, and Ax.-Prop. 31,2 extend this result to the ease
be concerned w ith equal bodies havin g different speeds.
of two colliding bodies. The remaining propositions are concerned with
8. A v e r y plausible assum ption. B u t it w o u ld n ot be true in the Special
T h e o r y o f R elativity.
various collision problems. The last four seem to represent the orientation
9. P reviously, in .Ax. l o i , he had defined a force double another as ecjual to tw o of Newton’s thought towards the general problem of the collision of two
Hr.K^ori M
162 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE 11/^.b’ TE il O O A 163
rotating bodies to which the complete solution is given in MS. V. The
fact that these four propositions were entered separately at folio 39, in a
hand rather more mature than the last of the preceding propositions, is
probably an indication that they were not only entered but also composed
at a somewhat later date.

Text
27.® If two bodys b and c [Fig. i] move from (0) their center of gravity
they shall have equall motion.^ For suppose h moved into the place d\

h d o e c
Figure i

bxdo
then putting, c : b :: do oe (ax. 25) the body c must be then
c
moved into the place e. Alsoe c :b : :bo = oc (ax. 25) therefore
b x b o — b xd o b xb d
ec — , that is cXec bxbd. But (ax. or)
c c 26
cXec : bdx b : : the motion of c, to the motion of d, and therefore c and
d have equall motion towards o.
If b-2 the body b [Fig. 2] move through the places d, f, r and the body c
move through the places e, g, r and their center of [motion] 0, p, q, r, the
line opqr shall be a streight line. For nameing the lines be — g, cr = h,
BX
br k,bd ^ X . d e : x:ce. Then ce — ^ . Supposing be parallel to dv
d
g k -g x
parallel to ps then k : g : : k —x ; dr. b-{-c : c : : de : pe : : dv :
k
hx , ex hx
ps : : ve : es also k : h : - - = cv, and ^ ve. Therefore
k d k
cgk~cgx cekx— cdhx ex
ps and es cr— ce = er — h —
bdk^edk
cekx— cdhx dh— ex Figure 3.

bdk-\-cdk d
2 8 . If two bodys b and c [Fig. 3] move in the lines br and cr. The body c
bdhk A- edhk— bkex— cdhx moveing through the space eg in the time vs, and th[rJough^/e in the time
Or rs
bdk~\~dck nv, and through kr in the time nr. and the velocity of the body b is to the
bA-c : c : : be : CO : : a : CP
h : -A - : : bh A-ch :cp : :rs : velocity of c as if : e, and as the line eg to the line be, or as ck to br,'^ then
CO. c r : CO
^ b-i-c b+ c ^ ^ when the body c is in the place g, b will bee in e, and when c is in k, b
sp : : bdhk-\-cdhk~bkex— dhcx : cdgk— cdgx. Whence will be in r. to find the line which the center of their motion describes,
cdgkbh — edgxbh+ edgkeh— cdgxch = bdhkcg cdhkcg — kexbcg— dhexeg. viz. dfo. Then nameing the quantitys br = a, cr f, be g. e : d : :
164 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOO K 165
da ef— da
a : - — ck. kr = — ^— . If o be the center of motion‘dof the bodys at k q moves over the space qa in the time vw, and ap in the time wt. Also
suppose another body b (= q) and equivelox to {q) that is to move over
and r, then b+ c :b^ : : ^ , .^.^1 qa\ . . . vw\
e eb^-ec ■' the space bc\>= i/tt,^m thp time \ when (c) is in [g) or [k),
er] ap] wt] v/
passe through o. againe making gk = v. then d \ e \ \v ev (b) will bee in {e) or (r) and {q) in (a) or (p). Then drawing four^ streight
er. and
7

if be parallel to f i parallel to em, then a: g : -7^ := er : — em. and


d ad
r ev fev
mr, gr — gk-\-kr = —^ 4
-a d
ev-\-ef— ad fev adev4 -adef— aadd~feev^
gni — gr— mr = —— ------ ■'— = ------ '---- A______ ,
e ad ade
S in ce/is the center of motion in the bodys at ^and e ’tis b~fc : c : ; ge ;
gev egev
jg. b \ c : c :: eg : fg : : em = = f i : : gm = etc :
ad abd-\~acd
cadev+ cadef— caadd— cfeev ev-\-ef— ad
gl gr = gk+kr =
bade-\-cade
ev-fef~ ad , abd—bef bev-\-cev4 -cef— cad
go = gr— or — -----^--------1---------- £ — ---- ------ — L____.
e be-\-ec eb-^ec
adbev^ cfeev abdv^cefz fec-f-abd
go—gi — 10 . CO ~ cr— or
bade-\-cade abd-\-acd eb-\-ec
C9
b-\-c \ c : \ g : — = cd. Now if the lines oi : if : : oc : cd. Then the lines qc, ag, pk if : c^ :: be : cd :: eg : fg :: rk : ok\ the points
o-)-c
d,f, and 0, shall be the centers of motion'^ of the bodys b and c, when they
line o[f\d must bea streight line: but of ; // : : adb^efe : ege : : oc : cd : :
are in the places b and c, e and g, r and k, and (prop. 28) therefore the line
; eg : :fec-\-abd : ecg. therefore the line d[f]o is a streight line, dfo is a streight line. Likewise if it bee q-\-c : c : : qc : Ic : : ag : mg \ :pk
: nk, then the points I, m, n are centers of motion to the bodys {q and c)
which which [^fc] may bee found by the two points d and o. The
being in the places (q) and (c), a and g, p and k. Then drawing the lines
demonstration is the same if the body b moved from a^ to b.
Id, mf, no (twixt the neighbouring centers of motion) since b-j-c : c^ : :
29.* If two bodys q and c [Fig. 4] be moved in divers plines, then find q^ c : c :: be : cd :: qc : Ic therefore Z qbc = ZJdc and by the same
the shortest line {pr) which can bee drawne from one line {cr) to the reason Zgfm = Agea and Z krp = Akon. Wherefore all the lines qb,
other line {qp) in which those bodys are moved, and that Xmtpr shall bee ae, pr, Id, mf, no are parallell to one another. And b-\-c \ c^ \ \ be : dc : :
perpendicular to both the lines cr and qp, viz. Aqpr — Arps = pre — qb : Id : : eg :fg : : ea {= qb) : mf : : kr : ko : : pr — {bq) : no, soe that
recto, then draw qb equall and parallell to pr and draw br = qp. Then Id = mf = no and since these line line [«r] Id, mf, no are parallell equall
shall the plaine qbrp be perpendicular to the plaine bcr. Suppose alsoe in the same plaine Idon, and stand upon the same streight line do,^ the
eg 1 vw i line [Imn) in which their other ends I, m, n are are [sic] terminated (i.e.
the body c moves over the space gk | in the time wt 1 and that the body in which are all the centers of motion'' of the bodys (c and q)) must bee
kr ] tr ] a streight line.
166 D Y N A M IC A L W R IT IN G S IN TH E W ASTE B O O K II II D Y N A M IC A L W R IT IN G S IN TH E W A STE B O O K 167

'Fhe demonstration is the same if {q) moved from {p) to {q). b


30.j’'" Suppose the bodys b and c moved towards r; [Fig. 5] so that when
(h (c
h is in { e then f is in ( and theire centers of motion describe the line dq.
[k
Then the motion of theire centers of motion shall be uniforme. For if pw
parallel to nt parallel to ey parallel to fs parallel to he pr : er : :pw : ey : :

Figure 5.

nt : fs^ \ : nq : fq. that is pr : ep (= er—pr) : : nq : fn — (fq— nq) and


therefor since the motion of the body in epr is uniforme, the motion of
theire centers of motion in the line fnq must be uniforme, that is have
allway alike velocity.
The demonstration is the same in all other cases.
28 and 3 0 . Supposing the things suppose in the 28th prop by schem
30th it may be thus done er : br :: ey : be :: fs \ dc. [Fig. 6] Also ep :
eb :: eg : gk : \ ey : yw and eg : ek : : ey : aw : : gy (= cy— eg) : kw (=
ew— ek) : : gs : kt : : sy : tw : : be : bp cs et : : de--fs : de— nt etc.
Makeing fs parallel to dc parallel to fit. and mf parallel to qn parallel to
be : bp : : dm : dq : : mf : qn. and consequently the points dfn are in one
ct, then is mf — cs and qn ~ ct. and/y = me, and nt — qc ~ is. Then be :
streight line, and since the motion of (b) is uniforme and be : bp \ : dm :
bp :: ey : cw : '.eg : ck (so is the velocity of h to the velocity of c) : : gy
dq : : df : fn, the motion of the center d is uniforme
(= ey— eg) : kw (= cw— ck) : : sy \ tw (for c^ h : :: eg : ef : : gy:
sy : :kp : np : : kw : tw) : : mf (= c y —sy) : qn {— ew— tw). Againe br : er 28 and 30"’“ Or Thus the bodys {b and c) being in b and c [Fig. 7], e and
: :hc : ey : : dc :fs ^ me (for b-\-c : : : be : dc : : eg :fg : : ey : fs) whence g, r and k, in the same times, and dn being described by their centers of
be (-= br—er) : br : : dm (= dc — mc) : de. Also br : pr : : be : pw : : dc : motion. Also making de parallel to fs parallel to ey, and m/parallel to en.
nt (-- qc). Therefore be : bp (-- br - pr) : : dm : dq (— dc qc). That is Then be :br : : ey : cr : : eg : ck (for the motions of b and c are uniform)
168 DY N A M I CA L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BOO K 169
; :g y { ^ cy~cg) : kr (= c r - c k ) : :gs : kn (for b + c : c : :g e : g f : :gy : motion of the bodys {b) and (r) when they are in the places g and e, and
g s : : k r : kn) [: :] m f (= cs — cg-\^gs) : cn ck-\-kn). Againe hr : er : : it is in the line kp . The demonstration is same in all cases.
be : e y : : dc : fs = me (for (prop.
b + e : e : : g e : g f : : ey : f s : : be : de
32.^ If the bodys {b and e) reflect at q [Fig. 9], to e and^, and the centers
25))- Therefore be : br : : dm : d e : : m f \ en, and consequently the points of their motion describe the line kdop the velocity of that center (0) after
dfn are in one streight line, also since be : br : : d f : dn the center of
reflection shall bee equall to the velocity of that center {d) before reflec­
motions motion must bee uniforme. tion. For from the center {d) draw the line a/perpendicularly to kp and

Figure 9.

A suppose the line a f to have the same celerity which (the point d ) the
Figure 8.

31.° If two bodys (h and e) meete and reflect one another at q [Fig. 8] center of motion hath before reflection, soe that when the bodys (after
their center of motion shall bee in the same line {kp) after reflection in reflection) are in e and g, the line a f may bee in hr. Also drawing ab
which it was before it. For the motion of b towards d the center of their parallel to kp parallel to fe parallel to eh parallel to rg parallel to kp. Then
motion is equall to the motion of e towards d, by prop. 2 5 . then drawing since d is the center of motion in [b) and (c), the bodys {b) and (c) have
bk J_ kp, and em _j_kp, then e d : b d : : em : bk, therefore the bodys b and e equall motion towards d, but b d : ba : ; de : f e . Therefore the bodys {b)
have equall motion towards the points k and m, that is towards the line and (c) have equall motion towards a and / that is towards the line adf.
kp. And at their reflection so much as (r) presseth fb) from the line k p ; Now when the bodys reflect, so much as the body b presseth the body e
so much [b) presseth (r) from it (ax. 121). Wherefore they must have from the line a f (or st) or towards p soe much the body e presseth the
equall motion from the line kp after reflection, that is drawing g p _]_ kp and body b from the same line, or towards k (by ax. 1 19) therefore the bodys
7 te _L kp, (e) and (g) have equall motions towards (n), (p ), then drawing
b and e have equall motion from the line af, after reflection (by ax. 121)

the line eog tis ne : n o * \ : g p \go. Therefore e z n d g have equall motion that is when [they] are at e and g they doe equally move from the points
from the point 0^^ which by prop. 25'*^ must? therefore be the center of h and then drawing eg, tis eh :e o : \rg :go. Therefore*^ the bodys doe
* In error for f’o. equally move from the point (o) which (by ax. 25) must bee their center
170 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 171
of motion, and since the motion of the line [ a f or hr) is uniforme (by from the Globe {g).~^^ Let the same be supposed of h km . Then suppose
supposition) and the point o is in the line hr, and also in k p (by prop. 31) (for distinctions sake) (^) have 8 parts of force, with which it presseth f h .
its motion must be uniforme. Then must/A presse with 8 parts of force; that is (since^ = g h or c d =
Note that by this and the 31st prop. I can find the center of motion of dn) with 4 parts on the point h, and with 4 on the point/upon the body
two bodys at any given time; and by prop. 9, or def. I can find their efk, so that e f k must presse with 4 parts of force viz. (since it presseth
distance, 17 and by prop. 25 their distance from their center of motion equally on the the [«V] points e and k ) it presseth on k with 2 parts of
that is the 2 spheres in whose perimeters they must be found; There force and with the other 2 at e on the body aem, so that aem presseth with
wants therefore onely their determination to bee knowne that their 2 parts of force, viz. with one on the point m with the other on the point
places in the sphaere bee found'^

a ; Soe that the body {hkm ) hath 7 parts of pression upon the point n, 4 at
h, 2 at k , and one at m, and since the pressure of all the points h, k , and
m is directly towards n, n will be pressed by it all, but the Globe causeth
but one part of pression upon a. Now if these bodys f h , ek, aem, be
Figure 10.
understood continually to diminish and come nearer to the line adn
untill it bee coincident with it, the pressure of the body g upon a and n
33. '^Suppose the body dcgk [Fig. 10] to be immoveable, the surface deg will still bee the same that is as i is to 7, and so is the line dn to da. By
being plaine. Also let the shaerical body am n bee moved in the perpen­ the same reason it may be generally pronounced a d : dn : : pressure of
dicular ch, so as to be reflected in c. Then since the side am hath as much the body g upon n : to the pressure of it upon a.
force to weigh or press towards {d) as the side an to press towards e by 35. Or if the bodys a and n bee [Fig. 12] supposed united by the line
reason that the center of its motion is in the line ch, the body must be {and) and another body {g) moving towards them hit perpendicularly
in equilibria neither pressed towards d nor e but reflected back in the line upon the line an 2X d\ as dn to a d so is the pressure of g upon a, to its
ch. The same may be said of any bodys whose motive center is in the pressure upon n, so is the motion in (<2) to the motion in {n) which is
perpendicular to the reflecting point. generated in them by those pressures of g , that is which they received
34. ®Take an = 2bn = e^cn — Sdn [Fig. ii] soe that a d : dn : : y : i from g , at the moment of reflection, and which they might continually
Then draw the perpendiculars eb, f c , g d , hm . And set a body (aem) upon enjoy as in fig. 6 [Fig. did not there union by the line adn [Fig. 12]
the points a and m and let {efk) stand on the points e and k which are in hinder.
the perpendiculars eb and h km , and f h on the points / and h, and lay a By the same reason if g reflect not twixt the bodys [Fig. 15a, b] then
a d : d n : : pression of { n ) towards ^ : the pression of a towards r : : motion
Globe {g) on the midst off h . Suppose also the bodys aem, e f k , f h , to have
noe pressure on one another or on the line [ajti) except what they receive of w to ^ : motion of a to r.
172 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOO K 173
Note that here a and n are taken for the centers of motion in a and n ps = and ^ A qdA -qp x qr
dt —
and adn for a line which passeth through them. n xpd qp
[36a]*^ AH" things put as before that a and n are loose, then [Fig. i6] qd
: p d : : motion of n : motion of a received from^ (pr. 34) Therefore (by Therefore dt = ^ _ ^*2 ^ ^ _[_qr. Now if in the same time
nXpdXqp qp
that the body g moved from {h) to {d) in the same time suppose that a
O- and n move to r and s, and the point d to the point t, and the body g to
d o
Figure 12.

CL n @
________________d __ 1
.s
Figure 15 h.

the point e, then must et = dh (by ax: Let the whole motion of ^
(at h towards d) be called m. the whole motion of a and and [«c] w to r
and s be called then the motion of g after reflection = m — y and tn :

m—y : ; hd : de. Or de = ^ and since et = hd,


m

zhdxm — hdxy axqrxqdxdq qrxqd


tis dt = qr.
tn nxpdx pq qp
And since the whole motion of a and n toward r and s is equall to
, axqdxqr _ pdxy
a X qr-{-n x p s a X q r A ------ ^ yZ 4 or, -v--------------- qr.
Figure 14.
^ pd axpq

prop, i i ^ y ^ n x p d : a x q d : :velocity of (a) : velocity of {n). Orsupposeing Wis d t ^ ^ d 'A m — h d x y q d x q d x .y dqxpdxy ^p d x y etc .25
that the bodys a and n move through the distances qr and p s in the same m nxpqxpq axpqxpq axpq
time then, n x p d : a x q d : : qr : p s. and producing h d to [t in) the line
Or thus
rs, since qr parallel to d t parallel t o p s , qp = ri : is p s — qr : : qd ~ rv :
36. If the bodys/globes a and n [Fig. 17] doe rest, but soe that the body
p s X q d — qr X dq {g) moving perpendicularly to qp to them and reflecting on the line qp
vt.
qp
174 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN T H E W A S T E B O O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BO O K 175
k (which is supported by but not fastened to the bodys a and n and ought
now to be conceived a line onely) doth move them by communicating
its whole motion to them which it selfe looseth, tis required what motion
a and n shall receive from g . Suppose that in so much time as g moveth
to [d ) before reflection in so much time it moveth from d to e after
reflection and in so much time the bodys a and n move the one to r the
other to s, and that then the point of reflection {d) is moved to (^)a Then
naming the given quantitys g d = b, qd = c, qp ~ e. dp = e — c = f . qr —
z the whole motion of {a) and {n) to (r) and {s) call x x , that is a X qr-\r
n X p s = xxd ^ or if : w : ; p w : zvq, (then w is the center of the bodys
motion) and if w l parallel to d t parallel to qr parallel to p s, then (Iw) is
a line described by their center of motion. Then is ( )xx =
X /w.27 Now, as the motion of a to the motion of n (prop. 34) so is [dp)
to {dq)\ Therefore (ax. 113) as the velocity of {a) to the velocity of « : :
caz
n x pd : a X qd qr ps that is fn \ ca \ ; ps. but
fn

a z ^ n X p s = xx;

caz fxx fxx


that is az -f or qr.
/ af-]-ac ae

caz cxx
and ps
fn en
fx x cxx fn xx— caxx
IS ri : is : : rv : tv. therefore,
ae fie ane
cfnxx— ccaxx
tv =
anee
efnxx— cfnxx-^ccaxx ffnxx~\-ccaxx
and td ~ qr
anee anee
Also (by ax: gd = et - b Therefore
ffnxx^ccaxx— banee
ed
anee
Now since g hath soe much motion before reflection as all three bodys
{g-fa-\~n) have after-ward, therefore (ax. T-if) gh = xx-{-gde; Or,

st
gb— xx ffnxx^ccaxx— banee
g anee
Figure 17. That is 2abeegn = aeenxx-\-gffnxx-\-ccgaxx.
zabeegn
Or, XX
aeen -^gffn -{-gcca
176 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S I N T H E W A S T E B O O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 177
zabeegn (when they are not equivelox) rs is longer than pq, the one cannot be at
Or, calling « + « — d\ then = wl.
adeen -\-gdffn -\-gccad ^ when the other is at r, but they will check the one the others motion
Soe that by this equation the point I twixt the bodys at r and ^ being soe as their centers of motion shall not describe streight lines (as {qr) or
then their center of motion may bee always found. Note that the line qr {ps)) but crooked ones (perhaps Trochoides as qmk, phi). Yet the com­
mon center of their motion w or I shall retaine both the same determina­
tion and velocity that it would did the bodys move parallell to
themselves or were they not united (by ax. Soe that if the conjoyned
bodys (fig. z'^) [Fig. 18] move to m and h in the same time that they would
have moved to r and s were they [free ?] their center of motion (/) when they

are at m and h is the same that it would be were they at r and 5 and there­
fore may be found by the former rule. viz. aeedn-\-gdffn-\-gccad : zaeegn
\ :b : w l: ; the velocity of the point I to the velocity of the body g before
reflection. Vide pag 39.
Vide'''^ pag: 15. But here observe that unlesse the reflecting line adn bee
drawn through the point (w) the center of motion in the whole body
aiwn [Fig. 19] the determination of the motion of adn will not be the
same with the determination of the motion of g before reflection (as in
the first figure) [Fig. 19] but verge from it (as in the 2^ fig) [Fig. 20] that
/ ^ is wl and gdi will not bee parallell. For since the chiefe resistance of the
I / body adn is from its center of motion (prop. 32)^^ that is from w towards
/ d, and not from i towards d, the body g will find more opposition on that
Figure i8. side towards the center w, than on the other side towards a and therefore
and ps must be described by the centers of motion of 2 bodys on divers at its reflection it must incline toward v (ax. 120) and not returne in the
sides of the point d that is ar by center of motion of the body [a) or {ad), line dg. But if the body awn presse g towards v then g presseth the body
and ps by that center of {n) or [dn). awn towards the contrary parte as from w towards I (ax. 119) and not
37. Now when a and n or ad and dn are united together (as in the 2^ fig) from w towards m, if wm parallel to gd. But if the line adn pass through
[Fig. 18] they cannot separate the one from the other, and therefore since the point w (as in fig i®‘) then-^^
178 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE WASTE BO O K II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK 179

\ 38. If the superficies ahr (fig. 3^^) [Fig. 21] circulate [about r\ all its points
\ in the line cd move with equall velocity from c towards d, ffor make
,^sfr = Tier = recto and Asrf = / ert and draw ta _L 6c then is the
motion of the point e from c to the motion of the point/from c as ae to
CY /K s f
but ae = (for Arsf similis Aret therefore — et also Aaet

er X ae erxsf
similis A er/therefore er \fr : :et :aeor, et and ae = sf)
fr fr
therefore the motion of e from c is equall to the motion of/ from c

39. If the body g reflect on the immoveable surface {dv) at its corner o
(fig 4th) [Fig, 22] its parallell motion (viz. from d to v) shall not bee
hindered by the surface dv, (viz. if the center of g'& motion w^ere distant
from the perpendicular dn an inch at one minute before reflection it shall
bee so farr distant from it at one minute after reflection), ffor dv is noe
ways opposed to motion parallel to it, and a body might slide/move upon
it without looseing any motion, and if at the first moment of contact the
body g should loose its perpendicular and only keep its parallel motion
it would (perhaps) continue to slide upon it and not reflect.^^
40. The body g reflecting on the plaine vd [Fig. 22] at its corner o all its
points in the line op vd shall move from the plaine vd with the same
velocity which before reflection they moved to it. ffor the point 0 (prop.
9) moves with that velocity backwards which it before did forwards (viz.
to vd) and all the other points (prop. 38) move with the same velocity
Figure 21. from it.
180 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II II D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W A S T E BOOK 181
a. F o l. i j v begins. 6. Probably in error for r.
b. F rom here to beginning o f A x .-P r o p . 28 deleted. 7. Error for 3.
c. M a r g in a l title T w o bodys b ein g u n iform ely m oved in the same plaine their 8. As in the previous proposition Newton writes b f c ; c in place o i b A c : a.
center o f m otion w ill describe a streight line. Once again the consistent use of the error ultimately makes no difference.
d. S u b stitu ted fo r grav ity deleted. 9. Since eg and bk are divided at /and n in the same ratio.
e. Throughout x x stands fo r x^. 10. As before these should read b y e : c and b -V c : b, respectively.
f. M a r g in a l entry T h e y doe the same in divers plaines. 11. Newton’s search for brevity and elegance finds its goal in this version.
g. F o l. 1 4 begins. 12. Rather by the generalization of Prop. 27 to the case where the centre of
h. S u b stitu ted f o r grav ity deleted. motion is not at rest.
i. S u cceed ed by their other ends (the centers o f m otion o f c and a) bun m ust 13. This does not strictly follow' from the previous assumption. One cannot
bee in the same straight line Imn, w h ich line deleted. argue from a com ponent of the relative motion to the tota l relative motion.
j. M a r g in a l title O f the v elo city o f the center o f m otion. 14. Once again a more appropriate reference would seem to be to the con­
k. T h is section deleted. verse of Prop. 27.
l. M a r g in a l entry T h e 2 8 and 30*'’ prop done otherwise. 15. The meaning seems to be this; originally, when the bodies were at b and c
m . T h is section deleted. their relative motions towards the line a f W'ere equal. This will be true at the
n. M a r g in a l entry O r thus opposite last line o f preceding section. moment of impact of the position of the line a f at that time (assuming its motion
o. M a rg in a l title T h e center o f m otion is in the same straight line before and uniform). It will likewise be true immediately after impact and will thus
after reflection. continue to be true thereafter. It must be remembered that the motions towards
p. F o l. 14 V begins. a f are relative motions.
q. M a r g in a l title T h e center o f m otion in finite bo dys hath the same v elo city 16. Once again this does not seem to follow from eh : eo \ : rg : go and motion
before and after reflection. towards h == motion towards r. He should first have added motion tow^ards
r. M a r g in a l entry T h is ou gh t to be p roved b y the 3 4 “’ and 35'^, and the 36*’’ n = motion towards p .
b y this concern in g the im presse o f {g) on (qdp). 17. Assuming the bodies to be perfectly elastic.
s. M a r g in a l entry O f the advantages o f force in divers positions to som e center. 18. Notice the reference to ‘Prop.’ 25 whereas in the previous number it is to
t. T h is section is unnum bered in the m anuscript an d is deleted. ‘Ax.’ 25.
u. F o l. 1 5 begins. 19. A similarly brilliant summing up is given in § 11 of MS. V .
V. S ucceed ed by T h e n (b y ax. 9th) et = g d and since b y reflection noe m otion 20. That is, the bodies are assumed light.
is lost or gotten g X g d - a X a r + n X w s + g X f/e. A n d (b y prop. 113 ) as the 21. Between this and diagram 12 occurs diagram 13 not specifically referring
v elo city and b y prop. 34 the m otion o f « is to a deleted. to any of the results obtained. Its relevance, however, to the general result at the
w. F o l. Jp begins. T h e zchole passage dozen to the beginning o f A x .-P r o p . 3 8 end of Prop. 34 is obvious.
deleted. 22. In error for ‘axiom’.
23. The point dividing the line joining r, s in the ratio qd : dp has a constant
1. T h e p ro o f assum es that the centre o f g ra v ity is at rest. It is true gen erally velocity equal to that of the point d of the line qp immediately after impact, et is
i f for m otion is su b stitu ted ‘ m otion relative to centre o f g r a v ity ’ . T h is general therefore the measure of the velocity of g relative to qp immediately after
result is used in A x .-P r o p . 31, 2 tho u gh N e w to n there appeals to A x .-P r o p . 25, impact.
instead o f n u m b er 27. 24. Omitting the constant time factor.
2. In this first approach to the p roblem o f the m otion o f the centre o f mass o f 25. The calculation breaks off at this point.
a pair o f bodies, to w h ich he u ltim ately in A x .-P r o p . 32 gives the m o st general 26. Omitting the constant time factor.
solution, N e w to n characteristically considers the sim plest case in w h ich the 27. Meaning { a - f n ) x l z c .
bodies o rigin ally coincide at r. 28. Since no motion is generated or destroyed by their interaction.
3. T h e calculation breaks o ff at this poin t. T h e last equation reduces to dh 29. The significance of this reference is obscure.
he. Sin ce d je = x jee, this gives x h — kce, w h ich is equivalent to bdjbr - cejer. 30. The above argument seems of doubtful validity. If the direction of
T h is last result w ill be satisfied if b oth bodies m ove un iform ly and reach r sim u l­ motion of g before impact is perpendicular to the face of the other body then the
taneously. In that case the result erjeo = rsjsp, from w h ich the final equation impulse between them on impact will likewise be perpendicular to this face, and
resulted, w ill be true and the p oin t p w ill lie on or, so that the centres o f m otion the subsequent motions of both g and zc should be parallel to the original line of
w ill be collinear. In the n ext section N e w to n e x p licitly introduces the assum p ­ motion of g.
tion o f u n iform ity o f m otion for bo th bodies. F a ilin g this the proposition does 31. Newton probably divined this result (which does not seem obvious) by
n ot hold. approximating to the actual circular arcs described b y/ and e by the lines/i and
4. S o that b reaches r as <: reaches k. et. The component of velocity of e from c w'ould then be proportional to ea.
5. T h is ratio should have read h -^ c : c and the same error occurs elsewhere in 32. For example in the case of optical reflection at glancing incidence.
the calculations. T h e final result, how'ever, is unaffected.
182 D Y N A M I C A L W R I T I N G S IN THE W ASTE BOOK II
Ilga Ill
If the body b [Fig. i] move in the line bd and from the point d two
lines da^ dc be drawne the motion of the body b from ad is to its motion THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T
from dc as ab parallel to dc is to cb parallel to ad^
Coroll 1.2 the body b receiving two divers forces from a and c and the MS. Add. 3958, folio 45, consists of a torn legal parchment on which a
force from ba is to the force from be as ba to be then draw ad parallel to lease is engrossed, the calculations appearing on the back. Attention
be and cd parallel to ab and the body b shall be moved in the line bd. was first drawn to this manuscript by the late H. W. Turnbull in a
letter of 3 October 1953 to the Manchester Guardian and some extracts
a were published by A. R. Hall [2]. The manuscript itself has been repro­
duced photographically in Isis 52, part 4 (1961), with a commentary
by Herivel [4], and at pp. 46-54 of vol. iii of the Correspondence. The
present interpretation follows closely that given in the Isis article
which appears to be substantially the same as that in vol. iii of the
Correspondence.
As first noticed by Turnbull, the original data on which the calcula­
tions are based appears to have been taken by Newton from Galileo’s
Dialogue, probably from Salusbury’s translation. ^ From the hand­
writing and other indications it seems probable that the manuscript was
Fi gure i. composed very early, most probably in 1665 or 1666.2
In this manuscript Newton calculates the ratios of the force of gravity
a. At fol. 38. to the centrifugal forces due to the diurnal and annual motions of the
1. Assuming that the motion from ad (or dc) means the component of earth. Beginning with two primitive calculations possibly preceding
motion perpendicular to ad (or be), the result given would only be true in the any clear understanding of centrifugal force, he then calculates the two
special case of ad perpendicular to dc. For a correct statement relating to resolu­ ratios making implicit use of the following result;
tion of motion (or velocity) see MS. V, § 2.
2. The statement in this so-called corollary is correct, though it cannot be a body moves in a straight line under the action of a force equal to the centri­
derived from the previous, incorrect result. It is given as an independent result fugal force for a given motion in a circle, radius R \ then in the time for motion
in MS. V, §3. in the circle through distance R, the body will move in the straight line
through distance \R.
At first, the value assumed for the rate of fall due to gravity is that
given on p. 200 of Salusbury’s translation of the Dialogue, namely 100
cubits in 5 seconds. Later, becoming dissatisfied with this result, perhaps
as the result of some crude experiment, he sets out to redetermine the
value himself experimentally, making ingenious use of the following:
(i) in a conical pendulum of semi-angle 45° the force of gravity equals
the centrifugal force; (2) the time of complete revolution of a conical
pendulum equals that for a simple pendulum of length equal to the ver­
tical depth of the conical pendulum below the point of support.
In this way he finally arrives at a value of corresponding to a fall of
196 inches in one second, about double the figure assumed originally.
184 THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T III
hence explaining the final doubling of the value originally obtained for
the diurnal and annual ratios, namely, i : 144 and i ; 3749, respectively.

C o m m e n t a r y a n d I n t e r p r e t a t io n

Newton’s arguments in this manuscript can be divided into three


groups, primitive calculations, calculations based on the correct formula
for centrifugal force, and calculations of the acceleration, due to
gravity. They will be considered separately in that order. A rough grid is
used for reference purposes. For example, the calculation 133225 : 500c
is found at (2, 4), 2 divisions down and 4 divisions across from the top
left-hand corner.

d e s c r ip t io n of c a l c u l a t i o n s

I. Primitive calculations
At (2, 3) occurs the statement:
^Terra sub Equatore movet 165000004 cubit [.yfc] in 6 horis\
Basing himself on Galileo’s law of falling bodies^ expressed for example
at (6, i), where y represents time in seconds, and x distance in braces
or cubits, and assuming with Galileo that a body falls 100 cubits in
5 seconds (i, i)h e then calculates (3, 1-2) it will fall through 165 X lo^
cubits in 2031-1 seconds. This leads to the ratio
90 X 60 X 60/2031=159-5 ( L 3-4)
and the statement (i, 5-9)
‘the force from gravity is 159-5 tiiues greater than the force from the
Earth’s motion at the equator’.
The use of 90 is puzzling. I suggest that he confused degrees with hours
when working with the quarter circumference (see diagram at (2, 4), and
so substituted 90 in place of the correct figure of 6 hours. He would
then seem to compare the magnitude of two ‘forces’ by the times taken
to move the body through a distance equal to a quarter of the earth’s
circumference. A somewhat similar comparison is made in the second
primitive calculation ^ x
i 360/23-935 = 15, (3, 3)
where 360 is now 6 hours expressed in minutes, and 23-935 (5>
time in minutes for free fall through half the distance of the quarter
circumference of the earth. ^ ' f 't \ i t'

II. Calculations based on correct formida for centrifugal force


Half-way down the left-hand side of the manuscript occur a series of
statements concerned with the centrifugal forces of the diurnal and The Vellum manuscript
Ill THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T 185
annual motions of the earth. All these are based, implicitly, on the fol­
lowing expression^ of the centrifugal force law:
A body moves in a straight line under the action of a constant force
equal to the centrifugal force for a given uniform motion in a circle,
radius R\ then in the time required for motion in the circle through
distance R, the body will move in the straight line through distance

In terms of this expression, referred to hereafter as (N), and of


Galileo’s law, referred to hereafter as (G), these statements on centri­
fugal force become clear.
First he calculates (bottom right-hand corner) that
‘The Earth in about 83677 minutes moves the length of the solar
distance’ (given immediately above as 525 X 10^ braces) (7, 1-5); then
'v is g ra v ita tis in 83677 minutes m ovebit corpus p e r distantiam
100826500737600 braces’ (G) (4, 3)-(5, 4).
'v is terrae a sole m ovebit corpus p e r distan tiam 262 5 X i o"7( = 525 X 10^/2)
braces in 83677 minutes’ (N).
'v is g ra v ita tis in 60 seconds m ovebit corpus p e r dista n tia m 14400 braces’

(G)-
'v is terrae a sole in 60 seconds m ovebit corpus p e r d ista n tia m 2625 X 10^/
7001840329 = 3749014354 (braces)’ (G) (4, 3)-(5, 3) and (5, 5).
‘so that the force of a body from the sun is to the force of its gravity
as one to 3749 or thereabouts’ (6, 3).
Immediately below follow the statements for diurnal motion. The
figure 229-09 equals the time in minutes for a point on the equator to
turn through a distance equal to the Earth’s radius

_ 24 _ ^ _ 818 hours (4, 5).


2 tt II

'v is terrae a centro m ovebit corpus in 229-09 minutes p e r distantiam


5250000 braces’ ( == 3500 miles of 3000 braces (7, i)) (N).
'v is g r a v ita tis in 229-09 . . . minutes 755747081 braces’
(G) (3, 4)-
‘So that the force of the Earth from its centre is to the force of gravity
as one to 144 or thereabouts. (755 . . . /525000 = i43'9) (4, 4)~(4> S)-
Immediately beneath this result we find
‘Or rather as i : 300 : : vis a centro terrae: vim g r a v ita t is '
and beneath this
186 t h e v e l l u m m a n u s c r i p t III Ill THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T 187
. . 1:7500 : : vis terrae a sole : vim gravitatis.^ The division by two was an afterthought which will be explained presently.
In order to understand this doubling of results we must turn to the Since the pendulum string is inclined at 45° to the horizontal the force
final group of calculations on the acceleration due to gravity. of gravity on the body will equal the centrifugal force (II), and the
above statement follows from an application of (N) to the given circular
III. Calculations of the acceleration due to gravity motion; 28-64 inches is and 0,0002. • . /2 hours should be the time
At (3, 8) we find for motion along the circumference through a distance R, namely, 1/277 X
‘Grave cadit 2| yds in i second or 10 yds in 2 seconds’ 1/1512 hours. At (3, 5) we find 44:7 : : 1/756 exactly twice the result just
and immediately beneath quoted. This explains the final division of the time by two. The calcu­
lation of the time in hours is carried out at (3, 6), and then converted
secundam Gallil. caderet 4 cubits id est 3 yds in i second’.
to minutes, seconds, and second seconds, finishing with the result
This disagreement between the two values of ‘g\ one quoted by 45-38961102, and, on division by two, 22-6958 [«c] second seconds (5, 8).
Galileo, the other possibly obtained from a rough experiment by Newton Newton next applies {g) to calculate the distance moved under
himself, may have led him to undertake the calculations now to be de­ gravity in one second. First he uses 0-756 seconds, approximates this
scribed. by I and finds the result 50-915 inches (5, 7) quoted as:
Besides the previous assumptions (G) and (N), implicit use is made of
‘A heavy thing in falling moves 50 inches in one second’ (5, 8-9).
two further assumptions, hereafter referred to as I and II respectively:
Later, realizing his initial mistake, he corrects the time to second, and
I. The time of revolution of a conical pendulum equals the period of
oscillation of a simple pendulum of length equal to the depth of the deduces beneath that the body falls 200 inches in one second. Immedi­
‘centre’ of the conical motion below the point of support. ately beneath this he states:
As Newton expresses it:^ ‘or rather 196 inches = 5 yds.’
‘Pendulum gyrans et undulans si sint aeque profunda in eodem tempore There is no trace of a recalculation of the figure 200 inches in one
redeunt.' second, and I suspect the 196 derives from the second calculation.
Newton may well have devised a mechanism for maintaining steady
II. In a conical pendulum, the ratio of the gravity of the body to the
motion in a conical pendulum with the string at a given inclination.
centrifugal force due to its circular motion equals the tangent of the angle
Otherwise he would have been familiar with the difficulty of initiating
of inclination of the string to the horizontal.
and maintaining a given motion accurately. In any case he felt the need
In particular, the only case here considered by Newton, if the string
for a second independent experiment; the corresponding calculation
is inclined at 45° to the horizontal, so that the ‘depth’ of the conical
will now be described.
pendulum equals the radius of the circle described, the force of gravity
equals the centrifugal force. Second calculation. At (6, 8) we find:
Based on I and II we find two independent calculations of g. ‘A pendulum of 6o| inches vibrates 3024 in an hour -j- 1/30.’
First calculation. At (4, 8) there is a faint drawing of a conical pendu­ The figure 3024 refers to the number of to and fro vibrations.
lum of length 81 inches. The string is inclined at 45° to the horizontal He begins to use this result at (6, 4) with 7:22: : 1033:3024, continuing
as follows from the calculation 812/2 = 57'28 (4, 9). dowm to (7, 6) but then breaks the calculation off.
This pendulum makes 1512 ‘ticks'^ in hora' (3, 8). The figure 3024 Next he states (7, 8)
immediately beneath could refer to the number of to and fro vibrations ‘a pendulum of 56-I- vibrating (.^) 1512 times in 1,005 (0 - -
of the equivalent simple pendulum.
This time the calculation is carried right through. At (3, 5-6) we find
Beneath the diagram we find
44:7 : : 1003/1512,'° the time for motion in the corresponding conical
‘gravitas movebit corpus per 28-64 inches in hours. . . .’ pendulum, revolving 1512 times in 1-005 hours, through a distance equal
188 THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T III III THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T 189
to the radius (I). This expression equals 0-000105745 hours (3, 7), and
A ppendix A
is converted to 0-380682 seconds at (4, 7). Using II and (N), he arrives
Units and distances
at the result: gravity moves a body through |(56|) —- 28] inches in
0-380682 seconds. The distance x moved through in one second is I am indebted to the late II. W. I ’urnbull for pointing out that almost
therefore given b y : all the original data for Newton’s calculations in this manuscript must
1:0-14491802376 : : X1281 (G) (4, 7-8). have come from Galileo’s Dialogue, most probably from p. 200 of
Salusbury’s translation. On the corresponding page (239) of Santillana’s
This is first calculated roughly at (6, 5) approximating to 0-579672 edition of Salusbury (Santillana[i]) we find:
by 0-58, and then more fully at (5, 6)” leading to the result x = 195 (1) value of 'g' given as 100 cubits or brace (translated yards by Salus­
(immediately under conical pendulum diagram). bury) in 5 seconds (i, 1-2);
(2) the distance of the lunar concave from the centre of the earth as
D iscussion 196,000 (Italian) miles = 56 semi-diameters of the earth, yielding a
The value for ‘g' obtained in the second calculation, corresponding to value for radius = 196,000/56 = 3500 miles ((i, i) almost indeci­
196 inches = i6|^ ft. of fall in one second, is roughly twice the value pherable) ;
(of 4 cubits = 3 yards) assumed in the calculations of centrifugal force. (3) 17,280 miles = 51,840,000 cubits yielding value 3000 cubits == i
This presumably explains the doubling of the original results. The (Italian) mile (i, 4-6).
calculations of ‘g^ would then be later than those of centrifugal force; In the second, later, manuscript IVa he takes
independent evidence for this is furnished by the manuscript itself at I mile = 1000 passus
(7, 5) where part of the abortive calculation based on the pendulum of i.e. I passus = 3 brace
length 6o| is seen to jump over the last three zeros of the solar distance. then I passus = 5 pedes (feet)
It is natural to compare the value 300 for the ratio (force of gravity/ i.e. 3 braces = 5 pedes.
centrifugal force of diurnal motion) to the value 350 given by Newton His value of in this manuscript is 16 pedes = i 6 x f brace in one
in MS. IVa. Allowing for the differing units and values for 'g' in the two second. Comparing this with the value 4 braces per second originally
manuscripts, these two ratios may be proved equivalent. used in the present manuscript, the ratio of the force of gravity to the
The significance of the ‘primitive’ calculations remains to be consi­ centrifugal force of diurnal motion should come out at
dered. Rejecting the possibility of Newton having forgotten the true
48 .
formula for centrifugal force, once found, these calculations must be dated 144 X = 345^6
20
prior to the second group. Moreover, his manner of finding the ‘force
from the Earth’s motion’ purely in terms of the uniform motion along the in exact agreement with the value i6/y og (— 350) obtained in the second
circumference (allowing for the error of 90 in place of 6), and the omis­ manuscript, IVa.
sion of any reference to the centre compared with his later use of A ppendix B
‘the force of the Earth from its centre’, makes it probable that the first
Miscellaneous calculations
primitive calculation was made before Newton had any true concept
of centrifugal force. The second primitive calculation, in which the A number of calculations remain unaccounted for; these will now be
(correct) time for the diurnal motion through the quarter circumference considered.
is compared with the time for free fall through half that distance, may I. At (i, 8-9) occur the figures
date from a period of uncertainty preceding the true concept of centri­ 21-6
fugal force, and the great discovery of ‘the force with which a globe re­ 7-54
volving within a sphere presses the surface of the sphere’. 56-
190 THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T III HI THE V E L L U M M A N U S C R I P T 191
Beneath we find a calculation equivalent to the result 1512 = i / x ^\^X56. 8. See para. 3 of MS. IVa.
9. Newton may have limed his conical pendulum by observing its passage
The pairs of figures quoted seem therefore to refer to his calculation of across the ends of a diameter. The time between successive passages would then
the number of revolutions per hour (1512) of the conical pendulum of have been equal to the time for a single ‘tick’ of the corresponding simple
length 81 inches used in the first determination of ‘g\ pendulum.
1005 I
2. At (2, 4) we find the statement: 10. Newton’s method of writing - X— .
1512 2TT
T 33225:5000 :: vis terrae a centro ad vim ejus a sole' and immediately 11. But there appears to be a small error in this calculation.
beneath 12. See Appendix A above.
13. See Portsmouth Draft Memorandum as reproduced above at Part I,
‘a centro 26,645 that a sole'
Chapter 4, p. 66.
The figure 133225 is arrived at (immediately above) as 365 X 365, while
5000 is the solar distance taking the earth’s radius as unit. This calcula­
tion must therefore have been made at a time when Newton had realized
his formula for centrifugal force was equivalent to RjT^ (a form he uses
explicitly in MS. IVa). Having thus found the ratio of the centrifugal
forces due to the diurnal and annual motion, he proceeds at (4, 5-6)
to use it as a check of his original calculation multiplying by 144 to
obtain 3836,88 in sufficient agreement with the figure 3749 (or more
accurately 3841 (6, 3) already found.
3. There remain calculations at
(4, 3-4) ^/656250oooo == 81009,2, 3600)81009,2 = 22
(4.5) 44:7:
(6.5) 23,9357:229,09
(i, 5-6) 1000000:4345
None of these play any part in the main calculations. Each of them can
be given a reasonable interpretation apart from the last.
1. See Appendix A above.
2. See above Part I, Chapter 6.2.
3. Newton himself does not use the term acceleration. It is used here for
convenience, sometimes abbreviated as ‘g'.
4. Cf. Appendix A above for the origin of the units and dimensions used by
Newton.
5. That the distance moved in a straight line under the action of gravity
varies as the square of the time. Newton extends the law to the case of a con­
stant force equal to the centrifugal force.
6. An equivalent result, corresponding to the time for a complete revolution,
is given explicitly in MS. IVa. In the present manuscript Newton is put to
considerable trouble to calculate the time for motion through a distance equal
to the radius. This would seem to indicate that the present manuscript is the
earlier one. See above Part I, Chapter 6.1.
7. For uniform speed V, the time for motion in the circle through distance
R = RjV. In this time, under acceleration V~/R, the body will move in a straight
1 j/2 R
line through distance “ (—j = .
IVa ON C I R C U L A R MOTION 193
IV throughout and gives the impression of being a final draft possibly
intended for publication.
T h e s e two papers are juxtaposed in section 5 of MS. Add. 3958. The Text
close similarity of the handwriting in both papers, and the fact that they I. Corporis A [Fig. i] in circulo A D versus D gyrantis, conatus a
are written on paper of the same size, possibly indicate that this centro tantus est quantus in tempore A D (quod pono minutissimum
juxtaposition corresponds to a close connexion between the original esse) deferret a circumferentia ad distantiam DB: siquidem earn dis-
manuscripts as regards either times of composition or drafting. This tantiam in eo tempore acquireret si modo conatu non impedito libere
possibility is reinforced by David Gregory’s statement relating to his moveret in tangente AB.
visit to Newton at Cambridge in 1694.
I saw a manuscript [written] before the year 1669 (the year when its author
Mr Newton was made Lucasian Professor of Mathematics) where all the
foundations of his philosophy are laid: namely the gravity of the Moon to the
Earth, and of the planets to the Sun. And in fact all these even then are sub­
jected to calculation. I also saw in that manuscript the principle of equal times
of a pendulum suspended between cycloids, before the publication of Huy­
gens’s Horologium Oscillatorium.
It seems probable (as suggested at fn. i of p. 301 of vol. i of the Corre­
spondence) that Gregory was here referring to the present manuscripts.

IV a

ON C I R C U L A R M O T I O N

MS. Add. 3958 (5), folios 87, 89 (left half), among the papers listed as
‘Early Papers by Newton’ in the Catalogue of the Portsmouth Collection Jam cum hie conatus corpora, si modo in directum ad modum gravi-
(Cambridge, 1888). The text of the manuscript with translation and tatis continue urgeret, impelleret per spatia quae forent ut quadrata
commentary was published first by Hall [2], and then at pp. 297-303 of temporum:^ ut noscatur per quantum spatium in tempore unius revo-
vol. i of the Correspondence. As pointed out in Hall’s paper and in the lutionis A D E A impellerent,^ quaere lineam quae sit ad B D ut est
Correspondence, this manuscript is undoubtedly the one referred to quadratum periferiae A D E A ad AIH. Scilicet est B E . B A : : B A . BD
by Newton in his letter of 20 June 1686 to Halley. For example, (per 3 elem). Vel cum inter B E ac DE ut et inter B A ac D A
the ratio 10000 to 56 referring to the ratio of the maximum distances differentia supponitur infinite parva, substituo pro se invicem et emergit
of the sun and moon from the Earth was originally written 100,000 DE .D A \ : D A .DB.-\ Faciendo denique DA'i (sive D E x D B ).
to 559^ as in the present manuscript. As noted above, it was also ADEA^
most probably the manuscript referred to by David Gregory in a ADEA^ : : D B .— >obtineo lineam quaesitam (nempe tertiam pro-
DE
memorandum referring to a visit to Newton at Cambridge in May 1694
portionalem in ratione periferiae ad diametrum) per quam conatus
(U.L. Edinburgh, Greg. C 43) reproduced at p. 331 of vol. iii of the
recedendi a centro in directum constanter applicatus propelleret corpus
Correspondence. According to this memorandum the manuscript was
in tempore unius revolutionis.^
composed before Newton’s appointment to the Lucasian Chair of
Mathematics in 1669. f Notice that in this and succeeding manuscript Newton writes D E jD A , etc., as
Apart from a small number of unimportant deletions the text is clean D E .D A in place of D E : D A as in the Waste Book.
858205 O
194 ON C I R C U L A R MOTIOxN IVa IVa ON CIRCULxVR MOTION 195
Verbi gratia cum ista tertia proportionalis aequat 19,7392 semidiame- lunae a terra 7o6|,^2 gt conatus ejus recedendi a terra ad conatum terrae
tros si conatus accedendi ad centrum^ virtute gravitatis tantus esset recedendi a sole ut 5 ad 4 circiter. Et sic vis gravitatis erit 5000'“^vicibus
quantus est conatus in aequatore recedendi a centro propter motum major conatu terrae recedendi a Sole. Sit Magni orbis |diam 100000,
terrae diurnum: in die periodico propelleret grave per 19I semidiame- terrae Jdiam. xEritque 3651x365!^; (sive 132408 ita conatus hominis
tros terrestres sive per 69087^ milliaria. Et in bora per 120'’”^*. Et in a terra, ad conatum ejus a sole.^s
minuto primo per 1/30™^^ sive per 100/3 passus, id est 500/3 pedes. Denique in Planetis primarijs cum cubi distantiarum a sole reciproce
Et in minuto se[cun]do per 5/108®^*^, sive per 5/9 digit. At revera tanta sunt ut quadrat! numeri periodorum in dato tempore conatus a sole
est vis gravitatis ut gravia deorsum pellat 16 pedes circiter in i" hoc est recedendi reciproce erunt ut quadrata distantiarum a sole. Verbi gratia
3505 vicibus longius in eodem tempore quam conatus a centro circiter, est in $, ©, ut i, 27’ , qof, sive ut i, 3I, 6f, 15I,
adeoque vis gravitatis est toties major, ut ne terra convertendo faciat 183^, 614^-, reciproce. Vel directe ut 614; 173; 91; 39; 3^; i.
corpora recedere et in aere prosilire.
3. Pendulum gyrans et undulans si sint aeque profunda in eodem
2. Coroll. Hinc in diversis circulis conatus a centris sunt ut diametri tempore redeunt.^7
applicatae ad quadrata temporum revolutionis,^ sive ut diametri ductae
4. Si pendulum gyrans et undulans sint aeque profunda, arcus vibrantis
in numerum revolutionum factarum in eodem quovis tempore. Sic cum
a perpendiculo descriptus est ut’^ chorda arcus quern gyrans descripsit
Luna revolvit in 27 diebus 7 horis et 43'7 sive in 27,3216 diebus (cujus
in eodem tempore.
quadratum est 746I) ac distat 59 vel 60 semidiametris terrestribus a
terra. Duco distantiam lunae 60 in quadratum revolutionis Imnaris i ;
ac distantiam superficiei terrestris a centro i, in quadratum revolutionum Translation
746I, et sic habeo proportionem 60 ad 746I, quae est inter conatum The endeavour from the centre of a body A revolving in a circle A D
Lunae et superficiei terrestris recedendi a centro terrae. Itaque conatus towards D is of such a magnitude that in the time [corresponding to
superficiei terrestris sub aequatore est I2-| vicibus circiter major quam movement through] A D (which I set very small) it would carry it away
conatus Lunae recedendi a centro terrae. Adeoque vis gravitatis est from the circumference to a distance DB\ since it would cover that
4000 vicibus major conatu lunae recedendi a centro terrae, et amplius.^ distance in that time if only it were to move freely along the tangent
Et si conatus ejus a terra efficit ut cum eadem facie terram semper res- without hindrance to its endeavour.
piciat;^ Hujus Lunaris et terrestris systematis conatus recedendi a sole Now since this endeavour, provided it were to act in a straight line
debet esse minor quam conatus Lunae recedendi a Terra, aliter luna in the manner of gravity, would impel bodies through distances which
respiceret solem, potius quam terram. are as the square of the times to know through what space they would
Sed ut de hac re justiorem aestimationem faciam sit 100000 distantia [be] impell[ed] in the time of a single revolution AD EA, I ask for a line
systematis Lunaris a sole, & y distantia lunae a terra. Et cum luna con- which may be to BD as the square of the circumference AD E A to the
ficit i3revoi^s]g J28'r 52' in anno stellari, sive 13,369 revolutiones (cujus square of AD. Now BE jBA ~ B A jB D (by [Book] 3 [of Euclid’s]
quadratum est 178,73): duco distantiam solis 100000 in quadratum ejus Elements). But since the difference between B E and DE, and also be­
revolutionis i, et distantiam Lunae y in quadratum ejus revolutionum tween B A and D A is supposed infinitesimally small, I substitute one for
178,73 et fit 100000 ad 178,733;, ita conatus terrae a sole ad conatum the other in each case and it follows DEjDA = DAjDB. And then by
Lunae a terra. Unde constat quod distantia lunae a Terra debet esse making DA^ (or D E x D B ) to ADEA^ as D B to ADEA^jDE I obtain the
major quam 100000/178,73 sive 559^ respectu distantiae solis 100000. required line (namely the third proportional of the circumference to the
Et inde Solis maxima parallaxis in orbita lunari non erit minor 19''*' diameter) through which its endeavour of receding from the centre w'ould
et solis horizontalis parallaxis in terra non minor 19'^^ puta cum O et impel the body in the time of a complete revolution when applied con­
}) distant 90“^’ab Apogaeis. Pone vero parallaxim esse 24" et erit distantia stantly in a straight line.-
196 ON C I R C U L A R MOTION IVa IVa ON C I R C U L A R MOTION 197
P'or example, since that third proportional equals 19.7392 semi­ is 178-73) I multiply the distance of the Sun, 100,000, by the square of
diameters, if the endeavour of approaching to the centre^ [of the Earth] its revolution, i, and the distance of the Moon [from the Earth], y, in
in virtue of gravity were exactly equal to the endeavour of receding from the square of her revolutions 178-73 and make 100000 to 178-733^ as
the centre at the equator due to the diurnal motion of the earth: then in the endeavour of the Earth [and Moon] from the sun to the endeavour
a periodic day it would impel a heavy body through 19I terrestrial semi­ of the Moon from the Earth. From which it follows that the distance of
diameters, that is through 69087"^ miles: and in an hour through 120 the Moon from the Earth ought to be greater than 100000/178-73 or
miles. And in a first minute through i/30 mile or through 100/3 paces, that 5 5 9 i compared with the distance of the Sun, 100000. And hence the
is 500/3 feet; and in a second minute through 5/108 feet or 5/9 inches. greater solar parallax in the lunar orbit will not be less than 19 minutes,
But actually the force of gravity is of such a magnitude that it moves and the Sun’s horizontal parallax not less than 19 seconds,” reckoned
heavy bodies down about 16 feet in one second, that is about 350^ times when the Sun and Moon are distant 90° from their apogees. Assume the
further in the same time than the endeavour from the centre [would parallax actually to be 24 seconds and the distance of the Moon from the
move them], and thus the force of gravity is many times greater that what Earth y o b f a n d the endeavour of the Moon to recede from the Earth
would prevent the rotation of the earth from causing bodies to recede to the endeavour of the Earth to recede from the Sun will be about 5:4.^^
from it and rise into the air. And so the force of gravity will be 5000” times greater than the endeavour
of the Earth to recede from the Sun. If the great orbit’s semidiameter be
2. Corollary: Hence the endeavours from the centres of divers circles 100000, X the Earth’s semidiameter, then the endeavour of a man from
are as the diameters divided by the squares of the periodic times,^ or as the Earth to his endeavour from the Sun will be 365^X 365|^c or 132408
the diameters multiplied by the [squares of the] numbers of revolution to unity ^5
made in any given time. So that since the Moon revolves in 27 days 7 Finally since in the primary planets the cubes of their distances from
hours and 43 minutes or in 27-3216 days^ (whose square is 746I) and is the Sun are reciprocally as the squares of the numbers of revolutions
distant 59 or 60 terrestrial semidiameters, from the Earth. I multiply the in a given time:’^the endeavours of receding from the Sun will be re­
distance of the moon 60 by the square of the Lunar revolution, i, and the ciprocally as the squares of the distances from the Sun. For example in
distance of the surface of the Earth from the centre, i , by the square of the Mercury, Venus, Earth, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn as ^7, i, 2 ^ , 27I, qof,
revolutions, 746^, and so I have the ratio 60 to 746^, which is that between or as I , 3f, 6f, 15!, 183^, 614I, reciprocally. Or directly as 614; 173;
the endeavour of the Moon and the surface of the Earth of receding from 91; 39; 3 i ; I-
the centre of the Earth. And so the endeavour of the surface of the Earth 3. If a rotating pendulum and a pendulum swinging to-and-fro are of
at the equator is about 12-|- times greater than the endeavour of the Moon the same depth they return in the same time.”
to recede from the centre of the Earth. And so the force of gravity [as at
4. If a rotating pendulum and a pendulum swinging to-and-fro are of
the surface of the Earth] is 4000 and more times greater than the en­
the same depth, the arc of swing described from the perpendicular is
deavour of the Moon to recede from the centre of the Earth.^ proportional to the chord of [twice] the arc which the rotating pendulum
And if the Moon’s endeavour from the Earth is the cause of her always describes in the same time.^^
presenting the same face to the Earth,^ the endeavour of the lunar
a. The sense seems to require im pellerentur .
and terrestrial system to recede from the Sun ought to be less than the b. Preceded by lit distantia gyrantis a loco initiali sive deleted.
endeavour of the Moon to recede from the Earth, otherwise the Moon
1. As follows from the extension of Galileo’s law for bodies falling under
would look to the Sun rather than to the Earth. gravity to the case of a body moving under the action of any constant force or
But that I may make a more exact estimate in this matter, let 100,000 conatus. The same extension has already been used in MS. III.
be the distance of the lunar system from the Sun, and y the distance of 2. Since the ratio in question equals 2tt^, approximated to by 19,7392 in the
succeeding paragraph, it follows that the distance moved by the body in a
the Moon from the Earth. And since the Moon completes 13 revolutions straight line under the action of the conatus in the time of a complete revolution
4 sig. 12 gr. 52' in a stellar year, or 13-369 revolutions (whose square equals zn^R. Ry a further application of the t^ law it follows that the distance
198 ON C I R C U L A R MOTION IVa IVb ON MOTION IN A CYCLOID 199
m o ved in the tim e for m otion along the circle th rough distance R equals ztt^R x Oscillatorhim. This would certainly have been very plausible if it were
(R I zttR-Y — R / z , the result em p loyed in M S . I I I . not for the statement by Gregory quoted above. The importance at­
3. In contrast to the endeavour o f receding from the centre due to circular tached by Newton to the possible derivation of a value for from the
m otion. N e w to n has ev id e n tly in m in d the p ossibility o f a balance betw een the
time of vibration of a cycloidal pendulum in the last paragraph of the
tw o o pp osin g tendencies.
4. N o tic e 19 -7 3 9 2 X 3 5 0 0 = 69087-2 so that the figure assum ed for the
paper is interesting. It should be read in the light of the other method of
radius o f the E arth is 3500 m iles. T h e value ultim ately derived for the ratio o f determination in MS. III.
the endeavour due to gravity to that due to the diurnal m otion proves that these The text is relatively clean and shows no sign of any major develop­
m iles are Ita lia n , so that N e w to n is taking over the figure for the radius o f the
ment.
E arth used in M S . I l l , itself taken from G a lile o ’s D ialogue (see note 5 below and
M S . I l l , A p p e n d ix A , Section 2).
5. A s show n in A p p e n d ix A to the interpretation o f M S . I l l , this result
agrees w ith that derived there on the basis o f the uncorrected figure for ‘g ’ , cor­
responding to 20/3 ft o f fall from rest in one second, the radius o f the E arth
b ein g set equal to 3500 Italian miles. See above. Part I, C h a p ter 4, p . 68, for
the bearing o f this result on the problem o f N e w to n ’s first test o f the inverse
square law o f gravitation.
6. I f the distance m o ved in the tim e, T , o f a com plete revolution is p ro po r­
tional to R , then b y the law the distance m o ved in unit tim e (the natural basis
o f com parison for different m otions) w ill be proportional to R jT ^ .
7. In M S . A d d . 3996 C . U . L . (from w h ich are taken the extracts given in
M S . I) the len gth o f the lunar m onth is given at p. 20 as alm ost 27 days 8 hours.
8. T h e large discrepancy betw een this figure and the correct figure o f about
3600 results from the erroneous figure ad opted for the radius o f the earth. T h is ,
in turn, differs som ew hat from the figure o f 60 m iles to a degree o f latitude m en ­
tioned in the accounts o f Pem berton and W h iston. See above. Part I, C h a p ter 4,
p. 68.
In Fig; prima
9. A s su ggested b y N e w to n in his letter o f 23 June 1673 to H u ygen s (see
extract at M S . V i l a below). Sit D CE [Fig. i] Trochoides ad circulum B C Y pertinens quae
10. S in 19 ' — 559J/100000. planum horizontal tangat in C insistens ei normaliter. Inque curva D C
11. A ssu m in g radius o f m o o n ’s orbit == 60 x radius o f Earth. grave descendat a D ad C dilapsum per puncta 8, P, et tt . Et agantur SYS,
12. 5 5 9 ^ X 2 4 /19 = 706-74.
13. R atio o f endeavours = 24/19 — 5/4.
PVR, ttxQ parallelae ad DE, etc.
14. A ssu m in g previous result that vis g ra vitatisjcona tu s L u n a e > 4000.
I Dico quod gravitatis efiicacia sive descendentis acceleratio in singulis
15. P resu m ab ly in error for (365J)^x 1000000 • In M S . I l l the solar distance
is taken as 50000 X radius o f Earth. descensus locis, D, S, P, etc est ut spatium describendum DC, SC, P C
16. K e p le r ’s T h ir d L a w o f Planetary M o tio n . etc. Scilicet obliquitas descensus minuit efficaciam gravitatis ita ut si
17. A result already qu oted in M S . I la , § 6, and used in M S . I I I .
gravia duo descensura sint ad C alterum B recta per diametrum BC,
18. A s su ggested in Correspondence, vol. i, p. 303, note 14, this result is true
i f for ‘the chord o f the arc’ is read ‘ the chord o f tw ice the a rc’ .
alterum oblique per chordam YC: Minor erit acceleratio gravis Y
propter obliquitatem descensus idque in ratione Y C ad B C ita ut ambo
gravia simul perveniant ad C.^ Est autem B C parallela curvae in D,^
IV b
ac Y C parallela ipsi in S,^ ideoque acceleratio gravis in D est eadem cum
ON M O T I O N IN A C Y C L O I D acceleratione gravis descendentis in B C ut et acceleratio gravis in S
eadem cum acceleratione gravis descendentis per YC.^ Quare descen­
MS. Add. 3958(5), folios 90-91V, with diagrams at fol. 89 (right half).
dentis acceleratio in D est ad accelerationem ejus in S ut B C ad YC, sive
The text of this manuscript together with a translation have already been
published in Hall and Hall [i], pp. 170-80. They consider that it may ut eorum dupla D C ad SC.
have been composed after Newton’s receipt of Huygens’s Horologium Q.E.O.
200 ON MOTION IN A CYCLOID IVb IVb ON MOTION IN A CYCL OID 201
2 Gravia^ in Trochoide descendentia, alterum a Z), alterum a quolibet 2 Quod OP et OR in directum jacent propter parallelismum rectarum
alio puncto P, simul pervenient ad C. Nam ut sunt longitudines DC, DS, BT. Adeoque omnis recta perpendicularis ad I'roch DC tanget
PC, ita accelerationes sub initio motus in Z) et P : quare spatia primo Troch AD et contra.
descripta puta Dd et P/>‘=erunt in eadem ratione.^ Unde dividendo est
3 Quod est PO — TB — DS = ^ curvae DR, adeoque zPQ sive PR =
DC. PC :: dC.pC. Quare accelerationes in delp permanent in eadem DR. Et recta P P + curva RA = toti curvae DRA = Rectae CA.
ratione, et '^etiamnum generabunU velocitates descendentium in eadem
ratione, efficientque ut gravia pergant describere spatia dh et p-n in 4 Quare si ARP sit filum datae longitudinis,^ cui pondus P appenditur ita
undulans intra trochoides AD et AE ut filum ab ipsis paululum prohi-
beatur ne in rectum protendatur, quemadmodum videre est in parte AR,
ubi se applicat ad Trochoidem: Tunc pondus P undulabit in Trochoide
DCE, adeoque quamlibet utcumque longam vel brevem undulationem
in eodem tempore perficiet.

5 Patet etiam quod undulationes in circulo FCI centre A descripto modo


sint perbreves (puta los^ hinc inde vel minus) sunt ejusdem temporis
proximo ac in Trochoide DCE.^ Nam undulatio in utroque casu fit circa
centrum A nisi quod filum paululum incurvatur in uno casu; quae
curvatura quam parva sit ex eo percipies quod R tantum supra rectam
DE esse debet imaginari quantum P cadit infra.
In Figura tertia
1 Stantibus jam ante positis cum gravis a D [Fig. 3] per P ad C descen-
F'igure 2.
dentis velocitas in loco quolibet P est uts radix altitudinis BV^ hoc est ut
eadem ratione. Adeoque spatia SC'" et ttC erunt in ilia ratione idque
linea B T pro designanda ilia velocitate exponatur^^ eadem BT.
continue donee utrumque simul in nihilum evanescat. Quare gravia
simul attingent punctum C. 2 Dein sit Pp particula spatii DC in ejusmodi particulas infinite multas et
Potuit etiam hoc inde ostendi quod posito DC. SC ; : PC. vC sit aequales divisi, et agatur par parallela ad PTV secans semicirculum in a
D 8 . P tt : : ^/BS.^'RO : : velocitas post descensum ad profunditatem et rectam TC in r. Jam propter parvitatem, curvarum portiunculae Pp ac
B S ad velocitatem post descensum ad profunditatem RO.^ Ter pro rectis haberi possunt, adeoque Pp ac Tr erunt aequales propter
parallelismum et inde t T erit datae licet infinite parvae longitudinis;
3 Itaque si grave undulet in Trochoide undulationes quaelibet erunt
ductaque semidiametro TK, triangula Tar, TKB erunt similia, siquidem
ejusdem temporis.
latera unius sunt perpendiculariter posita ad alterius latera correspon-
In ffig: seda
dentia viz To ad TK, T t ad TB et ar ad BK. Quare est BT. TK : : rT.
Super diametrum Trochoidis DE [Fig. 2] erige perpendiculum BA—
ra sive BTxTa = TKxTr. Adeoque cum TKacrT pro datis habenda
BC et a puncto A hinc inde describe duas semi-Trochoides AD, AE
sunt, erunt BT ac Ta reciproce proportionalia. Cum itaque tempus et
tangentes rectam DE in D et E, adeoque ejusdem magnitudinis cum
velocitas quibus datum spatium ut Pp describitur sunt reciproce propor­
Trochoide DCE. Jam puncto Q in BD ad arbitrium sumpto, fac arcus
tionalia, et P T pro velocitate exponitur exponi potest etiam Ta pro
BT ac DS aequales longitudini DO et comple parallelogramma BOPT ac
tempore. Atque ita si spatii Dp pars quaelibet Pp describitur in parte
DORS. Et constat.7
tempo[re] Ta, describetur totum spatium Dp in toto tempore A^a.
I Quod OP normaliter insistit Trochoidi DC in P et quod OR tangit
Trochoidem DRA in R. 3 Hinc posito quod semicircumferentia BTC designat tempus in quo
202 ON MOTION IN A CYCLOID IVb IVb ON MOT ION IN A CYCL OID 203
spatium D C percurriturp' ut noscas in quo tempore pars D P describetur sed etiam quod descendet a B ad F in tempore B T vel a i? ad C in
age P T parallelus D B et arcus B T designet tempus. tempore B C ; et contra,
4 Potest etiam tempus per angulum^CT vel per inclinationem descensus Tempora etiam descensus ab alijs curvae punctis ut P exhinc no-
Pp aut per longitudinem DO^^ designari. scuntur siquidem partes proportionales in aequalibus temporibus pera-
guntur.i2
5 Caeterum ut tempora perpendicularis descensus cum temporibus
descensus in hac curva conferantur, pone quod grave B per V ad C Sed praecipuum est quod ex dato tempore in quo pendulum datae
longitudinis vibrat, datur tempus in quo grave ad datam profunditatem
descendet.^ Nam si grave decidat a B ad C in t e m p o r e f a c BC^ .B T C ‘
: : B C .Ay, ac decidet ah A ad y in tempore BTC^^ quod est unius semi-
vibrationis. Posito a u t e r n = i,ooo, calculus dabityly 1,2337, per cujus
quadruplum 4,9348 descendet in tempore unius vibrationis, hoc est per
^AC fere, et per 19,7392 sive ig §A C fere in vibratione replicata.

Nota [i] quod motus gravis a D ad C descendentis persimilis est motui


puncti in rota uniformiter mota quod describit Trochoidem, respectu
velocitatis.

2 Quod pendulum ex argento vivo confectum diutius perseverat in motu.

Translation
In the first figure
Let D C E [Fig. i] be a trochoid belonging to the half circle B C Y and
touching the horizontal plane, to which it is normal, at C. Suppose a
heavy body descends in the curve D C from D to C falling through the
points 8, P, and tt. And draw 8 Y S, PV R , iryO parallel to D E etc.
Figure 3.
I. I affirm that the efficacy of gravity, or the acceleration of descent, in
descendit, et cum linearum B T quadrata sunt ut lineae BV: exponatur the singular points D, S, P, etc of the descent are proportional to the
B T pro designando tempore descensus ad V. Adeo ut si grave descendat spaces to be described DC, 8C, P C etc. Clearly the obliquity of the
ad C in tempore BC, descendet ad V in tempore BT. descent diminishes the efficacy of gravity so that if two weights are about
6 Jam cum descensus aeque a D ac i? sub initio sunt ad Horizontem to descend to C, the one B directly by the diameter B C , the other C
perpendiculales, manifestum est quod utrumque grave D ac B incipit obliquely by the chord YC : the acceleration of the weight Y will be less
aequaliter’*^descendere, etsi D confestim in obliquum fertur. Adeoque on account of the obliquity of the descent in the ratio Y C to B C so that
lineae per quas tempora descensuum designantur ita debent inter se both weights will arrive simultaneously at C.^ But B C is parallel to the
constitui ut initialiter exhibeant aequalia tempora descensuum aeque curve at D,^ and Y C is parallel to it at 8,^ so that the acceleration of the
altorum et postea recte exhibebunt tempora descensuum aeque altorum weight in D is equal to the acceleration of the weight descending in
ut fiunt sensim inaequalia. Et hinc patet arcum et ejus chordam B T (cum BC, and the acceleration of the weight in 8 the same as the acceleration
sint initialiter aequalia) non modo recte designare haec tempora seorsim, of the weight descending in YC.^ Therefore the acceleration of descent
sed et inter se conferre. Ita ut posito quod grave defertur a D ad C in at D is to the acceleration at S as B C to YC, or as the ratio of their
tempore BTC , non modo sequetur quod deferetur ad P in tempore BT, doubles [i.e.] D C to SC. Q.E.O.
204 ON MOTION IN A CYCLOID IVb IVb ON M O TI O N IN A CYCLOID 205
2. Weights descending in the cycloid, one from Z), the other from any centre A, provided only they are very small (for example lo-'’ or less on
other [given] point P, reach C simultaneously. For as are the distances each side) are approximately of the same duration as in the cycloid DCE.
DC, P C so are the accelerations at the beginning of the motions at D For the oscillations in both cases are about the centre A except that the
and P : therefore the spaces described to begin with, for example Dd string in one case curves slightly inwards; and how small this curvature
and Pp, will be in the same ratios [as before]. Whence by divisionPC/PC is can be seen from the fact that P is to be thought of as far above the
= dCIpc. Therefore the accelerations at d and p remain in the same ratio, line DE as P falls below it.
and so now generate velocities of descent in the same ratio, which ensure
that the weights continue to describe spaces dS and prr having the same In the third figure
ratio. And so the distances SC and ttC will be continually in the same 1. On the same assumption as before when a heavy body [falls] from P
ratio until both simultaneously dwindle to nothing. Therefore the [Fig. 3] to C via P the velocity of descent in any place whatsoever, P, is
weights reach the point C simultaneously. as the square root of the length PF,^ that is as the line BT^^\ and so BT
It can also thereby be proved that given DC/SC = PC/ ttC then DS/P tt may be used for denoting that velocity.
= V(PN)/V(PO) = velocity after descent through depth PiS is to velocity 2. Then let Pp be a small element of the space DC which is divided into
after descent through distance RQ.^ infinitely many equal elements of the same length, and let par be drawn
3. And so if a heavy body oscillates in a cycloid all oscillations whatsoever parallel to PTV cutting the semicircle in a and the straight line 7'C in t .
will occupy the same time. Then on account of their smallness the elements Pp and Ta oi the curve
can be taken as straight, and so Pp and Tr will be equal by parallels and
In the second figure
then t T will be [equal] to the given arbitrarily small length; then the
On the diameter of the cycloid DE [Fig. 2] erect a perpendicular
radius T K being drawn, the triangles Tar, T K B will be similar, so that
B C and on both sides of the point A describe the half-cycloids AD , A E
the sides of one are set perpendicularly to the corresponding sides of
touching the line D E at D and E, and of the same size as the cycloid
the other, namely, Ta to TK, Tr to TB and ar to B K . Therefore is
DCE. Having chosen the point Q anywhere in BD, make the arcs B T
B T / T K = rT/ra or P P x Ta = T K x Tr. Therefore since T K and rT
and D S equal in length to D O and complete the parallelograms B O P T
are to be taken as given, B T and Ta will be reciprocally proportional to
and DORS. We have then^
each other. Since therefore the time and velocity in which a given space
1. That Q P stands normally to the cycloid D C in P and that OR touches such as Pp are described are reciprocally proportional, and B T [from i]
the cycloid D R A in R. represents the velocity, Ta can then represent the time. And thus if any
2. That O P and OR are collinear on account of the parallelism of the part whatsoever Pp of the space Dp is described in the part of time Ta,
lines D S and B T . And so every line perpendicular [i.e. normal] to the the total space Dp will be described in the total time A^a.
cycloid D C touches the cycloid A D and conversely. 3. This being so since the semicircumference BTC represents the time
3. T h a tP P = 7’P = D S = i curve P P , and that 2PO or P P ~ P P . And in which the space DC is traversed, to know in what time the part DP
the line P P + cu rve RA = whole curve DRA = line CA. is described draw PT parallel to DB and the arc BT will represent the
4. Therefore if A R P is a string of given length,^ to which a weight P is [required] time.
attached oscillating between the cycloids A D and AE, so that the string 4. The time can also be represented by the angle BCT or by the inclina­
is just prevented from stretching in a straight line as can be seen in the tion of the descent Pp, or by the length DO.^^
part A R where it is applied to the cycloid: then the weight P will 5. Moreover that the time of the perpendicular descent may be compared
oscillate in the cycloid DCE, so that howsoever long or short the with the time of descent on the curve, assume that a body descends from
oscillation may be it will be executed in the same time. B to C via V ; then since the square of the line B T is proportional to the
5. It also appears that the oscillations in the circle P C I described about line BV, BT may be taken to represent the time of descent to V. So that
206 ON MOTION IN A CYCLOID IVh IVb ON MOTION IN A CYCLOID 207
if the body descends to C in the time BC, it descends to V in the time g. Follozved by quadra cancelled.
BT. h. Follozved by illius B V radix [?] est B T si modo diameter cancelled.
i. In error for B.
6. Now since the descents from D and B are initially both perpendicular j. Follozved by arcus B T designet tempus in quo spatium DP cancelled.
to the horizontal, it is clear that both D and B begin to descend equally, k. Follozved by in eodem tempore cancelled.
l. Followed by Nam si grave descendat a D ad C in tempore DTC — 15708,
although D is immediately forced in an oblique direction. And so the decidet ab 5 ad C in tempore BC = 10000. Et facto BC^.BTC^ : : BC . Ay
lengths representing the times of descent should be so constituted = 24674 [decidet?] ad y in tempore BTC, hoc est dum semissis undulationis
relative to one another that initially they exhibit equal times of descent peragitur, adeoque in tempore unius undulationis decidet per 4Ay sive per
spatium 98696 cancelled.
by lengths as equal one to the other, and immediately afterwards they
represent equal times of descent as becoming unequal. And this proves 1. Newton may have been familiar with the result through Galileo. It is given
in Theor. 6, Prop. 6, of the Discorsi.
that the arc B T and the corresponding chord B T (since they are initially 2. That is, the tangent to the curve at D is parallel to BC.
equal) do not only rightly represent these times separately, but also in 3. A standard property of the cycloid (-- trochoid).
the correct proportions one to the other. And so assuming that the body 4. This is true only of the tangential component of the acceleration. Newton
is translated from D to C in time B T C , it follows not only that it is throughout ignores the normal component.
5. Understood to be described in the same short interval of time.
translated to P in the time BT, but also that it descends from 5 to F in 6. Since the ratio of the accelerations of the two weights remains the same
time B T , or from B to C in time BC, and conversely. throughout the motion, the same will likewise be true of the speeds so that Speed
Moreover the times of descent from other points of the curve such as at S/Speed at tt = DCjPC. Now D CIPC^ hC/zrC, from which it follows by use
of he = zC Y ,C Y ^ = CS.CB and analogous relations that DC/PC = f(BS/RQ)
P are likewise known provided only proportional parts are covered in ~ Speed atS/Speed atvr. That the velocities of vertical descent through distances
equal times. BS, RQ are proportional to fB S , fR Q follows from Galileo’s law of falling
But especially important is the fact that given the time in which the bodies.
7. Results I to 3 follow easily from standard properties of the cycloid.
pendulum vibrates a given distance, there follows the time in which a 8. According to the preceding argument the length of the string would need
heavy body falls through a given depth. For if the heavy body falls from to be equal to that of the arc AD of the cycloid ARD.
jB to C in time B C make BC^jBTC^ = BCjA y, and it falls from A to y in 9. Compare the result quoted at the end of paragraph 2 of the 2nd section on
Fig. I .
the time BTC,^^ which is one half oscillation. Putting A C — looo calcu­
10. Since BT^ = BV.BC.
lation gives Ay 1-2337, through whose quadruple 4*9348 it descends in 11. Compare Fig. 2.
the time of one oscillation, that is through ^AC approximately, and 12. The significance of this statement is obscure.
through 19-7392 or through ig^AC approximately in a double oscilla­ 13. From Galileo’s law of falling bodies.
tion.
Note [i] that as regards velocity the motion of a heavy body falling from
Z) to C is very similar to the motion of the point of the uniformly moved
wheel which describes the cycloid.
2. That a pendulum made from quicksilver continues longer in motion.

a. In error for Y.
b. Followed by a quolibet puncto P descenclet ad C in eodem tempore ac si
descendisset a D cancelled.
c. Followed by [} quantum vis parva cogit] deleted.
d-d. Inserted in text in place of cancelled generant/o//o?a’wg descendentium.
e. Folloiced by DS, ttP et eorum residua cancelled.
f. Followed by Nam punctum R tunc baud recedit a puncto A et filum vix
omnino incurvatur cancelled.
V THE L A W S OF M O TIO N PAPER 209
Whence its velocity towards them is in such proportion as its distance
V from them that is, as AB , A C , AD , A E etc.
T H E LAIVS O F M O T I O N PAPER 3.^' If a body A [Fig. 2] move towards B with the velocity jR,^ and by
the way hath some new force done to it which had the body rested would
MS. Add. 3958 (5), folios 81-3, listed in the catalogue of the Portsmouth have propelled it towards C with the velocity S. Then making A B :A C : :
Collection (Cambridge, 1888) among ‘Early Papers by Newton’. There R : S, and completing the Parallelogram B C the body shall move in the
exists also a rough autograph draft of the same manuscript. There can Diagonall A D and arive at the point D with this compound motion in
be little doubt that this is an early manuscript written well before the the same time it would have arrived at the point B with its single motion.
Principia. For a discussion of the question of its order of composition
among the early manuscripts see above Part I, Chapter 6.1. The hand­
writing is Newton’s apart from the first lines of section i, the marginal
title of § II, and the passage headed ‘Some observations on Motion’,
which are all in the hand of Newton’s friend and one-time chamber
fellow John Wickins. For some information regarding Wickins see B
Newton Correspondence, vol. ii, p. 447, note 2. The text of the manu­
script has previously been published in full at pp. 60-64 of vol. iii of
the Correspondence and by Hall and Hall [i], and the text of §§ 5, 9, 10
together with an interpretation by Herivel [5].
D
The original is clean throughout apart from a very small number of
unimportant deletions and was possibly intended for publication.
4. ®In every body there is a certaine point, called its center of motion
Text
about which if the body bee any way circulated the endeavours of its
The Laws of Motion parts every way from the center are exactly counterpoised by opposite
How solitary bodys are moved endeavours.^ And the progressive motion of the body is the same with
Sect, i.^ There is an uniform extension space or expansion continued the motion of this its center^ which always moves in a streight line and
every way with out bounds: in which all bodys are each in severall uniformly when the body is free from occursions with other bodys.
parts of it : which parts of space possessed and adequately filled by them And so doth the common center of two b o d y s w h i c h is found by divid­
are their places. And their passing out of one place or part of space into ing the distance twixt their propper centers in reciprocal! proportion to
another, through all the intermediate space is their motion.^ Which their bulk.’^^And so the common center of 3 or more bodys etc.*^ And all
motion is done with more or lesse velocity accordingly as tis done through the lines passing through these centers of motion are axes of motion.
more or i^lesse space in equal times or through equall spaces in more or 5. ^ The angular quantity of a bodys circular motion and velocity is more
lesse time. 2But the motion it selfe and the force to persevere in that motion or lesse accordingly as the body makes one revolution in more [or] lesse
is more or lesse accordingly as the factus of the bodys bulk into its timers but the reall quantity of its circular motion is more or lesse accord­
velocity is more or lesse.^ And that force is equivalent to that motion ingly as the body hath more or lesse power and force to persevere in
which it is able to beget or destroy.*^ that motion; which motion divided by the bodys bulke is the reall
2.<^’5 The motion of a body tends one way directly and severall other ways quantity of its circular velocity. Now to know the reall quantity of a
obliqly. As if the body A [Fig. i]^ move directly towards the point B bodys circular motion and velocity about any given axis E F [Fig. 3];
it also moves obliquely towards all the lines B C , BD, B E etc. which passe suppose it hung upon the two end E and F of that axis as upon two poles:
through that point B : and shall arrive to them all at the same time. And that another globular body of the same bignesse, whose center is
858205 P
210 THE L A W S OF M O T IO N PAPER THE LAWS OF M O T IO N PAPER 211
A, is so placed that the circulating body shall hit it in the point B and 1 find such a point P from which the perpendiculars {PK, PH) let fall to
strike it away in the line B A G (which lyeth in the same plane with one of those axes bee reciprocally proportional to the angular velocitys about
the circles described about the axis EF) and thereby just loose all its owne those axes (that is P K .P H : :R:S). And drawing the line PC, it shall
motion. Then hath the Globe gotten the same quantity of progressive bee the new axis about which the compound motion is performed. And
motion and velocity which the other had of circular, its velocity being the summe of C H j C P x R and C K j C P x S when the perpendiculars
the same with that of the point C which describes a circle touching the P H and P K fall on divers sides of the axis PC, otherwise their difference,
line BG. The radius D C of which circle I may therefore call the radius of is the angular quantity of circulation about that axis; which in the angle
A C P jB C P tends contrary to the circulation about the axis ACjBC.^^

8. * Every body keepes the same reall quantity of circular motion and
velocity so long as tis not opposed by other bodys.^^ And it keeps the
same axis too if the endeavour from the axis which the two opposite
circular motion or velocity about the axis EF. And the circle described quarters twixt the Equator and every meridian of motion have, bee exactly
with the said Radius of Circulation in that plane which cuts the axis E F counterpoised by the opposite endeavours of the 2 side quarters, and
perpendicularly in the center of motion I call the Equator of circulation then also its axis doth always keepe parallel to it selfe.^® But if the said
about that axis, and those circles which passe through the poles, meri­ endeavours from the axis bee not exactly counterpoised by such oppo­
dians etc.i^ site endeavours: then for want of such counterpoise the prevalent parts
shall by little and little get further from the axis and draw nearer and
6. " A body circulates about one axis (as P C [Fig. 4]) directly and about
nearer to such a counterpoise, but shall never bee exactly counterpoised.
several other axes (as AC, BC, etc.) obliquely. And the angular quantity
And as the axis is continually moved in the body, so it continually moves
of its circulations about those axes {PC, A C, B C etc.) are as the sines
in the space too with some kind or other of spirall motion, always draw­
{PC, AD, BE, etc.) of the angles which those axes make with the Equator
ing nearer and nearer to a center or parallelisme with it selfe, but never
{EG) of the principall and direct axis (PC). *7
attaining to it. Nay tis so far from ever keeping parallel to it selfe, that
7. ^ If a body circulates about the axis A C [Fig. 5] with the angular it shall never be twice in the same position.-^
quantity of velocity R : and some new force is done to it, which, if the
body had rested, would have made it circulate about another axis BC, How Bodys are Reflected--
with the angular quantity of velocity S. Then in the plane of the two 9. J Suppose the bodys A and ot [Fig. 6] did move in the lines DA and ey.
axes, and in one of those two opposite angles (made by the axes) in which till they met in the point .6: that B C is the plane which toucheth them
the two circulations are contrary one to another (as in the angle ACB), in the point of contact B : that the velocity of the Body A towards the
212 THE L A W S OF M O TIO N PAPER V V THE L A W S OF M O TIO N PAPER 213
said plane of contact is B and the motion A B ; and that the change which Which mutations x, and v tend all of them from the plane of Contact.
is made by reflection in the velocity and motion is x and Ax. Suppose And these four rules I gather thus: The whole velocity of the two points
also that from the body A its center of motion two lines are drawne the of contact towards one another perpendicularly to the plane of contact is
one A B to the point of contact the other A C to the plane of contact; \Q (arising partly from the bodys progressive velocity 5 and ^ and partly
that the intercepted line B C is F: that the axis of motion which is per­ from their circular D and 3): And the same points are reflected one from
pendicular to the plane A B C and its equator are called the axis and another with the same quantity of such velocity. So that the whole change
equator of reflected circulation: that the radius of that equator is G : of all that their velocity which is perpendicular to the plane of contact is
that the reall quantity of velocity about that axis is D, and the motion 0 . Which change must bee distributed amongst the foure opposed velo­
citys B, /3, D and 8 proportionably to the easinesse (or smallnesse of resis­
tance) with which those velocitys are changed, that is, proportionably to
I j F (f)
A’ oc’ AG’ ay
Soe that
1+1+JL+. 0 O
I ±
A a AG ay A ^ AG ^ ay
Q = 8_ (f>Q r 1
that is F — y and — P [ - v]
AP ~ aP ^ AGP ayP
ii.i Now if any two reflecting bodys A and a, with the quantity of
their progressive and angular motions, and their position at their
meeting and consequently their point and plane of contact etc be given
to know how those bodys shall bee reflected, first find B and fl by Sec. 2.
Then the lines F and cf) and the axis of reflected circulation by Sec. 9
A D : that the change which reflection makes in that velocity and motion
and their Radij G and y by Sec. 5. Then their angular quantity of velo­
is y and A y ; And that the correspondent lines and motions of the other
city about the axes of reflected circulation by Sec. 6, and the reall quantity
body a are a^, <f), y, S, aS, v and (xv. Lastly for brevity sake suppose
D and 8 by Sec. 5. Then P and Q by Sec. 9. Then x, i, y and v by Sec. 10.
that T T F . (f)
Then the bodys new progressive determinations and velocitys by Sec.
A ^ a^ A G ^ ocy
3. Then the angular quantity of that circulation (y and 1^), which is
n Q 2DF 28(f) generated by reflection by Sec. 5. And lastly the new axes and angular
And 0.
G y quantity of velocity about them by Sec. 7.
Observing that at the time of reflection if in either body the center of
Some Observations about Motion’" ^^
motion doth move from the plane of contact, or those parts of it nearest
the point of contact doe circulate from the plane of contact: then the Only those bodys which are absolutely hard are exactly reflected accord­
said motion is to bee esteemed negative and the signe of its velocity ing to these rules. Now the bodys here amongst us (being an aggregate
B, D or 8 must bee made negative in the valor of Q. of smaller other bodyes) have a relenting softnesse and springynesse,
which makes their contact be for some time and in more points than one.
10A The velocitys B, D and 8 and they only are directly opposed and
And the touching surfaces during the time of contact doe slide one
changed in Reflection; and that according to these rules
upon another more or lesse or not at all according to their roughnesse.
Q — X ^ ^ _V and — v And few or none of these bodyes have a springynesse soe strong as to
AGP-y y^p-"- force them one from another with the same vigor that they came together.
214 THE L A W S OF M O TIO N PAPER V V THE L A W S OF M O TIO N PAPER 215
Besides, that their motions are continually impeded and slackened by For completing the square Bj3 , the body a shall move in the
dou bled . 25
the mediums in which they move. Now he that would prescribe rules Diagonall ocC, and arrive at C but at the same time it would have arrived at
for the reflections of these compound bodies, must consider in how many j8 without reflection, see the third section.
points the two bodies touch at their meeting, the position and pression 5. Motion may be gained by reflection.
of every point, with their planes of contact etc.: and how all these are For if the body a return with the same motion back again from C to a.
varyed every moment during the time of contact by the more or lesse The two bodyes A and a after reflection shall regain the same equall
relenting softnesse or springynesse of these bodies and their various motions in the lines A D and aS (though backwards) which they had at
first.

a. Marginal entry o f Place m otion, v e lo city and force.


b. At this point Newton took over from Wickins.
c. Marginal entry W ith w h at v e lo city a b o d y m oves severall w ays at once.
d. Marginal entry H o w tw o progressive m otions are jo yn e d into one.
e. Marginal entry o f centers and axes o f m otion and the m otion o f those
centers.
f. Marginal entry o f circular m otion and v e lo city about those axes.
g. Marginal entry W ith w h at v elo city a b o d y circulates about severall axes at
once.
h. Marginal entry H o w tw o circular m otions are jo y n e d into one.
i. Marginal entry In w h at cases a circulatin g b o d y perseveres in the same
state and in w h at it doth not.
j. Marginal entry Som e nam es and letters defined.
k. Marginal entry T h e R u le for Reflection.
l. Marginal entry T h e conclusion.
m . T h is section w ritten in W ick in s ’s hand.

1. T h is definition o f m otion, based on the p recedin g definition o f space and


place, corresponds to the definitions o f absolute space, tim e, place and m otion
given in D e f. 2 -4 o f the Scholium to the D efinitions o f Book I o f the Principia.
Figure 7. See M S . V I for som e indications o f the genesis o f N e w to n ’s view s on this subject.
2. A s noted p reviously ( M S . l i d , n. 20), N e w to n alm ost always w orked w ith
slidings. And also what effect the air on other mediums compressed the ratio o f one v elo city to another, rather than w ith a single velo city. B u t the
betwixt the bodies may have. definition o f m otion in the im m ed iately fo llo w in g sentence is v e ry close to a
direct one.
2. There are some cases of Reflections of bodies absolutely hard to which
3. See M S . H e, D e f. 3.
these rules extend not: As when two bodies meet with their angular 4. T h is m ethod o f m easuring force b y the corresponding m otion created or
point, or in more points than one at once; Or with their superficies. But destroyed had already been em p loyed b y N e w to n in M S . II, especially at A x .-
these cases are rare. Prop. 3 -6 , 23 o f M S . I ld .
5. T h is , and the su cceed ing section, should be com pared w ith the entries
3. In all reflections of any bodies what ever this rule is true; that the on fob 38 o f the Waste Book (see M S . H g). A proof oi the rule for co m po u n din g
common center of two or more bodies changeth not its state of motion in dependent m otions appears first in L e m m a i o f Version H I o f the tract de
or rest by the reflection of those bodies one amongst another. 24 Motu (see M S . IX c).
6. T h e s e and subsequen t diagram references are taken from the original
4. Motion may be lost by reflection. As if two equall Globes A [Fig. 7] m anuscript.
and a with equall motions from D and S done in the perpendicular lines 7. In all know n later form ulations o f the result b o th m otions are assum ed to
have been generated sim ultaneously. F o r the possible significance o f this fact see
D A and Sa, hit one another when the center of the body a is in the line DA. Part I, C h a p ter 2 .1, p p . 39-40.
Then the body A shall loose all its motion and yet the motion of a is not 8. T h e dynam ical definition o f centre o f m otion corresponds to that already
216 THE LAWS' OF M O TIO N PAPER V TH E L A W S OF M O T IO N PAPER 217
f?iven in D e f. lo o f M S . l i e . F ro m the present definition it follows easily that the
17. A s follow s im m ediately b y resolution, regarding angular v e lo city as a
centre o f m otion w ill coincide w ith the centre o f mass o f the b o d y. F o r i f the
(polar) vector.
b o d y is assum ed to be m ade up o f particles rn-i, w hose directed distances
18. T a k e directions and sense o f rotations o f R and S as in diagram 5, so that
from a given axis th rou gh the centre o f m otion are r^, rz,..., then the fa ct that
in the angle A C B the resulting m otions are opposite. A ssu m in g that the reaction
the various endeavours from the axis balance requires that ^ t-gnig a>l — o, cog
S
(if any) to the applied couple acts through C , the new total angular m om en tum
b ein g the angular v e lo city o f the p article m,, about the axis. Since cOg w ill be the w ill be equal to the vector sum o f the original angular m om en tu m p lus that due
same for all parts o f the b o d y it follow s that '^ n ig T g = o. I f Xg, y>g are the re- to the applied couple. T h e resulting rotation w ill therefore b e about the axis C P ,
S

solved parts o f r , w ith respect to an y tw o m u tu ally perpendicular axes through Ji R sin P C H == / , S sin P C K ,
the centre O in a plane p erpendicular to the axis, the above equation requires
and its m agn itude w ill be given b y
V nigXg ~ 2 ^^hy’ s - O) so that the centre o f mass o f the b o d y m u st lie on the
LgV. ly R cos P C H ! /a 6" cos P C K .
axis throu gh O . I f this is true for every axis th rough O , as required in the defini­
tion, then O m u st be at the centre o f mass o f the body. T h e results given b y N e w to n then fo llo w on the assum ption ly - h -- h .
9. See A x .-P r o p . 17, M S . I ld . O th erw ise th ey w o u ld seem to be untrue.
10. A s follow s from the principle o f inertia. 19. T h is statem ent follow s, o f course, fio m the p rinciple o f angular m o m en ­
1 1 . A s p roved b y N e w to n in A x .-P r o p . 2 7 -3 0 o f M S . I lf. tum .
12. T h e definition given in A x .-P r o p . 25 o f M S . I ld . 20. T h is corresponds, although it does n ot appear to be actually equivalent,
13. A n extension n o t given in M S . I I . T h e p ro o f is g iv en in the P r in cip ia at to the m otion of principal axes of rotation.
C oroll. 4 to L a w s o f M o tio n . 2 1. I t is to be regretted that N e w to n d id n ot provide a quantitative ju stifica­
14. A x is o f m otion b ein g defined b y im plication at the begin n in g o f the tion o f this statem ent. H is treatm ent o f the p ro blem o f the collision betw een
section. tw o rotating bodies in the present m an uscript m akes it seem en tirely possible
15. See A x .-P r o p . 19 o f M S . I ld . that such a justification w o u ld have been w e ll w ith in his powers.
16. T o elucidate the m eanin g o f the various term s in the p recedin g section, 22. T o elucidate N e w to n ’s treatm ent o f this p roblem in the tw o follow in g
let us solve the collision prob lem b y ‘m o d ern ’ m ethods. sections it is necessary to reform ulate it in m odern terms.
Let M be mass o f either body, In ad dition to the term s defined b y N e w to n in § 9 l e t ;
u> be angular v elo city o f the rotating b o d y before im pact, H, Cl' b e the (clockwise) angular v e lo city o f A before and after im pact,
I m o m en t o f inertia o f rotating b o d y about axis E F , oj, <x)' be the (anticlockwise) angular v elo city o f a before and after im pact,
V be speed in du ced in A , B ', be the velocities o f A and a respectively aw ay from the plane o f contact
r = CD, after im pact,
P = m agn itu d e o f im pulse experienced b y A . I , i be the m om ents o f inertia o f A , a respectively about the axes o f rotation
Then P = M V. th rough A , cx.
P x r ~ I c j, since the im pulse P actin g on the rotating b o d y m u st be equal T h e fo llo w in g equations then ho ld;
and o pposite to that on A , and the m o m en t o f this im pulse about E F equals the Conservation of linear momentum perpendicular to plane of contact:
en su ing dim in u tion o f the angular m om en tu m o f the rotating b o d y about
A B ~ ol^ = ol^ '-A B '. ( i )
EF.
M V ^ Iz I v P jz , assum ing (i) the rotating b o d y is brou gh t to rest, (2) that Conservatioyi o f angular momentum about B (through w h ich the force o f im pact
en ergy is conserved. T h is later assum ption im plies that the collision is elastic. m ust act) for A :
m \BAF - I Q '- B 'A F ; (2)
F ro m these equations w e deduce
sim ilarly for or. ioj—^af ~ ico' (.3)
I = Mr^, and V = rcu.
C onservation o f energy f o r elastic collision (from section ‘ Som e observations about
S o that N ezvton's 'radius o f circular motion or velocity about the axis E F ' equals our m o tio n ’ it is clear the collision is assum ed to be ela stic):
radius o f gyration k : w h ile the quantities o f circular m otion and v e lo city o f the
rotating b o d y, b y definition equal to V and M V respectively, are eq ual to roj ~ I C P j z f - A B ^ l z + ioj'^jz-roc^^lz = I C l'^ lz - fA B '^ jz ^ ia o '- lz - y a ^ '^ lz . (4)
koj, and M r o j = M k co, respectively. In other w ords, N e w to n ’s real qu a n tity o f F ro m these four equations it follows that
circular v e lo city is that o f the b o d y on its equator o f circulation, and the real
qu antity o f circular m otion, w h ich he takes, b y definition, as the m easure o f the B —C IF ^ to<l> ~ B ' C l ' F (5)
b o d y ’s p ow er to persevere in this rotation, is equal to the momentum o f a single i.e. the relative v elo city o f separation after collision equals the relative v e lo city
particle o f mass M rotating w ith the b o d y around the equator o f circulation. o f approach before, the assum ption m ade b y N ew to n . M o reover, referring to
T h is measure o f the p ow er to persevere in rotation should be contrasted w ith note 16, the value o f this relative v e lo city — l ( z B z ^ — z D F j G + z S f l y ) — Q j z
the m odern m easure o f angular m o m en tu m ; the tw o differ b y a factor k. (allow ing for an un im portant difference in sign).
218 THE L A W S OF M O TIO N PAPER
O n solvin g i, 2, 3, and 5 w e ultim ately find:

O VI
{B' + B) ( 6)
AP’

.0
E X T R A C T S FROM MS. A D D . 4003
cxP’ (7)
QF
(0^-0) (8) U .L.C. MS. Add. 4003 consists of a small book of forty pages in
IP '
Newton’s hand in Latin. The text of the manuscript together with an
(co~o)') — (9 )
introduction and translation has been published by Hall and Hall [i].
ip ’
After a short introduction there are four definitions of certain basic
where Q , P have the values given b y N ew to n .
physical concepts followed by a long philosophical discussion. Then
Sin ce I = A G ^ , i ^ ay^ the last tw o equations m ay be written
come fifteen more definitions, followed by a section entitled Propositiones
( 8)' defluido non elastico containing two propositions, five corollaries, and a
concluding Scholium. Although the presence of this section on hydrosta­
{yoj —ycxj') =1^ Q i (9)' tics may be an indication that the preceding part was originally intended
ayP
by Newton as an introduction to a projected treatise on hydrostatics,
N o tin g that B ' F B , give the changes x, ^ in the corresponding linear the true importance of the book lies elsewhere. In the first place, it
velocities, and that G O '— G i l , yco~ya>' give the changes y , v in the real quantities
contains what is to my knowledge the only known extended writing by
o f circular m otion (cf. note 16) w'e find
Newton on a purely philosophical subject ; as such it throws most inter­
O = .r,
Q C FQ fQ esting light on Newton’s standing as a philosopher. In the second place,
AP ocP AGP
y, ayP
it provides conclusive evidence both for Descartes’s influence on Newton,
as given b y N ew to n .
and for the nature of Newton’s reaction to Descartes’s philosophy. And
23. T h e first part o f this section proves how clearly N ew to n had understood
finally it throws important light on Newton’s view^s on space, time and
the conditions actu ally go vern in g collision betw een bodies in practice as opposed
to the ideal conditions assum ed in §§ 9, to. body.
24. A s p roved for the case o f tw o bodies in Prop. 32, M S . I lf. The philosophical discussion between Def. 4 and 5 may be divided
25. T h is rather surprising result follow s from the assum ptions o f conservation up as follows, (i) pp. 3-10: An attack by Newton on the definition of
o f en ergy and m o m en tu m and that the collision is such that A receives no motion in the true and absolute sense given in Part 2 of Descartes’s
m otion p erpen dicular to D B . It also seems to in dicate that N e w to n had n ot
Principia Philosophiae. (2) pp. 11-19: An exposition of Newton’s own
realized the -vectorial nature o f the law o f conservation o f m om entum .
26. A good exam ple o f the reversibility o f classical N ew ton ian dynam ics.
views on space, time and motion. (3) pp. 20-31 : A criticism of Descartes’s
identification of body and extension, and of his assertion of an absolute
dichotomy between mind and body, together with Newton’s own views
on the nature of body.
Extracts will largely be restricted to those of dynamical interest, and
those bearing on Newton’s theory of space. For a discussion of the
question of dating see above, Part I, Chapter 6.2.
Apart from a small number of unimportant deletions the text is clean
throughout.

Text
I. De^ Gravitatione et aequipondio fluidorum et solidorum in fluidis
scientiam duplici methodo tradere convenit. Quatenus ad scientias
Mathematicas pertinet, aequum esl ut a contemplatione Physica quam
220 E X T R A C T S FRO M MS. ADD. 4003 VI VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 221
maxime abstraham. Et hac itaque ratione singulas cjiis propositiones Definivi praeterea motum esse loci mutationem,'^ propterea quod
e principijs abstractis et attendenti satis notis, more Geometrarum, motus, transitio, translatio, migratio etc videntur esse voces synonymae.
stricte demonstrare statui. Deinde cum haec doctrina ad Philosophiam Sin malueris esto motus transitio vel translatio corporis de loco in locum.
naturalem quodammodo affinis esse censeatur, quatenus ad plurima ejus Caeterum in his definitionibus cum supposuerim spatium a corpore
Phaenomena enucleanda accommodatur, adeoque cum usus ejus exinde distinctum dari et motum respectu partium spatij istius, non autem
praesertim elucescat et principiorum certitudo fortasse confirmetur, respectu positionis corporum contiguorum determinaverim ne id gratis
non gravabor propositiones ex abundanti experimentis etiam illustrare S contra Cartesianos assumatur, ffigmenta ejus tollere conabor.
ita tamen ut hoc laxius disceptandi genus in Scholia dispositum, cum 2. ^ Jam vero quam confusa et ration! absona est haec doctrina’ non
priori per Lemmata, propositiones et corollaria tradito non confundatur. modo absurdae consequentiae convincunt, sed et Cartesius ipse sibi
ffundamenta ex quibus haec scientia demonstranda est sunt vel contradicendo videtur agnoscere. Dicit enim Terram caeterosque
definitiones vocum quarundam; vel axiomata et postulata a nemine non Planetas proprie et juxta sensum Philosophicum loquendo non mover!,^
concedenda. Et haec e vestigio tradam. eumque sine ratione et cum vulgo tantum loqui qui dicit ipsam mover!
propter translationem respectu fixarum (Art. 26, 27, 28, 29 part 3). Sed
postea tamen in Terra et Planetis ponit conatum^ recedendi a Sole tan­
Definitiones.
quam a centro circa quod moventur, quo per consimilem conatum Vorticis
Nomina quantitatis, durationis et spatij notiora sunt quam ut per alias gyrantis in suis a Sole distantijs librantur Art 140 part 3.3° Quid itaque?
voces definiri possint. an hie conatus a quiete Planetarum juxta Cartesium vera et Philo-
Def: 1.3 Locus est spatij pars quam res adaequate implet.'^ sophica, vel potius a motu vulgi et non Philosophico derivandus estP^'
D e f: 2. Corpus est id quod locum implet.*^ 3. *^ Ex utraque harum consequentiarum^^ patet insuper quod e motibus
Def: 3. Quies est in eodem loco permansio.
nullus prae alijs dici potest verus absolutus et proprius, sed quod omnes,
D ef: 4. Motus est loci mutatio.'^
sive respectu contiguorum corporum sive remotorum, sunt similiter
philosophici, quo nihil absurdius imaginari possumus. Nisi enim con-
Nota. Dixi corpus implere l o c u m, h o c est ita saturate ut res alias
cedatur unicum cujusque corporis motum physicum dari, caeterasque
ejusdem generis sive alia corpora penitus excludat, tanquam ens im-
respectuum et positionum inter alia corpora mutationes, esse tantum
penetrabile."^ Potuit autem locus did pars spatij cui res adaequate inest,
externas denominationes: sequetur Terram verb! gratia conari recedere
sed cum hie corpora tantum et non res penetrabiles spectantur, malui
a centro Solis propter motum respectu fixarum, et minus conari rece­
definire esse spatij partem quam res implet.
dere propter minorem motum respectu Saturni et aetherei orbis in quo
Praeterea cum corpus hie speculandum proponitur non quatenus est
vehitur, atque adhuc minus respectu Jovis et aetheris circumducti ex
substantia Physica sensibilibus qualitatibus praedita sed tantum quatenus
quo orbis ejus conflatur, et iterum minus respectu Martis ejusque orbis
est quid extensum mobile et impenetrabile; itaque non definivi pro more
aetherei, multoque minus respectu aliorum orbium aethereae materiae
philosophico, sed abstrahendo sensibiles qualitates (quas etiam Philo-
qui nullum Planetam deferentes sunt propiores orbi annuo Terrae;
sophi ni fallor abstrahere debent, et menti tanquam varios modos cogi-
respectu vero proprij orbis non omnino conari quoniam in eo non
tandi a motibus corporum excitatos tribuere) posui tantum proprietates
movetur. Qui omnes conatus et non conatus cum non possunt absolute
quae ad motum localem requiruntur. Adeo ut vice corporis Physici
competere dicendum est potius quod unicus tantum motus naturalis
possis figuras abstractas intellegere quemadmodum Geometrae con-
et absolutus Terrae competit, cujus gratia conatur recedere a Sole, et
templantur cum motum ipsis tribuunt, ut fit in prop 4 & 8, lib i Elcm
quod translationes ejus respectu corporum externorum sunt externae
Euclid .5 Et in demonstratione definitionis decimae, lib i i debet fieri;
tantum denominationes.
siquidem ea inter definitiones vitiose recensetur et potius inter proposi­
tiones demonstrari debuit, nisi forte pro axiomate habeatur. 4.35 Denique ut hujus positionis absurditas quam maxima pateat, dico
222 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 VI VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 223
quod exinde sequitur nullam esse mobilis alicujus determinatam veloci- et ad naturam substantiae magis accedit. Nihili nulla datur Idea neque
tatem nullamque definitam lineam in qua movetur. Et multo magis quod ullae sunt proprietates sed extensionis Ideam habemus omnium claris-
corporis sine impedimentis moti velocitas non dici potest uniformis, neque simam abstrahendo scilicet affectiones et proprietates corporis ut sola
linea recta in qua motus perficitur. Imo quod nullus potest esse motus maneat spatij in longum latum et profundum uniformis et non limitata
siquidem nullus potest esse sine aliqua velocitate ac determinatione. distensio.2” Et praeterea sunt ejus plures proprietates concomitantes
hanc Ideam, quas jam enumerabo non tantum ut aliquid esse sed simul
5. ^^ Quin imo sequitur motum Cartesianum non esse motum, utpote
ut quod sit ostendam.
cujus nulla est velocitas, nulla determinatio et quo nullum spatium,
distantia nulla trajicitur.'^ Necesse est itaque ut locorum determinatio 7.2’' Denique spatium est aeternae durationis et immutabilis naturae,
adeoque motus localis ad ens aliquod immobile referatur quale est sola idque quod sit aeterni et immutabilis entis effectus emanativus. Si-
extensio vel spatium quatenus ut quid a corporibus revera distinctum quando non fuerit spatium, Deus tunc nullibi adfuerit, et proinde spatium
spectator, Et hoc lubentius agnoscet Cartesianus Philosophus si modo creabat postea ubi ipse non aderat, vel quod non minus rationi absonum
advertat quod Cartesius ipse extensionis hujus quatenus a corporibus est, creabat suam ubiquitatem. Porro quamvis fortasse possumus imagi-
distinctae ideam habuit, quam voluit ab extensione corporea discrimi- nari nihil esse in spatio tamen non possumus cogitate non esse spatium;
nare vocando genericam. Art. 10, 12 et 18 part 2 Princip. Et quod quemadmodum non possumus cogitate durationem non esse, etsi possi-
vorticum gyrationes, quibus vim aetheris recedendi a centris, adeoque bile esset fingere nihil omnino durare. Et hoc per extramundana spatia
totam ejus mechanicam Philosophiam deduxit, ad extensionem hance manifestum est, quae (cum imaginamur mundum esse finitum) non
genericam tacite referuntur.'^ possumus cogitate non esse, quamvis nec a Deo nobis revelata sunt, nec
per sensus innotescunt nec a spatij s intramundanis quoad existentiam
6. *'^ De extensione jam forte expectatio est ut definiam esse vel substan-
dependent. Sed de spatijs istis credi solet quod sunt nihil. Imo veto sunt
tiam vel accidens aut omnino nihil. At neutiquam sane, nam habet
spatia. Spatium etsi sit corpore vacuum tamen non est seipso vacuum.
quendam sibi proprium existendi modum qui neque substantijs neque
Et est aliquid quod sunt spatia quamvis praeterea nihil. Quin imo
accidentibus competit. Non est substantia turn, quia non absolute per
fatendum est quod spatia non sunt magis spatia ubi mundus existit quam
se, sed tanquam Dei effectus emanativus, et omnis entis affectio quae-
ubi nullus est, nisi forte dices quod Deus cum mundum in hoc spatio
dam subsistit; turn quia non substat ejusmodi proprijs affectionibus
creabat, spatium simul creabat in seipso vel quod Deus si mundum in
quae substantiam denominant, hoc est actionibus, quales sunt cogita-
his spatijs posthac annihilaret, etiam spatia annihilaret in seipsis.
tiones in mente et motus in corpore. Nam etsi Philosophi non definiunt
Quicquid itaque est pluris realitatis in uno spatio quam in altero, illud
substantiam esse ens quod potest aliquid agere, tamen omnes hoc
corporis est et non spatij, quemadmodum clarius patebit si modo
tacite de substantijs intelligunt, quemadmodum ex eo pateat quod facile
puerile illud et ab infantia derivatum praejudicium deponatur quod
concederent extensionem esse substantiam ad instar corporis si modo
extensio inhaeret corpori tanquam accidens in subjecto sine quo revera
moveri posset et corporis actionibus frui. Et contra baud concede­
nequit existere.
rent corpus esse substantiam si nec moveri posset nec sensationem aut
perceptionem aliquam in mente qualibet excitare. Praeterea cum ex­ 8.22 Cum autem aqua minus obstat motibus trajectorum solidorum quam
tensionem tanquam sine aliquo subjecto existentem possumus dare argentum vivum et aer longe minus quam aqua, et spatia aetherea adhuc
concipere, ut cum imaginamur extramundana spatia aut loca quaelibet minus quam aerea rejiciamus praeterea vim omnem impediendi motus
corporibus vacua; et credimus existere ubicunque imaginamur nulla esse trajectorum et sane naturam corpoream penitus rejiciemus. Quem­
corpora, nec possumus credere periturum esse cum corpore si modo admodum si materia subtilis vi omni privaretur impediendi motus
Deus aliquod annihilaret, sequitur earn non per modum accidentis globulorum, non amplius crederem esse materiam subtilem sed vacuum
inhaerendo alicui subjecto existere. Et proinde non est accidens. Et disseminatum. Atque ita si spatium aereum vel aethereum ejusmodi
multo minus dicetur nihil, quippe quae magis est aliquid quam accidens esset ut Cometarum vel corporum quorumlibet projectilium motibus
224 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 VI VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 225
sine aliqua resistentia cederent crederem esse penitus inane. Nam impos- Def. 10. Gravitas est vis corpori indita ad descendendum incitans.
sibile est iit fluidum corporum non obstet motibus trajectorum, puta si Hie autem per descensum non tantum intellige motum versus centrum
non disponitur ad motum juxta cum eorum motu velocem (Part 2 Epist terrae sed et versus aliud quodvis punctum plagamve, aut etiam a puncto
96 ad Mersennum),23 quemadmodiim suppono. aliquo peractum. Quemadmodum si aetheris circa Solem gyrantis conatus
Hanc autem vim omnem a spatio posse tolli manifestum est si modo recedendi a centro ejus pro gravitate habeatur, descendere dicetur aether
spatium et corpus ab invicem differunt; et proinde tolli posse non est qui a Sole recedit.^i Et sic analogiam observando, planum dicetur
denegandum antequam probantur non differre, ne paralogismus, horizontale quod gravitatis sive conatus determination! directe oppo-
petendo principium admittatur. nitur.
Sed nequa supersit dubitatio, ex praedictis observandum venit quod Caeterum harum potestatum, nempe motus, vis, conatus, impetus,
inania spatia in rerum natura dantur. Nam si aether esset fluidum sine inertiae, pressionis, et gravitatis quantitas duplici ratione aestimatur;
poris aliquibus vacuis penitus corporeum, illud, utcunque per divisionem utpote vel secundum intensionem earum vel extensionem.
partium subtilitatum, foret aeque densum atque aliud quodvis fluidum, Def. II. Intensio potestatis alicujus praedictae est ejus qualitatis
et non minori inertia motibus trajectorum cederet, imo longe majori, gradus.
si modo projectile foret porosum; propterea quod intimos ejus poros Def. 12. Extensio ejus est spatij vel temporis quantitas in quo exer-
ingrederetur, et non modo totius externae superficiei sed et omnium cetur.
internarum partium superficiebus occurreret et impedimento esset. Def. 13. Ejusque quantitas absoluta est quae ab ejus intensione et
Sed cum aetheris e contra tarn parva est resistentia ut ad resistentiam extensione componitur. Quemadmodum si quantitas intensionis sit 2, et
argenti vivi collata videatur esse plusquam decies vel centies mille vicibus quantitas extensionis 3, due in seinvicem et habebitur quantitas absoluta
minor: sane spatij aetherei pars longe maxima pro vacuo inter aetherea 6.
corpuscula disseminate haberi debet. Quod idem praeterea ex diversa Caeterum hasce definitiones in singulis potestatibus illustrare juvabit.
gravitate horum fluidorum conjicere liceat, quam esse ut eorum den- Sic itaque motus intensior est vel remissior^^ quo spatium majus vel
sitates sive ut quantitates materiae in aequalibus spatijs contentae mon- minus in eodem tempore transigitur, qua quidem ratione corpus dici solet
strant turn gravium descensus turn undulationes pendulorum.^^ Sed his velocius vel tardius moveri. Motus vero magis vel minus extensus est
enucleandis jam non est locus, quocum corpus majus vel minus movetur, sive qui per majus vel minus
9. Def. 5. Vis est motus et quietisms causale principium. Estque vel exter- corpus diffunditur. Et motus absoluta quantitas est quae componitur ex
num26 quod in aliquod corpus impressum motum ejus vel generat vel utrisque velocitate et magnitudine corporis moti. Sic vis, conatus, im­
destruit, vel aliquo saltern modo mutat; vel est internum principium^^ petus, et inertia intensior est quae est in eodem vel aequali corpore
quo motus vel quies corpori insita conservatur, et quodlibet ens in suo major; extensior est quae est in majori corpore; et ejus quantitas abso­
statu perseverare conatur et impeditum reluctatur. luta quae ab utrisque oritur. Sic pressionis intensio est ut eadem super­
Def. 6. Conatus est vis impedita sive vis quatenus resistitur.28 ficiei quantitas magis prematur, extensio ut major superficies prematur,
Def. 7. Impetus est vis quatenus in aliud imprimitur. et absoluta quantitas quae resultat ab intensione pressionis et quantitate
Def. 8. Inertia29 est vis interna corporis ne status ejus externa vi superficiei pressae. Sic denique gravitatis intensio est ut corpus habeat
illata facile mutetur. majorem gravitatem specificam, extensio est ut corpus grave sit majus,
Def. 9. Pressio est partium contiguarum conatus ad ipsarum dimen- et absolute loquendo gravitatis quantitas est quae resultat ex gravitate
siones mutuo penetrandum. Nam si possent penetrare cessaret pressio.3° specifica et mole corporis gravitantis. Et haec quisquis non dare distin-
Estque partium contiguarum tantum, quae rursus premunt alias sibi guit, ut in plurimos errores circa scientias mechanicas incidat necesse
contiguas donee pressio in remotissimas cujuslibet corporis duri mollis est.
vel fluid! partes transferatur. Et in hac actione communicatio motus Potest insuper quantitas harum potestatum secundum durationis
mediante puncto vel superficie contactus fundatur. intervallum nonnunquam aestimari: qua quidem ratione quantitas
858205 Q
226 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 VT VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 227
absoluta erit quae ex omnibus intensione extensione ac duratione com- extended, mobile and impenetrable, I have defined it not in a philosophical
ponitur. Quemadmodum si corpus 2 velocitate 3 per tempus 4 move- manner, but in abstracting sensible qualities (which unless I am mis­
tur: totus motus erit 2X3X4, sive I2[s^c].-^^ taken philosophers ought also to abstract, and assign to the mind as vari­
Def. 14, Velocitas est motus intensio, ac tarditas remissio ejus. ous modes of thinking excited by the motion of bodies) I have posited
only properties requisite for local motion. So that instead of physical
Translation bodies you may understand abstract figures in the same way as they are
I. is proper to expound a knowledge of the heaviness and equili­ regarded by Geometers when they assign motion to them, as is done in
brium of fluids and of solids in fluids by a double method. In so far as Prop. 4 and 8 Book I of Euclid’s Elements.s And as ought to be done in
this knowledge relates to mathematical topics, it is proper that I should the demonstration of Definition 10 of Book II, since it is taken as a defini­
depart as much as possible from physical considerations. And so on tion in error and ought rather to be demonstrated among the proposi­
this account I have decided on a rigorous demonstration of particular tions, unless perhaps it should be regarded as axiomatic.
propositions of the subject from self-evident abstract principles in the Moreover I have defined motion to be change of place, because
manner of mathematicians. But then since this subject is considered to motion, transition, translation, migration etc. seem to be synonymous
be somewhat akin to Natural Philosophy, in so far as it is employed in words. If you prefer it let motion be the transition or translation of a
elucidating many of the phenomena thereof, and also that its usefulness body from place to place.
may be particularly evident and the certainty of its principles perhaps In addition, since in these definitions I shall suppose space to be given
confirmed, I shall not hesitate also to illustrate propositions by abundance apart from bodies, and motion in respect of the parts of this space, and
of experiments yet in such a way that this freer type of argument I shall not determine it in respect of the position of neighbouring bodies,
assigned to scholia may not be confused with the form expounded in lest this is taken as gratuitously contrary to the Cartesians I shall [first]
lemmas, propositions and corollaries. endeavour to dispose of his [Descartes’] imaginings.
The foundations from which this science is to be deduced are either
2. ^ Now truly not only the absurd consequences of this doctrine"^ prove
definitions of certain terms or else axioms or postulates admitted by all.
how confused and foreign to reason it is, but Descartes himself by con­
And these I set forth herewith.
tradicting himself seems to acknowledge this to be the case. For he says
Definitions. the Earth and other planets are at rest speaking truly and in the philo­
The names quantity, duration and space are too familiar to be definable sophical sense,s and that he wEo says it is moved on account of its trans­
in other terms. lation relative to the fixed stars lacks reason and speaks only in the vulgar
Def. 1.3 Place is a part of space that a thing fills evenly.**^ sense (Art. 26, 27, 28, 29, Part 3). But later he nevertheless posits in
Def: 2. Body is that which fills a place. the Earth and the planets an endeavour*^ to recede from the Sun as if
D e f: 3. Rest is continuance in the same place. from a centre about which they are moved, by means of which and the
D e f: 4. Motion is change of place.^ like endeavour of the revolving vortices they are poised at their distances
from the Sun (Art. 140 Part 3).!° What then? Is this conatus to be
Notes. I have said that a body fills a pl ace, that is so completely that
derived from the Planets’ rest, according to Descartes true and philo­
it utterly excludes other things of the same kind or other bodies, like an
sophical, or from their vulgar and non-philosophical motions?”
impenetrable thing.^ On the other hand, place could have been defined
as a part of space in which a thing exists uniformly, but since bodies only 3 . From both of these consequences'’ it appears moreover that of
and not penetrable things are here considered, I have preferred to define motions no one can be said to be true, absolute, and more proper beyond
it as a part of space which a thing fills. the others, but that all in respect of both neighbouring and remote
Moreover, since the body discussed here is put forw'ard not as a physi­ bodies are equally philosophical, than which w^e are able to imagine
cal substance endowed w'ith sensible qualities but only as something nothing more absurd. For unless a unique physical motion is allowed
228 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4 0 0 3 VI
VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 229
to any particular body, additional changes of its situation and position
means, for it has a certain mode of existence proper to itself which
among other bodies being regarded as external denominations only, it
befits neither substances nor accidents. It is not substance, then, because
will follow, for example, that the earth will have an endeavour to recede
on the one hand it does not subsist absolutely by itself, but like an effect
from the centre of the sun on account of its motion relative to the fixed
emanating from God and as a certain affection of each thing; on the other
stars, and a less endeavour on account of its lesser motion relative to
hand because it does not sustain the peculiar effects which characterise
Saturn and the aetherial orbit in which it is carried, and so much the less
substance, that is actions, such as thoughts in mind and motion in body.
again relative to Jupiter and the surrounding aether composing its orbit,
For although Philosophers do not define substance as a thing capable
and less again relative to Mars and its aetherial orbit, and much less
of some action, nevertheless they all tacitly understand this of substances,
relative to other aetherial orbits which carry no planets and are closer to
on which account, for example, it is evident that they would readily
the annual orbit of the Earth; and indeed relative to its own orbit no
admit extension to be substance in the manner of body if only it were
endeavour to recede at all since it is not moved in that orbit. And since
able to be moved and enjoy the actions of body. And conversely, they
all these endeavours and non-endeavours are incapable of absolute agree­
would scarcely admit body to be substance if it were incapable either of
ment, it must rather be affirmed that there is only one natural and absolute
being moved, or of exciting sensation or perception in some mind or
motion appropriate to the Earth thanks to which it endeavours to other. Moreover, since we can clearly conceive extension existing alone
recede from the Sun, and that its translations relative to external bodies
without any subject, as when we imagine extra-mundane spaces or cer­
are external denominations only.J*^
tain places devoid of bodies; and since we believe it to exist wherever we
4.^5 Finally that the absurdity of this position may appear most evident, imagine absence of bodies and cannot believe it to perish with a body
I say that it then follows that any moving thing has no determinate velo­ (if God were to annihilate that), it follows that it does not exist in the
city and no definite line in which it is moved. And much more that the manner of an accident inhering in a certain subject. And hence it is not
velocity of a body without impediment to its motion cannot be said to an accident. And much less can it be said to be nothing, in as much as it
be uniform, nor the line straight in which its motion takes place. Nay is more thinglike than an accident, and approaches more closely to the
rather that there can be no motion since there is none without a certain nature of a substance. There is no idea attached to nothing, but of
velocity and determination. extension we have the clearest idea of all by abstracting corporeal
5.I*’ Indeed it follows that Descartes’ motion is not motion, seeing that effects and properties, so that there remains only a stretching out
it has no velocity, no determination and that by it no space and no of place uniform and unlimited in length, breadth, and d e p t h . A n d
distance is covered. Jt fg necessary therefore that the assignment of besides there are many properties of space concomitant with this idea,
places (and thus likewise local motion) should be referred to a certain which I shall now enumerate that I may show not only that space is some­
immobile entity, such as extension or space alone in so far as it is regarded thing but what it is.
as something truly distinct from bodies. And this the Cartesian Philo­ 7.2* Then finally space is of eternal duration and immutable nature, and
sopher would more easily acknowledge if he would but notice that is thus because it is an effect emanating from an eternal and immutable
Descartes himself had the notion of such extension as distinct from being. If ever space had not been, God would then have been nowhere,
bodies, which he intentionally distinguished from bodily extension by and then he either created space later where he was not present himself,
calling it generic, Art. 10, 12, and 18 Part 2. Principia. Also that the or else, and no less absurd, he created his own ubiquity. Moreover
gyration of vortices (from which he deduced the force of aether to recede although we may perhaps imagine that there is nothing in space yet we
from the centres and thus his whole mechanical philosophy) are referred cannot think space non-existent; just as we cannot think that there is
implicitly to this generic extension. no duration [of time], even though it might be possible to imagine
that nothing at all endures. And this is made manifest by extra-mundane
6.^9 Now concerning extension it may perhaps be expected that I would
spaces, which (since we imagine the world to be finite) we cannot think
define it as either a substance or accident or nothing at all. But by no
to be non-existent, although they are neither revealed to us by God, nor
230 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 VI VI E X l ’R A C TS FROM MS. ADD. 4003 231
become known through the senses, nor depend for their existence on is on the contrary so small that compared to the resistance of quick­
intra-mundane spaces. But such spaces are usually believed to be noth­ silver it seems to be more than ten or one hundred times smaller, clearly
ing. Yet truly they are spaces. Space even if it were empty of bodies by far the greatest part of aetherial space must be regarded as emptiness
yet would not be empty of itself. And [space] is something because spread between aetherial corpusculcs. And the same may be conjectured
there are spaces although there may be nothing else besides. Again it besides from the divers heaviness of these fluids, which is as their den­
is necessary that spaces are not more space where the world is than sities or the quantities of matter contained in equal spaces, as is shown
where there is no world, unless perhaps you would say that when God both by the descent of heavy bodies and the vibration of pendulums.2+
created the world in this space he simultaneously created space itself, But this is not the place to go into these matters.
or that if God later annihilated the world in these spaces he were also to 9. Def. 5. Force is the causal principle of motion and rest,25 and is either
annihilate these spaces themselves. And so whatever is more real in one something externaF^ which, impressed in a certain body, either generates
space than in another belongs to body and not to space, as will appear or destroys its motion, or at least to some extent changes it; or it is the
more clearly provided only that puerile prejudice derived from childhood internal principle27 by which the motion or rest imprinted on the body
is given up according to which extension inheres in a body as an accident is conserved, and by which every entity endeavours to persevere in its
in a subject without which it cannot actually exist. actual state, and opposes itself to any impediment.
8.22 However, since water opposes the motion of solid projectiles less Def. 6. Conatus is an impeded force, or a force in so far as it is resisted.28
than quicksilver, and air much less than water, and aetherial spaces that Def. 7. Impetus is force in so far as it is impressed on something else.
mueh less again than air-filled ones, if we reject all force of impeding Def. 8. Inertia2^ is the internal force of a body [ensuring] that its state
the motion of projectiles we must surely also entirely reject any corpo­ is not easily changed by any external force.
real nature [in empty space]. For example, if subtle matter were deprived Def. 9. Pressure is the conatus of adjacent parts [endeavouring]
of all force of impeding the motion of globes, I would no longer believe mutually to penetrate their [respective] boundaries. For if they were able
it to be subtle matter but rather disseminated vacuum. And so if aerial or to penetrate [each other] the pressure would c e a s e . And it belongs to
aetherial space were of such a kind that it yielded without any resistance adjacent parts only, which [nevertheless] press all other adjacent parts,
to the motions of comets or bodies of any kind, then I would believe it to until the pressure is transmitted into the remotest parts of the given body
be entirely empty. For it is impossible that a corporeal fluid should not whether it be hard, soft, or fluid. And communication of motion springs
oppose the motions of projectiles, assuming (as I suppose) that it is not from this action of contact across a point or surface.
set in motion with the same speed (Part 2 Letter 96 to Mersenne).2 > Def. 10. Gravity is the intrinsic force imparted to a body inclining it
But it is evident that all this force [of opposing the motion of projectiles] to descend. By descent, however, is here to be understood not only the
can be removed only if space and body differ from each other; and then motion towards the centre of the earth, but also towards any other point
the possibility of this removal must not be denied before they are proved or region, or also [motion] away from any point. For example, if the
not to differ, lest we commit a paralogism by positing the principle in conatus of the ether revolving about the sun to recede from the centre is
question. taken as its gravity, ether receding from the sun is said to descend.31
But lest any doubt remain, from what has been said it follows that And, analogously, it is to be observed that a plane may be said to be
empty spaces exist in the natural world. For if aether were a fluid with­ horizontal because it is directly opposed to the determination of the
out any empty pores, entirely corporeal, it would, however subtilised by gravity or conatus.
division of parts, be equally dense as any other such fluid, and would yield Moreover the quantities of these powers such as motion, force, conatus,
not with less but with much more inertia to the motion of projectiles impetus, inertia, pressure and gravity may be estimated in two ways;
if these were porous; because then it would enter the intimate pores, according, namely, to their intensity or their extension.
and run against and impede not only the total external surface but also Def. II. The intensity of any of the aforementioned powers is the
all the surfaces of the internal parts. But since the resistance of aether measure of its quantity.
232 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 VI VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 233
Def. 12, Its extension is the quantity of space or time in which it 5. T h e significance o f these references is obscure.
acts. 6. A t p. 3.
7. T h e double theory o f m otion ad vanced b y D escartes in his Principia Philo­
Def. 13. And its absolute quantity is that compounded from the
sophiae, especially in A rt. 25, Part 2, and A rts. 28, 29, Part 3, o f w h ich N ew to n
intensity and extension. For example, if the intensity of the quantity be has ju s t giv en a v e ry detailed and careful account.
2, and the quantity of its extension 3, multiply one by the other and the 8. N e w to n was p ro b ab ly unaware that D escartes had argued in Le Monde
for the m otion o f the earth and the planets b u t had w ithdraw n the w o rk from
absolute quantity is given by 6.
publication on learning o f G a lile o ’s condem nation b y the In quisition. T h e fact
Further it is proper to illustrate these definitions in the case of particu­ that Le Monde was based on a single theory o f m otion w h ich resulted in the
lar powers. Thus motion is more intense or remiss^^ according as a greater m o vem en t o f the planets, whereas the Principia contained a double theory o f
m otion w h ich resulted in the planets b ein g really at rest, th o u gh th ey m o ved in
or lesser space is traversed in the same time, for which reason a body is
the v u lga r sense, has usually b een taken as an indication that D escartes d e ­
usually said to be moved faster or slower. Motion is greater or less ex­ velop ed his peculiar definition o f m otion in the true and philosophical sense in
tended in so far as the body moved is greater or smaller, that is in so far as order to escape the fate o f G alileo , W h ile this no d o u b t supp lied the original in ­
cen tive for D escartes to develop a theory o f proper m otion, insufficient attention
it is spread through a greater or a smaller body. And the absolute quantity
seems to have been directed to other possible m otives. I f one com pares Le Monde
of motion is that which is compounded from both the velocity and magni­ w ith the Principia it is clear that the form er can o n ly be regarded as a prelim inary
tude of the body moved. Force, endeavour, impetus, and inertia is more draft o f the latter, w ith its far m ore detailed developm en t o f D e sca rte s’s view s
on m atter and m otion. In particular, D escartes’s identification o f m atter w ith
intense which is greater in the same or an equal body; is more extensive
extension in evita b ly led to an en tirely undifferentiated, featureless universe
which is in a greater body; and its absolute quantity is that which unless som e further factor w as in troduced to accoun t for the separateness and
derives from both. So the intensity of pressure is more when it consists in d iv id u ality o f bodies. T h is elem ent could o n ly be supp lied b y m otion, and
of a greater pressure on the same quantity of surface, and is [more] abso lute m otion at that, since m otion in the vulgar sense was ju st as subjective
and relative as any o f the secondary qualities. T h a t this is w h at D escartes had in
extensive as it presses a greater surface, and the absolute quantity is that
m in d is m ade quite clear in the Principia itself. In A rt. 23, P art I I (C ousin
which results from the intensity of pressure and the quantity of the sur­ edition), he states '’que toutela diversite des formes qiii s'y rencontrent depend du
face pressed. And so again the intensity of gravity is greater in the body mouvement local'; in A rt. 24 he shows that m otion in the vulgar sense is subjective,

having a greater specific gravity, and its extent [is greater] in the larger that depen din g on our p oin t o f view w e can say o f a th in g‘qu'en mime temps elle se
meat et ne se meut point'. F in ally, in A rt. 25, he puts forw ard a definition o f m otion
body, and speaking absolutely the quantity of gravity is that which w h ich enables us ‘lui attribuer une nature qui soil determinee'.
results from the specific gravity and the bulk of the gravitating body. 9. T h e centrifugal conatus accom p an yin g circular m otion p layed as central a
And anyone who does not clearly distinguish these things must neces­ role in D escartes’s vortex theory (see especially A rt. 140 o f P art 3 o f Principia
Philosophiae) as centripetal force was ultim ately to p lay in N e w to n ’s ow n theory
sarily fall into many errors concerning the science of mechanics. o f gravitation.
It is possible in addition that the quantities of these powers may be 10. I t is striking how close this explanation o f the stability o f a circular orbit
sometimes calculated in respect of the duration of intervals: in which is to that advanced b y Borelli (see Borelli [i]). It is o n ly necessary to replace D e s ­
cartes’s endeavour to the centre due to the surrounding v ortex m aterial b y
case the absolute quantity will be that compounded from all of intensity,
B o relli’s natural ten den cy tow ards the central b o d y. It is also n otew orth y that
extension and duration. For instance if a body 2, with velocity 3 is moved in D e f. 10 o f this present m an uscript N e w to n actually instances as a potential
for time 4, the total motion will be 2X3 X4, or 12^3 [^/c!]. case o f gravity the conatus o f ether m o vin g circularly about the sun aw ay from
the sun.
Def, 14. Velocity is the intensity of motion, and retardation its remis­
1 1 . T h e drift o f this and the su cceed in g argum ent against D escartes w ould
sion. seem to b e : absence o f m otion cannot produce any real effect. B u t there is a real
effect— the conatus from the centre. T h is cannot, therefore, be due to the absence
1 . C o m m en c in g at the b egin n in g o f the m an uscript w h ich lacks a title.
o f m otion in the philosophical sense. It could, how ever, be due to the presence o f
2. N o such experim ental illustrations, how ever, are actually given.
circular m otion, though D escartes o n ly takes this to b e present in the vu lgar
3. C o m pare this and the three im m ed iately su cceed in g definitions w ith D e f.
sense. H en ce the latter (vulgar) m otion is to be preferred to the former, w h ich
7, 5, 8, 9, respectively, o f M S . X a.
leads to a contradiction — the im proper m otion p ro ducin g the real effect.
4. A s opposed to D escartes, w ho, at least in his Principia Philosophiae, d id not
12. A t p. 6, follow in g a series o f argum ents against D e sca rtes’s double
regard im pen etrability as an essential p ro perty o f bo dy. L eib n iz, likewise, d is­
theory of m otion.
agreed w ith D e sca rte s’s view o f im pen etrability as a secondary cjuality.
13. T h e tw o consequences referred to were ( i) the im possibility o f true
234 E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD. 4003 VI E X T R A C T S FROM MS. ADD.
VI 4 0 0 3 235
m otion in the interior o f a b o d y given that any interior part was always in co n ­
24. A t first sight this clear realization o f the distin ction b etw een mass and
tact w ith the same im m ediate n eighb o u rin g parts, (2) the existence o f in n u m er­
w eigh t w o u ld seem to go against a su pp osedly early date o f com position of the
able true m otions in a b o d y, as follow ed from the assertion (A rt. 25, P a rt 2,
m anuscript. B u t the extract in § 5 o f M S . I points to N e w to n h a vin g m ade this
Principia Philosophiae) that the true m otion o f a b o d y w as shared b y all its
distinction v e ry early, in all p ro b ab ility before the end o f 1664.
interior parts, even if these were in relative m otion am ong them selves. In the
25. W hereas in M S . I I force w as the causal prin ciple o f m otion only, no m en ­
present extracts N e w to n seems o n ly to be referring to the second o f these tw o
tion b ein g m ade o f rest.
consequences.
26. R em in iscen t o f the ‘ external causes’ responsible for ch an gin g the inertial
14. C om pare this passage w ith N e w to n ’s use o f centrifugal force in D e f. 9
state o f a b o d y in the general p hilosophical prin ciple (A rt. 37, Part 2, Principia
o f M S . X a for draw ing a distinction betw een relative and absolute m otion.
Philosophiae) from w h ich D escartes derived the p rinciple o f inertia.
See above, Part I, C h a p ter 3, for a discussion o f N e w to n ’s views on centrifugal
27. C o m pare this wdth the vis corporis said to be responsible for a b o d y ’s en ­
conatus.
deavour to continue in its state o f m otion in D e f. 2 o f V ersion I o f the tract de
15. A t p. 8. T h is extract has been given for its implicit reference to the
Motu (M S . IX a).
p rinciple o f inertia; the absence o f any explicit references to any o f the p urely
28. T h u s m aking it clear that for N e w to n at the tim e o f com posin g this work
dynam ical articles o f D esca rtes’s Principia is a curious feature o f a m an uscript
conatus, in clu d in g the conatus due to circular m otion, was a real species o f p oten ­
otherwise so w e ll furnished w ith detailed chapter and verse. It is p o ssib ly an
tial force. See above, Part I, C h a p ter 3, for a discussion o f N e w to n ’s concept o f
indication o f h o w absolu tely N e w to n had set his face against D escartes at the
conatus.
tim e o f com posin g the present m anuscript.
29. T h e use o f inertia as an alternative for the internal force, or principle, o f a
16. A t p. 10. C o m in g at the end o f a w hole set o f argum ents against D e s ­
b o d y responsible for m aintaining its state o f m otion or rest is interesting. I t is
cartes’s double theory o f m otion, this passage is m em orable as contain in g
n o t used in M S . I X and first appears in M S . X l b , D e f. 3.
N e w to n ’s first assertion o f the necessity o f som e absolute frame o f reference
30. T h e conatus w o u ld then beco m e actual.
against w h ich to m easure the position and m otion o f bodies.
3 1 . T h is exam ple reinforces the im pression that N e w to n believed at this tim e
17. T h is result follow ed for N e w to n from the im possibility o f determ ining
in the real existence o f cen trifugal conatus. See above. Part I, C h a p ter 3.
accurately the true position o f a b o d y in the Cartesian sense at an y previous
32. T h e use o f these term s, and the previous definitions o f in ten sity or e x ­
instant o f tim e, itse lf due to the im possib ility o f determ ining the corresponding
tension, p ro vid e an indication o f the possible influence on N e w to n o f the late
positions of all the surrounding particles.
scholastic doctrine o f the intension and remission o f form s, especially in its
18. T h e last sentence allows o f the possibility o f a continual belief b y N e w to n
application to kinetics b y the M e rto n C o llege S ch ool. See M a ie r [i] for an
in the m echanism o f D esca rtes’s vortex theory; see, for exam ple, the reference to
illu m in atin g discussion o f this question. F o r a discussion o f the contribution
‘ C artesiu s’s V o rtic e s’ in W h isto n ’s account (reproduced above, in Part I,
o f m edieval p h iloso ph y to the birth o f dynam ics see C la g e tt [i]. Chapters i i
C h a p ter 4, p. 65).
and 12.
19. A t p. 1 1 . T h is passage is a good exam ple o f N e w to n ’s purely philosophical
33. A similar notion is that of the total force in a given time found in M S . I l d
w ritin g. It is also interesting to com pare the v ie w here expressed o f space as
at A x .-P r o p . 22.
'Dei effectus emanativiis’ w ith N e w to n ’s later v ie w o f space as the sensorium o f
G o d , and w ith the view s p u t forw ard b y C larke in his controversy w ith L eib n iz.
F o r a discussion o f N e w to n ’s view s on space in the ligh t o f this co ntroversy see
A lexan d er [i], p p . x x x ii-x l.
20. A process o f abstraction strongly rem iniscent o f that adopted b y D e s ­
cartes in his Principia Philosophiae.
2 1. A t p. 19. A good sum m ary o f the properties o f absolute space advanced
in p recedin g sections.
22. A t p. 30. In tb e previous paragraph N e w to n had refused to allow the
capacity o f bodies to excite perceptions in m ental beings as secondary, able to be
stripped aw ay in the Cartesian process o f reduction to the essence. T o rem ove
this facu lty, he said, w ou ld be as serious as to rem ove that other fa cu lty o f
m utual interaction o f bodies, and this w o u ld reduce bodies to em p ty space. T h e
present passage discusses the consequences o f such a reduction. I t should be
com pared w ith a rather sim ilar passage in the Scholium to Prob. 5 o f V ersion
I I I o f the tract de Motu (M S . IX c).
23. N e w to n m u st here be referring to vol. ii o f C lerselier’s edition o f D e s ­
cartes’s Correspondence. A t para. 5 o f letter 96 o f this volu m e D escartes explains
h o w he conceives o f a b o d y m o vin g w ith o u t resistance in a m edium w h en the
velo city o f the latter is ex actly equal to that o f the bo dy.
VII CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 537
that the greatest distance of the sun from the earth is to the greatest
VII distance of the Moon from the earth, not greater than 10000 to 56 and
therefore the parallax of the Sun not less than Parallax of the
E X T R A C T S FROM C O R R E S P O N D E N C E
M oon; Because were the sun’s distance less in proportion to that of the
PRIOR TO 1684 Moon, she would have a greater conatus from the sun than from the
earth. I thought also sometime that the moons libration might depend
T h e passages following appear to be the only important discussions of upon her conatus from the Sun and Earth compared together, till I
dynamical topics in extant Newton letters prior to 1685. This is rather apprehended a better cause.
surprising, given what we know of Newton’s earliest researches in
dynamics, and is in marked contrast to the fairly large number of mathe­ 1. C f. Correspondence, vol. i, p . 290. T h is letter p layed an im portant role in the
matical discussions in the same period. But on examining these latter N e w to n -H a lle y correspondence o f 1686 arising out o f H o o k e’s claim s regarding
the inverse square law.
we find that most if not all of them arose as the result of some definite
2. N e w to n ’s presentation co p y o f H u y g e n s ’s H orologium O scilla to r him .
query, which queries in turn were occasioned by the widespread 3. T h e rem ainder o f the extract was un acco u n tably om itted from the co py
knowledge of, and interest in, mathematics, as in the case of Collins. o f the letter forw arded b y O ld e n b u r g to H u ygen s. T h e w h ole passage was
Dynamics, on the other hand, was a much more esoteric subject reproduced b y N e w to n in his letter o f 27 Ju ly 1686 to H alley. In a previous
a knowledge of which was restricted almost entirely to a very small letter (14 July 1686) he had claim ed that the argum ents p u t forw ard in this
paragraph had been taken from an earlier paper ‘w rit 18 or ig years a go ’ . T h e re
number of original thinkers, so that it is not surprising that Newton had
can be no do u bt that the paper in question is that reproduced in M S . IV a . F o r
seldom occasion to discuss it in letters with his correspondents. In any the possible bearing o f the present passage on N e w to n ’s view s on centrifugal
case, given his extreme (and understandable) secrecy in regard to a force, and on the p roblem o f the test o f the inverse square law o f gravitation
subject in which he may possibly have sensed he was to make his sup­ during the Plague Y ears, see above, Part I, C h a p ter 3, p . 56, and C h a p ter 4,
reme contribution to knowledge, it is rather doubtful if he would have p. 7 1 , respectively.

gone any further in revealing his actual discoveries in dynamics than in


the first paragraph of the letter of 23 June 1673 Oldenburg. The V llb
omission of this paragraph from the version later forwarded by Olden­
burg to Huygens, if not actually indicative of this secrecy, at least provides E x t r a c t ' from N e w t o n ’s L etter of 20 J une 1674 to

a memorable symbol of it. C o l l in s

Sr
I thank you for your kind present.^ Mr Andersons book is very in­
V ila
genious, and may prove as usefull if his principles be true. But I suspect
E x t r a c t ’' f r o m N e w t o n ’ s L e tt e r of 23 J u n e 1673 to one of them, namely that the bullet moves in a Parabola. 3 This would
O l d e n b u r g be so indeed were the horizontal celerity of the bullet uniform, but I
Sr should think its motion decays considerably in the flight. Suppose for
I received your letters with M. Hugens kind present, ^ which I have instance a bullet shot horizontally from A moves in the line AE, and A I
viewed with great satisfaction, finding it full of very subtile and usefull being perpendicular to the horizon in it take A F, AG , AH , A I etc in
speculations very worthy of the Author. 13 am glad that we are to expect proportion as the square numbers i, 4, 9, 16 etc: and its certain that if in
another discours of the vis centrifuga, which speculation may prove of one moment of time the bullet descend as low as F, in the next moment
good use in naturall Philosophy and Astronomy as well as mechanicks. it shall descend as low as G, in the third as low as H etc. And therefore
Thus for instance if the reason why the same side of the Moon is ever drawing the horizontal! lines FB, GC, HD, 1 E\ the bullet at the end
towards the earth be the greater conatus of the other side to recede from of the first moment will be somewhere in the line F B suppose at B,
it; it will follow (upon supposition of the Earths motion about the Sun) and at the end of the second moment it will be somewhere in the line
238 CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 VII VII CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 239
G C suppose at C etc. But that FB, GC, HD and IE are in Arith­ once a day about its center C from west to east according to the order of
metical! progression (which is the condition of the Parabola) seems not the letters BDG\ and let A be a heavy body suspended in the Air and
probable; for if it were so, the celerity of the bullet would increas moving round with the earth so as perpetually to hang over the same
becaus the spaces A B , BC, CD, D E described in equall times are the point thereof B. Then imagin this body A let fall and it’s gravity will
latter bigger than the former; whereas I should rather think that the give it a new motion towards the center of the Earth without diminishing
celerity decreases very considerably. And perhaps this rule for its de­ the old one from west to east. Whence the motion of this body from west
creasing may pretty nearly approach the truth, v iz: Letting fall the per­ to east, by reason that before it fell it was more distant from the center of
pendiculars B K , CL, DM, etc to make IK , K L , L M etc, a decreasing
Geometricall progression. If you should have occasion to speak of this
to the Author, I desire you would not mention me becaus I have no
mind to concern my self further about it.

1. C f. Correspondence, vol. i, p. 309.


2. C o p ies o f the same book were sent b y C o llin s to James G r e g o r y and W a llis.
T h e form er gave his opinion o f the w ork in a letter to C o llin s o f 8 O cto b e r 1674
(see R ig au d [i], vol. ii, letter 215). G r e g o r y fo u n d A nderson [and StreeteJ’s
book ‘ p itifu l s tu ff’ . L ik e N e w to n he criticized the assum ption that the horizontal
m otion w o u ld be uniform . W allis, in his letter o f 24 A u g u s t 1674 to C o llin s (see
R ig au d [i], vol. ii, letter 339), su ggested that A nd erso n m igh t have taken his
principles from Prop. 8, C ap . 10, o f W a llis’s o w n M ech a n ica . H e also criticized
the assum ption o f the u n iform ity o f the horizontal m otion in practice as opposed
to theory, referring to the S ch o liu m to the above proposition in w h ich the
effect o f the resistance o f the air was noted.
3. It is curious that now here in an y o f the extant dyn am ical m anuscripts does
N e w to n discuss the ideal, parabolic p ath o f a projectile. T h e first reference to
G a lile o ’s deduction o f the result occurs in M S . X a , L a w 2, and is repeated at the
b egin n in g o f the S ch o liu m to the laws o f m otion in the P rin cip ia . I t w o u ld be
interesting to kn ow h o w N e w to n first learnt o f the parabolic path, w h eth er
d irectly from the translation o f the D iscorsi in S a lu sb u ry’s translation, or in ­
directly, perhaps throu gh T o rricelli [i]. Likew ise, w h ether he had th o u gh t o f the
effect o f air resistance him self, or was p ro m pted to do so b y the discussion o f
this and other p ertu rb in g factors in G alileo [D iscorsi, ed. N a z., p. 274]. the earth then the parts of the earth at which it arrives in its fall, will be
greater then the motion from west to east of the parts of the earth at
VIIc which the body arrives in it’s fall: and therefore it will not descend in
the perpendicular A C , but outrunning the parts of the earth will shoot
E x t r a c t ^ f r o m N e w t o n ’s L e tt e r of 2 8 N ov e m be r 1679
forward to the east side of the perpendicular describing in it’s fall a
TO H ooke
spiral line AD EC, quite contrary to the opinion of the vulgar who think
I am glad to heare that so considerable a discovery as you made of the that if the earth moved, heavy bodies in falling would be outrun by its
earth’s annual^ parallax is seconded by Mr Flamstead’s Observations. parts and fall on the west side of the perpendicular. The advance of the
In requital of this advertisement I shall communicate to you a fansy of body from the perpendicular eastward will in a descent of but 20 or 30
my own about discovering the earth’s diurnal motion. In order thereto yards be very small and yet I am apt to think it may be enough to determin
I will consider the Earth’s diurnal motion alone without the annual, the matter of fact. Suppose then in a very calm day a Pistol Bullet were
that having little influence on the experimt I shall here propound. Sup­ let down by a silk line from the top of a high Building or Well, the line
pose then BD G [Fig. i] represents the Globe of the Earth carried round going through a small hole made in a plate of Brass or 'Einn fastened to
240 CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 VII VII CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 241
the top of the Building or Well and that the bullet when let down al­ least if the falling Body were supposed in the plaine of the equinoxciale
most to the bottom were setled in water so as to cease from swinging supposing then the earth were cast into two half globes in the plaine of
and then let down further on an edge of steel lying north and south to the equinox and those sides separated at a yard Distance or the like to
try if the bullet in setling thereon will almost stand in aequilihrio but yet make Vacuity for the Desending Body and that the gravitation to the
with some small propensity (the smaller the better) decline to the west former Center remained as before and that the globe of the earth were
side of the steel as often as it is so let down thereon. The steel being so supposed to move with a Diurnall motion on its axis and that the falling
placed underneath, suppose the bullet be then drawn up to the top and body had the motion of the superficial! parts of the earth from whence it
let fall by cutting clipping or burning the line of silk, and if it fall con­
stantly on the east side of the steel it will argue the diurnall motion of
the earth. But what the event will be I know not having never attempted
to try it. If any body may think this worth their triall the best way in
my opinion would be to try it in a high church or wide steeple the windows
being first well stopt. For in a narrow well the bullet possibly may be
apt to receive a ply from the straitned Air neare the sides of the Well, if in
its fall it come nearer to one side then to another. It would be convenient \E

also that the water into which the bullet falls be a yard or two deep or
more partly that the bullet may fall more gently on the steel, partly that
the motion which it has from west to east at its entring into the water
by meanes of the longer time of descent through the water, carry it on
further eastward and make the experiment more manifest.

1. C f. Correspondence, vol. ii, p p . 3 0 1 -2 . F o r an illum in atin g account o f the


w hole N e w to n -H o o k e correspondence o f the w in ter 16 79 -8 0 see K o y r e [2].
F igu re 2.
2. T h e r e can be su rely no d o u b t that it was H o o k e ’s reference to his ow n su p ­
posed discovery o f the parallax due to the earth’s an m ial m otion w h ich p ro m pted was Let fall Impressed on it, I conceive the line in which this body
N e w to n ’s su ggested experim ent for the d isco very o f the diurnal m o tio n . N ew to n ,
would move would resembles An Elleipse:for Instance Let A B D E [Fig. 2]
o f course, had lon g before (M S . IV a) learnt h o w to calculate the centrifugal
force due to the E a r th ’s rotation, or the 'force o f ascent at the equator, arising represent the plaine of the equinox limited by the superficies of the earth;
from the earth’s diurnal m o tio n ’ as he expressed it in his letter o f 14 J u ly 1686 C the Center therof to which the lines of Gravitation doe all tend. Let
to H alley. T h a t it required an external stim ulus to persuade him to consider A represent the heavy Body let fall at A and attracted towards C but
the m atter again is perhaps an indication o f a certain lack o f interest in dyn am ics
in the p eriod 1667 to 1679.
Moved also by the Diurnall Revolution of the earth from A towards
BD E etc. I conceive the curve that will be described by this desending
V lld body A will be A F G H and that the body A would never approach neerer
the Center C then G were it not for the Impediment of the medium as
E x t r a c t ^ f r o m H o o k e ’s L etter of 9 D e cem be r 1679
Air or the like but would continually proceed to move round in the Line
TO N e w t o n
A F G H A F G etc. But w[h]ere the Medium through which it moves has a
But as to the curve Line which you seem to suppose it to Descend power of impeding and destroying its motion the curve in which it would
by (though that was not then at all Discoursed of) Vizt a kind of spirall move would be some what like the Line A IK L M N O P etc and after
which after sume few revolutions Leave it in the Center of the Earth many resolutions would terminate in the Center C. But if the Body litt
my theory of circular motion^ makes me suppose it would be very differ­ [5/c] fall be not in the aquinochill plain as here at London Ja 51°. 32' the
ing and nothing att all akin to a spirall but rather a kind Elleptueid. At elleipsed will be made in a plain inclined to the plaine of the Equinox’
242 CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 VII
V II C O R R E SPO N D E N C E PRIOR TO 1 6 8 4 243
51.32 soe that the fall of the Ball will not be exactly east of the per­
3. T h is w ould seem to rule out the p ossib ility o f the p ath actu ally bein g an
pendicular'^ but South East and indeed more to the south then the east;s ellipse.
as lett N L O S [Fig. 3] represent the Meridian of London and O the 4. T h e p erpendicular in question w'ould have been assum ed b y H ooke to
equinox L London and P L the parrallel in which it moves about the rotate w ith the earth.
5. H o o k e ’s reason for this assum ption is n o t clear. N ew to n , how ever, agreed
Axis N S : the body let fall at L would desend in the plaine L C supposed w ith it subject to the qualification that the b o d y was let fall from som e consider­
at Right angles with the plaine of that Meridion N LQ SR and not in able h e igh t above the earth.
the superficies of the cone P L C whose apex is C the Center of the earth
V ile
E xtract' from N e w t o n ’s L e t t e r of 13 D ecember 1 67 9
TO PIOOKE

Sr
I agree with you that the body in our latitude will fall more to the
south then east if the height it falls from be any thing great. And also

s
Figure 3.

and whose base is the plaine of the parrallel circle PL. I could adde many
other conciderations which are consonant to my Theory of Circular
motions compounded by a Direct motion and an attractive one to a
Center. But I feare I have already trespassed to much upon your more
Usefull thoughts with these my impertinants yet I would desire you not
to look upon them as any provacations to alter your mind [to] more
mature and serious Resolutions. Goe on and Prosper and if you succed
that if its gravity be supposed uniform it will not descend in a spiral to
and by any Freind Let me understand what you think fit to impart, any
the very center but circulate with an alternate ascent and descent made
thing from you will be Extremly Valued by
by it’s vis centrifiiga and gravity alternately overballancing one another.
Sr Your very Humble Sarvant
Yet I imagin the body will not describe an Ellipsoeid but rather such
R O ; HOOKE
a figure as is represented by A F O G H IK L etc. [Fig. 4] Suppose A the
1. C f. Correspondence, vol. ii, pp. 305-6.
2. U n fo rtu n ately for H ooke he was n ever able to p ut the theory on a firm,
body, C the center of the earth, A B D E quartered with perpendicular
quantitative basis, as was m ade evident b y his failure to w in the book prom ised diameters AD , BE, which cut the said curve in F and G ; A M the tangent
b y W ren to H a lle y and h im self for a p ro o f o f the inverse square law' for m otion in which the body moved before it began to fall and GA^ a line drawn
in an ellipse. See H a lle y ’s letter o f 29 June 1686 to N ew to n .
parallel to that tangent. When the body descending through the earth
244 CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 VII VII CORRESPONDENCE PRIOR TO 1684 245
solution. T h e r e is, for exam ple, no firm indication th at he had actually attem pted
(supposed pervious) arrives at G, the determination of its motion shall
a quantitative solution. In this connexion see Pelseneer [i]. H o w ever, N e w to n ’s
not be towards N but towards the coast between A^and D. For the motion assertion that he m igh t have added som eth ing to the p roblem ‘ b y poin ts quam
of the body at G is compounded of the motion it had at A towards M and p roxim e' could be interpreted as an in dication that his th o u gh t on the problem
of all the innumerable converging motions successively generated by had advanced further than he w as prepared to adm it to H ooke.

the impresses of gravity in every moment of its passage from A to G:


The motion from A t o M being in a parallel to G N inclines not the body
to verge from the line GN. The innumerable and infinitly little motions
(for I here consider motion according to the method of indivisibles)
continually generated by gravity in its passage from A to F incline it to
verge from G N towards D, and the like motions generated in its passage
from F to G incline it to verge from G N towards C. But these motions
are proportional to the time they are generated in, and the time of passing
from A to F (by reason of the longer journey and slower motion) is greater
then the time of passing from F to G. And therefore the motions gene­
rated in A F shall exceed those generated in F G and so make the body
verge from G N to some coast between N and D. The nearest approach
therefore of the body to the center is not at G but somewhere between
G and F as at O. And indeed the point O, according to the various propor­
tions of gravity to the impetus of the body at A towards M, may fall any
where in the angle B C D in a certain curve which touches the line BG
at C and passes thence to D. Thus I conceive it would be if gravity were
the same at all distances from the center. But if it be supposed greater
nearer the center the point O may fall in the line CD or in the angle
D C F or in other angles that follow, or even no where. For the increase
of gravity in the descent may be supposed such that the body shall by
an infinite number of spiral revolutions descend continually till it cross
the center by motion transcendently swift.
Your acute Letter having put me upon considering thus far the species
of this curve, I might add something about its description by points
qiiam proxime. But the thing being of no great moment I rather beg your
pardon for having troubled you thus far with this second scribble wherin
if you meet with any thing inept or erroneous I hope you will pardon
the former and the latter I submit and leave to your correction remaining
Sr
Your very humble Servant
IS. NEWTON.

I. C f. Correspondence, vol. ii, p p . 3 0 7-8 . It is chiefly m em orable for the


eviden ce it provides o f the u n developed state o f N e w to n ’s thought on the p ro b ­
lem at w h at was p resu m ably o n ly a short tim e before he arrived at a definitive
VllI THE KE PLE R- M OT IO N PAPERS 247
VIII Let A [Fig. 2] be the center towards which the body is attracted, and
suppose the attraction acts not continually but by discontinued impres­
T H E K E P L E R - M O T I O N PAPERS sions® made at equal intervalls of time which intervalls we will consider
as physical moments. Let B C be the right line in which it begins to
T here are two closely similar versions of the present manuscript. One move ffrom and which it describes with uniform motion in the first
in Newton’s hand,i of which the text is reproduced here, and another physical moment before the attraction make its first impression upon it
among the Locke papers- bearing the title: ‘A Demonstration!that the
Planets by their gravity towardsj the sun may move in Ellipses' The two B D

versions will be termed the Newton and Locke copies, respectively.


The Locke copy is not in Newton’s hand but according to Cranston^
in that of Locke’s valet and amenuensis Brownover.
Given that the Locke copy is endorsed in Locke’s hand ‘Mr. Newi:on
Mar 1689/90’ it is natural to assume that the original of both copies was
composed after the Principia especially for Locke’s benefit, most pro­
bably shortly before March 1689/90. Nevertheless for the reasons given
above in Part I, Chapter 6.6, it is possible that the original was composed
before the Principia^ and in that case most probably in 1679 or 1684.
The normal procedure has been followed of dividing footnotes into
two sets, numerical and alphabetical, the non-trivial variations between
the two copies being included in the latter set. Trivial variations are
largely due to the erratic use of ‘contractions’ and ‘expansions’ in the
two copies.

T he N ew ton C opy

Hypoth. 1.4 Bodies move uniformly in straight lines unless so far as they
are retarded by the resistance of the Medium or disturbed by some
other force.
Hyp. 2.5 The alteration of motion is ever"* proportional to the force by
which it is altered.
Figure 2.
Hyp. 3.^ Motions imprest^ in two different lines, if those lines be taken
in proportion to the motions and completed into a parallelogram, com­ At C let it be attracted towards the center A by one impuls Ror impres­
pose a motion whereby the diagonal of the Parallelogram shall be de­ sion of force, and let CD be the line in which it shall move after that
scribed in the same time in which the sides thereof would have been impuls. Produce B C to I so that C l be equall to B C and draw ID parallel
described by those compounding motions apart. The motions^/? [hig. i] to C A and the point D in which it cuts CD shall be the place of the body
and A C compound the motion AD at the end of the second moments. And because the bases B C C l of the
Prop, id triangles A B C , A C I are equal those two triangles shall be equal. Also
because the triangles A C I, A C D stand upon the same base A C and be­
If a body move in vacuo and be continually attracted toward[s] an
tween two parallels^' they shall be equall. And therefore the triangle A C D
immoveable center, it shall constantly move in one and the same plane,^
described in the second moment shall be equal to the triangle A B C
and in that plane‘s describe equal areas in equall times.
described in the first moment. And by the same reason if the body at
248 THE K EP LE R -M OT IO N PAPERS VI] I VIII THE KE P L E R -M O T I O N PAPERS 249
the end of the 2^, 3^, 4^^, 5*^ and following moments be attracted 'by are tangents to the Ellipsis at its two ends A and C and that E M and
single impulses' in Z), E, F, Gi etc. describing the line D E in the 3^^ D N are perpendiculars let fall from the points E and D upon those
moment, E F in the 4^*', F G in the 5*^ etc: the triangle AED shall be tangents: and because the Ellipsis is alike crooked at both ends those
equall to the triangle A D C and all the following triangles ^AFE, A G F perpendiculars E M and D N will be to one another as the squares of the
etc. to the preceding ones and^^ to one another. And by consequence the arches A E and CD, and therefore E M is to D N as FC^ to F A ‘^. Now in
areas compounded of these equall triangles (as ABE, AEG, A B G etc.) the times that the body by means of the attraction moves in the arches
are to one another as thetimes^ in which they are described. Suppose now A E and CD from A to E and from C to D it would without attraction
that the moments of time be diminished in length and encreased in move in the tangents from A to M and from C to N. Tis by the force of

number in infinitum, so that the impulses or impressions of the attrac­


tion may become continuall and that the line BCD E FG by the infinite
number and infinite littleness of its sides BC, CD, D E etc. may become
a curve one: and the body by the continual attraction shall describe
areas of this Curve ABE, AEG, A B G etc. proportionall to the times in
which they are described. '"W. W. to be Dem.”'
the attractions that the bodies are drawn out of the tangents from M to E
Prop. 2."
and from N to D and therefore the attractions are as those distances
If a body be attracted towards either focus of an Ellipsis and the
M E and ND, that is the attraction at the end of the Ellipsis A is to the
quantity of the attraction be such as suffices to make the body revolve in
attraction at the other end of the Ellipsis C as M E to N D and by conse­
the circumference of the Ellipsis; the attraction at the two ends of the
quence as FC*? to FA^. W. W. to be dem.
Ellipsis shall be reciprocally as the squares of the body in those ends from
that focus. Lemma, i.
Let A E C D [Fig. 3] be the Ellipsis, A, C its two ends or vertices, E' If a right line touch an Ellipsis in any point thereof and parallel to
that focus towards which the body is attracted, and AF'E, CFD areas that tangent be drawn another right line from the center of the Ellipsis
which the body with a ray drawn from that focus to its center, describes which shall intersect a third right line drawn from the touch point through
at both ends in equal times: and those areas by the foregoing Proposi­ either focus of the Ellipsis: the segment of the last named right line
tion must be equal because proportionall to the times: that is the rect­ lying between the point of intersection and the point of contact shall be
angle ^ A F x A E and ^ F C x D C must be equal supposing the arches equal to half the long axis of the Ellipsis.
A E and CD to be so very short that they may be taken for right lines Let A P B O [Fig. 4] be the Ellipsis; A B its long axis; C its center; F, /
and therefore A E is to CD as F C to E'A. Suppose now that A M and CiV its ffoci; P the point of contact; PR the tangent; CD the line parallel to
250 TH E K E P L E R -M O T IO N P A P E R S VIII VIII THE KE PLE R- M OT IO N PAPERS 251
the tangent, and PD the segment of the line FP. I say that this segment gent, X Y the subtense'^' produced to the other side of the Ellipsis and
shall be equal to AC."^ Y Z the distance between this subtense and the first line. I say that the
For joyn i y i ’ and draw/F parallel to CD and because 'is‘ bisected rectangle Y X I is to the rectangle A B x P O as YZ'^ to KL^.
in C,® F E shall be bisected in D and therefore 2^PD shall be equal to^‘ For let FA be the diameter of the Ellipsis parallel to the first line P F
the summ of P F and P E that is to" the summ of P F and Pf, that is to and G H another diameter parallel to the tangent PX , and the rectangle
A B and therefore PD shall be equal to AC.^ W.W. to be Dem. Y X I ^will be to the square of the tangent PX^^ as the rectangle A C F to the
rectangle G C H that is as AF'^ to GH^. This a property of the Ellipsis
Lemma, 2, demonstrated by all that write of the conic sections. And they have also
Every line drawn through either Focus of any Ellipsis and terminated demonstrated that all the Parallelograms circumscribedy about an Ellipsis
at both ends by the Ellipsis is to that diameter of the Ellipsis which is
parallel to this line as the same Diameter is to the long Axis of the
Ellipsis.
Let A P B O [Fig. 4] be the Ellipsis, A B its long Axis, F ,f its foci, C
its center, P O the line drawn through its focus F, and V C S its diameter
parallel to PO and P Q will be to V S as V S to AB.
For draw fp parallel to Q F P and cutting the Ellipsis in p. Joyn Pp
cutting V S in T and draw PR which shall touch the Ellipsis in P and
cut the diameter V S produced in R and C T will be to C S as C S to
CR, ^as has been shewed by all those who treat of the conic sections'^.
But C T is the semisumm of F P and fp that is of F P and F O and there­
fore 7.CT is equal to PO. Also z C S is equal to V S and (by the fore­
going Lemma) zCR is equal to A B . Wherefore PO is to V S as V S to
A B . W.W. to be Dem.
Corol. A B x P Q ^ VS^^ = ^CS‘J

Lem. 3.
If from either focus of any Ellipsis unto any point in the perimeter are equall. Whence the rectangle z P E x G H is equal to the rectangle
of the Ellipsis be drawn a right line and another right line doth touch A B X K L and consequently GH is to K L as A B that is (by Lem. i) 2PD
the Ellipsis in that point and the angle of contact be subtended by any to 2PE and ^in the same proportion is P X to YZ^. Whence P X is to
third right line drawn parallel to the first line; the rectangle which that G H as Y Z to K L and PX^ to GH^ as YZ'? to K L ‘h^^ But^‘ Y X I was to
subtense conteins with the same subtense produced to the other side of as SV^ that is (by Cor. Lem. 2) A B x P O to GH^, whence inver-
the Ellipsis is to the rectangle which the long Axis of the Ellipsis conteins tedly Y X I is to A B x P O as PX'> to GH‘>and by consequence as Y Z ‘'
with the first line produced to the other side of the Ellipsis as the square to K D l W. W. to be Dem."'
of the distance between the subtense and the first line is to the square
Prop. I l l
of the short Axis of the Ellipsis.
Let A K B L [Fig. 5] be the Ellipsis, A B its long Axis, K L its short If a body be attracted towards either focus of any Ellipsis and by that
Axis, C its center, F ,f its foci, P the point of the perimeter, P F the first attraction be made to revolve in the Perimeter of the Ellipsis: the
line P O that line produced to the other side of the Ellipsis P X * the tan- attraction shall be reciprocally as the square of the distance of the body
* T h is letter and V , Z written in capitals in the text but in lower case on Fig. 5. from that focus of the Ellipsis.
252 THE K E P L E R -M O T I O N PA PERS VIII VIII THE K E P LE R -M O T I O N PAPERS 253
Let P [Fig. 6] be the place of the body in the Ellipsis at any moment Axis of the Ellipsis. And by the third Lemma Y X I will be to A B X PQ as
of time and P X the tangent in which the body would move uniformly FZ*^ to KL^ and by consequence Y X will be equall to
were it not attracted and X the place in that tangent at which it would
arrive in any given part of time and Y the place in the perimeter of the A B x P O x YZ^i
XIxKL<i
Ellipsis at which the body doth arrive in the same time by means of the
attraction.9 Let us suppose the time to be divided into equal parts and And in like manner if be the chord of another Arch py which the
that those parts are very little ones so that they may be considered as revolving body describes in a physical moment of time and px be the
physical moments and that the attraction acts not continually but by tangent of the Ellipsis at p and xy the subtense of the angle of contact
drawn parallel to pF, and if p F and xy produced cut the Ellipsis in q and
i and from y upon p F be let fall the perpendicular y z : the subtense yx
shall be equal to
ABxpqxyz^^^^^^’ - di

And therefore Y X shall be to yx as


A B x P Q x YZ^ AB xpqx
X lx K L i xi X KL^
Lb
that is as^^^ YZ^ to ^ ysfswad-
XI XI

And because the lines P Y py are by the revolving body described in


equal times, the areas of the triangles P Y F pyF must be equal by the
first Proposition; and therefore the rectangles P F x Y Z an6.pFxyz are
PQ
equal, and by consequence Y Z is to as ^P to PP. Whence Y Z ‘i
JCl
is to ^ yziitiad. as ppquad. M ppquad.^ therefore Y X is to yx
XI A .1 XI

as p p q iia d . p p q u a d .^
intervalls once in the beginning of every physical moment and let the XI ^ xi
first action be upon the body in P, the next upon it in Y and so on per­ And as we told you that X Y was the line generated in a physical
petually, so that the body may move from P to F in the chord of the moment of time by the force of the attraction in P, so for the same reason
arch P Y and from Y to its next place in the Ellipsis in the chord of the is xy the line generated in the same quantity of time by the force of the
next arch and so on for ever.^^ And because the attraction in P is made attraction in p. And therefore the attraction in P is to the attraction in p
towards F and diverts the body from the tangent P X into the chord P F ”
as the line X Y to the line xy, that is a s^ ^ ppiuad.^Q^ ppquad.^
so that in the end of the first physical moment it be not found in the place XI xt
X where it would have been without the attraction but in F being by the Suppose now that the equal times in which the revolving body
force of the attraction in P translated from X to F : the line X Y gene­ describes the lines P F and py become infinitely little, so that the attrac­
rated by the force of the attraction in P must be proportional to that tion may become continual and the body by this attraction revolve in
force and parallel to its direction that is parallel to PF.^'’ Produce X Y the perimeter of the Ellipsis and the lines PO, X I as also pq, xi be-
and P P till they cut the Ellipsis in I and O. Joyn F Y and upon F P let PO
fall the perpendicular Y Z and let A B be the long Axis and K L the short coming coincident and by consequence equal, the quantities - y ppiund.
JCJ
254 THE K E P LE R -M O T I O N PA PERS VIII VIII THE KE P LE R- M OT IO N PAPERS 255
di. The Locke copy continues P Y , py are b y the rev o lv ­
N o w because the lines
and ~ ppmiad- become and And therefore the attrac- ing b o d y described in equal tim esf the areas o f the triangles P YF, pyF m ust be
xt equall b y the first Proposition and therefore the rectangels P F x YZ and P F x yz
are E q u a l; and pF is to P F as YZ to yz and pF‘^'""^ to as YZ'"^""^ to
tion in P will be to the attraction in p as pF'^ to PF^, that is reciprocally
y^quad.^ and (if yo u m u ltip ly the antecedents alike and the consequents alike)
as the squares of the distances of the revolving bodies from the focus of
ppm ad ^ ^ H p p q u a d as YZ'inad yz'"''"^ that is « as ^ to
the Ellipsis. W. W. to be Dem. XI XI XI X IX KL'^
ABxpqXyz'"'-'"^ . , • • D 1
■------------------------ that IS as YX to yx therefore as the attraction in P to the
xt X KL'^
a. Absent from Locke copy. attraction i n p b y H y p o th : 2 and 3.
b. Succeeded by by forces in Locke copy. Sup pose n o w that the E q u al tim es in w h ich the revolvin g b o d y describes
c. Succeeded by which a right line drawn continually from its own center to the lines PY and py beco m e infinitely litle so that the attraction m a y becom e
the immoveable center of attraction in the Locke copy. continual and the b o d y b y this attraction revolve in the perim eter o f the E llipsis
d. The Locke copy has lines. and the lines PQ, X I as also pq, xi beco m in g coincident, and b y consequence
e. Succeeded by or impulses in Locke copy.
f-f. Absent from Locke copy. equal the quantities pF" and^ PF '' w ill becom e pF'^ and PF'', and therefore
A j XI
g-g. Replaced in the Locke copy by Produce BC to I so that C l be equal to the attraction in P w ill be to the attraction in p as pF" to PF'' that is reciprocally
BC. In CA take CR in such proportion to C l as the motion which the impulse as the squares o f the distances o f the revolvin g b o d y from that focus o f the
alone would have begotten hath to the motion of the body before the impulse E lip sis tow ards w h ich the attraction is directed. W h ic h was to be dem onstrated.
was imprest. And because these two motions apart would in the second moment
of time have carried the body the one to I by reason of the Equality of C l and “ by multiplying the terms of the ratio b y A B and dividing them by K L ''.
B C and the other to R by reason of the aforesaid: proportion: complete the b by the conclusions of the two last paragraphs.
parallelogram ICRD and they shall both togeather in the same time of that second 1. M S . A d d . 3965(1).
moment carry it in the Diagonal of that Parallelogram to D by Hypoth. 3. 2. M S . L o ck e C 3 1, f. 1 0 1 -4 , B odleian L ib ra ry, O xfo rd .
h. The Locke copy has parallel lines A C and DI. 3. See Cran ston [i], p. 337.
i-i. The Locke copy has again by single impulses successively, 4. C o m pare this definition o f the prin ciple o f inertia w ith that in D e f. i o f
j . Succeeded in the Locke copy by H referring to an additional point in the dia­ V . I o f the tract de Motu.
gram of the Locke copy compared tvith the Nezoton copy. 5. C o m pare this w ith the enunciation o f the same law in V . H I o f the tract de
k-k. Absent from Locke copy. Motu. N o tice the absence o f any reference to a state o f rest.
1. Replacing lines cancelled in Newton copy. 6. A m ore prim itive en unciation o f this ‘parallelogram la w ’ is given in H y p . 3
m-m. Written out in full in Locke copy. o f V . I o f the tract de Motu. O n the other hand, a com plete en unciation o f the
n. This proposition is not found in the Locke copy. same law has already been given in § 3 o f M S . V .
o. The Locke copy has CB. 7. C o rrespo n din g to Prop, i o f the tract de Motu.
p. Replacing P F deleted. 8. T h e r e is no m ention o f this fact in any o f the enunciations o f the corre­
q-q. In the Locke copy this passage reads and FE are bisected in C and D, spo n d in g propositions in the various versions o f the tract de Motu.
PD shall be Equall (to half the Summ of P f and PE, that is to half the summ of g. T h e sam e assum ption is m ade in all o f N e w to n ’s kn ow n proofs o f Prop, i
P F and Pf, that is to half A B that is) to CB.
corresponding to K e p le r ’s second law o f planetary m otion.
r-r. Replacing and Fe are deleted.
10. N o tice the striking sim ilarity betw een the assum ptions in this paragraph
s. Succeeded by and D deleted. and those m ade in Prop. i.
t. Probably inserted.
1 1 . N o tice the peculiar m ixture o f m otion both along the p o lygo n and the
u. u. Succeeded by half deleted.
tangent. T h e same sort o f assum ption is m ade, tho u gh less explicitly, in the
v-v. This passage absent from Locke copy. p ro of o f Prop. 2.
w. Succeeded by X I the same subtense in the Locke copy.
12. T h a t A F is parallel to the direction o f the force (or im pulse) at P, i.e.
x-x. Written Shall be to PX^ the square of the tangent in Locke copy.
parallel to PF, is assum ed b y N e w to n w ith o u t proof. It can be show n to follow
y. Replacing subscribed cancelled in Locke copy.
from the assum ption (2nd paragraph) that X and F are the points arrived at b y
z-z. The Locke copy has by consequence as P X to YZ.
the b o d y in one and the same tim e on the tangent and the ellipse respectively.
ai-aj. The Locke copy has But P X ‘ was to GH'‘ as Y X I to S V ‘ and SF'^ (by
B u t it w ould be necessary to replace the ellipse b y an inscribed p o lygo n through­
Cor. Lem. 2) is equal to x P 0 , and therefore Y X I to A B x PQ as YZ'' to K L ''.
out and follow the type o f argum ent (based on H ypo th esis 3) found in the p ro of
W.W. to be Dem. to Prop. I.
bj. Succeeded by PX'' was to GH'' as deleted, as in the Locke copy.
Cx. Succeeded by as is manifest by the third Hypothesis in Locke copy. I R e p la c in g lines d e le t e d .
256 THE K E P L E R -M O T I O N PAPERS VIII
That -iAF is proportional to the magnitude of the force (or impulse) at P is a
basic assumption which Newton justifies neither here nor in the tract de Motu. IX
In Prop. 6, Theor. 5, of Book I of the Principia, however, he justifies the same
assumption by an appeal to the second law of motion. T H E T R A C T DE M O T U
In Prob. 3 of the tract de Motu Newton derives the inverse square law for
motion in an ellipse under a force to a focus as a special case of the general formula
T h e r e are five known versions of the tract de Motu, three in that part
for motion in any curve given in Prop. 3. The dynamical argument is therefore
concentrated in Prop. 3 , and the mathematical argument, corresponding to the of the Portsmouth Collection in the University Library, Cambridge,*
three lemmas in the present paper, in Prob. 3 . In Prop. 3 of the tract de Motu one in the archives of the Royal Society of London, and one in the
he omits all reference to the two points on the ellipse and the tangent being Macclesfield Collection. All are substantially the same, so that the
reached in the same time. Instead he takes a point Q on the curve close to the possibility of independent origins can be excluded. For convenience’
initial point P, and draws a line through Q parallel to SP intersecting at R the
tangent to the curve at P. He then simply states, without any justification, that for sake the versions in the Cambridge University Library will be numbered
motion in a given time from P to Q the centripetal force at P will be proportional I, II, III, corresponding respectively to M SS. IXa, IXb, IXc. As shown
to QR. It is clear, then, that the dynamical argument in the present document, later, I is undoubtedly the earliest version, and II is essentially a copy
though still incomplete, is more detailed than that given in the tract de Motu. See of I, as is also the case for the Royal Society and Macclesfield versions. 2
above. Chapter 1.3, p. 19. Version III, however, has substantial additions compared with I, and
1 3 . No such comparison between two distinct points on the curve is made in
Prop. 3 of the tract de Motu. Instead he makes an ingenious application of represents a more advanced state of dynamical thought.
Galileo’s P law. The full text of I is given in § i together with exegetical and textual
1 4 . The limiting process here envisaged is effectively a double one. It is footnotes. Certain of these latter footnotes refer to differences between
necessary, in the first place, because the ellipse has been replaced (partially, at I, II, and III. These form the basis of the general comparisons between
least) by an inscribed polygon; and in the second place, because the results I and II, and I and III in §§ 2, 3 respectively. In § 3 the additions in III
already obtained are merely approximate. Only the second type of limiting pro­
cess is necessary in Prop. 3 of the tract de Motu where the curve is not approxi­ compared with I are also given.
mated to by an inscribed polygon. The question of the probable dates of composition of Versions I and
III is discussed above in Part I, Chapter 6.4. A tentative identification
of Version II with all but the last of the actual propositions carried by
Paget from Newton to Halley in late 1684 is given in Part I, Chapter 6.5.
1. Manuscript Add. 3 9 6 5 ( 7 ) , fols. 5 5 - 6 2 V , 6 3 - 7 0 , 4 0 - 5 4 , respectively.
This is certainly true in the case of the Royal Society copy, first published
2.
in Rigaud [i]. Appendix I, and then in Ball [i], pp. 35-51. I understand on good
authority that it is also true in the case of the elusive Macclesfield Version.

1. V e r s io n I
De Motu Corporutn in Gyrum
Def Vim centripetam appello qua corpus impellitur vel attrahitur
versus aliquod punctum quod ut centrum spectatur.
Def 2^ Et vim corporis seu corpori insitam qua id conatur perseverare
in motu suo secundum lineam rectam.
Def 3^ ‘^
‘I Et resistentiam quae est medij regulariter impedientis.
Hypth Resistentiam*^' in proximis novem propositionibus nullam
esse, in sequentibus esse ut corporis celeritas et medij densitas conjun-
ctim.
s.'isuo.') S
258 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 259
Hypoth Corpus omne sola vi insita uniformiter secundum rectam SDE, ipsi SC D et SEE ipsi SD E aequale erit. Aequalibus igitur tem­
Jineam in infinitum progredi nisi aliquid cxtrinsecus impediat. poribus aequales areae describuntur. Sunto jam haec triangula numero
Hypoth Corpus in dato tempore viribus conjunctis eo ferri quo infinita et infinite parva, sic, ut singulis temporis momentis singula
viribus divisis in temporibus aequalibus successive. respondeant triangula, agente vi centripeta sine intermissione, et con-
stabit propositio.
Hypoth [Spatium quod corpus urgente quacunque vi centripeta ipso
motus initio describit esse in duplicata ratione temporis.] Theorem 2^
Corporibus in circumferentijs circulorurn uniformiter gyrantibus vires
centripetas esse utv arcuum simul descriptorum quadrata applicata ad
radios circulorurn.

Corpora B, b [Fig. 2] in circumferentijs circulorurn BD, bd gyrantia


Theorema
simul describant arcus BD, bd. Sola vi insita describerent tangentes BC,
Gyrantia omnia radijs ad centrum ductis areas temporibus propor­ be his arcubus aequales. Vires centripetae sunt quae perpetuo retrahunt
tionals describere. corpora de tangentibus ad circumferentias, atque adeo hae sunt ad
Dividatur tempus in partes aequales, et prima temporis parte describat invicem ut spatia ipsis superata CD, ed, id est productis CD, ct/adFet/ut
corpus vi insita rectam A B [Fig. i]. Idem secunda temporis parte si T in q u a d Uf-quad J )J)q u a d hAquad

nil impediret" recta pergeret ad c describens lineam Be aequalem ipsi —r^E Cn j? ' -j— • Hoquor despatijsB D ,b d minu-
A B adeo ut radijs A S , B S, cS ad centrum actis confectae forent aequales tissimis inque infinitum diminuendis sic ut pro \CF, \ef scribere liceat
areae A S B , BSc. Verum ubi corpus venit ad B agat vis centripeta circulorurn radios SB, sb. Quo facto constat Propositio.
impulsu unico sed magno, faciatque corpus a recta Be deflectere et Cor Hinc vires centripetae sunt ut celeritatum quadrata applicata
pergere in recta B C . Ipsi B S parallela agatur eC occurrens B C in C ad radios circulorurn.
et completa secunda temporis parte^ corpus reperietur in G.® Junge S C Cor 2 Et reciproce ut quadrata temporum periodicorum applicata ad
et triangulum S B C ob parallelas SB, Ce aequale erit triangulo SBc atque radios.
adeo etiam triangulo SA B . Simili argumento si vis centripeta successive Cor 3 Unde si quadrata temporum periodicorum sunt ut radij circu-
agat in C, D, E, etc., faciens corpus singulis temporis momentis singulas lorum vires centripetae sunt aequales. Et vice versa.
describere rectas CD, DE, EE, etc., triangulum .SC/) triangulo S B C et Cor 4 Si quadrata temporum periodicorum sunt ut quadrata radiorum
Myp. I." Ivcm. I.*' vires centripetae sunt reciproce ut radij. Et vice versa.
260 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX TH E T R A C T DE M O TU 261

Cor 5 Si quadrata temporum periodicorum sunt ut cubi radiorum Corol. Hinc si datur figura quaevis et in ea punctum ad quod vis
vires centripetae sunt reciproce ut quadrata radiorum. Et vice versa. centripeta dirigitur, inveniri potest lex vis centripetae quae corpus in
Schol.’i Casus Corollarij quinti obtinet in corporibus coelestibus. figurae illius perimetro gyrare faciet. Nimirumcomputandum est solidum
Quadrata temporum periodicorum sunt ut cubi distantarium a communi ---- — huic vi reciproce proportionale. Ejus rei dabimus exempla
centre circum quod volvuntur. Id obtinere in Planetis majoribus circa
Solem gyrantibus inque minoribus circa Jovem ""‘et Saturnum™* jam in problematis sequentibus,
statuunt Astronomi.
Prob.
Theor. 3I” Gyrat corpus in circumferentia circuli requiritur lex °ivis centripetae*^!
Si corpus P [Fig. 3] circa centrum S gyrando, describat lineam quamvis tendentis ad punctum aliquod in circumferentia.
curvam APQ , et si tangat recta PR curvam illam in puncto quovis P et
R

ad tangentem ab alio quovis curvae puncto Q agatur QR distantiae S P


parallela” ac demittatur O T perpendicularisad distantiam-SPidico quod Esto circuli circumferentia S O P A, [Fig. 4] centrum °'vis centripetae®*
^pquad 0 'J 'q u a d S, corpus in circumferentia latum P, locus proximus in quern movebitur
vis centripeta sit reciproce ut solidum ------- ----------- , si modo solidi Q. Ad SA diametrum et S P demitte perpendicula P K , Q T et per Q
illius ea semper sumatur quantitas quae ultimo fit ubi coeunt puncta ipsi S P parallelam age LR occurrentem circulo in L et tangenti PR
P et O. in R, p*et coeant TQ, PR in Z. Ob similitudinem triangulorum
Namque in figura indefinite parva Q R P T lineola OR dato tempore ZOR, ZT P , SPA^^ erit PP® (hoc est QRL) ad ut SA^ ad SP^. Ergo
est ut vis centripetal 2 gt data vi ut*^ quadratum temporis atque adeo OPLxSP*^ SPq
QT^. Ducantur haec aequalia in —~ et punctis P et O
neutro dato ut vis centripeta et quadratum temporis conjunctim, id est QR
ut vis centripeta semel et area S Q P tempori proportionalis (vel duplum S P qc Q T^ xSP'i
coeuntibus scribatur S P pro RL. Sic fiet . Ergo °‘vis
ejus S P x Q T ) bis. Applicetur hujus proportionalitatis pars utraque ad SAi OR
Spao
SP'^xOP^ centripeta®' reciproce est ut - - j - , id est (ob datum SA"') ut quadrate-
lineolam OR et fiet unitas ut vis centripeta et — — conjunctim,

SP^xOT^ cubus distantiae SP. Quod erat inveniendum.


hoc est vis centripeta reciproce ut Q.E.D. Schol."'^’*'* Caeterum in hoc casu et similibus concipiendum est quod
QR
" Lem. 2."' postquam corpus pervenit ad centrum S, id non amplius redibit in orbem
262 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 263
sed abibit in tangente. In spiral! quae secat radios omnes in dato angulo Prob. 3^^
vis centripeta tendens ad Spiralis principium est in ratione triplicata Gyrat corpus in ellipsi; requiritur lex ’‘‘vis centripetae*' tendentis ad
distantiae reciproce, sed in principio illo recta nulla positione deter- umbilicum Ellipseos.
ininata spiralem tangit. Esto Ellipseos superioris umbilicus S [Fig. 5]. Agatur S P secans
Ellipseos diametrum D K in P .y Patet E P aequalem esse semiaxi major!
A C eo, quod acta ab altero Ellipseos urnbilico H linea H I ipsi E C
parallela, ob aequales CS^ CH aequentur ES, EE adeo ut PPsemisumma
sit ipsarum PS, P I id est =''(ob parallelas HI, PR et angulos aequales IPR,
HPZY'^ ipsarum PS, P H quae conjunctim axem totum 2 A C adaequant.
Ad S P demittatur perpendicularis QT. Et Ellipseos latere recto princi­

pal! |seu j dicto L, erit L X OR ad L X P V ut OR ad P V id est ut

PE, (seu AC) ad P C e t L x P V ad G V P ut L ad G V et G V P ad OF^ ut


CP^ ad CD^I Et OV'^ ad ut M ad A" et ad
ut EP^ ad PF^ id est ut CA'^ ad PF^ sive^ ut CD'^ ad CP'^ et con­
junctis hie omnibus rationibus, LxQR^^ ad ut A C ad PCXL^^
ad G F + C P ^ ad ad ad CB^, id est ut A C x L (seu
2PGO ad P C X G F + C P ^ ad ad sive ut 2PC ad GFe^+
M ad N.^- Sed punctis 0 et P coeuntibus rationes ^^2PC ad ^^GVi^ et
M ad N hunt aequali tati sergo et ’^"ex his composita ratio'^'' L x OR
Prob. 2'5 Spa SP'^xOT'^
ad Ducatur pars utraque in et fiet L X SP^ = ---- - -— .
^ o/?
Gyrat corpus in Ellipsi veterum: requiritur lex Vis'"' centripetae ten-
Ergo"'* °”-vis centripeta®'* reciproce est ut L x S P ^ id est?'* in ratione
dentis ad centrum Ellipseos.
duplicata distantiae SP. Q.E.I.
Sunto CA, C B [Fig. 5]^* semi-axes Ellipseos, GP, D K diametri
Schol. Gyrant ergo Planetae majores in ellipsibus habentibus umbili­
conjugatae, PF, Qt perpendicula ad diametros, Q V ordinatim applicata
cum in centro solis, et radijs ad solem ductis describunt areas temporibus
ad diametrum G P et O V PR parallelogrammum. His constructis erit
proportionales, omnino ut supposuit Keplerus. Et harum Ellipseon
("‘ex conicis"') P V G ad OV^ ut PC^^ ad et QF® ad OP ut PO^ ad
pji'Qij et conjunctis rationibus P V G ad ut PC'^ ad et ad PP</, latera recta sunta'* punctis P e tQ ‘^"spatio quam minimo et quasi
OP PF'i QR
id est VG ad ut PO> ad - — • Scribe OR pro PF« et B C x C A infinite parvo distantibus'"*.
pro C D x P F , nec non (piinctis P et O coeuntibus) 2PC pro VG et Theorem 4'^
Ot^xPC'i zBC'^xCA^^ Posito quod vis centripeta sit reciproce proportionalis quadrato
ductis extremis et medijs in se mutuo, liet
~ PC ■ distantiae a centro,quadratatemporum periodicorum in Ellipsibus sunt
E st'‘ ergo vis centripeta reciproce ut ---- ^ — - id est (ob datum ut cubi transversorum axium.
Sunto Ellipseos axis transversus A B [Fig. 6] axis alter PD, latus
2BO^x CA^>) ut hoc est directe, ut distantia PC. Q.E.T. rectum L, umbilicus alteriter S Centro S intervallo S P describatur
PC
circulus PM D. Et eodem tempore describant corpora duo gyrantia
I’er Lem 4.'*- " Per. Lem. 4."'*
264 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 265
arcum Ellipticum PQ et circularem PM , vi centripeta ad umbilicum S umbilicus unus A, B, C, D loca Planetae observatione inventa et O axis
tendente. Ellipsin et circulum tangant PR, P N in puncto P. Ipsi P S transversus Ellipseos. Centro A radio 0 —A S describatur circulus FG
agantur parallelae QR, M N tangentibus occurrentes in R et N. Sint et erit ellipseos umbilicus alter in hujus circumferentia. Centris B, C, D,
autem figurae PQR, P M N indefinite parvae sic ut (per schol. Prob. 3) etc., intervallis Q — B S, Q ~ C S , Q — D S etc., describantur itidem alij
fiat L x Q R = et zSP^^xM N — MV'L Ob communem a centre quotcunque circuli et erit umbilicus ille alter in omnium circumferentijs
S distantiam S P et inde aequales vires centripetas sunt M N et OR atque adeo in omnium intersectione communi F. Si intersectiones omnes
aequales.22 Ergo QT'i ad MV'^ est ut L ad zSP, et Q T ad M V ut medium non coincidunt, sumendum erit punctum medium pro umbilico. Praxis
proportionale inter L et 2 ^^SP seu PD ad z SP'^k^^ H oc est area S P Q
___________ Q

-c

hujus commoditas est quod ad unam conclusionem eliciendam adhiberi


ad aream S P M ut area tota Ellipseos ad aream totam circuliA^ Sed partes possint et inter se expedite comparari observationes quamplurimae.
arearum singulis momentis genitae sunt ut areae S P Q et S P M atque Planetae autem loca singula A, B, C, D etc., ex binis observationibus,
adeo ut areae totae et proinde per numerum momentorum multiplicatae cognito Telluris orbe magno invenire docuit Halleus.26 Si orbis ille ma-
simul evadent totis aequales. Revolutiones igitur eodem tempore in gnus nondum satis exacte determinatus habetur,^? ex eo prope cognito,
ellipsibus perficiuntur ac in circulis quorum diametri sunt axibus determinabitur orbita Planetae alicujus puta Martis propius: Deinde ex
transversis Ellipseon aequales. 25 Sed (per Cor 5. Theorem 2) quadrata orbita Planetae per eandem methodum determinabitur orbita Telluris
temporum periodicorum in circulis sunt ut cubi diametrorum. Ergo et adhuc propius: turn ex orbita Telluris determinabitur orbita Planetae
in Ellipsibus. Q.E.D. multo exactius quam prius: et sic per vices donee circulorum inter­
Schol. Hinc in systemate coelesti ex temporibus periodicis Planetarum sectiones in umbilico orbitae utriusque exacte satis conveniant.28
innotescunt proportiones transversorum axium Orbitarum. Axem unum Hac method© determinare licet orbitas Telluris, Martis, Jovis, et
licebit assumere. Inde dabuntur caeteri. Datis autem axibus determina- Saturn!, Orbitas autem Veneris et Mercurij sic. Observationibus in
buntur orbitae in hunc modum. Sit S [Fig. 7] locus Solis seu Ellipseos maxima Planetarum a Sole digressione factis, habentur orbitarum
266 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 267
tangentes. Ad ejusmodi tangentem K L [Fig. 8] demittatur a Sole per- rectum Ellipseos. Sit istud L. Datur praeterea Ellipseos umbilicus S
pendiculum SL centroque L et intervallo dimidij axis Ellipseos des- Anguli R P S complementum ad duos rectos fiat angulus R PH et dabitur
cribatur circulus K M . Erit centrum Ellipseos in hujus circumferential^ positione linea P H in qua umbilicus alter H locatur. Demisso ad P H
adeoque descriptis hujusmodi pluribus circulis ^'^reperietur in omnium''^ perpendiculo S K et erecto semiaxe minore B C est SP^--2KPH^--{-PH^
intersectione. "'^Cognitis tandem"^ orbitarum dimensionibus, longitu- = SH^-^ = = {SP+PHy^<^d-Lx{SP-\-PH) = 5 P«+
dines horum Planetarum postmodum exactius ex transitu suo per discum 2SPH-\-PH^-~L (*S'P+PH). Addantur utrobique 2KPH^^-\-Lx{SP-\-
Solis determinabuntur.’^^^o P H )~ S P ^ -~ P m et fiet L x{SP -\-P H ) = 2SP H ^ 2K P W ^ seu S P +

K L
r‘ T

M
/
\ I /

F igu re 8.

Prob. 4'^^
Posito quod vis centripeta sit reciproce proportionalis quadrato dis-
tantiae a centro, et cognita vis illius quantitate: requiritur Ellipsis quam
corpus describet de loco dato cum data celeritate secundum datam
rectam emissum.
Vis centripeta tendens ad punctum S [Fig. 9] ea sit quae corpus 7r| in
circulo TTx centro S intervallo quovis Sn descripto gyrare faciat.^^ p)e
PH ad PH ut 2SP-\-2KP'°^ ad L. Unde datur umbilicus alter H. Datis
loco P secundum lineam PR emittatur corpus Py^ et mox inde cogente
autem umbilicis una cum axe transverse SP-\~PH datur Ellipsis. Q.E.I.
vi centripeta deflectat in Ellipsin PO. Hanc igitur recta PR ianget in P.
Haec ita se habent ubi figura Ellipsis est. ffieri enim potest ut corpus
Tangat itidem recta np circulum in tt sitque PR ad irp ut prima celeritas
moveat‘^3 in Parabola vel H yp er bol a. Ni mi rum si tanta est corporis
corporis emissi P ad uniformem celeritatem corporis 7 7 . Ipsis S P et Sn
celeritas ut sit latus rectum L aequale 2SP^2KP,'°^ ffigura erit Parabola
parallelae agantur RO et px haec circulo in x Ellipsi in O occurrens,
umbilicum habens in puncto -S' et diametros omnes parallelas lineae PH.
et a O etx ad SPtX Sn demittantur perpendicula Q T et nT. Est RO ad px
Sin corpus majori adhuc celeritate emittitur movebitur id in Hyperbola
ut vis centripeta in P ad vim centripetam in n^^ id est ut Sn^“^^^ad SP^*’^^*^,
habente umbilicum unum in puncto S alterum in puncto H sumpto
adeoque datur ilia ratio. Datur etiam ratio O T ad RP^^ et ratio P P a d pn
ad contrarias partes puncti P et axem transversum aequalem differentiae
seu x l. et inde composita ratio O P ad x1- De hac ratione duplicata aufer-
linearum P S et PH.
OP® nM •
atur ratio data OR ad vp et manebit data ratio ^ — ad — id est (per Schol Schol. Jam vero beneficio ^shujus Problematis solutF®, cometarum'“3
OP XP
orbitas definire concessum est, et inde revolutionum tempora, et ex
Prob. 3) ratio lateris recti Ellipseos ad diametrum circuli. Datur igitur latus
orbitarum magnitudine, excentricitate, Aphelijs, inclinationibus ad
t T h e archaic form vr for tt sometim es used by N ew ton in this passage has been planum Eclipticae et nodis inter se collatis cognoscere an idem cometa
replaced throughout by tt. vj is also found in Fig. 9. ad nos saepius redeat. Nimirum ex quatuor observationibus locorum
268 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 269
cometae, juxta Hypothesin quod Cometa movetur uniformiter in linea ut ^ffillipseos axis minor ad axem majorem et erit punctum P in Ellipsi
recta,37determinanda est ejus via rectilinea.3^Sit taAPBD , [Fig. lo] sint- atque acta recta S P "’^abscindetur area'"^ Ellipseos E P S tempori pro-
que A, P, B, D loca cometae in via ilia temporibus observationum, et S portionalis.'^s Namque area H S N M triangulo S N K aucta et huic aequali
locus solis. Ea celeritate qua cometa uniformiter percurrit rectam A D segmento H K M diminuta fit triangulo H S K id est triangulo H SC
finge ipsum emitti de locorum suorum aliquo P et vi centripeta mox
correptum deflectere a recto tramite et abire in Ellipsi Pbda. Haec
Ellipsis determinanda est ut in superiore Problemate.39 In ea sunto a, P,

aequale. Haec aequalia adde°» areae ESH, pffient areaeP* aequales E H N S


et EHC. Cum igitur Sector EH C tempori proportionalis sit et area E P S
areae E H N SN erh etiam area E P S tempori
proportionalis.

b, d loca cometae temporibus observationum. Cognoscantur horum loco- Prob. 5^2


rum e terra longitudines et latitudines. Quanto majores vel minores sunt Posito quod ^nis centripetal^ sit reciproce
his longitudines et latitudines observatae tanto majores vel minores proportionalis quadrato distantiae a centro*^*
observatis sumantur longitudines et latitudines novae. Ex his novis spatia definite quae ^“corpus recta®* cadendo
inveniatur denuo via rectilinea cometae et inde via Elliptica ut prius. Et datis temporibus describit.
loca quatuor nova in via Elliptica prioribus erroribus aucta vel diminuta Si corpus ^^*non cadit perpendiculariter
jam congruent cum observationibus ssexacte s a t i s . A u t si fortes^ errores describet id Ellipsin puta A P B [Fig. 12]
etiam num sensibiles manserint potest opus totum repeti. Et ne computa cujus umbilicus inferior puta S congruetcum
Astronomos moleste habeant suffecerit haec omnia per *^3descriptionem centro.^* Id ex jam demonstratis constat.
linearum’^3 determinare. Super Ellipseos axe majore A B describatur
Sed’3areas aSP, PSb, bSd temporibus proportionales assignare difficile semicirculus A D B et per corpus*^* decidens
est. Super Ellipseos axe majore EG [Fig. ii], describatur semicirculus transeat recta D PC perpendicularis ad axem,
EHG. Sumatur angulus ECH tempori proportionalis. Agatur SH eique actisque DS, PS, erit area A S D areae A S P
parallela C K circulo occurrens in K . Jungatur H K et circuli segmento atque adeo etiam tempori proportionalis.
H K M (per tabulam segmentorum vel secus) aequale fiat triangulum Manente axe A B minuatur perpetuo latitude Figure 12.

S K N . Ad EG demitteJ^ perpendiculum NQ, et in eo capei^^ PQ ad NO Ellipseos, et semper manebit area A S D tempori proportionalis. Minuatur
270 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 271
latitude ilia in infinitum et orbita A P B jam coincidente cum axe mento lineae D C proportionale est incrementum lineae AD. Ergo
A B et umbilico S cum axis termino B descendet corpus'^^ in recta incrementum spatij per incrementum lineae AD, atque adeo spatium
A C et area A B D evadet tempori proportionalis. Definietur itaque ipsum per lineam illam recte exponitur Q.E.D.
spatium A C quod corpus‘“ de loco A perpendiculariter cadendo tempore
Prob.
dato describit si modo tempori proportionalis capiatur area A B D et a
puncto D ad rectam A B demittatur perpendicularis DC. Q.E.F. Posita uniformi vi centripeta, motum corporis in medio similar! recta
Schol."3 Priore Problemate definiuntur motus''^ projectilium in acre ascendentis ac descendentis definire.
nostro hacce motus gravium perpendiculariter cadentium ex Hypothesi

quod gravitas reciproce proportionalis sit quadrate distantiae a centre


terrae quodque medium aeris nihil resistat. "''‘Nam gravitas est species
una vis centripetae.'''^’
Prob. 6^3ya Figure 14,
Corporis sola vi insita per medium similare resistens delati motum
definire. Corpore ascendente exponatur vis centripeta per datum quodvis rectan-
Asymptotis rectangulis AD C, CH [Fig. 13] describatur Hyperbola gulum B C [Fig. 14] et resistentia medij initio ascensus per rectangu-
secans perpendicula AB, D G in B, G. Exponatur turn corporis celeritas lum BD sumptum ad contrarias partes. Asymptotis rectangulis AC ,
turn resistentia medij ipso motus initio per lineam A C elapso^3 tempore CH per punctum B describatur Hyperbola secans perpendicula DE, de
aliquo per lineam"** D C et tempos exponi potest per aream A B G D in G, g et corpus ascendendo tempore DGgd describet spatium EGge,
atque spatium eo tempore descriptum per lineam AD. Nam celeritati tempore D G BA spatium ascensus totius EGB, tempore AB^G^D
proportionalis est resistentia medij et resistentiae proportionale est decre- spatium descensus BE^G atque tempore W^G-g^d spatium descensus
mentum celeritatis/^ i^4hoc esC*, si tempus in partes aequales dividatur, ^GEe^g\ et celeritas corporis resistentiae medij proportionalis, erit in
celeritates ipsarum initijs sunt‘=*differentijs suis proportionales. Decrescit horum temporum periodis ABED, ABed, nulla, ABE^D, ABe^d; atque
ergo celeritas in'* proportione Geometrica dum tempus crescit in Arith- maxima celeritas quam corpus descendendo potest acquirere erit BC.
metica. Sed <^*tale est decrementum'^* lineae D C et incrementum*'* areae Resolvatur enim rectangulum A H [Fig. 15] in rectangula innumera
AB G D , ut notum est. Ergo tempus per aream et celeritas per lineam Ak, Kl, Lm, Mn, etc. quae sint ut incrementa celeritatum aequalibus
illam recte exponitur. Q.E.D. Porro celeritati atque adeo decremento totidem temporibus facta et erunt'* Ak, Al, Am, An etc., ut celeritates
celeritatis proportionale est incrementum spatij descripti sed et decre- totae atque adeo" ut resistentiae medij in fine singulorum temporum
“ Lem. ** " H yp. >**
272 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 273
aequalium. j^ffiat A C ad A K , vel A B H C ad A B k K ut vis centripeta ad Ex loco quovis D [Fig. 16] ejaculetur corpus secundum lineam quamvis
resistentiam in fine temporis primi et erunt AB H C, KkH C, LIHC, rectam DP, et per longitudinem D P exponatur ejusdem celeritas sub initio
NnHC etc. ut vires absolutae quibus corpus urgetur atque adeo ut motus. A punctoPad lineam horizontalem D C demittatur perpendiculum
incrementa celeritatum, id est ut rectangula Ak, K l, Lm, Mn etc et PC, ut et ad D P perpendiculum C l ad quod sit D A ut est resistentia
proinde^ in progressione geometrica. Quare si rectae Kk, LI, Mm, Mn
productae occurrant Hyperbola in 17, A, /x, v etc. erunt areae ABrjK,
Kr]XL, LXfxM, MfjLvN etc aequales, adeoque turn temporibus aequali-
bus turn viribus centripetis semper aequalibus analogae. Subducantur
rectangula Ak, Kl, Lm, Mn, etc viribus absolutis analoga et relinquentur

areae Bkr], kr]Xl, lAixm, mixvn, etc resistentijs medij in fine singulorum
temporum, hoc est celeritatibus atque adeo descriptis spatijs analogae.
Sumantur analogarum summae et erunt areae Bkrj, BIX, Bm(i, Bnv etc.
spatijs totis descriptis analogae, nec non areae ABrjK, ABXL, AB[xM,
ABvN, etc. temporibus.Corpus igitur inter descendendum tempore
quovis ABXL describit spatium BIX et tempore LXfxn spatium Xlnv.
Q.E.D. Et similis est demonstratio motus expositi in ascensu. Q.E.D.
Schol. Beneficio duorum novissimorum problematum innotescunt medij ipso motus initio ad vim gravitatis. Erigatur perpendiculum A B
motus projectilium in aere nostro, ex hypothesi quod aer iste similaris cujusvis longitudinis et completis parallelogrammis, D A BE, C A B H per
sit quodque gravitas uniformiter et secundum lineas parallelas agat. Nam punctum B asymptotis DC, C P describatur Hyperbola secans DE in G.
si motus omnis obliquis corporis projeti distinguatur in duos, unum Capiatur linea n ad EG ut est D C ad CP, et ad rectae D C punctum
ascensus vel descensus alterum progressus horizontalis: motus posterior quodvis R erecto perpendiculo R tT quod occurrat Hyperbolae in T et
determinabitur per Problema sextum, prior per septimum ut fit in hoc D R tE -D R T B G
diagrammate. rectae EH in t, in eo cape Rr = et projectile tempore
Lt‘m. '’ 1
274 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX 4TIE TRA C 4' DE M O T U 275
D R T B G perveniet ad punctum r, describens curvam Jineam DarFK e^. Su cceed ed by esse ut corporis celeritas et m edij densitas conjun ctim

quam punctum r semper tangit, perveniens autem ad maximum aititu- deleted.


fi. Im m ediately beneath this hypothesis is zcritten H y p o th [3 ?]. R esistentiam in
dinem a in perpendiculo A B , I'deinde incidens in lineam horizontalem proxim is n ovem p ropositionibus n ullam esse in sequentibus esse u t celeritas ct
D C ad F ubi areae DFsE, D F S B G aequantur^i et postea semper m edij densitas co njun ctim deleted.
appropinquans Asymptoton PH CL. Estque celeritas ejus in puncto gL. W ritten in margin.
h]. T h e enunciation o f this hypothesis is taken fr o m V . I I , the title only being
quovis r ut curvae tangens rL.
given in V . I , in the m argin. I t is succeeded in V. I I [but n ot in V . I l l ) by a list
Si proportio resistentiae aeris ad vim gravitatis nondum innotescit; o f the enunciations o f a ll the subsequent theorems an d problem s follozved fin a lly
cognoscantur (ex observatione aliqua) anguli AD P, AFr in quibus curva by tzvo lemmas ziumbered 3 an d 4 agreeing zcith the corresponding lemmas in
V. I II .
DarFk secat lineam horizontalem DC. Super D F constituatur rectan-
ii. R eplacin g H y p . 3 deleted.
gulum DFsE altitudinis cujusvis, ac describatur Hyperbola rectangula ji. S ucceed ed by insertion celeritatum [qua ?] deleted.
ea lege ut ejus iina Asymptotes sit DF, ut areae DFsE, D F S B G ki- In V . II these corollaries are o m itted havin g already figured in the original
list o f en unciations o f theorem s and problem s,
aequentur et ut sS sit ad EG sicut tangens anguli AFr ad tangentem
h . T h is S ch oliu m is om itted from V . II.
anguli AD P. Ab hujus Hyperbolae centre C ad rectam D P demitte m i-m i. D ele te d in V . I I I .
perpendiculum C l ut et a puncto B ubi ea secat rectam Es, ad rectam D C ni- R eplacin g H y p . 4 deleted.
perpendiculum B A , et habebitur proportio quaesita D A ad C l, quae est Oi-Oj. R eplacin g gravitas deleted.
P i-p i- Inserted into V . I , present in V . I l l , missing fr o m V . I I .
resistentia medij ipso motus initio ad gravitatem projectilis. Quae omnia
cii- R eferrin g to Lem m a 4 o f V . I I I .
ex praedemonstratis facile eruuntur. Sunt et alij modi inveniendi ri. Sch oliu m om itted in V . I I .
resistentiam aeris quos lubens praetereo. Postquam autem inventa est Si. Preceded by gravitas deleted.
tj. T an d t are interchanged in the D iagram o f V . I I com pared u it h those o f V . I ,
haec resistentia in uno casu capienda est ea in alijs quibusvis ut corporis
I I I . A llow a n ce is made f o r this interchange in the subsequent p ro o f in V . I I .
celeritas et superficies sphaerica conjunctim (Nam projectile sphaericum Ui. Inserted into V . I , present in V . I l l , missing fr o m V . I I .
esse passim suppono) vis autem gravitatis innotescit ex pondere. Sic Vi. M a rg in a l fo o tn o te (b) to C o r. T h e o r . 3 in V . I I I .
\\q. R eferring again to Lem m a 4 o f V . I I I .
habebitur semper proportio resistentiae ad gravitatem seu lineae D A ad
Xi~x.. W ritten in above gravitas deleted.
lineam C L Hac proportione et angulo A D P determinatur specie figura yi- E t lineam O F in x et com pleatur parallelogram m um Q x P R inserted in
DarFKLP: et capiendo longitudinem D P proportionalem celeritati V . I l l fo r clarification since the same diagram is used as in P roh. 2 zvhile nozv Q R is
projectilis in loco D determinatur eadem magnitudine sic ut altitudo Aa supposed to be drawn p a ra llel to S P as opposed to C P . W hereas it is actu ally
p a ra llel to C P . I t is curious to fin d the same error in the diagram to the corre­
maximae altitudini projectilis et longitudo D F longitudini horizontali sponding proposiHon {P rop. X I , P rob . V I ) in the F ir st E d itio n o f the P rin cip ia .
inter ascensum et casum projectilis semper sit proportionalis, atque I n later editions it is corrected.
adeo ex longitudine D F in agro semel mensurata semper determinet Inserted in I , present in I I I , missing fr o m I I .
aa-ag. D eleted in V . I l l an d replaced by p unctis Q et P coeuntibus fit ratio
turn longitudinem illam DFt\im alias omnes dimensiones figurae DarFK
aequalitalis et Qx'^ seu Qr>'' est.
quam projectile describet in agro. Sed in colligendis hisce dimensionibus ba- A lte r e d fr o m QT'^ to Q t ‘ in V . I I to allozv f o r the interchange o f t fo r T in
usurpandi sunt logarithmi pro area Hyperbolica DRTBG. D iagram 5 previously n oted in fo o tn o te t^.
c ,. S ucceed ed by insertion fit in V . I I I .
Eadem ratione determinantur etiam motus corporum gravitate vel
do. T h is an d succeeding signs + a ll im ply m ultiplication.
levitate et vi quacunque simul et semel impressa moventium in aqua. ej-Ca. D eleted in V . I I I .
fa-fo. D eleted in V . I I I .
D eleted in V . I I I .
ai- C a n celled in V . I l l a n d replaced by L e x i.
ha. D eleted an d replaced by aequantur in V. I I I .
b]. E v ery th in g dozen to beginning o f Theorem i deleted.
i j. R ep laced by et in V . I I I .
C|. E v id en tly inserted as an afterthought betzveen D e f. 2 a n d H y p . i .
ja-jo. D eleted in V . I I I .
di. R ep lacin g the follozcing d eleted version o f the p rin cip le o f inertia C orpora
ka-ko. D eleted in V . I I I .
nec m edio im pediri nec alijs causis externis [qua?] m inus viribus insitae ct
la. D eleted in V . I I I .
centripetae exquisite eadem.
mo. S ucceed ed by insertion A eq u a n tu r in V. I I I .
276 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 277
H2. Marginal reference (b) to Cor. Th. 3 in V. III. C4. Replaced by erunt in F. III.
O2-O2. Written in above gravitas deleted in both VI and VIII. d4~d4. Replaced in V. I l l by proportione priore decrescit.
P2. Succeeded by insertion reciproce in V. III. C4. Replaced in V. I l l by posteriore crescit.
Q2. Succeeded by insertion quantitas in V. III. f4. Number 3 supplied in V. III.
g4. Altered to Lex 5 in V. III.
T2. Given in error in V. II as ~ - in place of h4. Number 3 supplied in V. III.
QR ^ •’ QR
S2. Succeeded by quae ultimo fit ubi coeunt in V. III. in. Succeeded by insertion nihil in V. III.
t2~t2. Deleted in V. III. j4~j4- After considerable emendation, partly illegible, this passage in V. HI
U2-U2. Missing from V. II. reads;
V2-V2. Replaced by reperientur in M omnium intersectiones in V. II represent­ Fiat A C ad A K vel ABH C ad A BkK ut vis centripeta ad resistentiam in prin-
ing an attempt to remove an imagined obscurity in the text. But the subject of cipio temporis deque vi centripeta subducantur resistentiae et manebunt ABHC,
reperietur was intended to be centrum and not intersectiones. V. I ll follows V. I. KkHC, LIHC, NnHC etc ut vires absolutae quibus corporibus in principio singu-
W2-W2. Replaced in V. II by Turn cognitis. lorum temporum urgetur atque adeo ut incrementa celeritatum, id est ut rectan-
X2. A long passage intervenes at this point in V. I l l before Prob. 4. See B of§j. gula Ak, Kl, Lm, Mn etc. et proinde in progressione geometrica. Quare si
Y2. Succeeded by ea celeritate qua sit ad celeritatem uniformem corporis m ut rectae Kk, LI, Mm, Nn productae occurrant Hyperbola in rj. A, p, v, etc erunt
recta quaevis PR ad rectam quamvis -mp deleted. areae ABrjK, Kt]\L, LXpM, MpvN etc. aequales adeoque turn temporibus
Z2. V. I I has ± 2KPH corresponding to the possibility of K lying in H P pro­ aequalibus num est autem area ABrjK ad aream Bkr) ut K t) ad hkK seu A C ad
duced as is actually the case in the diagram in that version. \A K viribus centripetis semper aequalibus analogae. Hoc est ut vis centripeta
83. Succeeded by = 4CH'Gnserted in V. III. ad resistantiam in medio temporis primi. Et simili argumento area rjKLX,
b3. ± 2 K P in V .I I . XLMp, pMNv, etc. Sunt ad areas 17/e/A, Xlnp, pmnv ut vires centripetas ad resis-
C3. Altered to moveatur in V. III. tentias in medio temporis secundi tertij quarti etc. Proinde cum areae aequales
ds-dg. Altered to soluti hujus Problematis in V. III. AKrj, rjKLX, XLMp, pMNv etc sunt viribus centripetis analogae, erunt areae
eg. Substitutedfor Planetarum in all versions. Bkrj, rjklX, Xlmp, pmnv etc resistentijs in medio singulorum temporum, hoc est
f g . Succeeded by insertion id adeo ut correctiones respondeant erroribus in celeritatibus atque adeo descriptis spatijs analogae.
V. III. k4. Immediately beneath in V. I l l occurs Et hae areae [ ?] rectangula numero
S3~g3- Deleted and replaced by quam proxime. At Si in V. III. infinita et infinite parva evadunt coincidunt cum Hyperbolicis deleted.
hg-hg. R e p l a c i n g Geometricam deleted. V. Illfollozvs V. I, zvhereas V. II I4-I4. Deleted in V. HI.
has praxin Geometricam.
ig . Replaced by Verum in V. III.
j g . Demittatur in V. III. Translation
k g . Capiatur in V. III. The Motion of Revolving Bodies
Ig. Succeeded by insertion est in V. III.
mg-mg. Altered to Abscindet aream in V. III. Definition i.^ I call centripetal that force by which a body is impelled
ng. Altered to proportionalem in V. III. or drawn towards any point which is regarded as a centre [of force].
03. Altered to addita in V. III.
pg-pg. Altered to facient areas in V. III. Definition 2.^ And I call that the force of a body or the force innate in a
qg-qg. Replacing gravitas deleted. body by reason of which it endeavours to persist in its motion along a
rg. Succeeded by terrae deleted.
S3-S3. Replacing gravia deleted. straight line.
tg. Replacing grave deleted.
Definition 3.3 And the resisting force that arising from the steadily
Ug. The Scholium in V. I l l is different. It is given belozc in § 3 C.
V g. Succeeded by gravium deleted. impeding medium.
Wg-Wg. Replacing sequentibus resistentia medij similaris primo absque gravi­
tate dum cum gravitate uniforme consideratur. Nam vis centripetae species una Hypothesis i.“^The resisting force in the next nine propositions is zero,
est gravitas deleted apart from vis centripeta allozced to stand. and in the succeeding ones jointly as the speed of the body and the
X g. V. II ends here. density of the medium.
Yg. Preceded in V. I l l by sub-heading De motu corporum in medijs re-
sistentibus. Hypothesis 2.5 Every body under the sole action of its innate force moves
Z g. Replaced by insertion datae longitudinis, elapso autem in V. III.
uniformly in a straight line to infinity unless anything extraneous hinders
a^. Succeeded in V. I l l by insertion indefinitam.
b4~b4. Replaced by proinde in V. III. it.
278 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 279
Hypothesis 3.^ A body is carried in a given time under the combined their innate forces alone they would describe tangents BC, he equal to
action of [two] forces so far as it would be carried by the forces acting these arcs. The centripetal forces continuously pull back the bodies from
separately in succession for equal times. the tangents to the circumferences, and consequently are respectively as
Hypothesis 4. [The space described by a body at the beginning of its the distances CD, cd by which the tangents exceed the circumferences,
motion under the action of any centripetal force is proportional to the BC~ hc^ BD^ bd^
that is, producing CD, cd to F and f, as — to or as T^^to .I
square of the time.] CF cf \C F w
speak of spaces BD, bd very small and infinitely decreased so that for
Theorem \CF, \ef it is permissible to write the radii SB, sb of the circles. Which
being done the proposition is established.
All bodies circulating about a centre [of force] sweep out areas pro­
portional to the times [of description]. Corollary i. Hence centripetal forces are as the squares of the speeds
Let the time be divided into equal intervals, and in the first interval of divided by the radii of the circles.
time suppose the body by reason of its innate force describes the line Corollary 2. And reciprocally as the squares of the periodic times divided
A B [Fig. i]. Likewise in the second interval of time if nothing were to by the radii.
impede it'* suppose it would continue straight on to c covering a length
Corollary 3. Hence if the squares of the periodic times are as the radii
Be equal to the line ABy so that the radii A S , B S, cS being drawn to the
of the circles the centripetal forces are equal. And vice versa.
centre [5 ] the areas A S B , BSc would be made equal. But actually when
the body comes to B let the centripetal force act [on it] with a single Corollary 4. If the squares of the periodic times are as the squares of the
great impulse, forcing the body to deviate from the line Be and continue radii the centripetal forces are inversely as the radii. And vice versa.
on in the line BC. Let eC be drawn parallel to B S meeting B C in C and Corollary 5. If the squares of the periodic times are as the cubes of the
on the completion of the second interval of time^^ the body will be found radii the centripetal forces are inversely as the squares of the radii. And
at C.^ Join S C and because of the parallels SB, Ce the triangle S B C will conversely.
be equal to the triangle SBc and so also to the triangle SA B . By a like
Scholium. The case of the fifth corollary holds for the celestial bodies.
argument if the centripetal force acts successively in C, D, E etc.,
The squares of the periodic times are as the cubes of the distances from
causing the body to describe separate lines CD, DE, EE etc. in separate
the common centre around which they revolve. Astronomers are agreed
intervals of time, the triangle S C D will be equal to SB C, and S C D itself
that this holds for the major planets circulating about the sun and for
equal to SDE, and SD E itself equal to SEE, Therefore equal areas are
the minor about Jupiter and Saturn.
described in equal times. Suppose now these triangles are infinite in
number and infinitely small so that the centripetal force acts without a Theorem 3**^
break, to the individual intervals of time corresponding individual
If the body P [Fig. 3] circulating about the centre 5 describes some
triangles, and the proposition will be established.
curved line APO , and if the straight line PR touches that curve in a
Theorem 2'' certain point P, and if from any other point O of the curve OR is drawn
to the tangent parallel” to S P and the perpendicular O T is dropped on
The centripetal forces of bodies revolving uniformly in the circum­
to the line SP: I say that the centripetal force will be inversely as the
ferences of circles are as the squares of the arcs described in the same
SP^xOT^
time divided by the radii of the circles. ratio---- — , provided only the quantity of that ratio is always taken
Suppose the bodies B, b [Fig. 2] revolving in the circumferences of the
as that which it becomes in the limit when the points P and O coincide.
circles BD, hd describe arcs BD, hd in the same time. By the action of
For in the indefinitely small figure O R PT the little line OR varies for
" 1 lyp oth fsis J. Ivemm.i r. a given time with the centripetal force,” and with the square of the time
280 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 281
when the force is given,^ and therefore when neither is given varies along the tangent. In a spiral which cuts all its radii at a given angle a
conjointly as the centripetal force and the square of the time, that is as centripetal force directed to the eye of the spiral is inversely as the third
the centripetal force directly and the area S O P proportional to the time power of the distance, but at the actual eye there is no line of determinate
(or the double of this area S P x OT) squared. Let each side of this pro­ position which touches the spiral.
portionality be applied to the little line QR and the centripetal force and
SP^xQT^ Problem
together make unity, that is the centripetal force is inversely
QR Given a body revolving in the ellipse of the ancients, there is required
SP^xOT^ the law of centripetal force directed to the centre of the ellipse.
as - . Q.E.D.
QR Let CA, CB [Fig. 5] be the semi-axes of the ellipse, GP, D K conjugate
Corollary. Hence if any particular figure is given and a point in it to diameters, PF, Ot perpendiculars to the diameters, Q V the ordinate
which the centripetal force is directed, it can be found what law of centri­ applied to the diameter G P and Q VPR a parallelogram. By these con­
petal force makes the body revolve in the perimeter of that figure. structions it will follow (by conic sections) that PV. VG 'i^toQV^ as PC^
SP^xO T^ to and QV^ to Q u as PC^ to PF^,^^ and taking these ratios together
Clearly the ratio — proportional to this force is to be calculated.
PV. VG to OU as PC^ to CD^ and PC^ to PF^, that is VG to as PC^
We shall give examples of this result in the following problems.
CD^xPF^
to . Writing OR for P F “ and B C X CA for CD X PF, and also
Problem PC~^
If a body revolves in the circumference of a circle there is required the (since the points P and 0 coincide) 2PC for VG and multiplying the
law of centripetal force tending to a certain point in the circumference. extreme and middle terms together, there results
Let S Q P A [Fig. 4] be the circumference of the circle, S the centre OVXPC^ 2BC^-x CA^
of the centripetal force, P the body carried in the circumference, and Q OR PC
the next place into which it will be moved. Drop perpendiculars PK^ Q T 2BC^ x CA^
Therefore the centripetal force is inversely as PC , that is (since
to the diameter S A and to SP, and through O draw LR parallel to S P
cutting the circle in L and the tangent P R in R, and let TQ, P R meet 2BC^ x CA^ is given) as — that is directly as the distance PC. Q.E.I.
in Z. On account of the similarity of the triangles ZQR, ZT P , SPA,
RP^ (that is OR.RL) will be to QT^ as SA^ to SP^, Therefore Prob. 3^^
O R .R L x S P ^ Given a body revolving in an ellipse there is required the law of
OT^
SA^ centripetal force directed to a focus of the ellipse.
SP^ Let S [Fig. 5] be the superior focus of the ellipse. Draw S P cutting the
Multiplying these equal quantities by and writing S P for RL as the
QR diameter D K of the ellipse in E. E P evidently equals the semi-major axis
AC, for drawing H I parallel to E C from the other focus, H, of the ellipse,
points P and Q coincide, one has . Therefore the
^ ^ SA^ OR ES, E l are equal because of the equal lines CS, CH, so that EP is half
SPs the sum of PS, P I that is (on account of the parallels HI, PR and the
centripetal force is inversely as that is (since SA^ is given) as the
equal angles IPR, HPZ) of PS, PH which together make up the whole
fifth power of the distance SP. Q.E.I. axis 2^C. Drop the perpendicular Q T to SP. And calling the latus
Scholium.'^ Moreover in this and like cases it is to be supposed that
rectum of the ellipse |or j L, L x QR to L x P V will be as QR to P V
after the body reaches S it will not return again in its orbit but go off

® Lemma 2 . “ By Lemma 4 .
282 ^rilE 'i 'R A C T DE MOTLJ IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T H 283
that is as P E (or A C ) to P C and L x P V to G V .V P as L to G V ar.d multiplied by a [certain] number of moments become equal to the whole
G V .V P to Q V- as CP~ to CD~. And OV^ to as M to A^, say, and areas. Therefore complete revolutions in ellipses are performed in the
Ox- to OT^ as EP^ to PF^, that is as CA^ to PF-, or“ as CD^ to CB-, same time as in circles whose diameters are equal to the transverse axes
and taking all these ratios together L X Oi? to QT^ as A C to P C x L to of the ellipses.25 But (by Cor. 5 Theorem 2) the squares of the periodic
G V X CP^ to C D ^ x M to N x CD^ to CB^ that is as A C x L (or zBC^) to times in circles are as the cubes of the diameters. And so also in ellipses.
P C x G V x CP^ to C B - x M to N, or z P C to G V x A l to N. But when Q.E.D.
the points P and O coincide the ratios z P C to G V and M t o N both equal Scholium. Hence in the celestial system from the periodic times of
unity: therefore the combined ratio of all these is L X OR to 0 T-. Multi­ the Planets the proportions of the transverse axes of the orbits become
plying both parts by there results L X S P ^ = . There­
known. It will be permissible to assume [the magnitude] of one axis.
t j ^ r j OR QJl Then the others will be given. But if the axes are given the orbits will
fore the centripetal force is inversely as Z>X S P - that is as the square be determined in this manner. Let S [Fig. 7] be the position of the sun
of the distance SP. Q.E.I. or one focus of the ellipse. A, B, C, D the positions of the planet found
Scholium. Therefore the major planets revolve in ellipses having a focus from observation and O the transverse axis of the ellipse. With centre A
in the centre of the sun and radii drawn to the sun describe areas pro­ radius Q — A S let the circle EG be described and the other focus of the
portional to the times, all as supposed by Kepler. And the latera recta ellipse will be in its circumference. With centres B, C, D, etc., and
OT- distances O — B S , 0 ~ C S , 0 — D S etc., let so many other circles be
of these planets equal the points Pand O being the least possible and
OR ^ similarly described and that other focus will be in all their circumferences,
as it were infinitely small distance apart. and so in their common intersection F. If all the intersections do not
coincide, the mean point will have to be taken for the focus. The con­
Theorem 4'^
venience of this procedure is that very many observations can easily be
Given that the centripetal force is inversely proportional to the square brought together and used to produce a single conclusion. Moreover the
of the distance from the centre^® the squares of the periodic times in individual position A, B, C, D etc., of the planet can be found from pairs
ellipses vary as the cubes of the transverse axes. of observations, given the great orbit of the Earth, as shown by Halley.26
Let A B [Fig. 6] be the transverse axis of the ellipse, P B the other axis, If that great orbit is not yet determined with sufficient accuracy,27 then
L the latus rectum, S one of the foci, and suppose the circle PM D with knowing it approximately the orbit of any other planet, for example
centre S and radius S P be drawn. And in the same time suppose the two Mars, will be determined more accurately: Then from the orbit of the
revolving bodies describe the elliptical arc PQ and the circular PM , the planet the orbit of the Earth will be determined still more nearly: then
centripetal force being directed to the focus S. PR, P N touch the ellipse from the orbit of the Earth the orbit of the planet will be determined
and the circle at P. Draw OR, Af A parallel to P S meeting the tangents in more accurately than before: and so by turns until the intersections of
R and iV. But the figures POR, P M N are indefinitely small so that (by the circles in the focus of both orbits agree sufficiently well.28
the Scholium to Problem 3) we have L X OR — OT^ and zSP^^ X MA^ = By this method the orbits of the Earth, Mars, Jupiter, and Saturn
MV^. On account of their common distance S P from the centre S and can be determined, but the orbits of Venus and Mercury thus: from
the resulting equality of the centripetal forces MA' and OR are equal.22 observations made at the maximum separation of the planets from the
Therefore O T- to MV^ is as L to zSP, and O T to M V as the mean pro­ Sun the tangents of the orbits are given. To such a tangent K L [Fig. 8]
portional between L and zS P or PD to zSPX^ That is the area S PO is a perpendicular SL is dropped from the Sun and with centre L, and radius
to the area S P M as the whole area of the ellipse to the whole area of the the semi-axis of the ellipse, a circle K M is described. The centre of the
circle.24 But the portions of area generated in individual moments are as ellipse will be in the circumference of this circle,2‘>and so when several
the areas SPO and SPM , and hence as the total areas, and hence when circles have been described in this way the centre will be given by the
" By Lemma 4. intersection of them all. Finally, knowing the dimensions of the orbits.
284 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX TH E T R A C T DE M O T U 285
the longitudes of these planets will be determined later more exactly by body is such that the latus rectum L equals 2SP-\-2KP, the figure will
their transit across the Sun’s disc.3° be a parabola having its focus in the point S and all its diameters parallel
to PH. If the body is projected with even greater speed, it will be moved
Problem 431 in a hyperbola having one focus in the point S and the other in a point H
Given that the centripetal force is inversely proportional to the square chosen on the other side of the point P, and having its transverse axis
of the distance, and knowing the magnitude of that force, required to equal to the difference between P S and PH.
find the ellipse which a body describes when projected from a given point Scholium. Now truly with the help of the solution of this problem it
with given velocity in a given straight line. is possible to define the orbit of comets, and thence their periodic times,
Suppose the centripetal force directed to the point S [Fig. 9] be such and by comparison of the orbital magnitudes, eccentricities, aphelions,
that a body tt may be made to revolve in a circle ttx centre S with any inclinations to the plane of the eclipse, and nodes to recognise if the same
radius S tt?^ Suppose the body P be projected from the point P along comet returns to us frequently. Certainly from four observations of the
the line PR and is thereupon immediately deflected by the action of the comet’s position on the hypothesis that the comet moves uniformly in a
centripetal force into the ellipse PQ. P R therefore touches this ellipse straight line37its rectilinear path may be determined. 38 Let that [path] be
at P. Let the straight line np likewise touch the circle at tt, and let PR be A P B D [Fig. 10], and let A, P, B, D be the positions of the comet at the
to TTp as the initial speed of the projected body P to the uniform speed of times of observation, and S the position of the sun. Now imagine the
the body tt.33 Draw RQ and px parallel to iSPand Sn, respectively, the comet projected from the point P with that speed with which it uniformly
one cutting the circle in the other the ellipse in O, and from O and x traverses the line AD , and constrained immediately by the centripetal
drop perpendiculars Q T and yT to S P and S t t . Then RQ is to px as the force to deviate from the straight path and go off into the ellipse Pbda.
centripetal force in P to the centripetal force at 77,34 that is as S tt^to SP^, This ellipse is to be determined as in the above problem .39 In it let a, P, b, d
and so that ratio is given. The ratios Q T to RP^^ and R P to prr or x'T_ are be the places of the comet at the times of observation. The longitude and
also given, and hence the composite ratio Q T to x"J- To this ratio squared latitude of these points relative to the Earth are known. By how much
Q T^ greater or less than these are the longitudes and latitudes of observation,
apply the given ratio QR to xp and there will remain the known ratio so much greater or less than observation are the new longitudes and
QR
X'~j2 latitudes to be chosen. From these new [positions] the rectilinear path of
to --A- that is (by Scholium Problem 3) the ratio of the latus rectum of
XP the comet is to be found anew, and hence the elliptical path as before.
the ellipse to the diameter of the circle. The latus rectum of the ellipse is And the four new positions in the elliptical path diminished or increased
therefore known. Let that be L. The focus S of the ellipse is also known. by the former errors now agree well enough with observation.4^ But if it
Let the angle R PH be the complement of the angle R P S to two right happens that sensible errors still remain the whole process can be repeated.
angles, and the line P H in which the other focus lies is given as regards And that the calculation may not be burdensome to astronomers it will
position. Then the perpendicular S K to P H having been dropped and suffice to determine everything by geometrical drawing.
the semi-minor axis B C being erected it follows that SP^— 2KP.PH-\^ But it is difficult to assign the areas aSP, PSb, bSd, proportional to
PH^ = SH^ = = {S P + P H Y -L x{S P + P H ) = the times. On the major axis EG [Fig. 11] of the ellipse let the semicircle
2S P .P H + P H ^ ~ L {S P + P H ). Adding to both sides 2K P .P H + EHG be described. Let the angle E CH be set proportional to the time.
L (S P + P H )-S P ^ -P H ^ there results L x { S P + P H ) = 2 P S .S H + Draw SH and C K parallel to it cutting the circle in K . Join H K and (by
zK P .P H or S P + P H to P H as 2SP-^2K P to L. And so the other a table of segments or secants) make the triangle S K N equal to the cir­
focus H is known. But given one focus together with the transverse axis cular segment H K M . Drop N Q perpendicular to EG, and in it choose
SP-\-PH the ellipse is known. Q.E.I. PQ to N Q as the minor to the major axis of the ellipse, and the point P
This is the way when the figure is an ellipse. But it can happen that will lie on the ellipse, and the line 5 P having been drawn an area E P S of
the body moves in a parabola ora hyperbola.3^ Thus if the speed of the the ellipse is cut off proportional to the time. For the area H SN M
286 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 287
increased by the triangle S N K and diminished by the equal segment the line DC, then the time may be represented by the area A B G D and
H K M makes up the triangle H SK , that is the equal triangle H SC . To the space described in that time by the line AD. For the resistance of the
these equal parts add the area E S H making the areas EH N S and EH C medium is proportional to the speed, and the decrease of the speed is
equal. Since therefore the sector EH C is proportional to the time, and proportional to the resistance,44 that is, if the time is divided into equal
the area E P S proportional to EHNS,^^ the area E P S will also be pro­ parts, the speeds at the beginnings of these parts are proportional to
portional to the time. their differences. Therefore the speed decreases in geometrical propor­
Problem 5^2 tion^* as the time increases in arithmetical proportion. But such is the
decrease of the lines D C and the increase of the area AB G D , as is well
Given that the centripetal force is inversely proportional to the square
known. Therefore the time can properly be represented by the area and
of the distance from the centre to define the spaces described in given
the speed by that line. Q.E.D. Moreover the increment of the space
times by a body falling straight to the centre.
described is proportional to the speed and so to the decrement of the
If the body does not fall down perpendicularly let it describe an
speed; but the increment of the line A D is proportional to the decrement
ellipse, A P B say [Fig. 12] whose inferior focus, say S, coincides with the
of the line DC. Therefore the increment of the space is represented by
centre [of force]. This follows from what has already been proved. On
the increment of the line AD, and thus the space itself is rightly repre­
the major axis A B of the ellipse let the semicircle A D B be described, and
sented by that line. Q.E.D.
through the falling body passes the line D P C perpendicular to the
axis, and D S, P S being drawn, the area A S D will be proportional to the Problem 7^5
area A S P and so also to the time. Retaining the a.xis A B let the width Given a uniform centripetal force, to define the motion of a body
of the ellipse be decreased steadily, and the area A S D will always remain ascending and descending rectilinearly in a uniformly resisting medium.
proportional to the time. Let the width be decreased indefinitely and the I'or the ascending body let the centripetal force be represented by a
orbit A P B now coinciding with the axis AB , and the focus S with the certain given rectangle B C [Fig. 14] and the resistance of the medium at
end B of the axis, the body descends in the straight line A C and the area the beginning of the ascent by the rectangle BD taken on the other side.
A B D comes out proportional to the time. And so the space A C which With rectangular asymptotes A C , CH let an hyperbola be drawn through
the body describes in falling perpendicularly from the position A in a. the point B cutting the perpendiculars DE, de in G, g, and the body in
given time may be defined, provided only the area A B D is taken propor­ ascending in time DGgd covers a distance EGge, and in time D G BA the
tional to the time, and from the point D the perpendicular D C is let fall space of the whole ascent EGB, and in time AB^G^D a distance of de­
to the line AB . Q.E.F. scent BE^G, and in time ^D^G^g^d the space of descent ^GEe^g: and the
Scholium. By the preceding problem the motions of projectiles in our speed of the body, proportional to the resistance of the medium, will be
air are defined, and the motions of heavy bodies falling perpendicularly in the ends of these times ABED , ABed, zero, ABE^D, ABe^d ; and so the
on the hypothesis that gravity is inversely proportional to the square of greatest speed that the body is able to acquire in descending will be BC.
the distance from the centre of the earth and that the medium of the air For if the rectangle A H [Fig. 15] is split up into innumerable rectangles
in no wise resists. For gravity is one species of centripetal force. Ak, Kl, Lm, Mn etc., which are proportional to the increments of the
Problem speed made in the like number of equal times, then Ak, Al, Am, An etc.
will be as the total speeds and therefore'^ as the resistances of the medium
To define the motion of a body carried along by its innate force alone
in a uniformly resisting medium. at the end of the individual equal times. So that A C is to A K , or A B H C
to A B k K as the centripetal force to the resistance at the end of the first
Let a hyperbola be described with rectangular asymptotes A D C , CH
[Fig. 13] cutting the perpendiculars AB , D C in B, G. I.et both the speed time, and ABH C, KkH C, LIHC, NnHC etc., will be as the absolute
forces by which the body is impelled, and so as the increments of the
of the body and the resistance of the medium at the beginning of the
motion be represented by the line A C , and after some lapse of time by L e m m a [ 3 ]. Hypothesis.
288 THE T R A C T DE M OTU IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 289
speed, that is as the rectangles Ak, Kl, Lm, Mn etc., and hence" in If the ratio of the resistance of the air to the force of gravity is not yet
geometrical progression. Therefore if the lines Kk, LI, Mm, Nn produced known, the angles AD P, AFr in which the curve DarFk cuts the
meet the hyperbola in rj. A, v etc., the areas AB-qK, KqXL, LXjxM, horizontal line D C may be discovered (by some experiment). On DE
MixvN etc., will be equal, and so analogous both to the equal times and let a rectangle DFsE of any altitude be drawn and a rectangular
to the constantly equal centripetal forces. Subtracting the areas Ak, Kl, hyperbola of such a form that one of its asymptotes is DF, that the areas
Lm, Mn analogous to the total forces there remain the areas Bkq, kqXl, DFsE, D F S B G are equal, and that 56” be to EG as the tangent of the
IXfxm, mfxvn etc., analogous to the resistances of the medium at the end angle AFr to the tangent of the angle AD P. From the centre C of this
of the individual times, that is to the speeds and so to the spaces hyperbola drop a perpendicular C l to the line DP, and from the point B
described. Taking the sum of analogous parts the areas Bkq, BIX, Bmfx, where the curve cuts the line Es drop a perpendicular B A to the line DC,
Bnv etc., will be analogous to the total spaces described, and besides the and the ratio sought for, namely the initial resistance of the medium to
areas A B qK , ABXL, ABjxM, ABvN etc., will be analogous to the times. the gravity of the projectile, will be given by D A to C l. All which things
The body therefore in descending for a certain time ABXL covers a dis­ may easily be sought out from what has already been proved. And there
tance BIX, and for a time LX(in a distance Xlnv [sic]. Q.E.D. And the are other methods of determining the resistance of the air which I gladly
demonstration of the motion in ascending is similar to that just given. pass over. However, after this resistance has been determined in one case
Scholium. By the help of the last two problems the movements of pro­ it is to be taken in all others proportional jointly to the velocity and the
jectiles in our air are known on the hypothesis that the air is homogeneous surface of the sphere (for I assume throughout the projectiles to be
and that gravity acts uniformly and in parallel straight lines. For if the spherical) whereas the force of gravity is known through the weight. And
total motion of the body is separated into two, the one ascent or descent, so the ratio of the resistance to the gravity on the line D A to the line C l
the other a progressive horizontal one; the latter motion will be deter­ is always known. By this ratio and the angle A D P the form of the figure
mined by Problem 6, and the former by Problem 7, as in this diagram. D arFKLP is determined and taking the length D P proportional to the
Let the body be projected from any place D [Fig. 16] along any line velocity of the projectile on the point D its size; so that the altitude Aa
DP, and let its speed at the beginning of the motion be represented by of the maximum elevation of the projectile and the length D F of the
the length DP. From the point P let the perpendicular P C be dropped horizontal length between the ascent and face of the projectile are
to the horizontal line DC, so that the ratio of the perpendicular C l to always in proportion, and so the length D F measured once in the open
D A is as the resistance of the medium at the beginning of the motion determines both the length D F itself and all the dimensions of the figure
to the force of gravity. Erect the perpendicular A B of any length and DarFK which the projectile describes in the open. But in calculating
having completed the parallelograms D ABE, C A B H describe through these dimensions logarithms are to be used in place of the hyperbolic
the point B an hyperbola with asymptotes DC, C P cutting in G. Take area DRTBG.
the ratio of line n to EG as D C to CP, and at any point R of the line D C By the same argument may be determined the motion of bodies moving
erect a perpendicular R tT cutting the hyperbola in T and the line EH in water under the simultaneous action of gravity or levity and any
. j . . , DvtE—DRTBG r r ii 1 • -i •
other force.
m t, and m it take Rr = ------------------ . 1 hen the projectile in time
n 1 . See V . H I , D e f. i . It is fittin g that N e w to n should b egin w ith the definition
o f vim centripetam giv en that the central proposition correspon din g to K e p le r ’s
D R TB G will arrive at the point r, describing a curved line DarFK
first tw o laws o f p lanetary m otion is concerned w ith such forces. It is interest­
which always touches the point r, reaching also to its maximum altitude in g also that now here in an y versions o f the tract de M o tu does N ew to n em p loy
a in the line AB , and from thence encountering the horizontal line D C the term centrifugal force.
2. See V . H I , D e f. 2.
at F (where the areas DFsE, D F S B G are equal) and afterwards always
3. See V . H I , D e f. 3.
approaching the asymptote PH CL. And its speed at any point r is pro­ 4. T h e corresponding version o f this hypothesis in V . H I is at L e x 5. T h e
portional to the tangent to the curve rL. definition o f resistance proportional to the v elocity corresponds to that used in
Prob. 6, 7.
" Lemma 3 .
290 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 291
5. See V . I l l , Lex i. 22. Sin ce th ey are the deviations from the inertial paths p roduced b y ecjual
6. A rather obscure form ulation o f the p arallelogram law for the com position forces in equal tim es.
o f indep en den t m otions given as Lemma i in V . I I I . Q TJ _ L QT
^ {L IzS P ) - ^j{{L K z S F ) ! { z S P - ) ]
7. C o rrespo n din g to K e p le r ’s second law o f planetary m otion. N o tic e the M V^ ■ ■ zS P M V
absence o f any reference in the enunciation to the planar nature o f the m otion QT PD
b u t V (T . z S P ) = \!{{2b~la)';<2a)} = 2b = P D .'.
8. N o tic e the absence o f an y ju stification o f this beautiful construction w h ich M V zS P '
depends on an application o f the parallelogram law referred to in the correspon d­ A re a S P Q QT PD 77 P D S P A rea of ellipse
24.
in g Prop. I, T h e o r . i , in the lectures de Motii and the Principia. T h e o n ly place A re a S P M M V z S P "" 2 tt S P ^A rea o f circle
w here the ju stification is giv en in detail is in the L o ck e c o p y o f the original o f 25. In other w ords, if is the com m on tim e to describe areas S P Q and
M S. V III. , ,1- . • . A A re a o f ellipse
S P M , the tim es o f revolution in the ellipse and circle are M x — 7------ >
9. C o rresp o n d in g to Prop. 4, T h e o r . 4, o f the lectures de Motu and the Prin­ A re a S P Q
cipia and to the sam e p roposition in V . I I I . T h e germ o f the p resent p ro o f has
M X ^---------respectively, and these are equal ow in g to the result
already been n oted in M S . IV a . B u t n o w all m en tion o f centrifugal conatus has A re a o f S P M
disappeared, the deviation CD, cd, directed to the centre, and n ot aw ay from it as A rea o f S P Q A rea o f ellipse
in M S . IV a g iv in g the measures o f the correspon din g centripetal forces. I t is also A re a o f S P M A re a o f circle
n otew orth y that ( i) neither here n or in the lectures de Motu nor the Principia is
an y ju stification offered for the proportionality betw een the deviation and the N o te that the specially favourable choice o f P at the end o f the m in or axis does
centripetal force, (2) the fact that the directions o f the ‘ deviation ’ are n ot quite n ot invalidate the p ro of since the central nature o f the force ensures that the
parallel to those o f the forces is ignored. F o r a discussion o f N e w to n ’s use o f the rates o f description o f area in b o th the circle and the ellipse are constant.
‘d eviatio n ’ as a m easure o f force see above Part I, C h a p ter 1.3, p p . 1 9 -2 2 . 26. I have been unable to trace the m etho d referred to here b y N ew to n .
10. C o rrespo n d in g to the sam e proposition in V . I l l , and to Prop. 5, T h e o r . 5, 27. Im p ly in g that the transverse axis is o n ly kn ow n approxim ately, and
o f the lectures de Motu (M S . X I ) . likew ise the positions A , B , C , D , so that the various circles w ill not quite
1 1. N o tic e the difference betw een this m etho d o f constructin g the ‘d e via tio n ’ intersect in a single point.
and that em p loyed in Prop. 2. 28. T h e success o f the m ethod sketched w o u ld depend on the convergence
12. O n ce again, as in Prop. 2, no ju stification is given for this assum ption. o f the series o f approxim ations w h ich w o u ld in turn be in dicated b y an im pro ve­
13. C o rrespo n din g to the same p roblem in V . I l l , and to Prop. 7, Prob. i, o f m en t in the closeness o f intersection o f the circles for the E arth and the Planet.
the lectures de Motu. N o n ew points o f dyn am ical interest arise in this and the 29. A s follow s at once from the bisector p ro perty o f the tan gen t and the
tw o su bsequ en t problem s. result S P + P H = za .
14. N o tic e the m asterly w a y in w h ich N e w to n deals w ith the m otion o f the 30. T h e im portance o f the transit o f an inferior p lanet across the sun’ s disc
Scholium is m issin g from
b o d y after reach ing the centre o f force. C u rio u sly this for determ in ing its true apparent m agn itude was recognized b y H orrox as early
the correspon din g problem in the lectures de Motu and the Principia. as 1639. See the extract in S h ap le y and H o w arth [i], p p . 58 -62 .
15. C o rrespo n din g to the same p roblem in \'^ III, and to the Scholium to 31. Co rrespo n din g to the same proposition in V . I l l , to Prop. 16, Prob. 8, o f
Prop. 7, Prob. 2, o f the lectures de Motu. the continuation to M S . X I , and to Prop. 17, Prob. g. B ook I, P rin cip ia
16. N o tic e how fundam ental this result was for N e w to n ’s treatm en t o f the ( is t edn.).
ellipse. 32. B u t to k n o w this circular m otion its uniform speed m u st have been
17. S in ce the angles QtV, PFC are rig h t angles, and LQVt = Z PCF by observed, or the exact form ulae for centripetal force, in clu d in g the mass d e p en ­
parallels. dence, m u st be know n. T h is represents a weakness o f the present m ethod.
18. T h e fact that N e w to n nam es this central proposition, corresponding to 33. T h u s ensuring that the arcs P Q , ttx are described in equal times.
K e p le r ’s first law o f p lanetary m otion, a problem is an indication o f the extrem e 34. Sin ce these deviations are generated in equal tim es, as noted in note
logicality o f his th o u g h t and n ot o f any failure to realize its im portance, as b e ­ 33 above.
comes evident from the Scholium. See the same proposition in V ersion I I I and 35. T h is ratio b ein g the tan gen t o f the given inclination o f the initial p ath to
Prop. 8, Prob. 5, o f the lectures de Motu. I t w ill be n oticed that apart from the SP.
tw o results for ellipses already em p loyed in Prob. 2, viz. that referred to in note 36. It w o u ld be interesting to kn ow how N e w to n arrived at this result.
16, and the co nstan cy o f the area o f circu m scribed parallelogram s, the o n ly n ew P o ssibly it was on the basis o f the im m ed iately su cceed ing consideration o f the
properties em p loyed are those o f the tan gen t bisectin g the exterior angle ratio o f z S P h 2 K P to L .
form ed b y the focal lines through its p oin t o f contact, and o f the sum o f the two 37. R igau d [i], p. 29, took this to m ean that N e w to n still b elieved in recti­
focal distances b ein g equal to the len gth o f the m ajor axis. linear paths for com ets at the tim e o f com posin g the tract de M o tu in spite o f the
19. C o rrespo n din g to the same p roposition in V . I l l , and to the rather deduction o f the elliptical paths o f the planets in that work. B u t an exam ination
different p ro o f in Prop. 15, T h e o r . 7 , o f the lectures de Motu. o f the su cceed in g argum en t show s that the rectilinear hypoth esis is only em ­
20. M e a n in g the centre o f force as opp osed to the centre o f the ellipse. p lo yed as a first approxim ation to the actual elliptical orbit. T h e p roblem o f
21. 7 / for a circle b ein g equal to the diameter. com ets caused N e w to n m uch trouble— witness the fo llo w in g passage in his
PLATE 5
292 THE T R A C T DE M O T V IX
\ U T>';,
letter o f 20 June 1686 to H a lley : T h e third zvatits y e T heory o f C om ets, h i A u tu m n
last [r6tS\5] I spent tzvo months in calculations to no purpose fo r zvant o f a good
m ethod. . . . H is treatm ent o f the problem in the P rin cip ia ((is t edn.), B ook H I ,
p p. 4 7 4 -e n d ) is pure!}’ m athem atical and is free from the weakness o f the present
m ethod w ith its assum ption o f an exact kn ow ledge o f the central force. It is
based on the su bstitu tion o f an approxim ate parabolic path for the actual
elliptical orbit o f the com et. T h is was p resu m ably the good m ethod N e w to n had
searched for in vain in the autum n o f 1685.
38. A s shown, for exam ple, b y N e w to n in Prob. 56 o f his A rith m etica U n iv er­
salis, a reference g iv e n b y R igau d [i], p. 29.
39. A s poin ted ou t above (note 32), this assumes a kn ow ledge o f the actual
value o f the cen trifugal force w h ich cou ld scarcely have been available to
'“H
N ew to n . I* J- ijf
40. It is n ot clear w h y the n ew elliptical p osition should be increased or d e­
creased b y the form er errors. N o r is it at all certain that the com plicated double
process o f approxim ation here envisaged w o u ld necessarily converge tow ards t .* v ^ vi.
the p ath o f the com et.
C-rl-
4 1. F ro m the m etho d o f construction o f the ellipse it follows that

A rea E H N Q a ^ A rea S N Q
so that b y subtraction
A rea E P Q ^ b‘ A rea S P Q
* «».v£ci
Area ^ N S _ ' ■— * cXmd*^.*4tx.
A r ea E P E ~ ree/* (Sc ^
42. C o rresp o n d in g to the same p roblem in V . H I , to Prop. 21, Prob. 13, o f the t y^u - Jv* *<«.w**< ^ ^
continuation jS^to M S . X I , and to Prop. 32, Prob. 24, Book I, Prin cip ia ( is t edn.).
43. C o rrespo n din g to the same problem in V . H I , and to Prop. 2, T h e o r . 2,
fc cL fic , r j m . a ^
B ook I I , P rin cip ia ( i st edn.). T h e interest o f this and the succeed ing p ro blem is
largely m athem atical. For a detailed interpretation in terms o f the calculus see
f
'T }’0«
Correspondence, vol. ii, pp. 4 5 9 -6 2.
■ y\e/04 VC A«-
44. F ro m the second law o f m otion.
45. C o rrespo n din g to the same p roblem in V . H I , and to Prop. 3, Prob. i.
Prop. 4, Prob. 2, o f B ook I I , P rin cip ia ( i st edn.).
A«cc A.v^r^ ----------- 5^'^ ^

2. C o m p a r is o n of V ersions I an d II I u , .j
In the first place, it is clear that V. II must have been composed after
X , Ct-rluf-wCCHi ii^grW ,
V. I. This is conclusively proved by the fact that with one exception
wherever there are deletions in V. I, V. II follows the final rather than
the original draft. Apart from this the texts of the two versions are so Cthpmym. **
nearly identical wherever they can be compared that V. II must have
been copied directly from V. I, or from another manuscript elTectively
identical with the emended draft of that version. And the one exception $ c jc L r
referred to above (note hg-hg) in which V. II follows the original <^>v« p>.fjp9 Ur
rather than the final draft of V. I, makes it probable that V. II was ' ^ ‘^ '■ '‘ - y ..— r-/’-. <Oi» Jut sH
^ c i. , Q ^ CH, id . rH * T <tl f
actually copied from V. I. V. II is also definitely not in Newton’s hand. ^^ ^«.0 ^ ^ 11^ _ ^
There are, however, a certain number of substantial differences -h ;" - 4-c-r ir c r , i ./
h 04
between the two versions: e n s U P Y r»jp0h'C tf ,

T h e first folio o f the tract de M o tu


IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 293
(«) Following the definitions and hypotheses in V. II— identical with
those in V. I— there is a complete list of the enunciations of the theorems
and problems of V. I. The corollaries to Theorem 2 are given in this list
and not after the theorem itself, as in V. I. Also, the enunciations to the
two lemmas numbered 3 and 4 are found at the end of the list. These
agree with those in V. III.
(b) The Scholium to Prop. 2 of V. I is absent from V. II.
{c) V. II lacks the last two problems of V. I though the enunciations
of these are given in the preliminary list of contents.
{d) Unlike the free-hand diagrams in V. I those in V. II were drawn
with instruments and differ in certain respects from those in V. I. For
example, T and t are interchanged in diagram 5 (note t^), and with one
exception (note rg) care has been taken to allow for this in the subsequent
proof (note b2). Also in Diag. 9 of V. II K lies on H P produced as op­
posed to between H and P as in V. I. Once again careful allowance has
been made for this possibility by the appropriate introduction of + and
— signs (notes Zo, bg).
(e) Certain insertions in V. I are missing from V. II but given in V. I ll
(notes pi-pi, Ui, Zi^Zi).
Apart from the differences noted above there are a certain number of
unimportant differences between the two versions such as small variations
in spelling, punctuation and use of capital letters, the use of ii in place
of ij, the absence of footnotes in V. II, and the omission in V. II of a
small number of words.
T o summarize: with the exception of that part of the list of contents
after the definitions and hypotheses, and the absence of the last two
problems, V. II was copied from V. I or another effectively identical
manuscript. This copying took place before the composition of V. I ll
((e) above) although the enunciations of Lemmas 3 and 4 in V. II were
presumably added after the composition of V. III. The copyist was
evidently something more than a mere amanuensis, for he had a real
acquaintance with mathematics, as evidenced by the changes noted in
notes Zo, bg, and also with Latin, as witness his attempts to improve the
clarity of the text— see note Vg. For some reason or other he omitted
the whole of the Scholium to Theor. 2, possibly an oversight. Judging
by the presence of their enunciations in the preliminary list. Problems
6 and 7 formed part of V. II originally, but have since become separated
from it.
It must be emphasized finally that V. II nowhere goes beyond V. I as
294 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX 4'HE T R A C T DE M O T U 295
regards dynamical content. Its interest, if any, is therefore purely his­ Lex 5.'^ Resistentiam medii esse ut medii illius densitas et corporis
torical. In fact, a case can be made out for identifying it with the originals moti sphaerica superficies et velocitas conjunctim.
of the set of propositions carried by Paget from Newton to Halley towards Lemma Corpus viribus conjunctis diagonalem parallelogrammi
the end of 1684. A discussion of this is given above in Part I, Chapter 6.6. codem tempore describere quo latera separatis.
Si corpus dato tempore vi sola m [Fig. i] ferretur ab A ad 5 , et vi sola
n ab A ad C, compleatur parallelogrammum A B D C , et vi utraque
3. V ersion III feretur id eodem tempore ab A ad D. Nam quoniam vis n agit secundum
De Motu Sphaericorum Corporum in fluidis lineam A C ipsi BD parallelam, haec vis, per Legem 2, nihil mutabit

Except for the small number of variants already noted in the alpha­ C
betical footnotes in § i, the greater part of V. I l l is a faithful copy of the
final emended draft of V, I. There are, however, some substantial
additions in V. I l l compared with V. I. Some of these represent impor­
tant conceptual advances in Newton’s dynamical thought, such as the
change in status of the parallelogram law from an hypothesis in V. I to
a derived lemma in V. III. These additions are reproduced below with
relevant footnotes in three sections. Section A consists of the preparatory
definitions, laws, and lemmas of V. III. These are largely new although
certain of the definitions and axioms of V. I reappear in the same or
slightly different guise. The remaining sections B and C represent two
Figure i.
large insertions in V. I ll compared with V. I.
celeritatem accedendi ad lineam illam B D vi altera impressam. Accedet
A igitur corpus eodem tempore ad lineam BD sive vis A C imprimatur
sive non, atque adeo in fine illius temporis reperietur alicubi in linea ilia
Def. 1.^ Vim centripetam appello qua corpus attrahitur vel impellitur
BD. Eodem argumento in fine temporis ejusdem reperietur alicubi in
versus punctum aliquod quod ut centrum spectator,
linea CD, et proinde in utriusque lineae concursu D reperiri necesse est.
Def. 2,^ Et vim corporis seu corpori insitam qua id conatur perseverare
in motu suo secundum lineam rectam. Lemma 2.^^ Spatium quod corpus urgente quacunque vi centripeta
Def. 3.^ Et resistentiam quae est medii regulariter impedientis. ipso motus initio describit esse in duplicata ratione temporis.
Def. 4.^ Exponentes quantitatum sunt aliae quaevis quantitates pro- Exponantur tempora per lineas AB , A D [Fig. 2]. Datis Ah, Ad pro-
portionales expositis. portionales,^- et urgente vi centripeta aequabili exponentur spatia
Lex I.'"' 5 Sola vi insita corpus uniformiter in linea recta semper per- descripta per areas rectilineas ABT", A D H perpendiculis BF, DH, et
gere si nil impediat. recta quavis A F H terminatas, ut exposuit Galilaeus.'^ Urgente autem vi
Lex 2.^ Mutationem^ status movendi vel quicscendi proportionalem centripeta inaequabili exponantur spatia descripta per areas ABC, ADE,
esse vi impressae et fieri secundum lineam rectam qua vis ilia imprimitur. curva quavis A C E quam recta A F H tangit in A, comprehensas. Age
Lex 3.^ Corporum dato spatio inclusorum eosdem esse motus inter rectam AE, parallelis BF', bf, dh occurrentem in G, g, e, et ipsis bf, dh
se sive spatium illud quiescat sive moveat id perpetuo et uniformiter in occurrat A F H producta in / et h. Quoniam area A B C major est area
directum absque motu circulari. A B F, minor area AB G , et area curvilinea A D E C major area AD H
Lex Mutuis corporum actionibus commune centrum gravitatis non minor area ADFJG, erit area A B C ad aream AD E G major quam area
mutare statum suum motus vel quietis. Constat ex Lege 2. ABF' ad aream ADEG, minor quam area A B G ad aream ADH, hoc est
296 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE M O T U 297
major quam area A bf ad aream Ade, minor quam area Abg ad aream
B
Adh. Diminuantur jam lineae A B , A D in ratione sua data usque dum
puncta Al, B, D coeunt, et linea Ae conveniet cum tangente Ah, adeoque At the end of the Scholium to Theorem 4 is the following paragraph;
ultimae rationes A bf ad Ade et Abg ad Adh evadent eaedem cum ratione Caeterum totum coeli Planetarij Spatium vel quiescit (ut vulgo
A bf ad Adh. Sed haec ratio est dupla rationis Ab ad Ad, seu A B ad AD. creditor) vel uniformiter movetur in directum et perinde Planetarum
Ergo ratio A B C ad A D E C ultimis illis intermedia jam fit dupla rationis commune centrum gravitatis (per Legem'^ 4) vel quiescit vel una move­
tur. Utroque in casu motus Planetarum inter se (per Legem'' 3) eodem
modo se habent, et eorum commune centrum gravitatis respectu spatij
totius quiescit, atque adeo pro centro immobili Systematis totius
Planetarij haberi debet. Inde vero systema Copernicaeum probatur a
priori. Nam si in quovis Planetarum situ computetur commune centrum
gravitatis hoc vel incidet in corpus Solis vel ei semper proximum erit.
Eo Solis a centro gravitatis errore fit ut vis centripeta non semper
tendat ad centrum illud immobile, et inde ut planetae nec moveantur in
Ellipsibus exacte neque bis revolvant in eadem orbita. Tot sunt orbitae
Planetae cujusque quot revolutiones, ut fit in motu Lunae et pendet
orbita unaquaeque ab omnium Planetarum motibus conjunctis, ut
taceam eorum omnium actiones in se invicem. Tot autem motuum
causas simul considerare et legibus exactis calculum commodum admit-
tentibus motus ipsos definire superat ni fallor vim omnium humani
i ng enii .Omi tt e minutias illas et orbita simplex et inter omnes errores
mediocris erit Ellipsis de qua jam egi. Siquis hanc Ellipsin ex tribus
observationibus per computum trigonometricum (ut solet) determinate
tentaverit, hie minus caute rem aggressus fuerit. Participabunt observa-
tiones iliac de minutijs motuum irregularium hie negligendis adeoque
Ellipsin de justa sua magnitudine et positione (quae inter omnes errores
A B ad AD, id est ratio ultima evanescentium spatiorum seu prima
mediocris esse debet) aliquantulum deflectere facient, atque tot dabunt
nascentium dupla est rationis temporum."
Ellipses ab invicem discrepantes quot adhibentur observationes trinae.
Lemma 3. Quantitates difFerentiis suis proportionales sunt continue Conjungendae sunt igitur et una operatione inter se conferendae obser­
proportionales. vationes quam plurimae, quae se mutuo contemperent et Ellipsin
Ponatur A ad A —B ut B ad B — C, tt C ad C —^D etc. et dividendo positione et magnitudine mediocrem exhibeant.
fiet A ad B ut B ad C, et C ad D, etc.
Lemma 4. Parallelogramma omnia circa datam ellipsin descripta esse C
inter se aequalia. At the end of problem 5 and before problem 6 is the following
Constat ex Conicis. Scholium:
Next come eleven propositions. The first nine of them are headed De Schol. Hactenus motum corporum in medijs non resistentibus exposui;
motu corporum in medijs non resistentibus. The last two are headed De motu id adeo ut motus corporum coelestium in aethere determinarem.
corporum in medijs resistentibus. Except for the following additions, the Aetheris enim puri resistentia quantum sentio vel nulla est vel perquam
text is substantially the same as that in Version I. exigua. Valide resistit argentum vivum, longe minus aqua, aer vero longe
298 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX THE T R A C T DE MOTU 299
adhuc minus.'5 Pro densitate sua quae ponderi fere proportionalis est habere conlirmavit, deflectente semper gravi a perpendiculo versus
atque adeo (paene dixerim) pro quantitate materiae suae crassae resistunt orientem et austrum ut in latitudine nostra boreali oportuit.
haec media. Minuatur igitur aeris materia crassa et in eadem circiter
a. In this an d the other lazvs L e x has been substituted f o r H y p . deleted.
proportione minuetur medij resistentia usque dum ad aetheris tenuitatem
b. P reced ed by insertion M o tu u m gen itu m deleted.
perventum sit. Celeri cursu equitantes vehementer aeris resistentiam c. R eplacin g H y p . deleted.
sentiunt, at ^^navigantes exclusis e mari interiore ventis'*^ nihil omnino ex
aethere praeterfluente patiuntur. Si aer libere interflueret particulas Translation
corporum et sic ageret, non modo in externam totius superficiem, sed etiam
The Motion of Spherical Bodies in Fluids
in superficies singularum partium, longe major foret ejus resistentia.
A
Interfluit aether liberrime nec tamen resistit sensibiliter. Cometas
infra orbitam Saturni descendere jam sentiunt Astronomi saniores quot- Definition i . H call centripetal that force by which a body is attracted or
quot distantias eorum ex orbis magni parallaxi praeterpropter colligere impelled towards any point which is regarded as a centre [of force].
norunt; hi igitur celeritate immensa in omnes coeli nostri partes in- Definition 2.^ And I call that the force of a body or the force innate in a
differenter feruntur, nec tamen vel crinem seu vaporem capiti circum- body by reason of which it endeavours to persist in its motion along a
datum resistentia aetheris impeditum et abreptum amittunt. Planetae straight line.
vero jam per annos millenos in motu suo perseverarunt, tantum abest Definition 3.^ And the resisting force that arising from the steadily
ut impedimentum sentiant. impeding medium.
Demonstratis igitur legibus reguntur motus in coelis. Sed et in aere
Definition The representatives of quantities are any other quantities
nostro, si resistentia ejus non consideratur, innotescunt motus proje-
proportional to those under consideration.
ctilium per Prob. 4 et motus gravium perpendiculariter cadentium per
Prob. 5 posito nimirum quod gravitas sit reciproce proportionalis qua- Law 1.5 By its innate force alone a body will always proceed uniformly
drato distantiae a centro terrae. Nam virium centripetarum species una in a straight line provided nothing hinders it.
est gravitas; et computanti mihi prodijt vis centripeta qua luna nostra Law 2.^ The change in the state of movement or rest [of a body] is pro­
detinetur in motu suo menstruo circa terram ad vim gravitatis his in portional to the impressed force and takes place along the straight line
superficie terrae, reciproce ut quadrata distantiarum a centro terrae in which that force is impressed.
quamproxime.^^ Ex horologij oscillatorij motu tardiore in cacumine Law 3.^ The relative motions of two bodies contained in a given space
montis praealti quam in valle liquet etiam gravitatem ex aucta nostra are the same whether the space in question rests or moves perpetually
a terrae centro distantia diminui, sed qua proportione nondum obser- and uniformly in a straight line without circular motion.
vatum est. Law 4.^ By the mutual actions between bodies the common centre of
Caeterum projectilium motus in aere nostro referendi sunt ad im- gravity does not change its state of motion or rest. It follows from Law 2.
mensum et revera immobile coelorum spatium, non ad spatium mobile
Law 5.'^ The resistance of a medium is proportional conjointly to the
quod una cum terra et aere nostro convolvitur et a rusticis ut immobile
density of the medium, the speed, and the spherical surface of the body
spectator. Invenienda est Ellipsis quam projectile describit in spatio illo
moved.
vere immobili et inde motus ejus in spatio mobili determinandus. Hoc
pacto colligitur grave, quod de aedificij sublimis vertice demittitur, Lemma A body acted on simultaneously by [two] forces describes the
inter cadendum deflectere aliquantulum a perpendiculo, ut et quanta sit diagonal of a parallelogram in the same time as it would the sides if the
ilia deflexio et quam in partem. Et vicissim ex deflexione experimentis forces acted separately.
comprobata colligitur motus terrae. Cum ipse olim hanc deflexionem If the body were carried in a given time from A [Fig. i] to B by the
Clarissimo Hookio significarem,^^ is experimento ter facto rem ita se force m alone, and from A to C by the force n alone, then completing the
300 THE T R A C T DE M O T U IX IX ^niE TRAC/r DE M O T U 301

parallelogram AB D C, it will be carried by both forces in the same time Lemma 4. All parallelograms drawn about a given ellipse are equal.
from A to D. For since the force n acts along the line AC, parallel to BD, It follows from conic sections.
this force, by Law 2, will nowise change the speed of attaining that line B
BD induced by the other force. Therefore the body will attain to the line Moreover the whole space of the planetary heavens either rests (as is
BD in the same time whether a force is impressed in A C or not, and commonly believed) or moves uniformly in a straight line, and hence the
therefore at the end of that time it will be found somewhere in that line communal centre of gravity of the planets (by Law 4) either rests or
BD. By the same argument at the end of the same time it will be found moves along with it. In both cases (by Law 3) the relative motions of
somewhere in the line CD, and hence it must be found at the intersection the planets are the same, and their common centre of gravity rests in
of the two lines. relation to the whole of space, and so can certainly be taken for the still
Lemma 2.” The distance a body describes from the beginning of its centre of the whole planetary system. Hence truly the Copernican system
motion under the action of any force whatsoever is in the duplicate ratio is proved a priori. For if the common centre of gravity is calculated for
of the time. any position of the planets it either falls in the body of the Sun or will
Represent the times by the lines AB , A D [Fig. 2]. Let Ab, A d be always be very close to it. By reason of this deviation of the Sun from
proportionah^ to these lines, then when [the body is] acted on by a uniform the centre of gravity the centripetal force does not always tend to that
centripetal force the distances covered will be represented by the rect­ immobile centre, and hence the planets neither move exactly in ellipse nor
angular areas A B F , A D H terminated by the perpendiculars BF, D H revolve twice in the same orbit. So that there are as many orbits to a
and a certain line AFH , as shown by Galileo. But when acted on by a planet as it has revolutions, as in the motion of the Moon, and the orbit
non-uniform centripetal force the distances covered will be represented of any one planet depends on the combined motion of all the planets, not
by areas A B C , ADE, terminated by a certain curve A C E which A F H to mention the action of all these on each other. But to consider simul­
touches at A. Draw a line A E cutting the parallels BF, bf, dh at G, g, e taneously all these causes of motion and to define these motions by exact
and let A F H produced meet these same bf, dh at / and h. Since the area laws allowing of convenient calculation exceeds, unless I am mistaken,
A B C is greater than the area A B F and less than the area A B C , and the the force of the entire human intellect.’ ^ Ignoring those minutiae, the
curvilinear area A D E C is greater than the area A D H and less than the simple orbit and the mean among all errors will be the ellipse of which
area ADEG, the ratio of the area A B C to the area AD EG will be greater I have already treated. If anyone tries to determine this ellipse by trigo­
than the ratio of area A B F to area ADEG, and less than the ratio of area nometrical computation from three observations (as is customary), he
A B G to ADH, that is greater than area Ahfto the area Ade, and less than will have proceeded without caution. For these observations will share
area Abg to area Adh. If now the lines AB, A D are diminished while in the very small irregular motions here neglected and so cause the
maintaining their ratio until the points A, B, D coincide and the line Ae ellipse to deviate somewhat from its actual magnitude and position (which
coincides with the tangent Ah, the limiting ratios Abf to Ade and Abg ought to be the mean among all errors), and so there will be as many
to Adh will coincide with the ratio Abf to Adh. But this ratio is the square ellipses differing from each other as there are trios of observations em­
of the ratio Ab to Ad, or A B to AD. Therefore the ratio A B C to A D E C ployed. Very many observations must therefore be joined together and
intermediate between these limits now becomes the square of the ratio assigned to a single operation which mutually moderate each other and
A B to AD, that is the limiting ratio of the evanescent spaces or the first display the mean ellipse both as regards position and magnitude.
ratio of the vanishing spaces is the square of the ratio of the times.

Lemma 3. Quantities proportional to their differences are continually Scholium. Thus far I have considered the motion of bodies in non­
proportional. resisting media: so that I may determine the motion of celestial bodies
Assuming A to A ~ B as B to B ~ C , and C to C — D etc., then by in ether. But as far as I can judge the resistance of pure ether is either
division we have A to ^ as /? to C, and C to D etc. nothing or excessively small. Quicksilver resists strongly, water much
302 THE T R A C T DE M O T U iX IX THE T R A C T DE MOTU 303
less, air certainly far less again, These media resist according to their released from the top of a high building will deviate a little from the
density which is almost proportional to their weight and so they resist vertical in falling, and also how much that deflection will be and to what
(or rather almost resist) according to the quantity of their solid matter. side. And conversely from experimental evidence of this deflection the
Therefore as the solid matter of air is diminished so is the resistance of [diurnal] movement of the earth is inferred. When I myself formerly
the medium and in about the same proportion up to the point that it pointed out this deflection to the most excellent Hook,’^he confirmed the
attains to the tenuity of ether. In swift flight horsemen feel the violent matter to be so by an experiment performed three times, the deflection
resistance of the air, but '^sailors inside the ship when the winds are in the heavy body being always from the vertical towards the east and
excluded!^ feel nothing at all of the ever flowing ether. If air were to south as in our northern latitude it should.
penetrate the parts of bodies freely and so were to act not only in the
1. S e e M S . X a , D e f. 16.
external surface of the whole but also in the surfaces of the individual 2. See M S . X a , D e f. 12.
parts, its resistance would be far greater. Now ether penetrates freely 3. See M S . X a , D e f. 17.
4. See M S . X a , D e f. 18.
but does not offer sensible resistance. That comets descend below the
5. See M S . X a , L e x i.
orbit of Saturn is the opinion of all those sounder astronomers who know 6. See M S . X a , L e x 2.
how to calculate their approximate distance from the parallax of the 7. See M S . X a , L e x 4.

great orbit: these comets are therefore carried with immense speed k See M S . X a , L e x 5.
9. See M S . X a , L e x 6.
indifferently in all parts of our heavens yet do not lose their tail nor the 10. See M S . X a , L e m m a i . A p a rt from a reference to L a w 2 n ot fo und in the
vapour surrounding their heads [by having them] impeded or torn away p resent p ro o f the tw o versions are identical. N o tice that the forces referred to in
by the resistance of the ether. And the planets actually have now per­ this lem m a are n ot continuous b u t im pulsive.
1 1 . See M S . X a , L em m a 2.
sisted in their motion for thousands of years, so far are they from ex­
12. T h e phrase is som ew hat obscure b u t it is probable that b, d are intended
periencing any resistance. to b e any tw o points on the line su ch that A b / A d = A B j A D . T h is is confirm ed
Motions in the heavens are ruled therefore by the laws demonstrated. e x p licitly in the pen ultim ate sentence o f the proof. T h e s e points are introduced
w ith the ultim ate lim itin g process in v i e w ; b, d are to b e kep t fixed w h ile By D
But the motions of projectiles in our air, ignoring its resistance, are
ten d to A so that A B j A D remains fixed and therefore equal to A b j A d .
known by Problem 4, and also the motions of heavy bodies falling per­ 13. See above, Part I, C h a p ter 2 .1. N e w to n , how ever, w as m istaken in su p ­
pendicularly by Problem 5, given of course that gravity is inversely p osing that G alileo ever gave a satisfactory proof o f the M e r to n R u le . It seems
proportional to the square of the distance from the centre of the earth. likely that Beeckm an w as the o n ly person to do so in the seven teen th century.
H is p ro of rem ained un kn ow n till the rediscovery o f his Journal b y de W aard.
For certainly gravity is one kind of centripetal force: and my calculations 14. C u rio u sly rem iniscent o f the line from L u cretiu s on R o u b ilia c ’s statue o f
reveal that the centripetal force by which our Moon is held in her monthly N e w to n in the chapel o f T r in it y C o llege , C am b rid ge— Qui genus humanumm
motion about the Earth is to the force of gravity at the surface of the earth ingenio superavit.
15. C f. M S . V I , § 8, first sentence.
very nearly as the reciprocal of the square of the distance [of the Moon]
1 6 -1 6 . T h e phrase is obscure. P o ssibly N e w to n th o u gh t o f the exclusis e mari
from the centre of the Earth. From the slower motion of oscillating a p p lyin g to the navigantes. A ltern a tive ly e mari could be an error for in nave.
clocks in the tops of very high mountains than in valleys it is clear also 17. C o m pare the p reced in g sentence w ith M S . V I , § 8, third paragraph.

that gravity is diminished by an increase in our distance from the centre 18. T h e first explicit reference b y N e w to n to this experimentiim crucis o f his
theory o f gravitation.
of the earth, but in what proportion has not yet been observed. 19. A reference to the correspondence w ith H ooke in the w in ter o f 1679.
Moreover the motions of projectiles in our air are to be referred to
the immense and truly immobile space of the heavens, not to the movable
space which turns round with the earth and our air and is commonly
regarded as at rest. The ellipse which the projectile describes in that truly
immobile space is first to be found, and then its motion in the mobile
space must be determined. Knowing this it is inferred that a heavy body
Xa D E F I N I T I O N S AND L AW S OF MOTION 305
omnium loca. In tempore quoad ordinem successionis, in spatio quoad
X ordinem situs locantur universa. De illorum essentia est ut sint loca et
Xa D R A F T S OF D E F I N I T I O N S A N D loca primaria mover! absurdum est. Porro vi illata moveatur una pars
spatij et vi tanta ad omnes in infinitum partes applicata movebitur totum,
LAWS OF M O T I O N
quod rursus absurdum est.
Xb D R A F T S OF D E F I N I T I O N S Def 4 Spatium relativum est quod respectu rei alicujus sensibilis con­
sideratur ut immobile: uti spatium aeris nostri respectu terrae. Distin-
T h e s e two manuscripts, referred to hereafter as MSS. Xa and Xb,
guuntur autem haec spatia ab invicem ipso facto per descensum gravium
clearly preceded the lectures de Motu,-\ constituting preliminary drafts
quae in spatio absoluto recta petunt centrum in relative absolute gyrante
of parts of the Definitions and Axioms of that work. It is also probable
deflectunt ad latus.
that they succeeded Version III of the tract de Motu. The actual order
of composition of the two manuscripts seems to be of no great impor­ Def 5'* Corpora in sensus omnium incurrunt ut res mobiles quae se
tance, but it will be convenient to give them in their probable order of mutuo penetrare nequeunt.
composition, namely Xa followed by Xb. Although there is a certain
Def 6^'^ Centrum corporis cujusque est quod vulgo dicitur centrum
amount of overlap between the two manuscripts, each contains material
gravitatis et axis corporis est linea quaevis recta per centrum transiens.
not found in the other. In particular, Xa alone contains drafts of the
discussion of absolute space, time and motion in the Scholium to the Def 75 Locus corporis est pars spatij in quo corpus existit, estque pro
Definitions of Book I of the Lectures de Motu (and the Principia), and genere spatij vel absolutus vel relativus.
of the Laws of Motion, whereas Xb consists largely of drafts of the
Def 8^ Quies corporis est perseverantia ejus in eodem loco, estque vel
Definitions.
absoluta vel relativa pro genere loci.
Both manuscripts contain a considerable number of insertions and
alterations. Def 9’ Motus corporis est translatio ejus de loco in locum, estque itidem
vel absolutus vel relativus pro genere loci. Distinguitur autem ipso facto
M S . Xa^ motus absolutus a relatiVO in gyrantibus, per conatum recedendi a centre,
D e M otu Corportim in m edijs regu la riter cedentibus quippe qui ex gyratione nude relativa nullus est, in relative quiescentibus
permagnus esse potest, ut in corporibus coelestibus quae ex mente
Cartesianorum^ quiescant, tamen a sole recedere conantur. Conatus ille
Definitiones
certus semper et determinatus arguit certam aliquam et determinatam
Def 12 Tempus absolutum est quod sua natura absque relatione ad
esse motus realis quantitatem in singulis corporibus, a relationibus quae
aliud quodvis aequabiliter fluit. Tale est, cujus aequationem investigant
innumerae sunt totidemque motus relatives constituunt minime pen-
Astronomi, alio nomine dictum Duratio.
dentem. Porro motum et quietem absolute dictos non pendere a situ et
Def 2^ Tempus relative spectatum est quod respectu fluxionis seu relatione corporum ad invicem manifestum est ex eo quod hae nunquam
transitus rei alicujus sensibilis consideratur ut aequabile. Tale est tempus mutantur nisi vi in ipsum corpus motum vel quiescens impressa, tali
dierum mensium et aliarum periodorum caelestium apud vulgus. ante vi semper mutantur; at relativae mutari possunt vi solummodo
Def 3 Spatium absolutum est quod sua natura absque relatione ad impressa in altera corpora ad quae sit relatio et non mutari vi impressa
aliud quodvis semper manet immobile, Ut partium temporis ordo in utraque sic ut situs relativus conservetur.
immutabilis est sic etiam partium spatij, Moveantur hae de locis suis et Def Velocitas^ est quantitas translationis quoad longitudinem itineris
mo\ ebuntur de seipsis. Nam tempora et spatia sunt suiipsorum et rerum certo tempore confecti. Iter vero est quod corporis puncto medio
t The reasons for this and succeeding assertions a.bout order of composition are describitur a Geometris dicto centro gravitatis. Loquor de motu
fii\ en aho\ e in Part I, Cliapter 6 .3 . progressive.
306 D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION Xa Xa D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION 307
Def i i ‘° Quantitas motus est quae oritur ex velocitate et quantitate et relativas ab invicem sedulo distinguere necesse fuit eo, quod phaeno-
corporis translati conjunctim. Aestimatur autem quantitas corporis^ ^ ex mena omnia pendeant ab absolutis. Vulgus autem qui cogitationes a
copia materiae corporeae quae gravitati suae proportionalis esse solet. sensibus abstrahere nesciunt semper loquuntur de relativis, usque adeo
Pendulis aequalibus numerentur oscillationes corporum duorum ejus- ut absurdum foret vel sapientibus vel etiam Prophetis apud bos aliter
dem ponderis, et copia materiae in utroque erit reciproce ut numerus loqui. Unde et sacrae literae et scripta Theologorum de relativis semper
oscillationum eodem tempore factarum.^^ intelligenda sunt, et crasso laboraret praejudicio qui inde de rerum
Def 12*3 Corporis'^ vis insita innata et essentialis est potentia qua id naturalium motibus absolutis PhilosophicisJ disputationes moveret.*^
perseverat in statu suo quiescendi vel movendi uniformiter in linea recta,
Leges Motus
estque corporis quantitati proportionalis, exercetur vero proportionaliter
mutationem status et quatenus exercetur dici potest corporis vis exer- Lex 1^1 Vi insita corpus omne^ perseverare in statu suo quiescendi vel
cita . . . cuius [?] una species est vis centrifuga*^ gyrantium. movendi uniformiter in linea recta nisi quatenus viribus impressis’"
cogitur statum ilium mutare. Motus autem uniformis hie est duplex,
Def i3*s.e Vis motus seu corpori ex motu sua adventitia est qua corpus
progressivus secundum lineam rectam quam corpus centro suo aequa-
quantitatem totam sui motus conservare conatur. Ea vulgo dicitur
biliter lato describet et circularis circa axem suum quemvis qui vel
impetus estque motui proportionalis, et pro genere motus vel absoluta
quiescit vel motu uniform! latus semper manet positionibus suis prioribus
est vel relativa. ^Ad absolutam referenda est vis centrifuga gyrantium^.
parallelus.
Def 14*6’^ Vis corpori illata et impressa est qua corpus urgetur mutare
Lex 2^2 Mutationem motus proportionalem esse vi impressae et fieri
statum suum movendi vel quiescendi estque diversarum specierum ut
secundum lineam rectam qua vis ilia imprimitur. Hisce duabus Legibus
pulsus seu pressio percutientis, pressio continua, vis centripeta, resi-
jam receptissimis Galilaeus invenit projectilia gravitate uniformiter et
stentia medij etc.
secundum lineas parallelas agente, in medio non resistente lineas Para-
Def 161*7 Vim centripetam appello qua corpus impellitur vel attrahitur bolicas describere. Et suffragatur experientia nisi quatenus motus pro-
versus punctum aliquod quod ut centrum spectatur. Hujus generis est jectilium resistentia aeris aliquantulum retardatur. Ab.
gravitas tendens ad centrum terrae, vis magnetica tendens ad centrum
Lex 3^3 Corpus omne tantum pati reactione quantum agit in alterum.
magnetis et vis coelestis cohibens Planetas ne abeant in tangentibus
Quicquid premit vel trahit alterum, ab eo tantum premitur vel trahitur.
orbitarum.
Si vesica acre plena premit vel ferit alteram sibi consimilem cedet
Def 17*8 !' Per medij Resistentiam in sequcntibus intelligo vim medij utraque aequaliter introrsum.'^ Si corpus impingens in alterum vi sua
regulariter impedientis. Sunt et aliae vires ex corporum elasticitate, mutat motum alterius et ipsius motus (ob aequalitatem pressionis
mollitie, tenacitate etc., pendente quas hie non considero. mutuae) vi alterius tantum mutabitur. Si magnes trahit ferrum ipse
Def 162*'^’ * Momenta quantitatum sunt ipsarum principia generantia vel vicissim tantum trahitur et sic in alijs. Constat vero haec Lex per Def. 12
alterantia fluxu continue: ut tempus praesens praeteriti et futuri, motus et 1424 in quantum vis corporis ad status sui conservationem exercita sit
praesens praeteriti et futuri, vis centripeta aut alia quaevis momentanea eadem cum vi in corpus alterum ad illius statum mutandum impressa,
impetus, punctum lineae, lineae superficiei, superficies solidi et angulus et vi priori proportionalis sit mutatio status prioris posteriori ea pos-
contactus anguli rectilinei. terioris.
Def 18 Exponentestemporumspatiorum, motuum celeritatum et virium Lex 4-3 Corporum dato spatio inclusorum eosdem esse motus inter se
sunt quantitates quaevis proportionales exponendis.^** sive spatium illud absolute quiescat sive moveat id perpetuo et uni­
Haec omnia fusius explicate visum est ut Lector praejudeijs [r/c] formiter in directum absque motu circulari. E.g. motus rerum in navi
quibusdam vulgaribus liberatus et distinctis principiorum Mechanicorum perinde se habent sive navis quiescat sive moveat ea uniformiter in
conceptibusimbutusaccederet ad sequentia. Quantitates autem absolutas directum.
308 D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION Xa Xa D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION 309
Lex 526 Mutuis corporum actionibus commune centrum gravitatis non a. T here are a considerable number o f unim portant an d p a rtly illegible deletions
mutare statum suum motus vel quietis. Haec lex et duae superiores se in the original text o f this definition.
mutuo probant. b. Introdu ced a t some tim e a fter com position o f present D e f. i S as proved by the
renumbering o f a ll D e f. 7 - 1 8 .
Lex 627.0 Resistentiam medij esse ut medij illius densitas et sphaerici c. R ep lacin g celeritas m otus deleted.
corporis moti superficies et velocitas conjunctim. Hanc legem exactam d. Preceded by V is corporis seu deleted.
e. T h is section deleted.
esse non affirmo. Sufficit quod sit vero proximo. Corpora vero Sphaerica
f - f . T h is section deleted.
esse suppono in sequentibus, ne opus sit circumstantias diversarum g. O rig in ally num bered 1 3 an d changed to 1 5 , presum ably in error f o r 1 4 .
figurarum considerare. h . T h is section deleted.
i. D eleted , presum ably after introduction o f previous D e f. 1 6 , as the number 1 6
Lemmata has not been altered.
Lem. Corpus viribus conjunctis diagonalem parallelogrammi eodem j. W ritten above absolutus.
k. Succeed ed by P erinde est ac si quis lunam [(in G em in i) ?] m agn itudin e non
tempore describere quo latera separatis.
apparente sed absoluta inter duo m axim a lum ina [G em in i ?] num erari co n -
tenderet cancelled.
l. S u b stitu ted f o r sem per deleted.
m . Succeed ed by im pedim entis deleted.
n. S u cceed ed by Si m agnes trahit ferrum ipsi vicissim tan tum trahitur deleted
an d inserted later belozc.
o. T h is section deleted.
p. E n ds abruptly here.
D

Translation

On the M otion o f B odies in uniform ly yield in g m edia


Definitions
B
Definition 12 Absolute time is that which according to its own nature,
Figu re i.
unrelated to anything else, flow's evenly. It is that whose equation
Si corpus dato tempore vi sola M ferretur ab ^ ad ^ [Fig. i] et vi astronomers investigate, and by another name is called duration.
sola N ab A ad C, compleatur parallelogrammum A B D C et vi utraque
Definition 2 Time regarded as relative is that which is uniform in
feretur id eodem tempore ab A ad D. Nam quoniam vis M agit secun­ respect of the flux or variation of any sensible thing. Such is the time of
dum lineam A C ipsi BD parallelam, haec vis nihil mutabit celeritatem days, months, and other periodic celestial phenomena as commonly
accidendi ad lineam illam BD vi altera impressam. Accedet igitur corpus
received.
eodem tempore ad lineam BD sive vis A C imprimatur sive non, atque
adeo in fine illius temporis reperietur alicubi in linea ilia BD. Eodem Definition 3 Absolute space is that which by its own nature and un­
argumento in fine temporis ejusdem reperietur alicubi in linea CD, et related to any other thing whatsoever always remains at rest. As the order
proinde in utriusque lineae concursu D reperiri necesse est. of temporal parts is immutable so also is that of parts of space. If these
were to move from their places they would move out of themselves. For
Lem. 229 Spatium quod corpus urgente quacunque vi centripeta ipso times and spaces are of themselves and all things the places. All things
motus initio describit, esse in duplicata ratione temporis. are located in time as regards order of succession, and in space as regards
Exponantur tempora per lineas AB, A D datis Ab Ad proportionales, order of situation. The essence of these is that they are positions and it
et urgente vi centripeta aequabili exponentur spatia descripta per areas is absurd that basic positions be moved. For example if one part of space
rectilineas A B F A D H perpendiculis.p mav be moved by a certain force then if an equal force be applied to all
310 D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION Xa Xa D E F I N I T I O N S AND L AW S OF MOTION 311
parts of space to infinity the whole of space will be moved, which is Definition lo^ Velocity is the quantity of translation as regards the
again absurd. length of path traversed in a certain time. Where of course the path is
that described by the middle point of the body called the centre of gravity
Definition 4 Relative space is that which is regarded as immobile in
by mathematicians, I speak of progressive motion.
relation to any sensible thing; such as the space of our air in relation to
the earth. However these spaces are in fact distinguished from each Definition ii**’ The quantity of motion is that which arises from the
other through the descent of heavy bodies which in absolute space seek velocity and quantity of a body conjointly. Moreover the quantity of a
the centre directly but in relative space rotating absolutely are deflected body” is to be estimated from the bulk of the corporeal matter which is
to one side. usually proportional to its gravity. The oscillations of two equal pendu­
lums with bodies of equal weight are counted, and the bulk of matter in
Definition 5^ By common consent bodies are moveable things unable to both will be inversely as the number of oscillations made in the same
penetrate each other. time.”
Definition 6“^ The centre of any body is what is commonly called its Definition 12” The internal and innate force of a body is the power by
centre of gravity, and the axis of a body is any straight line through the which it preserves in its state of rest or of moving uniformly in a straight
centre. line. It is proportional to the quantity of the body, and is actually exer­
cised proportionally to the change of state, and in so far as it is exercised
Definition 75 The place of a body is the part of space in which the body
it can be said to be the exercised force of the body, of which [ ?] one kind
exists, and according to the kind of space is absolute or relative.
is the centrifugal force” of rotating bodies.
Definition 8^ A body’s rest is its continuation in the same place, and Definition 13” The force of a body arising from its motion is that by
according to the kind of place is absolute or relative. which the body endeavours to preserve the total quantity of its motion.
Definition 9^ The motion of a body is its translation from one place to It is commonly called impetus and is proportional to the motion, and
another, and is consequently either absolute or relative according to the according to its kind is absolute or relative. The centrifugal force of
kind of place. But absolute motion is in fact distinguished from relative rotating bodies is to be referred to the absolute kind.
in circular motions by the endeavour to recede from the centre, which Definition 14^^ Force impressed on a body is that by which a body is
in an entirely relative circular motion is zero, but in a circular motion urged to change its state of moving or resting and is of divers kinds such
relative to bodies at rest may be very large, as in the celestial bodies as impulse or pressure of percussion, continuous pressure, centripetal
which the Cartesians® believe to be at rest, although they endeavour to force, resistance of medium etc.
recede from the sun. The fact that this endeavour [from the centre of
Definition ifij” I call centripetal force that by which a body is impelled
circular motion] is certain and determinate argues some certain and
or drawn towards a certain point regarded as centre. Of this kind is
determinate quantity of real motion in individual bodies in no wise
gravity tending to the centre of the earth, magnetic force tending to the
dependent on the relations [between the bodies] which are innumerable
centre of the magnet, and the celestial force preventing the planets from
and make up as many relative motions. For example, that motion and
flying off in the tangents of their orbit.
rest absolutely speaking do not depend on the situation and relation of
bodies between themselves is evident from the fact that these are never Definition 17^® By the resistance of the medium in the following I under­
changed except by force impressed on the body moved or at rest, and stand the force of a uniformly resisting medium. And there are other
are always changed after [the action of] such a force; but the relative forces arising from the elasticity, softness, tenacity etc., of bodies which
[motion and rest of a body] can be changed by forces impressed only on I do not consider here.
other bodies to which the relation belongs, and is not changed by a force Definition 162” The moments of quantities are their principles of gene­
impressed on both so that their relative situation is preserved. ration or alteration, as time present of the past and future, present
312 DEFIxNri’IONS AND L A W S OF MOTION Xa X;i D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION 313
motion of past and future motion, centripetal or any other momentary to itself both yield equally inwards. If a body impinging on another
force of impetus, as point of a line, a line of a surface, a surface of a solid, changes by its force the motion of the other then its own motion (by
and a contacting angle of a straight angle. reason of the equality of the mutual pressure) will be changed by the
same amount by the force of the other. If a magnet attracts iron it is
Definition i8 The representatives of times, spaces, motions, speeds and
itself equally attracted, and likewise in other cases. In fact this law
forces are any quantities whatsoever proportional to the things rep re­
follows from Definitions 12 and 14^4 in so far as the force exerted by a
sented
body to conserve its state is the same as the impressed force in the other
The aim of explaining all these things at length is that the reader may body to change the state of the first, and the change of state of the first
be freed from certain vulgar prejudices and imbued with the distinct is proportional to the first force and of the second to the second force.
principles of mechanics may agree in what follows to distinguish carefully
Law 425 The relative motion of bodies enclosed in a given space is the
from each other quantities which are both absolute and relative, a thing
same whether that space rests absolutely or moves perpetually and
very necessary since all phenomena depend on absolute quantities. But
uniformly in a straight line without circular motion. For example, the
ordinary people who fail to abstract thought from sensible appearances
motions of objects in a ship are the same whether the ship is at rest or
always speak of relative quantities, so much so that it would be absurd for
moves uniformly in a straight line.
wise men or even Prophets to speak to them otherwise [than of relative
quantities]. Hence both the sacred writings and theological writings are Law 52^ The common centre of gravity of [a number of] bodies does not
always to be understood in terms of relative quantities, and he who would change its state of rest or motion by reason of the mutual actions of the
on this account bandy words with philosophers concerning the absolute bodies. This law and the two above mutually confirm each other.
motions of natural things would be labouring under a gross misappre­ Law 6^7 The resistance of a medium is jointly proportional to the density
hension.
of that medium, the area of the moved spherical body and the velocity.
Lam of Motion- I do not assert this law to be exact. It suffices that it should be approxi­
mately true. Hereafter I actually suppose the bodies spherical lest it be
Lav^ 1 B y reason of its innate force every body preserves in its state of
a question of considering the states of different figures.
rest or of moving uniformly in a straight line unless in so far as it is
obliged to change its state by forces impressed on it. Uniform motion, Lemmata
however, is of tw'o kinds, progressive along a straight line which the body
Lemma A body acted on simultaneously by [two] forces describes
describes uniformly with its centre, and circular about a certain axis
the diagonal of a parallelogram in the same time as it would the separate
which either rests or with a motion of constant size always remains
sides.
parallel to its previous position.
If the body is carried in a given time by the force M alone from A
Law 2^^ The change of motion is proportional to the force impressed to B [Fig. i] and by the force N alone from A to C, then the parallelo­
and takes place along the straight line in which the force is impressed. gram A B D C being completed it will be borne by both forces in the same
By means of these two laws now widely acknowledged Galileo discovered time from A to D. For since the force M acts along the line A C parallel
that projectiles under a uniform gravity acting along parallel lines to BD, this force will nowise change the speed of attaining to that line
described parabolas in a non-resisting medium. And experiment sup­ BD impressed on it by the other force. The body will therefore attain
ports this unless in so far as the motion of the projectiles is a little to the line BD in the same time whether the force A C is impressed or
retarded by the resistance of the air. not, and so at the end of that time it will be found somewhere in that
Law 32-’ As much as any body acts on another so much does it experience line BD. By the same reasoning at the end of that time it will be found
in reaction. Whatever presses or pulls another thing by this equally is somewhere in the line CD, and thus it must be found in the inter­
pressed or pulled. If a bladder full of air presses or carries another equal section D of both lines.
314 D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION Xa Xa D E F I N I T I O N S AND L A W S OF MOTION 315
Lemma 2^^ The space described by a body from the beginning of its 22. C o rrespo n din g to the second law o f m otion, together w ith the germ o f
motion under the action of any force is proportional to the square of the the first part o f the S ch o liu m to the laws o f m otion in the lectures de M o tu and
time. the P rin cip ia .
23. A prim itive draft o f the third law o f m otion.
Let the times be represented by lines AB , A D to which Ab, Ad are 24. T h e reference here w o u ld seem to be to D e f. 12, 14 o f M S . X b .
proportional, then under the action of a uniform centripetal force the 25. C o rresp o n d in g to C o ro ll. 5 to the laws o f m otion in the lectures de
spaces described are represented by the rectilinear areas A B F , A D H by M o tu and the P rin cip ia .
26. C o rrespo n din g to C o ro ll. 4 to the laws o f m otion in the lectures de M o tu
the perpendiculars.
and the P rin cip ia .
27. C o rrespo n din g to Section I o f B ook I I o f the P rin cip ia .
1. M S . A d d . 3965 (5a), fols. 25, 26 (right half) 23, 24.
28. C o rrespo n din g to C o ro ll, i to the laws o f m otion in the lectures de M o tu
2. C o m pare this and the tw o fo llo w in g definitions w ith the corresponding ones
and the P rin cip ia .
in the Scholium to the D efinitions o f the lectures de Motu.
29. C o rrespo n din g to L e m m a X o f Sectio n I Book I o f the lectures de M o tu
3. C o m pare this w ith note (a) to D e f. 2 o f M S . V I . T h e r e is no correspon din g
and the P rin cip ia .
definition in the lectures de Motu or the Principia.
4. C o m pare w ith the original D e f. 3, later cancelled, o f the lectures de Motu
(M S. X I). M S . Xb^
5. C om pare this w ith D e f. 3 o f the Scholium to the D efinitions o f the lectures
de Motu and the Principia. De M otu C orporum
6. C o m pare this w ith D e f. 3 o f M S . V I . T h e r e is no corresponding definition
in the lectures de Motu or the Principia. Definitiones
7. T h e germ o f the celebrated attem p t to distin guish absolute from relative
m otion in the Scholium to the D efinitions o f (the lectures de Motu and) the
1.2 Quantitas materiae est quae oritur ex ipsius densitate et magnitudine
Principia.
8. T h is specific reference to the Cartesian p h ilo so p h y is significantly om itted conjunctim. Corpus duplo densius in duplo spatio quadruplum est.
both in the lectures de Motu and the Principia. Hanc quantitatem per nomen corporis vel massae designo.
9. N o definition o f v elo city is giv en either in the lectures de Motu or the
Principia. 2.3 Quantitas motus est quae oritur ex velocitate et quantitate materiae
10. C o rrespo n din g to D e f. 2, M S . X b , and to D e f. 4 o f the lectures de Motu. conjunctim. Motus totius est summa motuum in partibus singulis,
1 1 . C o m p a re the alternative definition o f qu a n tity o f m atter in D e f. i , o f M S .
adeoque in corpore duplo majore aequali cum velocitate duplus est et
Xb.
12. F o r a m ore detailed expression o f the same ideas see D e f. 7 o f M S . X b . dupla cum velocitate quadruplus.
13. A m ore detailed treatm ent o f this co n cep t is given in D e f. 3 o f M S . X b .
3. '^ Materiae vis insita est®potentia resistendi qua corpus unumquodque
14. T h e r e is a reference to centrifugal force as an exam ple o f the corporis
exercita in the cancelled definition 14 o f M S . X b , b u t no such reference occurs quantum in se est perseverat in statu suo vel quiescendi vel movendi
in D e f. 3 o f that m an uscript nor in the correspon din g definition o f the lectures uniformiter in directum: estque corpori suo proportionaliss neque differt
de Motu or the Principia. F o r a discussion o f N e w to n ’s concept o f cen trifugal
quicquam ab inertia massae nisi in modo conceptus nostri. Exercet vero
force see above, Part I, C h a p ter 3.
15. C om pare this w ith the cancelled D e f. 14 o f M S . X b . corpus hanc vim '^solummodo^ in mutatione status sui facta per vim
16. C o rrespo n din g to D e f. 4 o f M S . X b . aliam in se impressam estque Exercitum ejus Resistentia et Impetus
17. C o rresp o n d in g to D e f. 5 o f M S . X b . respectu solo ab invicem distinct!: Resistentia quatenus corpus reluc-
18. A n echo o f the corresponding definition in all versions o f the tract de
Motu. N o such definition is given in M S . X b , nor in B ook I o f the lectures de tatur vi impressae. Impetus'^ quatenus corpus difficulter cedendo conatur
Motu or the Principia. mutare statum corporis alterius. Vulgus apud resistentiam quiescentibus
19. N o trace o f this definition, later cancelled, is fo und in M S . X b nor in the et impetum moventibus tribuit: sed motus et quies ut vulgo concipiuntur
lectures de Motu or the Principia.
respectu solo distinguuntur ab invicem; neque vere quiescunt quae vulgo
20. C o m pare this w ith D e f. 4 o f V ersion I I I o f the tract de Motu. N o trace
o f it is fo u nd in M S . X b , or thereafter. tanquam quiescentia spectantur^.
21. C o rrespo n din g to the first law o f m otion. B u t the reference to tzvo
types o f uniform m otion, one rectilinear, the other circular, is not found else­
4. ® Vis impressa est "^actio in corpus exercita ad mutandum statum ejus
where. See above. Part I, C h a p ter 5, § 3. vel quiescendi vel movendi. Consistit haec vis in actione sola neque post
Xb D E F IN IT IO N S 317
316 DEFINITIONS Xb
reciproce ut numerus oscillationum eodem tempore factarum. Experi-
actionem permanet in corpore. Est autem diversarum originum, ut ex
mentis autem in auro, argento, plumbo, vitro, arena, sale communi,
impetu, ex pressione, ex vi centripeta.^'
aqua, ligno, tritieo, diligenter factis^ incidi semper in eundem oscilla­
5.9 Vis centripeta est vel actio vel potentia quaelibet qua corpus versus tionum numerum (ob hanc analogiam et defecta vocis commodioris
punctum aliquod tanquam ad centrum trahitur impellitur vel utcunque expono et designo quantitatem materiae per pondus etiam in corporibuss
tendit. Hujus generis est gravitas qua corpus tendet ad centrum terrae, quorum gravitatio non consideratur).
vis magnetica qua ferrum petit centrum magnetis, et vis ilia, quaecunque
Locus.
sit, qua Planetae retinentur in orbibus suis et perpetuo cohibentur ne
abeant in eomm tangentibus. Est autem vis centripetae quantitas triplex; 9. Quies.
absoluta, acceleratrix et inotrix. Quantitas absoluta (quae et vis absoluta 10. Motus.
dici potest) major est ad unum centrum minor ad aliud, nullo habito 11. Velocitas.
respectu ad distantias et magnitudines attractorum corporum; uti virtus
Quantitas motus est quae oritur ex velocitate et pondere corporis
magnetica major in uno magnete minor in alio. Quantitas seu vis acce­
translati conjunctim. Motus additione corporis alterius tanto cum motu
leratrix est velocitati proportionalis quam dato tempore generat; uti
fit duplus et duplicata velocitate quadruplus.
virtus magnetis ejusdem major in minori distantia minor in majori, vel
vis gravitatis major prope terram minor in regionibus superioribus. Quan­ 14.^-^ Corporis vis exercita est qua id conatur conservare* status sui
titas seu vis matrix est motus proportionalis quern dato tempore produ­ movendi vel quiescendi partem^ illam quam singulis momentis amittit
c t ; uti pondus majus in majori corpore minus in minore. Ita se habet estque status illius mutationi seu parti singulis momentis amissae pro­
igitur vis matrix ad vim acceleratricem ut matus ad celeritatem. Namque portionalis nec improprie reluctatio vel resistentia corporis dicitur.
oritur quantitas matus ex celeritate dueta in corpus mobile et quantitas vis Hujus^' una species est vis centrifuga gyrantium,
matricis ex vi acceleratrice ducta in idem corpus, ETnde juxta superliciem
a. S ucceed ed by inertia sive deleted.
terrae ubi gravitas acceleratrix in corporibus universis eadem est, gravi­ b - b . R eplacing an earlier and p a rtly illegible version.
tas motrix seu pondus est ut corpus: at si longius recedatur a terra, inque c - c . R eplacin g an earlier and p a rtly illegible version.
d -d . R eplacin g m ateriae abstracta consideratione deleted.
regiones ascendatur ubi gravitas acceleratrix fit minor, pondus pariter
e. Succeed ed by copiae m ateria deleted.
minuetur eritque semper ut corpus in gravitatem acceleratricem ductum. f. S ucceed ed by institutis reperi deleted.
Porro attractianes et impulsus eodem sensu acceleratrices matrices nomino. g. Preceded by non gravitantibus deleted.
Voces autem attractianis impulsus vel prapensianis cujuscunque in cen­ h. T h e headings only are given o f this an d the three subsequent definitions.
i. W ritten above is singulis m om en tis deleted.
trum indifferenter et pro se mutuo usurpo, has vires non physice sed
j. Su cceed ed by amissam deleted.
mathematice tantum considerando. Unde caveat Lector ne per hujusmodi k. Succeed ed by referenda deleted.
voces cogitet me speciem vel modum actionis causamve aut rationem
physicam alicubi definire, Translatian
6. ’'° Densitas corporis est quantitas seu copia materiae collata cum On the M otion o f B odies
quantitate occupati spatij. Defmitians
7. ” Per pondus intelligo quantitatem '^’seu copiam materiae movendae'^ 1.2 The quantity af matter is that arising conjointly from its density and
abstracta gravitationis consideratione quoties de gravitantibus non magnitude. A body twdce as dense in double space is four fold. This
agitur. Quippe'' pondus gravitantium proportionalc est quantitati quantity I designate by the name body or mass.
materiae et analoga per se invicem exponare et designare licet. Analogia
2.^ The quantity afmatian is that arising conjointly from the velocity and
vero sic colligabitur pendulis aequalibus numerentur oscillationes cor­
the quantity of matter. The total motion is the sum of the motion in
porum duorum ejusdem ponderis et copia materiae in utroque erit
318 DEFINITIOxNS Xb Xb DEFINITIONS 319
individual parts, and so in a body twice as large with the same velocity and the quantity of accelerative force from the accelerative force multiplied
[the motion] is double and with double velocity quadruple. into the same body. Hence near the surface of the earth where the
accelerative quantity is the same in all bodies, the motive gravity or
3.4 The internal force of matter is the power of resistance by means of
weight is as the body; but if one recedes further from the Earth, and
which any one body continues so far as it can in its state of rest or moving
ascends into regions where the accelerative quantity is less, the weight
uniformly in a straight line: and it is proportional to its bodys nor differs
at all from the inertia of matter except in our mode of conceiving it. In is diminished equally, and will always be as the body multiplied by the
fact a body only*^ invokes this force in changes of state produced in it by accelerative gravity. Moreover in the same sense I call attractions and
another force impressed on it, and its exercise is Resistance and Impetus impulses, accelerative and motive. And use the words attraction, impulse
which are distinct only in relation to each other; being resistance in so or propensity of any sort towards a centre indifferently and inter­
far as the body opposes itself to an impressed force, and impetus^ in so far changeably one for the other, considering these forces not in the physical
as the body by yielding with difficulty attempts to change the state of but only in the mathematical sense. Hence let the reader beware lest he
the other body. It is customary to attribute resistance to bodies at rest think that by words of this kind I define a type or mode of action or cause
and impetus to those in motion; but motion and rest as commonly con­ or physical reason of any kind,
ceived are distinct only in relation to each other: nor do those things truly 6. ’®The density of a body is the quantity or bulk of matter compared
rest which are regarded as if they rested by ordinary people. with the quantity of space occupied.
4.8 Impressed force is an action exercised on a body to change its state 7 . ” By the heaviness of a body I understand the quantity or bulk of
of rest or motion. This force consists truly in the action only, nor does matter moved apart from considerations of gravity as often as it is not
it remain in the body after the action. However it is of diverse origins, a matter of gravitating bodies. T o be sure the heaviness of gravitating
as of impetus, or pressure or centripetal force. bodies is proportional to their quantity of matter by which it can by
5.9 Centripetal force is a certain action or power by which a body is analogy be represented or designated. And the analogy can actually be
impelled or drawn or in any way tends towards a certain point as if to a inferred as follows. The oscillations of two equal pendulums of the same
centre: of this ilk is the gravity by which a body tends to the centre of weight are counted and the bulk of matter in each case will be inversely
the earth, the magnetic force by which iron seeks the centre of a magnet, as the number of oscillations made in the same time. But careful experi­
and that force, whatsoever it may be, by which the Planets are held in ments made on gold, silver, lead, glass, sand, common salt, water, lignite
their orbits and perpetually restrained from flying off at a tangent. and twill led always to the same number of oscillations. On account of
Moreover, there are three quantities of centripetal force: absolute^ this analogy and lacking a more convenient word I represent and desig­
accelerative and motive. The absolute quantity of a centripetal force nate quantity of matter by heaviness, even in bodies in which there is no
(which can also be called absolute force) is greater to one centre than question of gravity.
another, no attention being paid to the distances and the magnitudes of
8. Position,
the other bodies attracted; as the magnetic virtue is greater in one
magnet and less in another. The accelerative quantity ox force is propor­ 9. Rest.
tional to the velocity generated in a given time; as the power of the same 10. Motion.
magnet it is greater at a lesser distance less at a greater distance, or of the
11. Velocity.
force of gravity is greater near the Earth, less in the higher regions.
The motive quantity or force is proportional to the motion it produces in 12. ^^ The quantity of motion is that which arises jointly from the velocity
a given time; as of weight more in a larger body less in a smaller one. and quantity of matter of the moving body. The motion by addition of
Therefore motive force is to accelerative force as motion to speed, f'or another body of the same motion is double and with doubled velocity
quantity of motion is derived from speed multiplied by the body moved quadruple.
320 DEFINITIONS Xb

14.^3 The exercised force of a body is that by which it attempts to pre­


serve that part of its state of rest or motion which it gives up at particular XI
moments and it is proportional to the change or part of its state given up
at particular moments, and not improperly is said to be the reluctance T H E L E C T U R E S £)£ M O T V OF 1684
or resistance of the body, of which one species is the centrifugal force of
T h is manuscript, entitled De Motu Corporum Liber primus, and dated in
rotating bodies.
Newton's hand, in the right hand margin of fol. i, ‘Octob. 1684’, forms
1. M S . A d d . 3965 (5), fol. 21, fol. 26 (left half). part of MS. Dd-9-46 C .U .L. The original text has been subjected to
2. C o rrespo n d in g to D e f. i o f lectures de Motu. considerable emendation at certain points, including a number of omis­
3. C o rresp o n d in g to D e f. 4 o f lectures de Motu. sions and insertions. As emended, the manuscript agrees so closely with
4. C o rresp o n d in g to D e f. 5 o f lectures d e M otu . T h e latter part represents a
the corresponding part of Book I of the Principia^ that it must represent
considerably em ended version o f an earlier and p artly illegib le version.
5. T h e phrase estque co r po r i suo proportionalis agrees w ith that in the lectures
something very close to, if not identical wdth, the final draft of that work,
de M otu, rather than the Principia. from which was taken the copy transmitted to the Royal Society in 1686.
6. T h e possible significance o f solummodo here is discussed above in Part I, Consideration of the differences between the Principia and the revised
C h a p ter 1.4, p. 28. text of the present manuscript falls outside the scope of the present work,
7. N e w to n ’s co ncept o f impetus is touch ed on above in Part I, C h a p te r 1.4,
and we shall be concerned only with significant differences between the
p. 27.
8. C o rrespo n d in g to D e f. 6 o f lectures d e Motu. final and original versions.
9. A draft o f D e f. 7 - 1 0 o f the lectures de Motu. A discussion of the probable date of composition of the present manu­
10. N o such definition occurs in the lectures de M o tu or the Principia, script, and of its connexion with the other parts of MS. Dd-9-46 C.U .L.
althou gh the co ncept is used in D e f. i o f bo th those works. For N e w to n ’s co n ­ is given above in Part I, Chapter 6.4.
cept o f d ensity see above. Part I, C h a p ter 1.4, p. 25.
1 1 . See the reference to pon dus and to p en d u lu m experim ents at the end o f
D e f. 3 o f the lectures de Motu.
S ig n if ic a n t D if f e r e n c e s betw een O r ig in a l and F in a l
12. A return to D e f. 2.
13. T h e r e is no D e f. 13. T h is definition later cancelled. It corresponds to V e r s io n s
D e f. 3 and is in terestin g for the reference at the end to vis c en tr ifu ga g y r a n t iu m
Definitions
m issin g from the latter definition, at least in its final version.
Def. 1-3 in the original version read as follows:
I P Ouantitas materiae est copia seu mensura ejusdem orta ex illius densitate
et magnitudine conjunctim. Vas idem plus continet aeris vel pulveris cujust is
qui compressione magis condensantur. Corpus aiitem diiplo densius in duplo
spatio quadruplum est. Hanc quantitatem per nomen corporis vel massae
designo.
2. ^ Axis materiae est Tinea quaevis recta circum quam materia servato
partium situ inter se, in spatio libero absque impedimentis et incitamentis
uniformiter revoTci possit.
3. Centrum inatcriae est axium diiorum conciirsus,^ estque in corpore similari
punctum illud quod rulgo centrum gravitatis dicitur. Sed et in materia
dissimilari idem est cum centra gravitatis, si modo centrum illud non ex
magnitudine sed quantitate materiae determinatur. Verbi gratia centrum
gravitatis magnitudiniim globi aiirei et globi lignei punctum illud est quo
dividitur distantia inter centra globorum in ratione reciproca magnitudinum.
XI TH E L E C T U R E S DE M O T U OF 1 6 8 4 323
322 THE L E C T U R E S DE M O T U OF 1684 XI
at venini gravitatis centrum centrumque materiae est punctim illud quo autem qua urget planum vel faciem pO, eadem erit qua, sublato hoc piano,
dividitur haec distantia in ratione reciproca sen ponderum sen quantitatum distenderet filum pN, atque adeo est ad vim qua vel pondere suo vel ictu
materiae in globis. Nam materiam in corpore unoquoque esse ponderi pro- mallei, impellitur secundum lineam Hp in plana utp N ad pH, et ad vim qua
portionalem reperiper experimentum pendulorump uti posthac explicabitur. urget planum alterumpG utpN ad pH. Sed et vis cochlea per similem virium
Allowing for the dilferent numbering consequent on the original exis­ divisiofiem colligitur; quippe quae cunetis est a vecte impulsus.
tence of Defs. 2, 3 not found in the Principia, the next six definitions of Usus igitur Corollarij hujus latissime patet, et late patendo veritatem
the original version were subjected to trivial emendations only. This is ejusdem evincit, cum pendeat ex jam dictis Mechanica tota ah Authoribus
true likewise for the next definition (Def. V III of the Principia) up to diversimode demonstrata. Ex hisce enim innotescunt vires Machinarum quae
vim autem absolutam ad centrum (1. 12, p. 4, Principia) after which there ex rotis, tympanis, trochleis, vectibus, radijs volubilihus, nervis tensis et
is a substantial difference between the original and final version down to ponderibus directe vel oblique ascendentibus ac descendentibus, caeterisque
the end of the paragraph. The continuation in the original version read: potentijs Mechanicis componi solent; ut et vires nervorum ad animalium
. . . vel si mavis ad corpus aliquod in centro consistens, tanquam efficaciam ossa movenda, quatenus a contractione musculorum tendentur.
eius ad propagandas vires acceleratrices de se per regiones omnes in circuitu. Apart from the insertion in the Scholium of the phrase Et primus quidem
Mathematicus est hie conceptus. Nam virium causas physicas jam negligo. D. Wallisius, dein D. Wrennus et D. Hugenius inventum prodidit there are
In Physica referendae sunt vires absolutae ad earum causam veram sive no further substantial alterations of the original text.
causa ilia sit corpus aliquod in centro {uti magnes in centro vis jnagneticae
Article I : Method of prime and ultimate ratios
vel Terra in centro vis gravitatis) sive alia aliqua quae non apparet. Nam
centrorum quae sunt puncta Mathematica, vires j'evera niillae sunt. In With the exception of the insertion of the two corollaries to Lemma X
Mathesi autem has vires vel abstracte considerare licet, et disputationibus found in the Principia and the addition of the final paragraph of the
de causa vera omissis, ad centrum ceu principium Mathematicum simpliciter Scholium, there are no substantial alterations of the original text.
referre, vel corpori alicui in centro, ceu causae sine qua non sunt, atque adeo
Article I I : Propositions
a cujus efficacia et quantitate pendent concrete tribuere.
Thereafter there are no significant emendations in the original text Prop. I, Theor. i. The original enunciation of this proposition agreed
down to the end of the Scholium to the Definitions. with that of MS. IXc, Prop. i. An interesting addition to the original
text is the phrase
Latos of Motion in eodem piano cum triangulo A S B
Coroll. II beginning at S ifilio p r ... (1. 7, p. 1^, Principia) and continuing at the end of the fourth sentence from the beginning. The last sentence
down to the end of the corollary, read in the original version: of the original version is cancelled and replaced by the passage found in
Pondus autem v ip N trahit filum directe et vi IIN urget planum pG hide the Principia. Corollaries i, 2 found in the Principia are missing from
vi directum oppositum. Unde tensio fili hujus obliqui erit ad tensionem fili the original version.
alterius perpendicularis PA3 utpN ad pH. Ideoque si pondus p sit ad pondus Prop. 3, Theor. 3. The first three corollaries to this proposition
A in ratione qua componitnr ex ratione reciproca minimarum distantiarum originally read as follows:
filorum suorum AM , p N a centro rotae et ratione directa pH ad p N ; pon-
dera idem valebunt ad rotam movendam, atque adeo se mutuo sustinebunt Corol. I. Him si corpus unum radio ad alterum ducto describit areas tempo-
ut quilibet experiri potest. ribus proportionales, urgetur hoc corpus 7iulla alia vi praeter compositam
Per similem virium divisionem innotescit vis qua pondus simul urget plana illam ex vi centripeta ad corpus alterum tendente, et ex vi omni quae agit in
dua oblique quae et vis cunei est. Nam erecto ad lineam p N piano perpen- corpus alterum et in utrumque aequaliter {pro mole corporum) et secundum
dicularo pQ, si corpus p planis pO, pG utrinque incumhat, hoc inter plana lineasparallelas agere intelligitur. Namque additio et subductio virium in hoc
ilia consistens rationem habebit cunei inter corporis fissi facies internas: vis Theoremate sit secundum situm linearum, ut in Legum Coroll, i exponitur.
Y 2
324 THE L E C T U R E S DE M O T U OF 1684 XI XI THE L E C T U R E S DE M O T U OF 1684 325
CoroL 2. Et ijsdem positis si areae sint temporibus quam proxime proportio­ gulum Y P G ad rectangulum ZA O , id est, ob aequales, PG, AM , AO, ut
nates vis ilia communis aut aequaliter agit in corpus utrumque quamproxime, P Y a d A Z Q.E.D.
aut agit secundum lineas quamproxime parallelas, aut perquam exigua est si Prop. 13, Prob. 8. Originally there was the following Scholium to this
cum vi centripeta ad corpus alterum tendente conferatur. Proposition:

Corol. 3. Et vice versa si haec tria contingunt, corpus radio ad alterum S i vis centripeta ageret in omnibus distantijs aequaliter, corpus autem
corpus ducto describet areas quamproxime proportionates temporibus. hac vi urgente describeret curvam A B C G E et in A longissime distaret a
Prop. 4, Theor. 4. The original enunciation agreed with that in MS. IXc, centro S, perveniret idem corpus ad minimam a centra distantiam in C ubi
Prop. 2. Originally there were only five corollaries, as in MS. IXc, corol­ angulus A S C est n o graduum circiter, deinde ad Augem seu maximam a
laries 3, 7 in the Principia having been inserted later. The Scholium to centro distantiam in D ubi angulus C S D est aequalis angulo A S C , postea
this proposition was also emended considerably, the original version ad minimam a centro distantiam in E ubi angulus D SE est aequalis angulo
agreeing with that in MS. IXc. C SD et sic infinitum. Quod si vis centripeta reciproce proportionalis esset
Prop. 5, Prob. i. This was not in the original version. Its insertion distantiae a centro, corpus de loco maximae sui a centro distantiae A descen­
necessitated certain alterations in the numbering of the subsequent deret ad locum minimae a centro distantiae, puta ad G, ubi angulus A S G
propositions. The revised numbering will be adhered to thereafter for est quasi 136 vel 140 graduum, dein hoc angulo repetito ascenderet rursus ad
convenience of reference to the Principia. maximam a centro distantiam et sic per vices in infinitum. Et universaliter,
Prop. 6, Theor. 5. The end of the second paragraph originally agreed si vis centripeta decresceret in majore quam duplicata et minore quam tripli-
with the corresponding portion of the text of Prop. 3 of MS. IXc. cata ratione corpus prius minori quam duplicata ratione distantiae a centro
Prop. 10, Prob. 5. The corollary to this in the Principia was inserted. corpus ad maximam a centro distantiam prius rediret quam compleret
circulum, sui vis ilia decresceret in majore quam duplicata et minore quam
triplicata ratione corpus prius compleret circulum quam rediret ad maximam
Article III: De motu corporum in conicis sectionibus excentricis
a centro distantiam. A t si vis eadem decresceret in triplicata vel plusquam
This article number, and title, was inserted after Prop, i i , Prob. 5, triplicata ratione distantiae a centro, et corpus inciperet moveri in curva
having originally been immediately before Prop. 14, Theor. 6. quae in principio motus fecaret radium A S perpendiculariter, hoc si semeI
Lemma 13 of the Principia was inserted. The original lemma 13, inciperet descendere, pergeret semper descendere usque ad centrum, si semel
corresponding to lemma 14 of the Principia, read inciperet ascendere abiret in infinitum.
Quadratum perpendiculi quod ab umbilico Parabolae ad tangentem ejus Prob. 16, Theor. 8. The present manuscript ends at Coroll. 5 of this
demittitur est ad quadratum intervalli inter umbilicum et punctum contactus proposition.
lit lotus rectum principale ad latus rectum quod pertinet ad diametrum
transeuntem per punctum contactus. 1. H ere and elsewhere the reference is to the First E dition .
2. T h is version was subjected to considerable em endations and cancellations
Sit A O P Parabola, S umbilicus ejus, A vertex principalis, P punctum
and then finally replaced (at fol. 5v) b y the follo w in g version corresponding to,
contactus. P M tangens diametro principali occurrens in M, et S N linea th o u gh not identical w ith, D e f. i, P rincipia:
perpendicularis ab umbilico in tangentem. Produce S A ad Z lit sit A Z latus Quantitas m ateriae est mensura ejiisdem orta ex illius densitate et magnitudine con-
j un ctim . Aer duplo d ensior in duplo spatio quadruplus est. Idem intellige de n i v e et
rectum principale. Huic A Z erige perpendicularum Z Y , cui occurrat P Y
pulveribus p e r compressionem v e l liquefactionem condensatis. Et p a r est ratio c o r ­
ipsi A Z parallela, et erit haec P Y latus rectum pertinens ad diametrum po ru m omnium quae p e r operationes naturae diversim ode condensantur n eg le ct o
transeuntem per punctum contactus P. Id ex conicis patet. Dico igitur quod scilicet a d medium respectu, s iq uo dfuerit, in[ter]stitiapartium libere pervaden s. Inno-
sit PS^ ad SN'^ ut P Y ad A Z. Nam completis parallelogrammis AG PM , tescit autem quantitas m ateriae p e r corporis cujusque pondus. Nam p on der i p r o -
portionalem esse r ep e r i p e r experimenta pendulorum accuratissim e instituta, uti
Z Y P O ob aequalia triangula PSN , M S N et similia M SN , M PO, est P S i p o st ha c docebitur. Eandem v e r o sub nomine corporis v e l massae in sequentibus
ad SN^‘ ut PM'^ sell AG'' ad PO'', hoc est {ex natiira Parabolae) ut rectan- passim intelligo.
326 THE L E C T U R E S DE M O T U OF 1684 XI
3. B o th this and the su cceed in g definition were o m itted from the Principia. NOTE REGARDING PREVIOUS
T h e y are o f interest fo r the evidence th ey su p p ly o f the co n tin uity o f N e w to n ’s
P U B L I C A T I O N OF N E W T O N D Y N A M I C A L
dyn am ical tho u ght. See above, C h a p te r 5, p . 86.
4. C an ce lled and replaced b y intersectio. MANUSCRIPTS
5. N o tic e h o w this im portan t fact was incorporated in the final version o f
D e f. I given in n. 2 above.
I. MS. Add. 3996 has not yet been published in full. Certain extracts
other than those given here have been published by Hall [i].
II. Unpublished previously apart from certain extracts relating to centri­
fugal force in Herivel [i].
III. The Vellum MS. has been published previously by Herivel [4], and in
vol. iii of C or re sp on de nc e.
IVa. Published previously with translation by Hall [2], and in vol. i of
C o r re sp on de nc e.
IVb. Published previously with translation by Hall and Hall [i] apart from
the Diagrams which they reconstructed from the text.
V. Published previously in part by Herivel [5], and completely in vol. iii
of C o r re sp on de nc e.
VI. MS. Add. 4003 published previously with translation by Hall and Hall
[!]•
VII. Correspondence.
VIII. The Newton Copy MS. first published by Whiston [2] in a Latin ver­
sion and in English incompletely by Ball [i], and completely by Hall
and Hall [i]. The Locke Copy has been published previously by King
[i], and in vol. iii of C o r re sp on de nc e.
IX. The Royal Society Copy (Isaaci N e w t on i P r op os it io ne s d e M otu ) was the
first version to be published, by Rigaud [i]. An emended version of
the same manuscript was then published by Ball [i] who also gave the
substantial differences and additions of Version HI. Hall and Hall [i]
have published Version HI with translation giving certain of the differ­
ences between that version and the first two versions in footnotes.
Xa. Unpublished previously.
Xb. Definitions 1-5 published previously with translation by Hall and
Hall [i].
XL Unpublished previously.
BI BLI OG RAPH Y 329
H ai .l , a . R., and Hali., M . B. [ i ]. U npublished S cien tific Papers o f Isaac Nezvton
BIBLIOGRAPHY (C am bridge, 1962).
Herivel, j . W . [ i ], ‘ N e w to n ’s D is co v e ry o f the L a w o f C en trifu ga l F o r ce ’ ,
Isis, 5 1 , 5 4 6 -5 3 (i960).
A lexander, H . G . [ i ], T h e L e ib n iz -C la r k e Controversy (M anchester, 1956).
------- [2], ‘ O n the D a te o f C o m p o sitio n o f the F irst Version o f N e w to n ’s T r a c t dc
A ndrade, E . N . da C . [ i ]. S ir Isaac N ew ton (L o n d o n , 1954).
M o t u ', A rch iv es Internationales d 'H isto ire des Sciences, 13, 6 7 -7 0 (i960).
B all , W . W . R . [ i ]. A n Essay on N ew to n 's P r in cip ia (L o n d o n , 1893).
------- [3], ibid., p p . 7 1 - 7 8 .
B eeckman, I. [i\ , J o u rn a l, w ith in troduction and notes b y C . de W aard, 4 vols.
(L a H aye, 19 3 9 -53 ).
------- [4], ‘ Interpretation o f an early N e w to n M a n u scrip t’ , Isis, 52, 4 10 -16
(1961).
B irch, T. [ i ], A H isto ry o f the R o y a l S o ciety o f Lond on , 4 vols. (L o n d on ,
------- [5], ‘ N e w to n on R o tatin g B o d ie s’ , ibid. 53, 2 1 2 -1 8 (1962).
1 7 5 6 -7 )-
K in g , L ord [ i ]. L if e o f L o c k e (2nd ed., London, 1830).
B orelli, J. a . [ i ], T heorica medicearum planetarum a causis physicis deducta
(Florence, 1666).
K oyre, A . [i]. E tu des G alileen nes, Parts I - H I (Paris, 1939).
B oyer, C . B. [ i ]. T h e H istory o f the C a lcu lu s an d its C on cep tual D evelop m en t ------- [2], ‘A n U n p u b lish ed L e tte r o f R ob ert H oo ke to Isaac N e w to n ’ , Isis, 43,
(N e w Y o rk , 1959).
312-38 (1952).
------- [3], ‘L a m ecan ique celeste de J. A . B o relli’ , R ev u e d 'H isto ir e des Sciences, 5,
Brewster, D. [ i ]. M em oirs o f the L ife , W ritings, an d D iscoveries o f S ir Isaac
N ew ton , 2 vols. (E d in b u rgh , 1855). 101-38 (1952).
Bullialdus, I. [i], A stronom ia P h ilo la ica (Paris, 1645). ------- [4], ‘ L ’h yp oth ese et I’experience chez N e w to n ’ , B u ll. S o c. F r a n f. P h il. 48,
C ajori, F . [ i ], ‘ N e w to n ’s T w e n t y Y ears D e la y in A n n o u n cin g the L a w of 59-97 (1956).
G ra v ita tio n ’ , p p. 1 2 7 -8 8 o f S ir Isa a c N ezcton, a B icenten ary E v a lu a tio n o f ------- [5], F ro m the C lo sed W o rld to the In fin ite U niverse (Baltimore, 1957).
his W ork (Baltim ore, 1928). ------- [6], N ezvtonian S tu d ies (inpress).
------- [2] (Revisor), S ir Isaac N ezvton’s M a th em a tica l P rincip les . . . T ran slated L ohne, j . [ i ], ‘ H ooke versus N e w to n ’ , C entaurus, 7 , 6 -5 2 (i960).
into English by Andrezv M o tte (Berkeley, 1934). M ach, E . [ i ]. D ie M ech a n ik in ihre Entzoicklung (L e ip zig , 1921).
C lagett, M . [ i ]. S cien ce o f M ech a n ics in the M id d le A g es (M adison and O xfo rd , M agirus, j . [ i ], Physiologiae P erip a tetica e L ib r i S e x C u m Com m entariis . . .
(C a m brid ge edition, 1642).
1959).
C ohen, I. B. [i], F ra n k lin an d N ew ton (Philadelphia, 1956). M aier, A . [i], ZzveiP roblem e der scholastischen N a tu rp h ilosop h ie, (2nd ed., R om e,
C ostabel, P. [ i ], L e ib n iz et la dynam ique (Paris, i960). 1951)-
C ranston, M . W . [ i ], J o h n L o ck e (L o n d on , 1957). M ore, L . T . [ i ], Isaac N ezvton, a B iography (N e w Y o rk , 1934).
C rew, H . [ i ]. T h e R ise o f M od ern P h ysics (Baltim ore, 1928). P atterson, L. D. [ i ], ‘ H o o k e ’s G ravita tio n theory and its influence on N e w to n ’,
------- and S alvio , A . de [ i ] (Translators), G a lile o 's D ialogues Concerning Tzco Isis, 40 (1949).
N ew Sciences (D o v er edition o f 19 14 N e w Y o r k edition, no date). — — [2], ibid. 41 (1950).
C rombie, a . C . [ i ], A u g u stin e to G a lileo , 2 vols. (Lo n don , 1961). Pelseneer, j . [ i ], ‘ U n e lettre inedite de N e w to n ’ , Isis, 12, 2 3 7 -5 4 (1929).
DE V illamil , R . [ i ], Nezvton: T h e M a n (L o n d on , no date). ------- [2], ‘ L a p om m e de N e w to n ’ , d e l et Terre, 53, 190 -3 (1937).

D rake, S. [ i ] (Editor), G a lileo G a lilei, D iscourse on B odies in W ater. T ran sla te d Pemberton, H . [ i ], A Viezv o f S ir Isaac N ezvton's P h ilosop h y (D u b lin , 1728).
b y T homas S alusbury (U rbana, i960). R igaud, S. P. [ i ]. H isto rica l E ssay on the F irst P u b lica tio n o f S ir Isaac N ezvton's
------- and D rabkin , I. E. [i] (Translators), G a lileo G a lile i O n M o tio n an d O n P rin cip ia (O xford , 1838).
M ech a n ics (M adiso n , i960). ------- [2] (Editor), Correspondence o f S cien tific M e n o f Seven teen th C en tu ry ,
2 vols. (O xfo rd , 1841).
D ugas, R . [ i ]. L a M eca n iqu e an X V I F siecle (N eu ch atel, 1954).
------- [2], A H isto ry o f M ech a n ics translated b y J. R . M a d d o x (L o n d on , 1957).
S antillana, G . de [ i ] (Editor), G a lileo G a lilei, D ialogue on the G reat W orld

D lihem, P. [ i ], [2], [3], E tu d es stir L eon a rd de V in ci, Serie i , 2, 3 (Paris, 1906, System s (C hicago, 1953).
1909, 1913). S hapley, H. and H owarth, H . E. [ i ], A S ource B o o k in A stronom y (N e w Y o rk ,
E dleston, j . [ i ]. Correspondence o f S ir Isa a c Nezvton an d Professor C otes 1929)-
(L o n d on , 1850). S inger, C . [ i ], A S h o r t H istory o f S cien tific Ideas to i g o o (O xfo rd 1959).
F iersz, M. [ i ], ‘U b e r den U rsp ru n g u n d B ed eu tu n g der L eh re Isaac N ew to n s
S treet, T. [ i ], A stronom ia C arolin a: A Nezv Theory o f C oelestia l M o tio n (L o n ­
don, 1661).
vom absoluten R a u m ’, Gesnerus, i i , 6 2 -1 2 0 (1954).
G abbey, W . a . [ i ], ‘ D e sca rte s’ D y n a m ica l T h o u g h t ’ (un published thesis.
S tukeley, W . [ i ]. M em oirs o f S ir Isaac Nezvton s L ife , edited by W hite, A . W .
(L o n d o n , 1936).
Q u e e n ’s U n iversity, Belfast, 1964).
Hall , A . R . [i], ‘ Sir Isaac N e w to n ’s N o te Book, 1 6 6 1 -6 5 ’, Cam bridge H isto rica l
S ullivan , J. W . N . [i], Isaac Nezvton i 6 4 2 - i j 2 y (L o n d o n , 1938).
J o u rn a l, 9, 2 3 9 -5 0 (1948).
T orricelli, E . [ i ], D e M o tu Projectorum : O p . G eom etrica (Florence, 1644).

------- [2], ‘N e w to n on the C alcu latio n o f C en tral F o rces’ , A n n a ls o f Scien ce, 13, T oulmin, S. [ i ], P h il. R ev . 68, 1 -2 9 (1959).
I'u R N O R , E. [i]. C ollections fo r the H istory o f the Tozvn and S o k e o f G rantham
6 2 -7 1 (1957)-
(L o n don , 1806).
330 inBL10C;RAPHY
W hew ell , W. [ i ], H istory o f the I n d u c ti ve Sciences, 2 vols., 3rd ed. (London,
INDEX
1857)-
W h is to n , W. [ i ], M em oirs o f the Life o f Mr. William Whiston by himself, 2 vols. Where a manuscript is in Latin references are given only to the translation. Entries
(London, 1749). involving Newton and another individual are generally given under the latter only.
------[2], P r a ele ct io n es P h y s i c o -M a t h e m a t i c a l (Cambridge, 1710).
Acceleration, 203. body to persevere in its motion, 56, 3 11
Adam, A ., and Tannery, P., 44 n. Def, 13, 314 n. 14, 320 Def. 14; due to
Alexander, H. G ., 29 n., 234 n. 19. diurnal and annual motions of the
Anderson, A ., 237. Earth compared with gravity, see under
Andrade, E. N . da C., xiv. Force, of gravity; its replacement by
Antiperistasis, theory of, 125 n. 3. centripetal force, 13, 55, 59,73,289 n. i,
Archimedes, 41. 290 n. 9; law of, 196, derivation of, 1 1 -
Aristotle, i, 2, 38, 43 n., 124, 125 n. 3, 13, discovery of, 89, result equivalent
126 nn. 8 and 10. to, 185; of the M oon from the Earth,
Aston, F., 96, 104. 58, 72; of the planets from the Sun, 58,
Axis, of body, 310 Def. 6; of circulation, 72; physical origin of, 7; quantitative
210 § 5, 312 Law I. treatment of, 7 -1 3 ; question o f its
existence w'ithin framework o f Newton­
Ball, W . W . R., xiv, i i n., 12 n., 16, ian dynamics, 56, 62-63.
17 n., 23 0 ., 6 50 ., 70 n., 98 n., 102, Centripetal force, 277-89, 300 Lemma 2,
108 n., 117 n., 131 n. 2, 257 n. 2. 302, 318 Def. 4; and orbital motion, 13,
Barrow, I., 2, 3 n., 15. 55i 61, 73, 277-89; definition of, 28,
Beeckman, E, 340., 36, 52 n., 132 n. 6, 277 Def. I, 299 Def. i, 3 1 1 Def. 16,
303 n. 13. 318 Def. 5; different kinds of, 318 Def.
Birch, T ., 5 n., 103 n., 132 n. 6. 5; examples of, 318 Def. 5; general
Bodies, absolutely solid or hard, 143 Ax. formula for its calculation in orbital
9, 10, 151 n. 4, 213; colliding, spring of, motion, 17 0 ., 19, 279 Theor. 3; its
4, relative velocity of, 4, 83, 213; real nature as opposed to centrifugal
definition of, 226 Def. 2, 310 Def. 5; force, 13; its replacement o f centrifugal
descent of, in relative and absolute force, 13, 55, 59, 73, 289 n. i, 290 n. 9.
space, 310 Def. 4; distance between, law of, for motion in circle under
139 Def. 13; elasticity of, 151 n. 4; ex­ force to centre, 278 Theor. 2, for motion
tended, motion of, xiii n., 77-86, in circle under force to circumferential
collision between, 14 n., 32, 82-86, 90, point, 280 Prob. i, for motion in ellipse
171-9 , 2 1 1 -1 5 , 2 1 7 -1 8 ; falling, law of, under force to centre, 281 Prob. 2, for
see under Descartes, Galileo, and New ­ motion in ellipse under force to focus,
ton; motion towards one another, 77, 281 Prob. 3, for motion in equiangular
139 Def. 12; nature of, 227 § i ; pair spiral under force to eye, 280 Prob. i
or system of, centre of motion of, see Scholium-, uniform, 287 Prob. 7.
under Motion, centre of. Circle, tyranny of, 8, 52; uniform motion
Borelli, J. A., 59, 233 n. 10. in, 45-48, 51-52, 145 Ax. 19, and
Boyer, C. B., 2 n. Galileo, 37, 40, 46, and Hooke, 240,
Boyle, R., his receiver, 127 n. 22. 242, 242 n. 2, deviational treatment of,
Bradwardine, T ., 2 n. 12-13, 195-8, 278 Theor. 2, endeavour
Brewster, D., xiii n., xiv, i n., 14, 75 n., from centre in {see under Endeavour),
96 n., 97 n., 102, 108 n., 117 n. force from centre in, 9, polygonal treat­
Brownover, S., 108 n., 246. ment of, 7-10 , 18, 129-30, 139 n. f,
Bulk, proportionality of motion to, 133 146-8.
§ 3, 135 n. 3; and weight, 3 1 1 Def. i i . Clagett, M ., 2 n., 3 n., 126 n. 7, 235 n. 32.
Clarke, S., 29, 234 n. 19.
Cajori, F., 25 n., 66 n., 68. Clerselier, 234 n. 23.
Calculator, 2. Cohen, I. B., xiv.
Centrifugal force, absence from treatment Collins, J., 15, 237, 238 n. 2.
of orbital motion in Principia, 73 ; and Collisions, 142 A x. 7, 8, 9, 10; and D es­
Descartes, 7, 40, 47, 54; and Pluygens, cartes, 3, 4, 48, 49, 52; and Huygens,
15) 56, 7 1 ; as species of force of a 4-5, 52; and third law' of motion, 31,
332 INDEX I NDE X 333
312 Law 3; between extended body and Density, 25, 319 Def. 6, 320 n. 10. centre in motion in a circle, in half a motion in a circle, 37,40, 46, principle of
immovable surface, 83, 90, 170 Prop. Determination, of motion, 3, 45, 137 Def. revolution 8, 9, 147 A x. 22, in a whole inertia, 35, 36, problem of percussion,
33, 179 Prop. 39, 40; between extended 4; of centre of motion, 78. revolution, 148 A x. 24; centrifugal, see 37, 38, rate of fall under gravity, 125,
bodies, 14 0 ., 32, 82-86, 90, 1 7 1-7 , Deviation, as measure of centrifugal ten­ centrifugal force; centripetal, see centri­ 127 n. 24, 186, 189, second law of
2 1 1 -1 5 , 2 1 7 -1 8 ; elastic, 4, 137 Def. 5, dency in motion in a circle, 195; as petal force; concept of, 5-6, 7, and motion, 35, 36, 37.
142 Ax. 9; oblique, 31, 159 A x. 119, measure of centripetal force, 19-22, Galileo, 36, 37; definition of, 138 Def. his Dialogue, 10, 34 n., 36, 37, 38,
121, 122; perfectly elastic, 4, 5, 143 Ax. 249 Prop. 2, 252-3, 255 n. 12, 279 9; equality of, between colliding bodies, 41, 74, 127 n. 24, 132 nn. 4 and 5, 183,
9, 1 5 1 n. 5; perfectly inelastic, 3, 132- Theor. 3, 290 nn. 9 and i i , 291 nn. 22 6, 142 Ax. 7, 8; exercised, of a body, 189, 198 n. 4, Discorsi, 2 n., 4, io n .,
6, 143 A x. 9; problem of, 3, 4, 5, 6, 49; and 34; between actual and inertial 311 Def. 12, 320 Def. 14; impeded, and 34 n., 35 m, 36, 37, 38, 39, 40 m, 41,
see also Reflection. paths, 12. conatus, 13, 55; impressed, 28, and 91, 132 n. 5, 207 n. I, Discourse on
Comets, 99, 102, 284 Prob. 4 Scholium, Division, forbidden, 2, 3, 136 n. 9, 149, change of state, 312 Law 1 ,3 1 2 Law 3, Bodies in Water, 37, discovery of para­
291 n. 37, 302. 215 n. 2. 318 Def. 4, and change of motion, 299 bolic path of projectile, 35, 36, 39, 41,
Conatus, see under Endeavour. Drake, S., 37 n, Law 2, 312 Law 2, and motion of pro­ 312 Law 2, Siderius Nuncius, 125 n. 3,
Conduitt, J., 15 n., 1 7 0 ., 75, 97. Dugas, R., 5 n., 36. jectile, 123; impulsive, 18, 20, 21, 39, supposed use o f first and second laws
Conic sections, 249-51. Duhem, P., xiv, 36 n., 126 nn. 7, 10, and 140 n. 10, 247, 252, 278 Theor. i, 303 of motion, 31, 33, 35, P law of falling
Copernican system, i i , 301 B. 13- n. 10, 3 1 1 Def. 14; innate or internal, bodies, i i , 12, 35, 36, 38, 41, 74, 184,
Costabel, P., 5 n. of body or matter, 26-28, 277 Def. 2, 185, 195, 197 n. I, 207 nn. 6 and 13,
Cotes, R., xiii. Edleston, J., xiii, 98 n., 99 n., 102 n. H yp. 2, 278 Theor. i, 286 Prob. 6, 299 256n. 13; New ton’s homage to, 360., 53.
Cousin, V., 233 n. 8. Endeavour, along tangent, 51, 147 A x. 20; Def. 2, Law i, 311 Def. 12, 312 Law' i, Gassendi, P., 42, 43.
Cranston, M . W., 108 n., 246. from centre in motion in circle, 7, 1 2 - 318 Def. 3; instantaneous, 140 n. 10; Geometry, analytical versus synthetical, 3.
Crew, H., 25. 13, 48, SI, 52 , 54-64, 79 , 129 § I, 147 motive, 22, 318 Def. 5; nature of, 231 Gravitation, inverse square law of, 57, 58,
Crew, H., and Salvio, A., 37 n., 132 n. 5. A x. 21, 22, 148 Ax. 24, 25, 195-8, Def. 5; of a body, see force, innate or 62, 67 n., 70, 71, 72, 104, 106 n.,
Crombie, A. C., 126 n. 7. 231 Def. 10, and absolute motion, 228 internal; of a body’s motion, 156 Ax. 237 n. I ; and Bullialdus, 16 n .; deriva­
Curve, approximation to by broken line, § 3, 310 Def. 9, and centre of motion in 106, 161 n. 10, 3 1 1 Def. 13. tion of, 13; tests against M oon’s motion,
18, 21, 78, 115, 130, 145 Ax. 18, 151 n. rotating body, 209 § 4, and Descartes, of gravity, as centripetal force, 302, 13, 14, 23, 58, 59, 60, 65-76, 89-90, 92,
10, 247, 256 n. 14. 46, 47, 52, and gravity, 231 Def. 10, 318 Def. 5, compared with centrifugal 132 n. 2, 302.
233 n. 10, as impeded force, 13, 55; of force, 131 §§ 8, 9, 132 n. 8, at Earth’s Gravity, acceleration due to, 203; and
Degree of great circle on Earth’s surface, Earth from Sun compared with force of surface compared with centrifugal force endeavour, 231 Def. 10, 233 n. 10; and
65- gravity, 197; of Moon from Earth, there due to diurnal motion, 10, i i , levity, 43 n .; as species of centripetal
Descartes, R., and, action required to 69 n., compared with endeavour of 183-6, 188, 196, at Earth’s surface com­ force, 286 Prob. 5 Scholium, 318 Def.
create and destroy motion, 48, centri­ Moon from Sun, 15, 197, 237, com­ pared with endeavour of Earth from the 5; centre of, 85, 135 n. 6, 310 Def. 6,
fugal force, 7, 40, 47, 54, conservation pared with force of gravity at Earth’s Sun, 197, at Earth’s surface compared 3 1 1 Def. 10; definition of, 231 Def.
of motion, 3, 32, 49, 135 n. 4, definition surface, 196; of planets from Sun, 72, with endeavour of the Moon from the 10; efficacy of, on inclined plane, 203;
of motion, 3, determination of motion, 197. Earth, 196, compared with centripetal force of, see force of gravity; natural, i ,
8, 140 n. 6, horizontal pendulum, 132 Equiangular spiral, motion in, 280 Prob. i force on the Moon, 302, compared with 121, 123, 126 n. 13; of body and its
n. 6, impossibility of vacuum, 126 n. 15, Scholium. the resistance of the air, 289, its solidity, 125; rate of fall due to, i i , 88,
law o f falling bodies, 36 n., motion as a Equinoxes, precession of, 86. diminution due to diurnal motion, 58, 125, 127 n. 24, 185, 186, 187, 188, 206;
state, 160 n. 4, particle free to slide in Ether, resistance of, 301, 302. 62. uniform, 312 Law 2.
revolving tube, 47, 54, principle of Extension, 136 Def. i, 208 § i ; of powers, of planets from the Sun, 72; on a Gregory, D., 17 n., 72 n., 92, 94, 192,
inertia, 30, 40, 43, 44-45, 235 n. 26, 232 Def. 12. planet, 16, 18; physical, 6; qualitative 199.
problem of collisions, 3, 4, 48, 49, 52, definition of, 5, 6; resisting, 277 Def. Gregory, J., 15 n., 66, 238 n. 2.
stability of planetary orbits, 59 n., 227 Fiersz, M ., 29, 126 n. 16. 3, Hyp. I, 299 Def. 3, 299 Law 5, 313
§ 2, 233 n. 10. Flamsteed, J., 108, 238; his correspon­ Law 6; varying inversely as square of Hall, A. R., 560., 72 n., 183, 192.
his, concept of conatus ( = endea­ dence with Newton in winter of 1684/5, distance, 19, 20, 23, 34 n., 248 Prop. 2, Hall, A. R., and Hall, M . B., 29 n., 102,
vour) 46, 47, 52, correspondence, 103, 104, 107. 251 Prop. 3, 281 Prob. 3, 282 Theor. 4, 1 17 n., 198, 208, 219.
dynamical discussion in, 43 n., double Fluent, 2 n. 284 Prob. 4, 286 Prob. 5. Halley, E., 62, 70, 73, 105, 108, 257, 283;
theory o f motion, 125 § 3, 127 n. 19, Fluxions, 2, 17 n., 34 n., 66, 67, 93. his correspondence with Newton in
233 nn. 7 and 8, 234 n. 16, 310 Def. 9, Force, absolute, 318 Def. 5 ; accelerative, Gabbey, W. .A., 43 n., 52 n., 1 5 1 n. 4. 1686, 12, 16 n., 17, 22 n., 23 n., 57, 58,
314 n., 8 double theory o f motion and 20, 21, 22, 318 Def. 5; and change of Galilei, G., i, 2, 7, 29, 32, 3 5 -4 1; and, 59 n., 61, 62, 65 n., 71 n., 72, 74, 92 n.,
Newton, 219, 227-30, 233 n. 8, in­ motion, 48, 141 Ax. 3, 4, 6, 142 Ax. 5, area under velocity-time graph, 33, 97 n., 99, 104, 105, 106, 192, 237 nn. i
fluence on Newton, i, 29, 40, 41, 42-53, 150 Ax. 23, 150 n. 2, 157 Ax. 108, 158 34 n., 38, 300 Lemma 2, assumption and 3, 240 n. 2, 242 n. 2, discussion
150 n. I, 219, 234 n. 15, Principia Ax. 1 14, 115, 159 Ax. 1 18, 208 § I, 231 that distance moved in given time pro­ with Hooke and Wren in 1684, 97,
Philosophiae and Newton, 226-35, Def. 5; and rest, 27, 231 Def. 5; portional to magnitude of force acting, experiment of pendulum clock at St.
Vortex theory, 42, 60 n., 65, 66 n., 68, approximation to, by discrete impulses, 37, concept of force, 36, 37, inertial Helena, 58, 64, visits to Newton at
127 n. 19, 227 § 2, 228 n. 5, 233 n. 9, 18, 21, 70, 247, 252, 278 Theor. motion, 37, 42, 52 n., Merton Rule, Cambridge in 1684, 17 n., 23, 24, 75,
234 n. 18. I ; by which a body endeavours from io n ., 38,41, motion ( = momentum) 37, 97, lo i, 102, 103, 104, 107, 1 15.
j :?4 INDEX INDEX 3 35

Herivel, J. W., 103 n., 183, 208. 66 n., 67, 69, 125 n. 2, 132 n. 3, 197, Motion ( = M ovem ent); absolute, and en­ of extended body, 77-86, 143-5; of
Hooke, R., 24, 74, 75, 108, 303; and, con­ 198 n. 16, 279 Corol. 5 Scholium, 282 deavour from centre, 228 § 3, 310 globe, 122, 126 n. 7; of moon, 55, and
troversy with Newton over inverse Theor. 4, Def. 9, its distinguishing from relative test of inverse square law of gravitation,
square law of gravitation, 57, 58, 62, Kepler-motion, problem of, 13 n., 16 - motion, 57, 62, 310 Def. 9, 314 n. 7; 13, 14, 23, 58, 59, 60, 65-76, 89-90,
670., 7on., 71, 104, io6n., 237 n. i, con­ 22, 34 n., 60, 61, 7 1 ; solution to, 246- and, Descartes, 125, 127 n. 19, i6 o n . 4, 92, 132 n. 2, 302; of bodies toward one
troversy with Newton over optics, 15; 56, 278 T'heor. i, 281 Prob. 3, analytical 219, 227-30, 233 nn. 7 and 8, 234 n. 16, another, 77, 139 Def. 12; of planets,
his discussion with Halley and Wren in rather than synthetical, 13 n., 17 n. 310 Def. 9, 314 n. 8, impressed force, see under Kepler and Planets; of plane­
1684, 97, intervention of 1679, xiv, 13, Koyre, A., x iv n ., 16, 36, 42, 45 n., 57 n., 123, natural gravity, 121, 123, quantity, tary heavens, 301 B; o f projectiles, 12 1 -
14. 3 4 n., 7 5 . 1 14. 1 17. 238-45, 303 n. 59 n., 70 n., I l l n., 126 n. 16, 240 n. 123, rest, relative natures of, 318 Def. 3, 3, 302, and Galileo, 35, 36, 39, 41, 312
19, supposed discovery of parallax due spirit, 123; as state of body, 153 Ax. Law 2, in resisting medium, 287
to Earth’s annual motion, 238, 240 n. 2, Leibniz, G ., 5, 17 n., 29, 234 n. 19. 100, 156 Ax. 106, 160 n. 4. Prob. 7 Scholium, relative to rotating
theory of circular motion, 240, 242, Lever, principle of, 170 Prop. 34. centre of, in dynamical sense, 77, Earth, 238-45, 303 ; of solar system, 32;
242 n. 2. Levity, 289. 78-79, 80, 85, 138 Def. 10, 140 n. 12, orbital, and centripetal force, 13, 17 n.,
Horrox, J., 291 n. 30. Locke, J., 106, 108-17 pcissim, 120, 246, 209 § 4, 215 n. 8, in kinematical sense, 19, 55, 61, 73, 277-89; power to per­
Huygens, C., 14, 60, 72 n., 87, n o , 112, 254-s, 290 n. 8. 77-78 , 138 Def. 10, 140 n. 12, 144 A x. severe in, measure of, 208 § i ; relative,
132 nn. 6 and 7, 198, 236, 237 nn. 2 Lohne, J., 34 n. 13, 14a, IS, 145 Ax. 16, 17, 18, 209 § 4, its distinguishing from absolute motion,
and 3; and, centrifugal force, 6, 15, 56, Lucasian Chair of Mathematics, 72 n., of extended body, motion of, 176, 57, 62, 310 Def. 9, 314 n. 7, and con­
71, horizontal pendulum, 132 nn. 6 and 92, 98, 192. Prob. 37, of pair of bodies, 79, 80, 81, taining space, 299 Law 3, 313 Law 4;
7, problem of collisions, 4-5, 52. Lucretius, 303 n. 14. 84, 139 Def. II, 140 n. 13, 148 A x. 25, resolution of, 182, 209 § 3; second law
Hyperbola, motion in, 284. 209 § 4, of pair of bodies, motion of, 80, of, 20, 22, 26, 30-31, 161 n. 19, 246
Macclesfield Collection, 257. 162-70, of system of bodies, motion of, H yp. 2, 299 Law 2, 300, 312 Law 2,
Impetus, 27, 28, 231 Def. 7, 311 Def. 13, Mach, E., 25. 85, 209 § 4, 216 n. 13, 299 Law 4, 313 3 15 0 . 22, and Galileo, 35, 36, 37; third
318 Def. 3, 318 Def. 4, 320 n. 7; Magirus, J., i, 380., 121. Law 5. law of, 31, i6 i nn. 16 and 18, 312 Law
School, I. Alaier, A., 235 n. 32. circular ( — rotation), and distin­ 3, 315 n. 23; translational, 78; uniform,
Impulse, see under Force, impulsive. Marci, M ., 52 n. guishing between true and relative 312 Law I ; uniformly accelerated, in a
Indivisibles, method of, 244. Mass, and weight, 25, 127 n. 23, 231 § 8, motion, 57, 62, 310 Def. 9, and prin­ straight line, 7; violent, r, 43 n., 121-5.
Inertia, i, 26-28, 318 Def. 3; as internal 235 n. 24; centre of, and centre of ciple o f inertia, 312 Law i, angular
principle of conservation of rest or motion, 79, 85, 215 n. 8. quantity of, 78, axes of circulation of, Newton, I, and, apparent loss of interest
motion, 231 Def. 5; definition of, 231 Matter, quantity of, 317 Def. i, 319 210 § 5, 312 Law I, combination of, in dynamics betw een 1679 and 1684, 22,
Def, 8; principle of, 5, 28, 29-30, 35, Def. 7. 82, 210 § 7, continuation of, under no argument from simple to complex,
36, 43, 44-45, 141 A x. I, 2, 150 n. I, Mersenne, M ., 230. forces, 211 § 8, equator of circulation 78 n., assumption that distance moved
153 A x. 100, 234 n. 15, 246 Hyp. i, of, 210 § 5, measure of, 145 A x. 19, in given time proportional to force
Merton, College, 2 n. 3, 235 n. 32; Rule,
274 n. di, 277 Hyp. 2, 299 Law 1 ,3 1 2 10, 38, 41, 88. 209 § 5, 210 § 6, measurement of, in acting, 10, 22, attempted derivation of
Law I, 314 n. 21, for circular motion, Alore, H., 126 n. 16. terms of quantity of motion, 79, poles proportionality between force and
86; see also under Descartes and of circulation of, 210 § 5, principle of change of motion, 152-61, attraction of
More, L. T ., xiv, 15 n., n o n.
inertia for, 86, radius of circulation of, homogeneous sphere at external point,
Galileo. Moon. See under Endeavour, Gravitation,
Inertial movement, and Galileo, 37, 42, 81, 210 § 5, real quantity of, 81, 209 § 5, 23, calculations relating to comets in
Motion.
resolution of, 78. August 1685, 99, 102, confusion be-
52 n.; along tangent, 12, 18, 19; be­ Moscovici, S., 38 n.
tween impulses, 18. definition of, 136 Def. i, 226 Def. 4, tw'een motive and accelerative forces,
Motion ( = Momentum), and, Descartes,
310 Def. 9; determination of, 137 Def. 22, derivation of principle of lever, 170
Intension and remission of forms, 235 3, 8, 32, 49, 135 n. 4, Galileo, 37, power
4, 144 Ax. 15, and Descartes, 8, 140 Prop. 34, doctrine of intension and re­
n. 32. to persevere in state of movement, 137
n. 6; first law of, see under Inertia, mission of forms, 235 n. 32, drawing of
Intensity of power, 231 Def. ir. Def. 3; angular, principle of, 84;
principle o f; in circle, see Circle, axes of ellipse in error for conjugate
Isochronism of cycloidal pendulum, change of, and force, see under Force,
motion in; in curve, measurement of diameters, 17 n., exact formulation in
203-4. and change of motion; composition of,
velocity of, 149, 152 n. 20; in cycloid, principle of general solution to a prob­
law, i4 n ., 18, 31-32, 35, 39-40, 41, 182,
203-7; inertial, 12, 18, 19, and Galileo, lem 80, 84, exact law' of falling bodies,
Kepler, J., his first law o f planetary 209 § 3, 246 Hyp. 3, 278 Hyp. 3, 290 n.
37, 42, 52 n.; in ellipse, 7, 13, 16-20, 286 Prob. 5, explanation of invariable
motion, 16, 19, 22, 34 n., 102, 290 n. 6, 290 n. 8, 294, 299 Lemma i, 313
1 16, 130 § 3, 248-9, 251-4, 281-6; in aspect of Moon from Earth, 60, 236,
18, proposition corresponding to, 248 Lemma i ; conservation of, 3, 5,133 §§ 5,
hyperbola, 284, parabola, 284, in plena, extension of inverse square law down
Prop. 2, 251 Prop. 3, 281 Prob. 3; his 6, 135 n. 4, 142 A x. 7, 8, 159 A x. 122,
124, polygon, 9, II, resisting medium, to surface of the Earth, 23 n., extension
laws of planetary motion, 16, 42, 125 218 n. 25; definition of, 3, 136 Def. 2,
286-9; instantaneous direction of, 7 ; of Galileo’s law, i i , 190 n. 5, to
n. I, 281 Prob. 3 Scholiujn, 289 n. i; 3; gained or lost by reflection, 214 § 4,
in straight line, measure of velocity ot, case of non-uniform motion, 20, 22,
his second law of planetary motion, 16, 215 § 5; proportionality to, bulk, 133
149, 152 n. 20; in vacuo, 123-4; Kepler, 38 n., 109, 278 Hyp. 4, 279 Theor. 3,
19, 22, 34 n., qr, 78 n., 115, 255 n. 9, § 3, 135 n. 3, distance moved in given
see under Kepler-motion; laws of, 300 Lemma 2, 314 Lemma 2, geo­
290 n. 7, proposition corresponding to, time, 134 § 7, 135 n. 8; quantity of,
312-13, and Galileo, 31, 33, 35, corol­ metrical rather analytical proofs, 42,
246 Prop. I, 255 n. 9, 278 Thcor. i ; total, 3, 26, 49, 317 Def. 2, definition
laries to, 31-33, 315 nn. 25, 26 and 28. method of determining figures, 16 n..
his third law of planetary motion, 13, of, 3 11 Def. II, 317 Def. 2, 319 Def. 12.
336 INDEX 337
INDEX
Santlllana, G . de, 37 n., 132 n. 4, 189. Torricelli, E., 2, 238 n. 3.
17 n., nature of body, 219, necessity for Place, definition of, 226 Def. i, 310
Sine, versed, 22, 65. Toulmin, S., 29 n.
unique physical motion, 227 § 3, Royal Def. 7.
Singer, C., 36. Turnbull, H. W ., 183, 189.
Society of London, 94, 96, 97, 102, 103, Planets, com m on centre of gravity of,
Slusius, 66. Tum or, E., 15 n.
104, 105, 106, 107, 108, solution to 301B; determination of their orbits,
Kepler’s problem, 285, the falling 283 Scholium, 301B; force on 16, 18; Smith, Rev. B., 128.
Solar system, centre of gravity of, 85; Vacuum, 126 n. 15, 123-4.
apple, xiii, 65 n., 92, vectorial nature of force of, from Sun, 72; longitude of,
motion of, 32. Velocity, comparison of one w'ith another,
law of conservation of momentum, 285; mean distances of from Sun in
Space, 29, 208 § I, 219, 228-30; absolute, 2; composition of, 31, 32; definition of,
218 n. 25. relation to their periods of revolution,
309 Def. 3; of planetary heavens, its 3, 232 Def. 14, 311 Def. 10, 314 n. 9;
his absence from Cambridge due to 1 2 1 ; relative motion of, 301B; stability
motion, 301B; relative, 310 Def. 4. measurement of, 208 § i, for motion
plague, 92, Arithmetica Universalis, of their orbits, 59, 60, and Descartes
Speed, definition of, 136 n. 9. in, circle 145 Ax. 19, curved path, 149,
292 n. 38, attitude to hypotheses, i i i , 59 n., 227 § 2, 233 n. 10; their en­
Spirit, 123. 152 n. 20, straight line, 149, 152 n. 20;
1 12, belief in possibility of vacuum, deavour from Sun, 72, 197.
Spring of colliding bodies, 4. relative, of approach and separation of
123-4, belief in centrifugal force, 58- Plato, 125 n. 3.
Stability of lunar and planetary orbits, two colliding bodies, 4, 83, 143 A x. 9,
59, copy of Descartes’s Principia Philo- Polygon, motion in, 9, i i .
59, 60. 10, 151 n. 5, 213; resolution of, 14 n.,
sophiae, 51, 127 n. 20, departure from Portsmouth Collection, xiii n., xiv, xv,
State, motion as, 153 A x. 100, 156 Ax. 31, 39, 208 § 2.
Cartesian philosophy, 65, 67, drive 65 n., 96, 106, 208, 257.
106, 160 n. 4; perseverance of body in Vortex theory, see under Descartes.
towards generality, 77, 80, drive to­ Portsmouth Draft Memorandum, xiii n.,
its, 154, 155, 156; resistance to change
wards quantitative treatment o f dy­ 17 n., 66-67, 69, 70, 74, 92, 93 n.,
of, 318 Def. 3. Waard de, C ., 34 n., 303 n. 13.
namics, 5, 41, 132 n. 9, imagination of 125 n. 2, 191 n. 13.
Street, 125, 238 n. 2. Wallis, J., 4, 5, 52, 108, 238 n. 2.
an experiment to prove the diurnal Projectile, motion of, see under Motion.
Stukeley, W., xiii n., 65 n., 92. Weight, and bulk, 3 1 1 Def. 1 1 ; distinction
motion of the Earth, 16, 238-45, 310 Ptolemy, i i , 64.
Sullivan, J. W. N., xiv. betw'een mass and, 127 n. 23, 231 § 8,
Def. 4, mathematical researches, 15,
Qualities, absolute and relative, 312; Swiftness, estimation of, 136 Def. 2. 235 n. 24; proportionality of, to mass,
mother, 15, optical lectures, 98, optical
researches, 14, 15, 140 n. 9, Proposi- method of prime and ultimate, 3; 25-
moments of, 311 Def. 162; representa­ Tendency, centrifugal, as species of im­ Whewell, W., 34 n.
tiones de M otii, 23, 24, 96, 102, 105,
tives of, 299 Def. 4. peded force, 5 5; of M oon along tangent Whiston, W., xiii, 60 n., 65, 66 n., 6 7-
physical thought, the medieval back­
to her path, 65. passim, i i 7 n . , 1980. 8.
ground to, 121, 125 n. 3, preparation Reflection, of bodies, 4, 9, i i , 12, 18, Tim e, 219, absolute, definition of, 309 Whiteside, D . T ., 24 n., 34 n., 117 n.
for early discoveries in dynamics,
130 § 2, 137 Def. 5, 139 n. f, 142 A x. 9, Def. I ; relative, definition of, 309 Woolsthorpe, 14.
mathematics and optics, 121, researches 214 § 4, 215 § 5; optical, 181 n. 32. Def. 2. Wren, C., 4, 5, 52, 97, 242 n. 2.
in dynamics in 1684, 24, realization of Refraction of body, 138 Def. 7.
importance of direction of motion, 136 Relativity, Special Theory of, 160 n. 8.
n. 10, stepbrother, 15, stepfather, 128; Resistance, of air, compared with force of
on, body and time, 219, space, 219, gravity, 289; of ether, 301, 302; of
228-30. medium, 277 Def. 3, 299 Def. 3, 302,
Norwood, R., 66. 3 11 Def. 17, dependence on density and
speed, 277 Hyp. i, 299 Law 5, 302,
Ockham, W., 112, 126 n. 17. 313 Law 6; to change in state, 318
Oldenburg, H., 56, 57, 59, 60, 71, 74, Def. 3.
106, 236, 237 n. 3. Resisting medium, motion in, 286-9.
Optics, 14, 15, 98, 121, 140 n. 9. Resolution, of motion, 182, 209 § 3; of
Oughtred, W., 68 n. 3. velocity, 140., 31, 39, 208 § 2.
Rest, 231 Def. 5; and force, 27, 231
Paget, E., 17 n., 24, 93 n., 101-8, passim, Def. 5; and motion, relative nature of,
1 1 4 ,1 1 7 ,2 5 7 . 318 Def. 3; Definition of, 226 Def. 3,
Parabola, motion in, 284. 310 Def. 8; state of, 30.
Patterson, L. D ., xiii n. Restitution, coefficient of, 4.
Pelseneer, J., xiii n., x iv n ., 16, 245 n. Rigaud, S. P., xiii, 15 n., 102 n., 238 n. 2,
Pemberton, H., xiii, 23, 65, 66 n., 67, 257 n. 2, 291 n. 37, 292 n. 38.
68, 69, 70, 73, 74, 75, 92, 198 n. 8. Rooke, L., 4.
Pendulum, cycloidal, 72 n., 204-5; hori­ Roubiliac, L . F., 303 n. 14.
zontal, I I , 91, 131, 132 nn. 6 and 7, Royal Society of London, and problem of
186, 187; vertical, i i , 25, 58, 64, 125, collisions, 4, 5 n .; see also under
131, 186, 187, 231 § 8, 3 1 1 Def. II, Newton.
319 Def. 7.
Picard, J., 75. Salusbury, T ., 35, 37 n., 91, 183, 189,
Picot, 44 n. 238 n. 3.
PRIN TED IN G REAT BRITAIN
AT THE U N IV E R S IT Y PRESS, OXFORD
BY VIVIAN R ID L E R
PRINTER TO THE U N IV E R S IT Y

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi