Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 9

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/279925762

Values, Sociology of

Chapter · December 2015


DOI: 10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.32167-5

CITATION READS
1 6,348

1 author:

Helmut Thome
Martin Luther University Halle-Wittenberg
83 PUBLICATIONS   376 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Wertewandel View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Helmut Thome on 28 March 2018.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Author's personal copy

Provided for non-commercial research and educational use only.


Not for reproduction, distribution or commercial use.

This article was originally published in the International Encyclopedia of the Social
& Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, published by Elsevier, and the attached copy
is provided by Elsevier for the author’s benefit and for the benefit of the
author’s institution, for non-commercial research and educational use including
without limitation use in instruction at your institution, sending it to specific
colleagues who you know, and providing a copy to your institution’s administrator.

All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including


without limitation commercial reprints, selling or
licensing copies or access, or posting on open
internet sites, your personal or institution’s website or
repository, are prohibited. For exceptions, permission
may be sought for such use through Elsevier’s
permissions site at:
http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial

From Thome, H., 2015. Values, Sociology of. In: James D. Wright (editor-in-chief),
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Vol
25. Oxford: Elsevier. pp. 47–53.
ISBN: 9780080970868
Copyright © 2015 Elsevier Ltd. unless otherwise stated. All rights reserved.
Elsevier
Author's personal copy

Values, Sociology of
Helmut Thome, Martin-Luther-University Halle-Wittenberg, Halle-Wittenberg, Germany
Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
This article is a revision of the previous edition article by R. Rezsohazy, volume 24, pp. 16153–16158, Ó 2001, Elsevier Ltd.

Abstract

The first section of this article presents core elements in the object- or concept-focused definition of values, including some of
the functions ascribed to them: guiding and coordinating actions, marking personal and collective identities. The next section
introduces some additional analytical dimensions: the substantive, temporal, and social generalization of values; their
position in means–ends relationships; conceptual distinctions with regard to needs, attitudes, and norms. The third section
addresses some issues regarding the development of values on the personal and macrosocial level, concentrating on the
cognitive developmental approach. The final section presents a brief outline of two prominent approaches (initiated by
Inglehart and Schwartz) in studying the development and spread of values on the basis of data collected in a long-term series
of cross-national surveys conducted in an increasing number of countries worldwide.

Values are generally considered to play a crucial role in moti- be desired directly as such for whatever qualities it innately has
vating and guiding human action and to be constitutive (or is assumed to have). But in order to ‘value’ an object –
elements in the construction of personal and collective iden- according to Kluckhohn’s conception – it must fulfill certain
tities; they serve as a potent source of social integration but also criteria that transcend it. This transfer of meaning, however,
of conflict and division. Values are conceptualized quite may advance into something like a transformation of the
differently in various sociological theories. This article focuses object: it may take on a symbolic quality, which makes it
on those analytical distinctions and fundamental assumptions appear and then be treated as a value in itself, while its
that are widely shared among sociologists and other social connection to some ‘conception’ of desirability might recede in
scientists, but some of the issues on which theoretical per- the background; patriots, for example, may endow the national
spectives diverge will also be mentioned. flag with such a quality. Thus, the object-focused and the
concept-focused definitions are commensurate to some extent:
a value may be instantiated in or symbolically represented by
What Are ‘Values,’ How to Define Them? some object or behavior, which in turn becomes indicative of
the value construct.
There are numerous definitions – or rather explications of There is an element of circularity in Kluckhohn’s defini-
meaning – available in the sociological literature. Most of them tion: how can desirability be stated without referring to pre-
can be classified into two groups: (1) ‘values’ as something conceived values? This circularity can be mitigated by
directly attached or ascribed to preferred objects and (2) interpreting values as ‘second-order’ desires (H.G. Frankfurt)
‘values’ as (enduring) beliefs or conceptions that construe and explicating the experiences and processes by which values
something as preferable or desirable. The first approach is are generated or arrived at. A first-order desire can be
exemplified by Thomas and Znaniecki (1958: p. 21) who write: conceived as some want (drive, urge, impulse), directed
“By a social value we understand any datum having an toward some object that is given independently from any
empirical content accessible to the members of some social judgment regarding its appropriateness. We may act upon this
group and a meaning with regard to which it is or may be an want spontaneously. But since we experience different sorts of
object of activity. Thus, a foodstuff, an instrument, a coin, such first-order desires, some of them competing with each
a piece of poetry, a university, a myth, a scientific theory, are other and with those of other people, we are led into reflec-
social values.” In a similar vain, R.H. Turner (1968: p. 100) tions seeking or constructing criteria that enable us to evaluate
states: “A value is a category of objects..” The second and rank order our desires, abstracting and transforming them
approach, which has become the dominant one within soci- into second-order desires and, in an additional step, into
ology (in contrast to economic theory), is represented by C. a second-order volition. Of course, there is always the possi-
Kluckhohn (1951: p. 395) who, drawing upon Dewey, writes: bility of getting overwhelmed by our spontaneous urges and
“A value is a conception, explicit or implicit, distinctive of an desires.
individual or characteristic of a group, of the desirable which The evaluative standards applied in such processes comprise
influences the selection from available modes, means, and ends different elements; Parsons, for example, distinguishes cogni-
of action.” And he emphasizes, “that affective (‘desirable’), tive, appreciative, and moral standards (Parsons and Shils,
cognitive (‘conception’), and conative (‘selection’) elements are 1951: pp. 162ff.), and Kluckhohn (1951: p. 397) emphasizes
all essential to this notion of value” (ibid.). that “the consistent connection between values and notions of
The crucial point here is the distinction between something approval and disapproval implies the potentiality for rational
simply desired (matter-of-factly) and something conceived to justification”; he also sees a “union of reason and feeling
be desirable, based on some reasoned judgment. An object may inherent in the word value (ibid., 400).” The meaning of such

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 25 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.32167-5 47

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
Author's personal copy
48 Values, Sociology of

evaluative standards is revealed in binary (or bipolar) codes in they stabilize expectations needed to coordinate interaction
terms of which judgments are being made – like ‘good’ vs ‘evil/ over the long run. They perform these functions to the extent
bad’ (in the case of moral standards), or ‘true’ vs ‘false’ that they are uncontested. “They can be taken for granted and
(cognitive standards), ‘beautiful’ vs ‘ugly’ (aesthetic standards). this taken-for-grantedness can also be taken for granted”
Some of these codes may be applied reflexively. For example, (Luhmann, 1996: p. 31). In other situations, however, values
one may judge it as good or bad (right or wrong) to deliver or can also be disputed among persons and groups and thus
not deliver a moral judgment (in terms of good or bad) in instigate conflicts.
a specific situation; moralizing, however, might be considered
inappropriate with regard to certain issues in certain social
contexts. We thus move from second- to higher-order desires. Some Further Analytical Dimensions and Distinctions
The ‘moral matrix,’ i.e., the set of issues or dimensions
Dimensions of Generalization
requiring or allowing for moral judgment varies between
cultures and among social groups (Haidt, 2012). As concepts, values are symbolically (re-)presented by words,
Any culture offers to the person a repertoire of evaluative behavior (e.g., gestures and rituals), and visible objects (e.g.,
standards, social values; they are conveyed and inculcated, over badges or monuments). As symbols, they “involve ‘inter-
various stages of development, via socialization processes and personalizing’ the kind of ‘abstraction’ or ‘generalization’
supported by social practices and interaction rituals (Dur- which characterizes all stable systems of orientation” (Parsons
kheim, Collins), but they also need to be interpreted individ- and Shils, 1951: p. 161). Luhmann (1998: pp. 340f.)
ually and variedly depending on the specifics of the situational conceives of values as ‘symbolically generalized media of
context in which they are employed. A single act normally communication,’ and he distinguishes three interdependent
touches upon various (and often competing) values (like dimensions of generalization: the substantive, the temporal,
honesty and politeness); on the other hand, a single value may and the social.
be related to a larger set of actions. Values thus come into play The first dimension refers to the delimitation of semantic
not singularly but as a plurality, which means they must meaning, the substantive content, and thematic unity of the
somehow be harmonized, arranged into a value ‘system’ or concept, which is specified by some contrast or difference: what
comprehensive sets of value orientations in which they are pertains to it and what is excluded, e.g., equality vs inequality,
hierarchically ordered, to some extent at least. Such an respect vs disrespect, granted to whom and whom not. The
arrangement, however, must also allow for a considerable semantic meaning of a value concept can be abstracted to lower
degree of flexibility, it must remain open for context-specific or higher levels and specified across many or not so many
interpretations and modifications over time. In this sense, situations and institutional contexts.
values are enduring but not static. The temporal generalization is brought about by various
As cited above, Kluckhohn defines values as “distinctive of forms of custom building and habit forming or by explicit
an individual or characteristic of a group”; as such they may norm setting. Particularly, the norms connected with or in-
serve as markers of personal and collective identity. On what- herent in values lend certainty and stability to expectations
ever level of social generalization values are analytically derived from them: In case of disappointment it is not the
located, for most sociologists the concept contains an element expectation that needs to be corrected, rather the perpetrator is
of normativeness. Desirability implies a notion of shared in the wrong (on the distinction between norms and values see
beliefs and commitments, including a commitment to one’s below). Value surveys often fail to adequately capture the
true self, which incorporates the perspective of a ‘generalized element of normativity tight up with values.
other’ (Mead). The striving to realize some value is thus con- Social generalization seems to be an obvious ingredient of
nected with a sense of oughtness, something requested from values. They are shared among different persons – but shared to
oneself and from others, a request that, if not met, may elicit what extent? On the lower end of the scale we have ‘personal’ or
guilt and shame feelings (imposed upon oneself) or indigna- ‘privatized’ values, shared by only a few people; or they may be
tion and despise (at someone else), or, if met, pride and held in common by many people but unknowingly so and/or
respect. The reach and intensity of the ought component varies; without any normative request. ‘Social’ generalization is thus
there are values considered to be (more or less) ‘private,’ at intimately linked with temporal or normative generalization,
one’s personal disposal, others (particularly moral values) are and there are at least two subdimensions that need to be
more or less obligatory, and placed under public control. distinguished here. One is the factual range of agreement
Kluckhohn includes, as we have seen, a functional des- (consensus) or disagreement (dissent), the other is the
cription in his definition of values by stating that “[a] value assumed or perceived range of consensus or dissent. Perceived
influences the selection from available modes, means, and ends and factual agreement may fall apart in both directions. People
of action.” Some additional functions can be added here (for not only act on their own attitudes and personal values, but
a longer list see Rokeach, 1973: pp. 12–16): (1) Values not only also on what they perceive to be other people’s beliefs and
guide actions (though they are, by far, not the sole determi- values. Unfortunately, empirical value surveys usually limit
nant), they also influence perceptions and feeling states. (2) themselves to registering only the degree of factual consensus
They provide a ‘vocabulary of motives’ (Gerth and Mills, 1953), (by aggregating individual data, calculating means and vari-
which helps to make sense of and to interpret, explain, justify, ances); they regularly fail to ascertain at least the first level of
or criticize one’s own as well as other people’s behavior, reciprocity, i.e., their respondents’ perceptions of what other
prospectively and retrospectively. (3) Shared (social) values people think and value (more on this and normativity in
provide a base for commonalities and trustful communication; Thome, 2003).

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
Author's personal copy
Values, Sociology of 49

Instrumental and Terminal Values, Empirical concerning the interconnectedness of needs and values. They
and Transcendental Ends can be conceived as the input, the raw material from which
values are abstracted. Ball-Rokeach and Loges (1992: pp.
In his famous book on The Nature of Human Values, Rokeach
2222f.) contend that “(v)alues are cognitive representations of
(1973: pp. 7f.) distinguishes between ‘instrumental’ and
human needs . [they] unite individual’s needs with the
‘terminal’ values; in the same sense he also speaks of ‘means
broader needs of society.” Kluckhohn (1951: pp. 428f.) states:
and ends values.’ The former refers to ‘modes of conduct’ (e.g.,
“Values both rise from and create needs”, but he also notes that
being ‘ambitious,’ ‘self-controlled,’ ‘independent’), which are
“some choices do not involve value elements but solely need
thought to be instrumental in attaining the latter, also referred
elements.” The (relative) urgency of needs (depending on their
to as ‘end-states of existence,’ like ‘happiness,’ ‘freedom,’
respective level of satisfaction) changes with changing natural
‘salvation,’ or ‘self-respect’ (ibid., 12). When Rokeach considers
environments, technologies, and social conditions; needs may
all ‘moral’ values (like ‘honesty’) to form a subgroup within the
thus serve as a mediating factor in the development of values.
category of instrumental values, his conception runs counter to
what many other scholars construe as moral values. He
Attitudes
acknowledges the possibility “that one terminal value, so
Thomas and Znaniecki (1958: p. 22) define attitude as “indi-
defined, is instrumental to another terminal value or that an
vidual consciousness which determines real or possible activity
instrumental value is instrumental to another instrumental
of the individual.. The attitude is thus the individual coun-
value” (ibid.), but his focus lies on the assumption that there is
terpart of the social value.” Kluckhohn (1951: p. 423), too,
a certain type, a fixed set of values, which are all instrumental to
emphasizes the ‘exclusive referability to the individual’ as a core
a second type of values, the ‘terminal’ ones, which in turn
definitional element in the concept of ‘attitude,’ but he adds
cannot (by definition) be employed as means to attain an
a second ‘principal difference from value’ namely “absence of
‘instrumental’ value.
imputation of the ‘desirable.’” Though ‘attitude’ implies
Parsons’ conception of ‘means–ends chains’ is more flexible
a positive, negative, or indifferent stance taken toward some
on this: “concrete action does not take place in terms of isolated
object, for whatever reason, the concept as such implies no
ends with only one set of means, but rather in terms of very
element of oughtness. Attitudes may engage values, but values
long and complex ‘chains’ of means-end relationships, so
may also become the object of an attitude.
constituted that the ‘end’ of one sector of the chain is a means
to some further end (or more than one)” (Parsons, 1990: p.
Norms
322). The ultimate ends (Parsons also speaks of ‘ultimate ends
Norms are generally defined as (formally or informally given)
or values,’ p. 323) envisioned or gradually emerging (in the
rules about what persons – in most cases a specified set of
course of action) can be ‘empirical’ or ‘transcendental.’ Whether
persons – ought to do or not to do in given circumstances,
or not an empirical end is reached (by causally adequate
enforced by the threat of sanctions in the case of transgression.
means) can be checked by the actor and by an outside observer.
In contrast, values inspire and guide behavior, but they are
Whether or not a transcendental end has been attained is not
quite independent of specific situations, and they do not
arguable by an external observer in terms of scientific criteria. In
directly prescribe or proscribe a specific behavior. Norms are
this case, the means–ends relationship becomes ‘symbolic,’ e.g.,
restrictive in their sheer oughtness; values instead are
when people perform religious rituals. The ‘symbolic appro-
enhancing, they inspire a striving for something ‘greater than
priateness’ attributable to this relationship can be interpreted
oneself’ (see the concluding paragraph in the third section
by an external observer, it does not need to be explicitly
below).
conscious to the actor himself (Parsons, 1968: p. 258).
Values are regularly employed to justify and legitimate
Means–ends relationships are often looked at in only one
norms, but it can be misleading to say of norms (making it
direction: what has been attained as an end can, in the next
a part of their definition) that they ‘specify’ values, or that they
step, be employed as a means to reach another end. But Simmel
are ‘derived’ from them. Norms are needed to coordinate action
already pointed out that originally trivial means can be turned
and maintain social order particularly in circumstances where
into (ultimate) ends, referring to money as a striking example.
the actors involved hold different or conflicting values. To
perform this function (especially in highly differentiated soci-
eties), there must be available a repertoire of (mainly legal)
Related Concepts: Needs, Attitudes, and Norms
norms that are neutral with regard to any set of potentially
Needs conflictive particularistic values (see the long-standing discus-
Needs are generally conceived as more or less urgent wants or sions about the nature of ‘positive’ law and the relationship
desires, which are registered or make themselves felt as such by between legitimacy and legality). The construal of more highly
the actor herself/himself or by an observer. They can be given abstracted values that transcend the apparent discrepancies
independently from any evaluation (i.e., they are ‘first-order between more concretely specified values may also help to
desires’), though the way they are shaped and perceived (e.g., as prevent or mitigate conflict. Individuals who are in disagree-
necessities that assure survival in a natural and social envi- ment with norms that are imposed upon them might still
ronment) is likely to be influenced by some evaluative reflec- decide to obey them, not only for fear of sanctions but also
tions or other external considerations. Often they are seen as because they have made their compliance to legitimately
rooted in the organic system (physiological processes) or in established common or legal norms, a higher-order norm
‘human nature’ (including its social embeddedness), inde- (a principle) that they are willing to adhere to in order to serve
pendent from one’s volition. There are different conceptions the (universally) valued goal of peaceful coordination of

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
Author's personal copy
50 Values, Sociology of

action, whatever conflicts might arise on the level of lower- motivation are now seen as independent dimensions (Colby
order values. When norms are highly abstracted and formu- and Damon, 1995; Nunner-Winkler, 2004: pp. 306f.). Each
lated as principles, the analytical difference to values might get level of cognitive moral understanding can be associated with
blurred. These constellations have also triggered much theo- different types and varied strength of moral motivation,
retical debate among philosophers and social scientists seeking though some (correlational) affinity between these
to clarify the priority relationship between the ‘right’ and the dimensions seems to persist. A high level of moral
‘good.’ understanding might be tied up with a high level of moral
motivation: acting morally may become a central part of
a person’s self-identity; but it can also be associated with
Developmental Perspectives: Adopting, Generating, a low level of motivation or with an inclination to make use
and Changing Values of ‘neutralization techniques’ and cognitive distortions, which
pave the way to moral disengagement (Bandura et al., 1996).
The adoption and reconstruction of values on the personal There is also some debate on whether or not or in which way
level and in different stages of life have mainly been concep- such a ‘minimalized’ set of highly abstracted and universally
tualized and studied as a major element in processes of valid moral principles (most essentially: not to inflict harm
socialization shaped by the given and further evolving (sub-) on other people) can be or in fact are supplemented with
cultural systems and by their respective location within the more concretely prescribed moral rules associated with
differentiated structure of social systems. These processes have broader sets of values concerning the ‘good life’ as perceived
been theorized in widely differing ways by psychologists and and construed within particular communities of varied size
social scientists. In this section, I will concentrate on core and social location (see, e.g., Joas, 2000).
concepts of the cognitive developmental approach, which Nunner-Winkler (2004) registers a large-scale historical
focuses on moral norms and values and has its major roots in trend in societal development that has strengthened the
the work of Kohlberg. This approach is particularly interesting advancement toward higher levels of moral reasoning reached
because it offers hypotheses and empirical insights not only on by a growing number of individual persons. Her starting point
personal development, but also relates these processes to is Elias’ claim that there is a coevolution of societal and
certain features of large-scale societal structures that have been personality structure (Elias, 1994). In these processes, chains
evolving in recent history. At the end of this section, I will of interdependence among increasing numbers of interacting
briefly point out a rather different approach, which conceives of persons, institutions, and administrative units were elongated,
identity-constitutive values as arising out of emotion-laden thus calling for ever more individual insight and
‘experiences of self-transcendence.’ considerateness, i.e., self-control. Consequently, ‘outside
Kohlberg (1981, 1984) describes individual moral devel- constraints’ (level 1 in Kohlberg’s developmental theory) were
opment as a sequence of three major (and further subdivided) more and more replaced by internalized ‘self-constraints’
stages characterized by rising levels of (cognitive) under- (level 2). Many other theoretical models for analyzing long-
standing and different types of conformity motives. At the term societal developments could be introduced at this point,
‘preconventional level,’ norms are taken to be valid because e.g., Durkheim’s ideas on the erosion of collectivism; Weber’s
they are (re-)presented by authorities; they are followed in propositions concerning the increasing and multifaceted
order to avoid punishment or receive rewards. At the import of processes of rationalization; Riesman’s theses on
‘conventional level,’ moral values and the norms associated the shifting weights of tradition-, inner-, and outer-directed
with them are deemed valid because they are propagated in orientations as characteristic features of evolving cultures and
one’s group or society; they are primarily accepted and obeyed personality structures; more recent work by Wouters (1986)
in order to gain social acceptance and to avert guilt feelings. At has emphasized the increasing importance of processes of
the ‘postconventional level,’ reached by a smaller portion of ‘informalization.’ Most theorists are agreed upon assuming
people, individuals ascribe superior validity to universal moral that societies in the long run have become less hierarchically
principles (centered around the concepts of justice and fairness organized and more differentiated into interdependent
and equal basic worth of all human beings), which they respect subsystems performing specialized functions more or less
and voluntarily submit to on the basis of reasoned insight in autonomously and reaching out beyond national boundaries.
their legitimacy. The major factor propelling forward this These processes – including the dismantling of hierarchical
movement from one stage to the next, Kohlberg (taking the structures within the family – have made individuals become
lead from Piaget) saw in the developmental ‘logic’ inherent in increasingly more autonomous: free, but also forced, to make
the ontogenetic advancement of cognitive capacities from early their own choices, free to enter cooperative relationships but
childhood into adolescence. He also assumed a gradually also pushed to develop their competitive capacities. According
increasing consistency between the cognitive and the motiva- to Nunner-Winkler (and others), the sociohistorical changes
tional dimension of moral development, between judgments in societal structure and in socialization styles have, on the
(concerning the rightness of moral norms and the validity of level of individual personalities, promoted the transition from
moral values) and the willingness (motivation) to act in the second to the third level of Kohlberg’s scheme of moral
accordance with them. development: “a change from super-ego controls and
More recent research has led to several modifications and habitualized conformity dispositions towards more ego-
additional analytic distinctions. A major correction achieved syntonic types of conformity motivations” (Nunner-Winkler,
herein was to differentiate and disentangle the cognitive and 2004: pp. 309f.). But she also warns that “there might be
the motivational dimension – moral understanding and moral a rising risk that the increasing availability of ego-syntonic

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
Author's personal copy
Values, Sociology of 51

conformity motivation might go along with the dismantling of Values Surveys he has initiated. Since the mid-1990s, another
previously reliable barriers against amorality” (Nunner- approach on cross-cultural value research developed by S.H.
Winkler, 2000: p. 239). The structurally induced release from Schwartz, has received increasing attention as well. What
moral bind has been a central topic in theories of anomie, follows here is a brief outline of the major concepts and
with a broad range of empirical evidence particularly empirical findings advanced in both of these research groups
produced in studies of crime development (see, e.g., Messner (with respect to Inglehart, I draw upon a more
et al., 2008). comprehensive review in Thome, 2008). I also want at least
As indicated above, cognitive developmental theories assume to mention the cross-cultural studies by Hofstede (1980,
that on the highest level of personal moral development high- 2001) and by Triandis (1995) as well as the values research
conformity motives, i.e., the willingness to act in accordance based on experimental gaming strategies applied in
with moral values and norms considered universally valid, a laboratory setting (see, e.g., Wilke et al., 1986), which I
emanates directly from one’s reasoned insight into what is cannot review here due to space limitations (for an overview
‘right.’ Other scholars have argued that rational reflections as on these approaches see Karp, 2000).
such cannot produce motivation, that there is no motivation Inglehart is best known for his interpretation of value
without the press of emotions. Joas (2000), drawing on Ch. change (since the late 1960s) as a shift in preferences away
Taylor and others, expounds the idea that motivating from ‘materialist’ to ‘postmaterialist’ values. His initial
conceptions of the desirable are anchored in and ultimately hypotheses were derived from Maslow’s theses on need hier-
emerge from emotion-laden experiences of self-transcendence, archies (Maslow, 1954) stating that “people act to fulfill
in which a person is captivated by something that carries her a number of different needs, which are pursued in hierarchical
beyond her personal self, without losing it. Such (elevating, but order, according to their relative urgency for survival”
in other cases dejecting) experiences are evoked when (Inglehart, 1997: p. 22). On this view, the physical need for
smoothly proceeding routine activities of everyday life get sustenance and freedom from bodily harm takes precedence
interrupted or turned into a new and unexpected direction, over all else. Only to the extent that these are satisfied do we,
thus calling into question previous paths of behavior and according to these assumptions, turn our attention to the
hitherto held beliefs and interpretations. Examples are religious social need to belong and to be respected, and finally to the
revelations, falling in love, loosing one’s job, getting intensely personal need for self-actualization. With respect to political
praised or humiliated, having a friend dying in an accident, objectives (Inglehart’s primary value indicators), basic needs
being suddenly confronted with the misery of other people. find expression, for example, in the pursuit of economic
The elevating or disturbing feelings elicited in such situations stability and continuous growth; the need for security
call for articulation and narration in order to find new requires public order and protection from criminality and
interpretations that clarify, partially revise and partially (seemingly) hostile countries; the need to belong and to be
confirm, one’s own standing on what is good or bad (values) given respect motivates calls for participation in the
and how this is related to what is right or wrong (in terms of workplace and in politics; self-actualization requires legally
norms). In this perspective, the adequacy of norms can be enshrined freedoms and opportunities to arrange our lives as
judged rationally (with regard to their efficiency in we see fit. Inglehart’s idea was to ask people how urgent they
coordinating social action), the validity of values, however, is considered political goals he presented to them via
comprehended in the interplay of reflections and emotions questionnaire items classified in this way as indicating
arising from elevating or disturbing experiences that press for a stronger or weaker leaning toward the materialist or
articulation and interpretation (for a challenging view on the postmaterialist pole of such value orientations. The item
role of emotions in grounding moral values see De Sousa, 2008). batteries that Inglehart had designed to measure value
orientations via a rank ordering of political goals were
included in the Eurobarometer Surveys (EBS) conducted on
Empirical Research on Values and Value Change behalf of the European Commission since 1973 twice a year
(the data are available as an online trend file, see references
There is a long tradition of empirical studies on values and below, which also includes data from three earlier European
value change, in which a large array of strategies and tech- surveys as well). In addition to the EBS, Inglehart et al.
niques has been used to collect information and interpret data initiated more comprehensive European Values Studies and
from all sorts of written text, from participant and nonpartic- World Values Surveys starting in 1981, now in its sixth wave
ipant observation, from face-to-face interviews or scheduled to be concluded in March 2014. These surveys
questionnaire responses. A brief overview of empirical value have by now covered about hundred countries in all
studies of various types produced till the early 1980s is continents.
offered by Spates (1983). To study values in national and The European data till (roughly) 1990 confirmed, by and
cross-national perspective, large-scale survey studies based large, Inglehart’s prognoses concerning the shift toward post-
on representative samples of whole populations (or of materialism in central European countries. Since then the trends
specific subpopulations like highly qualified employees of diverged cross nationally, and despite further economic growth
large corporations, school teachers, or university students) postmaterialism declined in several countries. There was (and still
and repeated overtime have become the prime research is) considerable debate not only on Inglehart’s way of theorizing,
instrument. Since the 1970s, sociological discussions on but also on the adequacy of his instruments of measurement (see,
value change have been increasingly dominated by the work e.g., Clarke, 2000; Flanagan, 1987; Vinken, 2006), which have
of Inglehart (e.g., 1977, 1997) and the European and World become increasingly questionable as the surveys were expanded

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
Author's personal copy
52 Values, Sociology of

to include non-European countries as well. Inglehart himself has (Schwartz, 1994): power, achievement, hedonism,
extended his system for categorizing relevant value orientations. stimulation, self-direction, universalism, benevolence,
The dimension of materialism vs postmaterialism has been tradition, conformity, security. According to Schwartz, these
embedded in the more broadly conceived dimension of values represent three ‘universal requirements of human
‘survival vs self-expression,’ which includes additional existence,’ which he does not rank in advance: needs of
measurements of subjective well-being, trust in other people, individuals as biological organisms, coordinated social
political engagement, and tolerance for nonconformist interaction, survival, and welfare needs of groups. Surveys
lifestyles. The ensuing research has made increasingly clear that conducted in a set of 66 nations proved 45 of the 56
there has not been a departure from materialist values but (occasionally 57) value items to have similar meanings
rather an increasing emphasis on combining economic across nations (Schwartz, 2004). The 10 basic values are
prosperity with libertarian, antiauthoritarian value orientations grouped along two higher-order bipolar dimensions: the first
(Welzel, 2009). Inglehart has also constructed a second contrasts ‘openness to change’ (seeking stimulation and self-
analytical dimension, which contrasts ‘traditional’ and ‘secular- direction) with ‘conservation’ values (seeking security and
rational’ orientations (Inglehart and Baker, 2000; Inglehart and conformity, upholding tradition), the second opposes ‘self-
Welzel, 2010). Key points here are belief in God and religious transcendence’ (orientation toward universalism and
commitments, respect for authorities, regard for one’s own benevolence) with ‘self-enhancement’ (seeking achievement
nation and the family. Inglehart acknowledges in principle that and power); the tenth value, hedonism, cuts across the
these two dimensions may be combined in different ways in borderlines between self-enhancement and openeness to
different countries. While a continuous increase in economic change. Thus, the 10 basic values can be ordered to be more
prosperity promotes both secularization and self-expression congruent or more opposing to each other, rather close or
values, this development is ‘path dependent,’ considerably rather remote in their meaning. Schwartz (1994: p. 97) sees
determined by cultural traditions. Nevertheless, for the long run the cultural and the individual level of values conceptually
he sees both dimensions converge into a two-stage process of related, but he also points to specific cultural differences in
‘modernization’: Traditional values are replaced (or dominated) dealing with ‘critical issues that confront all societies.’ He
by secular-rational values in the process of industrialization; classifies these into three bipolar dimensions referring to the
self-expression values become predominant during the relative weight given to (a): ‘embeddedness’ vs affective or
transition from industrial to postindustrial (postmodern) intellectual ‘autonomy’ (of individuals in relation to social
societies. More recently, this approach has been further groups), (b) ‘hierarchy’ vs ‘egalitarianism’ (with respect to
expanded and modified into a ‘human development model’ social status and power distribution), and (c) ‘harmony’ vs
(Welzel and Inglehart, 2010). ‘mastery’ (striving for peace and for unity with nature, or for
Inglehart’s ordering of countries from all continents along self-assertion in attaining group or personal goals)
these two analytical dimensions is, in its overall configura- (Schwartz, 2004: pp. 45f.). This scheme thus comprises
tion, pretty much what one might expect. European countries seven categories of opposed or supplementary cultural
with large portions of Protestants load high on both orientations. Schwartz sees the validity of this scheme
analytical dimensions, those with large portions of Catholics confirmed by empirical analyses based on data collected on
are located around the center, whereas South-Asian and those 45 value items that were found to have similar
Islamic countries rank low on both dimensions. However, meanings across nations and cultures. For 67 nations and
it appears highly problematic (in some cases at least, e.g., cultural groups (represented by teacher and student
when inquiring religious beliefs) to use identical samples), the mean scores for each of these items were
questionnaire items in very different cultural regions. More registered and pairwise correlated. Multidimensional scaling
generally, it is highly problematic to use questionnaire analyses were then performed to map the cultural differences
items (as Inglehart does), which address different categories between nations. In this way Schwartz identified seven
of values on rather different levels of analytical abstraction transnational cultural groupings, which show ‘striking
and specificity. Also, the rankings of a set of value items parallels’ with the clusters found by Inglehart (based on
(particularly if specified as political goals) might be different analytical dimensions). So, for example, West
strongly influenced not just by the degree of desirability European countries load high on autonomy, egalitarianism,
ascribed to them, but also by the degree to which and harmony, whereas Confucian countries lean toward the
respondents consider them to be at risk or rather fulfilled opposite pole on all of these dimensions: embeddedness,
under given circumstances. These assessments should hierarchy, and mastery.
therefore also be explicitly measured in these surveys and Schwartz et al. (2001) also developed a second measurement
statistically controlled for when evaluating priority rankings instrument, the 40-item ‘Portrait Values Questionnaire’ (PVQ),
of values (cf Thome, 2003). which demands lower levels of abstract thinking so that it can
A theoretically and methodologically more elaborated be used in large population surveys not limited (like the
system of value categories and survey instruments applied in original instrument) to samples of highly educated people.
cross-cultural studies has been worked out by the social This instrument, too, has been validated across many cultures.
psychologist S. H. Schwartz (drawing on Hofstede, 1980). To be included in the series of European Social Surveys (ESS)
He has proposed a system of 10 basic value types, each starting (with 2 years interval) in 2002/03, a shortened,
specified by individual-level motivational emphasis and 21-items version of the PVQ has also been set up. In the
translated into a set of more than 50 personal goals meantime it has been shown, however, that this instrument

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
Author's personal copy
Values, Sociology of 53

does not represent the full range of the 10 value types identified Messner, S.F., Thome, H., Rosenfeld, R., 2008. Institutions, anomie, and violent
before (Meuleman et al., 2012). A thoroughly conducted crime. Clarifying and elaborating institutional-anomie theory. International Journal
of Conflict and Violence 2, 163–181.
comparative assessment of the validity of both the Inglehart
Meuleman, B., Davidov, D., Schmidt, P., Billiet, J., 2012. Social location and value
and the Schwartz value theories is offered by Datler et al. (2013). priorities. A European-wide comparison of the relation between social-structural
variables and human values. In: Gabriel, O., Keil, S.I. (Eds.), Society and
Democracy in Europe. Routledge, New York, pp. 45–67.
See also: Anomie; Collective Beliefs, Sociological Explanation Nunner-Winkler, G., 2000. Von Selbstzwängen zur Selbstbindung (und Nutzenkal-
of; Culture, Sociology of; Modernization, Sociological Theories külen). In: Endreß, M., Roughley, N. (Eds.), Anthropologie und Moral. Philoso-
of; Norms; Public Opinion: Social Attitudes. phische und soziologische Perspektiven. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg,
pp. 211–243.
Nunner-Winkler, G., 2004. Sociohistoric changes in the structure of moral motivation.
In: Lapsley, D.K., Narvaez, D. (Eds.), Moral Development, Self, and Identity.
Lawrence Erlbaum Ass, Mahwah, NJ, pp. 299–334.
Bibliography Parsons, T., 1968. The Structure of Social Action. Free Press, New York (Orig.
publ. 1937).
Ball-Rokeach, S.J., Loges, W.E., 1992. Value theory and research. In: Borgatta, E.F., Parsons, T., 1990. Prolegomena to a theory of social institutions. American Socio-
Borgatta, M.L. (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Sociology, vol. 4. Macmillan, New York, logical Review 55, 319–333.
pp. 2222–2228. Parsons, T., Shils, E.A., 1951. Values, motives, and systems of action. In:
Bandura, A., Barbaranelli, C., Caprara, G.V., Patorelle, C., 1996. Mechanisms of Parsons, T., Shils, E.A. (Eds.), Toward a General Theory of Action. Harvard
moral disengagement in the exercise of moral agency. Journal of Personality and University Press, Harvard, pp. 47–243.
Social Psychology 71, 364–374. Rokeach, M., 1973. The Nature of Human Values. The Free Press, New York.
Clarke, H.D., 2000. Refutations affirmed: conversations concerning the Euro- Schwartz, S.H., 1994. Beyond individualism/collectivism. New cultural dimensions of
barometer values battery. Political Research Quarterly 53, 477–494. values. In: Kim, U., Triandis, H.C., Kâgitçibaşi, Ç., Choi, S.-C., Yoon, G. (Eds.),
Colby, A., Damon, W., 1995. The development of extraordinary moral commitment. Individualism and Collectivism. Theory, Method, and Applications. Sage, Thou-
In: Killen, M., Hart, D. (Eds.), Morality in Everyday Life. Developmental sand Oaks, pp. 85–119.
Perspectives. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 342–370. Schwartz, S.H., Melech, G., Lehmann, A., Burgess, S., Harris, M., Owens, V., 2001.
Datler, G., Jagodzinski, W., Schmidt, P., 2013. Two theories on the test bench: Extending the cross-cultural validity of the theory of basic human values with a different
internal and external validity of the theories of Ronald Inglehart and Shalom method of measurement. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 32, 519–542.
Schwartz. Social Science Research 42, 906–925. Schwartz, S.H., 2004. Mapping and interpreting cultural differences around the
De Sousa, R., 2008. Really, what else is there? Emotion, values, and morality. Critical world. In: Vinken, H., Seoters, J., Ester, P. (Eds.), Comparing Cultures. Dimen-
Quarterly 50, 12–23. sions of Culture in a Comparative Perspective. Koninklijke Brill, Leiden, Nether-
Elias, N., 1994. The Civilizing Process. Blackwell, London (German orig. 1939). lands, pp. 43–73.
Flanagan, S.C., 1987. Values in industrial societies. American Political Science Spates, J.L., 1983. The sociology of values. Annual Review of Sociology 9, 27–49.
Review 81, 1303–1319. Thomas, W.I., Znaniecki, F., 1958. The Polish Peasant in Europe and America,
Gerth, H., Mills, C.W., 1953. Character and Social Structure. The Psychology of second ed., vol. 1. Dover Publ, New York (originally published in 5 Volumes
Social Institutions. Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc., New York. 1918–1920).
Haidt, J., 2012. The Righteous Mind. Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Thome, H., 2003. Soziologische Wertforschung. Ein von Niklas Luhmann inspirierter
Religion. Penguin, London. Vorschlag für die engere Verknüpfung von Theorie und Empirie. Zeitschrift für
Hofstede, G., 1980. Culture’s Consequences: International Differences in Work- Soziologie 32, 4–28.
Related Values. Sage, Beverly Hills. Thome, H., 2008. Value change in Europe from the perspective of empirical social
Hofstede, G., 2001. Culture’s Consequences. Comparing Values, Behaviors, Insti- research. In: Joas, H., Wiegandt, K. (Eds.), The Cultural Values of Europe. Liv-
tutions, and Organizations across Nations. Sage, Beverly Hills. erpool University Press, Liverpool, pp. 277–319.
Inglehart, R., 1977. The Silent Revolution. Changing Values and Political Styles in Trandis, H.C., 1995. Individualism and Collectivism. Westview, Boulder, CO.
Advance Industrial Society. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ. Turner, R.H., 1968. The self-conception in social interaction. In: Gordon, C.,
Inglehart, R., 1997. Modernization and Postmodernization. Cultural, Economic, and Gergen, K.J. (Eds.), The Self in Social Interaction. Wiley, New York.
Political Chance in 43 Societies. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ. Vinken, H., 2006. East Asian Values Surveys. Making a Case for East Asian-Origin
Inglehart, R., Baker, W., 2000. Modernization, cultural change, and the persistence Values Survey Concepts. Working paper no. 5 in 2006: ZUMA-Arbeitsbericht
of traditional values. American Sociological Review 65, 19–51. Nr. 2006/05. Mannheim.
Inglehart, R., Welzel, C., 2010. Changing mass priorities: the link between Welzel, C., 2009. Werte- und Wertewandelforschung. In: Kaina, V., Römmele, A.
modernization and democracy. Perspectives on Politics 8, 551–567. (Eds.), Politische Soziologie. VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften, Wiesbaden,
Joas, H., 2000. The Genesis of Values. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL pp. 109–139.
(German original 1997). Welzel, C., Inglehart, R., 2010. Agency, values, and well-being: a human
Karp, D.R., 2000. Values theory and research. In: Borgatta, E.F., Montgomery, R.J.V. development model. Social Indicators Research 97, 43–63.
(Eds.), Encyclopedia of Sociology, vol. 5. Macmillan Reference USA, New York, Wilke, H.A.M., Messick, D.M., Rutte, C.G. (Eds.), 1986. Experimental Social
pp. 3212–3227. Dilemmas. Peter Lang, Frankfurt.
Kluckhohn, C., 1951. Values and value-orientations in the theory of action. An exploration Wouters, C., 1986. Formalization and informalization: changing tension balances in
in definition and classification. In: Parsons, T., Shils, E.A. (Eds.), Toward a General civilizing process, theory. Culture & Society 3, 1–18.
Theory of Action, second ed. Harvard University Press, Harvard, pp. 388–464.
Kohlberg, L., 1981. Essays on Moral Development. In: The Philosophy of Moral
Development. Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice, vol. 1. Harper & Row, San Relevant Websites
Francisco.
Kohlberg, L., 1984. Essays on Moral Development. In: The Psychology of Moral
http://ec.europa.eu/public-opinion – Eurobarometer.
Development. The Nature and Validity of Moral Stages, vol. 2. Harper & Row, San
http://www.europeansocialsurvey.org – European Social Survey.
Francisco.
http://europeanvaluesstudy.eu – European Values Study.
Luhmann, N., 1996. The sociology of the moral and ethics. International Sociology
http://worldvaluessurvey.org – World Values Study.
11, 27–36.
(They all refer to the last section: Empirical Research on Values and Value Change).
Luhmann, N., 1998. Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am.
Maslow, A.H., 1954. Motivation and Personality. Harper and Row, New York.

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 47–53
View publication stats

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi