Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 13

Truth as Transcendental in Thomas Aquinas* Jan A.

Aertsen

Abstract. Aquinas presents his most complete exposition of the originality of Thomas's doctrine becomes manifest, and
transcendentals in De veritate 1, 1, that deals with the question that it is not by accident he presents his most complete
"What is truth?". The thesis of this paper is that the question of truth exposition of it in De veritate 1, 1.
is essential for the understanding of his doctrine of the transcen-
I develop this thesis in two parts. The first part
dentals.
The first part of the paper (sections 1--4) analyzes Thomas's (Sections 1--4) analyzes Thomas's conception of truth,
conception of truth. Two approaches to truth can be found in his and shows that his conception differs fundamentally
work. The first approach, based on Aristotle's claim that "truth is not from that of his contemporaries, particularly at those
in things but in the mind", leads to the idea that the proper place of points regarded as essential conditions for the tran-
truth is in the intellect. The second approach is ontological:Thomas scendentality of truth at the time. The second part
also acknowledges that there is truth in every being. The famous
(Sections 5--7) deals with the manner in which Thomas
definition of truth as "adequation of thing and intellect" enables him
to integrate the two approaches. Truth is a relation between two gives truth a place in the doctrine of the transcendentals.
terms, both of which can be called "true" because both are essential In this part it will become clear that his conception of
for the conformitybetween thing and intellect. truth leads to important innovations in this doctrine.
The second part of the paper (sections 5--7) deals with the
manner in which Thomas gives truth a place in the doctrine of the
transcendentals, and shows that his conception of truth leads to (1) A "magisterial" definition of truth: "the indivision
important innovations in this doctrine: the introduction of relational of being and that which is"
transcendentals and the correlation between spirit and being. If
"truth" is transcendental, it must be convertible with "being". Sect. 6 In his reply to the question as to what truth is, Thomas
discusses objections that Thomas advances himself to this converti- mentions in De veritate 1, 1, several definitions of truth
bility. Sect. 7 deals with a difficulty in his account of truth as a from the history of philosophy. 1 He presents definitions
relational transcendental. Ontological truth expresses a relation to
from Greek philosophy (Aristotle), the patristic period
an intellect but the relation to the human intellect is accidental for
the truth of things. Essential for their truth can only be a practical (Augustine and Hilary of Poitiers), early medieval
intellect that causes things. In this way, Thomas argues, the divine thought (Anselm of Canterbury), and Arabic philoso-
intellect relates to all things. phy (Avicenna). A n o t h e r definition of truth that appears
is the formula "adequation of thing and intellect", which
Thomas attributes to a Jewish philosopher of the tenth
Thomas Aquinas never wrote a separate treatise on the century, Isafic Israeli. Scholars have not been able,
transcendentals. He does, however, present a compara- however, to locate this definition in his works. 2 In
tively extensive exposition of this subject in his disputed addition, Thomas mentions an anonymous definition:
questions De veritate, which date from around 1255. Q. "The true is the indivision of being and that which is"
1, a. 1, deals with the question "What is truth?", and (verum est indivisio esse et quod est). It is to this latter
contains Thomas's most complete account of the con- definition that I want to devote attention initially.
cepts that "express a general m o d e of being". In the In another work (In I Sent., 19, 5, 1) Thomas calls
secondary literature this account is often discussed in this definition magistralis, which means that it was the
isolation from the context of the question of truth within definition of the magistri of the university. Indeed, we
which it is found. In my paper I intend to show that this find this definition in Albert the Great, Alexander of
context is essential for the understanding of Thomas's Hales, and Bonaventure) Of the definitions presented
doctrine of the transcendentals. My thesis is that it is in De veritate, the indivision formula is thus the most
precisely in relation to his conception of truth that the recent one.

Topoi 11: 159--171, 1992.


© 1992 KluwerAcademic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
160 J A N A. A E R T S E N

The origin of this definition can be traced back to the Great. 9 That their search was unsuccessful is not
Summa de bono (1230) of Philip the Chancellor. This surprising, however, for it seems plausible that it was
fact is of great importance because Philip's work, Philip himself who framed this definition. He borrowed
written twenty-five years before Thomas's De veritate, is its elements from two "metaphysicians", Aristotle and
usually regarded as the first account of the transcen- Boethius. 1°
dentals.4 In the Prologue of his Summa, Philip says that The central element in his definition is the notion of
he will deal with what is most general, namely, "being", "indivision". Now, it is striking that earlier in the
"one", "true", and "good".5 In the second question he Summa Philip defines "the good" in terms of "indivi-
discusses the relation of the true to being. sion" also. The reason he adduces for this is that the
The starting point of Philip's discussion are five most general must be defined "in the way one (unum) is
definitions of truth, which are also mentioned by defined", that is, by a negation. 11 He does not clarify,
Thomas in De veritate, namely, the definitions of however, why "one" should be the model for defining
Augustine, Hilary of Poitiers, Anselm, the adequation the other transcendentals. The explanation for his
formula, and, finally, the definition in terms of indivi- strategy must be sought in a discussion of Aristotle's,
sion. Philip asks which of these definitions is the most which was the basis for the medieval doctrine of the
appropriate. He objects to Hilary's definition ("Truth is transcendentals.
that which declares or manifests being"), because it In Book IV of the Metaphysics (c. 2, 1003 b 22ff.)
contains a reference to a knowing subject. The true must Aristotle discusses the relation between being and one.
be defined "without any relation to an intellect'.6 The This relation is marked by identity and difference. Being
definition, "adequation of thing and intellect", expresses, and one are interchangeable, for they are "the same
according to Philip, a secondary type of truth, namely, nature". Yet the terms "being" and "one" are not
the truth of the sign, because the adequation in question synonyms, for the concept of "one" is different from that
must be understood in terms of a mental sign and the of "being". What is conceptually expressed by "one" is
thing signified. From these objections it is obvious that the "undividedness" of being. From this it follows that
he is seeking a purely ontological definition of truth. one adds something to being without this addition
Augustine's definition "The true is that which is" (/d entailing a limitation of its extension. One retains its
quod est) seems then to be a suitable candidate, for in comprehensive, transcendental character, because it
his definition Augustine deliberately eliminates the only adds something conceptual, a negation, to being.
relation to a knowing subject] Such a relation would That is the reason why Philip prefers to define the other
"relativize" truth. Truth resides solely in the thing itself, transcendentals following the model established by one.
expressing its intelligibility. Thus, truth is identical with Truth must be defined in terms of indivision.
being, and this means, in the terminology of thirteenth- Philip defines truth as "the indivision of being and
century philosophy, that truth is a transcendental prop- that which is". The last part of the definition is bor-
erty. rowed from Boethius's De hebdomadibus, a treatise in
Indeed, Philip is of the opinion that Augustine's which a number of propositions about the structure of
definition indicates what truth is secundum substantiam. being that played a great role in medieval ontology
Yet he is not satisfied with this definition because it are presented. One of these, to which Philip explicitly
insufficiently expresses that by which truth, qua concept refers, reads: "In every composite to be (esse) is one
(rationem), differs from being. The statement "every thing, that which is another. ''12 The definition of truth
being is true" threatens to become a tautology. Augus- brings out that these components are undivided, that is,
fine's definition must therefore be modified, and this united.
modification gives rise to the fifth definition mentioned From the analysis of this "magisterial" definition it
by Philip: "the true is the indivision of being (esse) and becomes clear which conception of truth is behind the
that which is". incorporation of truth in the doctrine of the transcen-
Philip says of this definition that "it is taken a dentals. Philip's definition formulates the conditions for
Metaphysicis", 8 The modern editor of the Summa the transcendentality of the true. First, truth must be
confesses that he could not find the definition in the conceived purely ontologically; any relation to the
Metaphysics. He is in good company, for a similar intellect must be eliminated. Second, truth must be
remark was made in the thirteenth century by Albert the conceived as a negation, as indivision, in keeping with
TRUTH AS TRANSCENDENTAL IN THOMAS AQUINAS 161

the way in which Aristotle conceived one in relation to the good were true, and the bad were in itself false -- but
being. This first version of the doctrine of transcen- in thought. ''is
dentals had a great influence on later thinkers such as It is striking that Thomas, in his Commentary on the
Albert the Great and Bonaventure. 13 'Metaphysics', enters at length into this distinction
From De veritate 1, 1, it appears, however, that between the true and the good and gives a philosophical
Thomas does not share the opinion of the Masters. His justification for Aristotle's saying. This justification,
definition of truth contradicts both conditions that which recurs in many other places in his work, is based
Philip regarded as essential for its transcendentality. We on the insight that a spiritual substance relates to reality
must, therefore, look into the reasons that led Thomas in two different ways: Man directs himself at things by
to his conception of truth. knowing them and by desiring them. The object of
knowledge is the true; the object of desire is the good.
Between the two processes of knowing and desiring
(2) "Truth is not in things, but in the mind" (Aristotle) there is a fundamental distinction, which becomes
evident in their termini. Knowing is a process of assimi-
The basic idea running through Thomas's discussion of lation: it is completed when the similitude of the thing
truth, like a scarlet thread, is that relation to the intellect known is in the knower. Truth indicates this completion
is essential for truth. All three works in which he pres- or perfection of knowledge and is therefore in the mind.
ents a systematic account of truth, the Commentary on The appetite, in contrast, is not a process of assimilation
the "Sentences', De veritate, and the Summa theologiae, but a movement toward things. It is an inclination
cite a text of Aristotle's from Book VI of the Meta- toward the thing in itself, which is desirable because it is
physics (c. 4, 1027 b 25) to the effect that "truth and perfect. Good is therefore a perfection in things. 16 This
falsity do not exist, as good and evil, in things, but in the conclusion does not exclude that truth is a good, for it is
mind". The proper place of truth is in the intellect. This the good specific to the intellect. In this case the intellect
thesis forms a formidable obstacle to any purely is regarded as a thing that, like every other thing, is
ontological conception of truth. Thomas accordingly called "good" through its perfection, which for the
employs Aristotle's saying as a counterargument to the intellect exists in the truth. Thus this specific case
view that truth resides solely in things. 14 That he takes confirms the general thesis that the good is in things and
the statement of the Philosopher as more than merely an the true is in the mind. 17
argument from authority becomes apparent when we Aristotle in Metaphysics VI draws a far-reaching
look at the context of Aristotle's saying and Thomas's conclusion from his discussion of "being as what is true".
commentary on it. This kind of being falls outside the inquiry of meta-
In Metaphysics V1, c. 4, Aristotle discusses one of the physics, it "must be passed over" by the science that
meanings of being that he had distinguished in the fifth deals with being as being, for the cause of being as what
book, namely "being as what is true" (ens ut verum). is true is an operation of the intellect. Being in this sense
Being in this sense signifies the truth of a proposition, ff belongs therefore rather to logic or the science of the
we ask, for example, "Is a human being an animal?" and intellect. Metaphysics is concerned with the reality
we answer: "He/she is", then this "is" signifies that the outside the mind, with the kind of being that falls under
proposition is true. "Being as what is true" is being as a one of the categories, namely, substance, quality or
verbal copula, a sign of the composition of subject and quantity, and so on. 18
predicate in a statement. This being therefore has its The distinction that Aristotle makes here between
origin in the intellect that forms a judgment, or, in two modes of being, explained more extensively in
scholastic terminology, in the intellect that composes or Metaphysics V (c. 7), strongly influenced Thomas's
divides concepts. Thus, the context of the statement thought. In many places he presents a twofold division
cited by Thomas is a discussion in which truth is of being that corresponds with Aristotle's dichotomy39
presented as connected with being, but in an entirely The first mode of being (let us call it B1) is "outside the
different way than in the ontological conception of truth. mind", and is "perfect", because it is something positive
For in order to emphasize that "being as what is true" in reality. This is the being that is divided by the ten
does not signify something extra-mental, Aristotle then categories, and signifies either a substance or an
says: "Falsity and truth are not in things -- it is not as if accident. The second mode of being 032) is being
162 J A N A. A E R T S E N

considered as a verbal copula, and signifies what exists H e r e again it is instructive to examine the context of
only in the mind, namely, the truth of a proposition. this statement. In the first chapter of Metaphysics II,
Concerning the relation between B 1 and B2, Thomas Aristotle argues that "philosophy is rightly called the
in his Commentary on the 'Metaphysics' makes a science of truth". H e wants to make clear that meta-
number of observations that are not to be found in the physics -- out of all the philosophical disciplines -- pre-
same form in Aristotle? ° Three of these prove to be eminently (maxime) considers truth. The starting point
directly relevant for his analysis of truth. (1) B2 of Aristotle's argument is a general proposition: the
compares to B1 as effect to cause. Thomas does not cause of a property that is common to the cause and its
explain in what sense "cause" must be understood here. effect is the maximum of that attribute. Fire, for
B1 cannot be an efficient cause, for as we saw, the example, is the hottest, because it is the cause of the heat
distinction between the two modes of being consists in other things. This general proposition is then applied
precisely in that B2 is caused by an operation of the to truth. The term 'truth' is said universally of all things.
intellect. (2) The domain of B2 is greater than that of F r o m this it follows that that which causes subsequent
B1. According to B2 anything can be called a being things to be true is itself most true. This must be the first
about which a true proposition can be formed, even cause of the being of things. Since first philosophy deals
though it is a non-being according to B 1, as is the case with the first causes, metaphysics is par excellence the
with negations or privations. We can say, for example, science of truth. F r o m this reasoning Aristotle infers a
that there is evil, but this does not imply that evil is final corollary: Since those things which are the cause of
something positive in reality. In most of the texts where the being of other things are true in the highest degree, it
Thomas presents the distinction between the modes of follows "that each thing is related to truth in the same
being, his concern is the clarification of this second way as it is to being", or, as Thomas puts it, "that there is
feature of the relation between them. (3) B2 is acci- the same disposition of things in being and in truth". 22
dental to B 1. For the being of a thing, it is not essential This argument must have had a strong appeal for
that a true proposition be affirmed of it. Knowledge or Thomas, for he makes use of it in his proofs for the
science is essentially related to and dependent upon existence of G o d and in his doctrine of creation. 23
reality, but the reverse does not hold. Metaphysics II is also fundamental for his view that
In summary, Thomas follows the Aristotelian ap- there is an intrinsic connection between being and truth.
proach to truth: the place of truth is not in things but in In his reply to one of the objections in De veritate 1, 1,
the mind. The relation between being and truth is he presents an explanation of Aristotle's statement. The
determined by the distinction between two modes of thesis that there is the same disposition in being and in
being. Truth belongs to a secondary mode of being, truth means that the order (ordo) in both is identical.
intramental being. Viewed from this perspective, the The reason is that "to the degree to which a thing has
conditions for truth to be a transcendental property of entity (entitas), to that degree it is apt to be conformed
being seem to be absent. (aequari) to the intellect. Consequently, the notion of
truth follows upon that of being. ''24 This second ap-
proach to truth must therefore lead to the conclusion
(3) "There Js the same disposition in being and in that truth is not only an intramental mode of being but
truth" (Aristotle) also has an ontological dimension.
The approaches taken by Thomas result in two basic
The above conclusion is, however, only one facet of ideas about truth. The first approach leads to the
Thomas's conception of truth. H e also acknowledges conclusion, based on Aristotle's claim that truth is not in
that there is truth in every being. What is surprising is things but in the mind, that "being as true" falls outside
that for this idea Thomas again appeals to Aristotle's metaphysics. The second approach follows Aristotle's
Metaphysics. As a counterargument against objections statement that there is the same disposition in being and
that suggest that being and truth cannot be convertible in truth, and ends up with a conception of truth as being.
because truth is only in the intellect, he cites a statement Thomas himself speaks of a "twofold" truth, that of the
of the Philosopher in Book II of the Metaphysics (c. 1, intellect and that of the thing. 25
993 b 30--31): "There is the same disposition of things The crucial question is, of course, whether the two
in being and in truth. ''21 conceptions of truth are compatible. Aristotle does not
T R U T H AS T R A N S C E N D E N T A L IN T H O M A S A Q U I N A S 163

pose this question in his Metaphysics. Modern scholars with each other, it appears that the definition in terms of
have attempted to resolve the discrepancy between conformity acquires growing significance for Thomas. In
Books II and VI by supposing a development in the beginning of his career, in his Commentary on the
Aristotle's thought and suggesting that the second book 'Sentences' (I, 19, 5, 1), he presents the definition of
belongs to an early, Platonizing phase. Such a solution is Anselm of Canterbury ("Truth is rightness perceptible
foreign to Thomas, because for him the books of only to the mind") as the most comprehensive (compre-
Aristotle's Metaphysics form a unity.26 An aspect that is hendens omnes veritatis acceptiones). In his last account,
noteworthy in this regard is his procedure with respect in the Summa theologiae (I, 16, 1), the adequation
to the ontological conception of truth. He does n o t formula takes this place. In the account that is chrono-
appeal to Augustine's definition of truth, as one would logically intermediate, De veritate 1, 1, Thomas arranges
in fact expect, but appeals to Aristotle. A conscious the various traditional definitions of truth on the basis of
strategy could underlie this choice. Precisely by appeal- the three elements contained in the conformity formula:
ing to the same philosopher, who posits that the place of the thing, the intellect, and the relation between these
truth is in the intellect, Thomas suggests that the two two.
conceptions of truth belong together. Truth, he states, "can be defined in three ways". The
In his Commentary on the "Metaphysics' Thomas first way pertains to that which precedes the essence of
scarcely enters into the relation between these two truth and upon which truth is founded (fundatur). Here
conceptions. In his exposition of the second Book Thomas places the definitions of Augustine and Philip
though, he does refer to the conception of truth in the Chancellor, who defined truth in purely ontological
Metaphysics VI. That a thing is related to being in the terms. In the second way, truth is defined according to
same way as it is to truth is, so Thomas says, "because that in which the notion of truth is formally completed
the being of the thing is the cause of the true idea that (perficitur). The definition of truth as adequation falls
the mind forms of the thing. For truth and falsity are not under this heading. Finally, in a third way truth can be
in things, but in the mind, as it is said in the sixth defined according to the effect that follows upon it
book. ''27 This observation is not elaborated, yet it does (secundum effectum consequentem), namely, knowl-
make clear that for Thomas there is no opposition edge. And it is in this sense that Hilary of Poitiers says:
between the truth of the thing and the truth of the "Truth is that which declares or manifests being."
intellect, but rather a causal relation between the two. From this arrangement one can surmise why Thomas
The disposition of a thing is "the foundation and cause" preferred the conformity formula to the other defini-
of the truth of the intellect.28 tions of truth, for this definition expresses the relational
In order to determine the relation between the two character of truth to the fullest. Truth is not, as Philip
truths, it is first necessary to answer a question which is the Chancellor thought, a negation, but rather a relation
not explicitly dealt with by Aristotle. His statements between two terms, the res (the general name for reality)
attribute different places to truth but do not say what and the intellectus. Both are, although in different ways,
truth is. This very question is taken up by Thomas in De essential for the relation of adaequatio -- for which
veritate. Thomas also uses the terms conform#as and convenien-
tia. The notion of truth as conformity therefore enables
(4) Thomas's definition of truth: "adequation of thing him to integrate the two approaches to truth discussed
and intellect" earlier and that resulted in the truth of the intellect and
that of the thing.
In De veritate 1, 1, Thomas comes to the conclusion that The relation of intellect to thing is a relation com-
the definition which Philip the Chancellor had regarded pleted by an operation of the intellect, for knowledge is
as secondary expresses the essence of truth most com- a process of assimilation.3° Here is where the basic idea
pletely. That is, truth is "the adequation (conformity) of of Thomas's first approach to truth belongs. Because the
thing and intellect".29 This formula is often considered end-term of the process of knowing, truth, is in the
to be the medieval definition of truth. From a historical intellect and is realized by the intellect, the intellect
perspective, that is incorrect, for it is only with Thomas pertains to the essence of truth. For Thomas it is self-
that it becomes the most fundamental definition. evident that "all who define truth in the right way place
When we compare his three main accounts of truth the intellect in its definition".31
164 J A N A. A E R T S E N

The relation of thing to intellect consists in the the sense of intramental being (B2), which the Philoso-
knowability of the thing. This knowability is the condi- pher called "that which is true". 37
tion for the conformity between intellect and thing, and Given this criticism, the question which arises is how
constitutes the truth of the thing. H e r e Thomas can Thomas can still give truth a place in the doctrine of the
revert to the basic idea of the second approach to truth. transcendentals. For his conception of truth involves a
"There is the same disposition in being and in truth", denial of the view that Philip the Chancellor had
because something is apt on the basis of its being to regarded as a condition for the transcendentality of the
be conformed to the intellect. "Every being is called true, namely, that truth must be defined without any
true, insofar as it is conformed or conformable to the relation to the intellect. Josef Vande Wiele has argued
intellect. ''32 that Thomas, by defining truth in relation to the
The adaequatio formula not only expresses the intellect, leaves the level of metaphysics and places
relational character of truth but also specifies the rela- himself on that of the psychology of human knowl-
tion between thing and intellect. This relation must be edge. 38 After the analysis of the way in which Thomas
"adequate"; adequation for Thomas is a "commensura- conceives truth, we must thus turn to his conception of
tion". 33 The concept "truth" presupposes a measure truth as transcendental.
(mensura) for the relation between thing and intellect. 34
This normative relation becomes apparent in Thomas's
arrangement of the definitions of truth in De veritate. (5) Thomas's innovations in the doctrine of the
"That which is" is the "foundation", knowledge is the transcendentals
"effect" of truth. The res is that which measures.
The thing is the "cause" of the truth that is in the The line of Thomas's argument in De veritate 1, 1, is that
intellect. 35 It is this causal relation, as we saw at the end the investigation into what truth is, ends in the doctrine
of the preceding section, that Thomas uses in his of the transcendentals. The way in which he develops
Commentary on the 'Metaphysics' to establish a connec- this doctrine is one of the most remarkable aspects of
tion between Aristotle's approach to truth in Book II his exposition. Thomas reduces the question "What is
and that in Book VI. The fact that he takes the relation truth?" to that of the condition of all rational knowledge.
between the truth of the thing and the truth of the His method is the "reduction" or "resolution" of the
intellect to be a causal relation suggests that he con- contents of our knowledge to a first concept. In every
ceives the relation between the two truths in the same question as to what something is, we reduce that which
way as that between the two modes of being we saw is to be defined to something more general and better
earlier, extramental being (B1) and being as true (B2). known. When, for example, we ask "What is man?" we
The first characteristic of the relation between B1 and answer by giving the genus "animal" and adding to it a
B2 is that they relate to each other as cause and effect.36 specific difference. We can go on to ask what this genus
F r o m the above discussion of truth it has become clear is, and again reduce it to something even more general.
that "cause" must be understood here in the sense of This regress cannot, however, go on indefinitely, for an
"measure" and "foundation". "Cause" evinces features of infinite regress would render knowledge of things
an "exemplary cause". impossible. The reduction must end with something that
The central place that Thomas gives to the adaequatio is not known through anything else but is evident
formula in his arrangement of the definitions of truth through itself. 39
implies at the same time a criticism of the definitions of The principle to which the intellect reduces (resolvit)
Augustine and Philip the Chancellor. Their definitions all its concepts is being (ens). It is first known in the
are too limited and are imperfect because they concern sense that it is the condition of the possibility of all
only the foundation of truth. Thomas criticizes Augus- knowledge and is implicit in every concept. 4° This thesis
tine's definition ("that which is") because it does not forms the basis of Thomas's further account, for he
express the complete concept of truth, which consists in draws from it the conclusion that all other concepts
the conformity of thing and intellect. H e also proposes arise through an addition to being. But in what way is
an alternative interpretation that turns Augustine's this addition possible? Not, in any case, in the way in
definition in an Aristotelian direction. Whenever truth is which a difference is added to a genus. Being is not a
said to be "that which is", this 'is' must be understood in genus that can be specified by the addition of differ-
TRUTH AS TRANSCENDENTAL IN THOMAS AQUINAS 165

ences, because there is no difference that does not share important innovation in the doctrine of the transcen-
in being. 4~ Outside of being there is nothing. Other dentals. A transcendental determination is not solely a
concepts can only add something to being in the sense negation, as Philip thought, but it can also be something
that they express a mode (modus) of it which is not yet positive, namely, a relation.
made explicit by the term 'being' itself. Within the group of relational transcendentals Thomas
The explication of what is implicit in being is possible distinguishes two types, reflecting the twofold relation of
in two ways. First, what is expressed can be a special one being to another. Viewed according to their division
mode of being. Being is then contracted and limited. 42 (divisio), this relation involves a negative aspect, which
This occurs in the modes of being that Aristotle called is expressed by the transcendental "something" (aliquid).
the categories, for not every being is a substance, or a The term 'something', according to Thomas, means
quality, or a quantity, etc. The categories constitute the literally "another what" (quasi aliud quid) and indicates
first contractions of being. But what is expressed can the division of a being from every other thing. But in
also concern a general mode of being, something that addition to this there is a more positive relational mode
follows upon every being. The terms expressing these of being, namely, the "conformity" (convenientia) of one
general modes Thomas calls communia, or -- but rela- being to another. The condition for such a relation is
tively seldom -- transcendentia. 43 In this way his analysis something whose nature it is to accord with every being.
arrives at its intended goal, the doctrine of transcen- Such is, Thomas argues, the human soul, which accord-
dentals. An explicit definition of the notion of tran- ing to Aristotle (De anima III, c. 8, 431 b 21) "is in a
scendentality is not given by Thomas, but from his sense all things". In the soul there is both a cognitive
exposition it is clear that "transcendental" stands in power and an appetitive power. The conformity of being
opposition to categorial. A transcendental transcends to the appetite is expressed by the term 'good', the con-
the special modes of being, because it is not limited to formity to the intellect by the term 'true'. 46
one category. Thomas's second important innovation in the doc-
In the continuation of De veritate 1, 1, Thomas trine of transcendentals is the correlation he introduces
distinguishes two groups of transcendentals. The general between anima and being. He understands the tran-
mode of being expressed by the first group pertains to scendentals true and good in relation to the faculties of a
every being in itself (in se). To this group belongs first of spiritual substance, man. Thomas's doctrine manifests
all "thing" (res). What is significant is that Thomas an "anthropocentrism". But this term requires further
introduces one of the terms of the truth relation as a qualification since Metz, referring to, among other
transcendental. The distinction between being and thing things, De veritate 1, 1, has defended the thesis that
is that the name ens signifies "that which is", viewed Thomas's form of thought is anthropocentric and that
from the act of being, whereas res expresses the quiddity he is "the father of modern thought", in which subjec-
or essence of a being. 44 The distinction between ens and tivity is the model for the understanding of being. 47 The
res is thus connected with a central thesis of Thomas's conclusion that "the Copernican Revolution started in
metaphysics, namely, that every being is composed of Thomistic thought" is precipitate, however, as will be-
essence and the act of being (esse). He derives the term come clear from what follows (see section 7). Thomas's
res etymologically from the Latin ratus, which means doctrine of transcendentals manifests an anthropocen-
determinate, stable, and valid. 45 That every being is a trism in the sense that his introduction of relational
thing means that it possesses a determinate essence transcendentals is an acknowledgement of the special
whereby it is "thinkable". To the first group of tran- place man has among other beings in the world.
scendentals belongs, further, one (unum), which ex- Through this anthropocentrism Thomas does not,
presses a negation: it signifies that being is undivided. contrary to what Vande Wiele suggested, leave the tran-
This was the transcendental which served Philip the scendental level, for the intellect can in fact be viewed in
Chancellor as a model for determining the other tran- two ways. On the one hand, the intellect is a determinate
scendentals. thing and a particular faculty which, like every being, is a
The general mode of being expressed by the second "something" distinct from other things. But one can also
group of transcendentals pertains to every being in view the intellect -- and this is Thomas's point of view --
relation to something else (in ordine ad aliud). The as a faculty with a universal scope, "as apprehensive of
introduction of this second group is Thomas's first universal being". 48 This insight is expressed in Aris-
166 J A N A. A E R T S E N

totle's statement: "the soul is in a sense all things", which aspects that are characteristic of the relation among
Thomas, in his Commentary on De anima, interprets as transcendentals, their real identity and their conceptual
"man is totum ens". 49 Aristotle's phrase points to the difference. Yet Thomas's reasoning remains somewhat
perfection of intellectual substances. Knowing beings implicit, and we need to draw the argument out. In this
are distinguished from non-knowing beings in that they section we shall discuss the matter of convertibility, and
are by nature able to assimilate also the forms of other in the next section we shall focus on what the true adds
things; their nature has "a greater amplitude and exten- to being.
sion". 5° Man's horizon is unlimited; he has an "affinity" In Thomas's argument for the identity of verum and
to the whole of being. 51 Man, we might say, is marked by ens, the proper middle term is the notion of "act of
a transcendental openness; his object is being in general. being" or "actuality". His reasoning consists of the
Now, being is apt to be united to the soul in two ways. following steps:
In one way it can be in the soul, not according to its own
1. Something is called "true" insofar as it is apt to bring
mode of being, but in a spiritual manner, according to its
about a true idea of itself. That which is true is
ratio or species. In this case being is the object of the
knowable.
cognitive power, which is to say true. In another way
2. Everything is knowable insofar as it has being (esse),
being can be that toward which the soul is inclined. In
insofar as it is in act. 54 The actuality of a thing is the
this case being is the object of the appetite and it is
inner basis of its knowability. Following Aristotle,
called good. 52 That the soul is "in a sense all things" is
Thomas sees a close connection between truth and
the philosophical basis for Thomas's relating the tran-
act. Scientific knowledge is therefore directed to-
scendentals true and good to the intellect and will of
wards being in act. Being in potency cannot be
man.
known through itself, but only through that of which
De veritate 1, 1, is Thomas's most complete exposi-
it is the potency. 55
tion of the transcendentals, with respect both to their
3. Insofar as a thing is in act, it is called "being" (ens),
number and to their systematic arrangement. In com-
for the name 'being', Thomas says in De veritate 1, 1,
parison with Philip the Chancellor's treatise, this text
is taken from the act of being. By this act it is distin-
contains important new elements such as the introduc-
guished from non-being. Actuality is the ground of
tion of "thing" as transcendental, the notion of relational
both the knowability and the entity of things.
transcendentals, and the correlation of spirit and being.
4. From this it follows "that every being is true", and
These innovations result from Thomas's conception of
the converse.
truth as "conformity of thing and intellect", for this
conception forced him to a new consideration of the Elsewhere Thomas makes use of the Neoplatonic
transcendental status of truth. image of light to elucidate that whereby a thing is
knowable. Just as in the material world things become
visible through physical light, so also that through which
(6) The convertibility of being and the true things become knowable for the intellect can be called
"light". The actuality of the thing, then, is a light through
The transcendentality of truth can be further clarified by which the thing reveals itself to the mind, 56 or is
focusing attention on a general feature of the transcen- "unconcealed" in the terminology of Heidegger.
dentals, their convertibility. If "true" is a transcendental Through the identification of actuality with light,
predicate, it must be convertible, or interchangeable Thomas indicates two essential aspects of ontological
with "being". In the S u m m a theologiae I, 16, 3 (" Utrum truth: first, truth is actuality, which expresses what being
verum et ens convertantur") Thomas presents the is in itself, and second, truth is lucidity, which expresses
following argument for this convertibility. The true that being reveals itself to something other and is
includes a relationship to knowledge. Now, everything is knowable.
knowable insofar as it has being (esse) For this reason it One might wonder whether in his argument Thomas
is said that "the soul is in a sense all things". The true, has not moved far away from the view that the place of
therefore, is convertible with being, but the true adds to truth is in the intellect. At this point he advances certain
being a relation to the intellect, s3 objections to the convertibility of ens and verum, and
This argument is intended to do justice to the two these are highly illuminating for the understanding of
T R U T H AS T R A N S C E N D E N T A L IN T H O M A S A Q U I N A S 167

the proper nature of the transcendental true. The first T1 is convertible with B1 "in the way in which what
objection is that truth resides properly in the intellect, manifests is convertible with what is manifested".6° This
whereas being is properly in things, and that v e r u m and new type of convertibility is based on the idea that truth,
ens are therefore not convertible. 57 Against this it might as conformity, includes "the manifestation" of the thing
be said, as Thomas points out in his reply, that the by the intellect.
opposition is not as absolute as is suggested. Truth is A second objection to the convertibility of ens and
both in things and in the intellect, and there are also two v e r u m argues that terms are not convertible when one
modes of being, extramental being (B1) and being as has greater extension than the other. It seems that truth
what is true 032). But this observation does not take the has a greater extension than being, since it extends to
edge off the objection. Although between the two truths being and non-being. Thomas cites Aristotle's statement
and between B1 and B2 there is the same causal order, that there is truth "when what is is said to be and what is
the relation between the modes of being on the one not is said not to be". Therefore v e r u m and e n s are not
hand, and the modalities of truth on the other hand, is convertible.61 As a matter of fact, this objection bases
nevertheless not symmetrical. The reason for this is the relation between truth and being on one of the
precisely that truth, unlike being, expresses a relation to features of the relation between the two modes of being
the intellect. mentioned by Thomas. The extension of B2, being as
The primary sense of being is B1. But for Thomas the what is true, is greater than that of B 1, because anything
primary sense of truth is not the truth of the thing, about which a true proposition can be formed is being in
although the thing is the cause of the truth of the the sense of B2, even if it is a non-being according to
intellect. In this respect there is a significant difference B 1, as is the case with negations and privations.
between Heidegger and Thomas. According to both, The reference to the relation between the modes of
truth is said in a primary and in a secondary fashion. being already suggests the answer to the second objec-
According to the former, the unhiddenness of being tion. It is correct to say that T1, the truth of the intellect,
which makes the truth of the proposition possible has a greater extension than B1, but not that truth has
should rank as the original truth. 58 According to greater extension than being. B2 is also a mode of being,
Thomas, truth is not primarily found in being, even and this mode is coextensive with T1. The reply to this
though the knowability of being is the foundation of objection shows that e n s and v e r u m are not convertible
truth, but rather in that in which the concept of truth is because in all cases being is knowable through itself and
c o m p l e t e d . The relation of conformity is completed in is apt to be conformed to the intellect. It is also possible
and through the intellect. Therefore the truth of the that what is in itself a non-being is made knowable by
intellect is the primary sense of truth (T1); the proper the intellect, such that it acquires the character of an e n s
place of truth is, as Aristotle posited, in the mind. Truth rationis. 62 This conclusion complements Thomas's
belongs to the thing only in a secondary sense (T2), exposition in D e veritate 1, 1. The modes of being
namely, insofar as it is related to the intellect.59 Between discussed there are the categories and the transcen-
the modes of being and those of truth there is therefore dentals, but rational being is not mentioned as a mode of
no symmetry with respect to the order of primary and being.
secondary: B1 is to B2 as T2 is to T1. Being is primarily
in things, truth primarily in the intellect.
The first objection accordingly compels Thomas to (7) T h e true as a relational t r a n s c e n d e n t a l
modify the thesis of convertibility. Implicitly, he recog-
nizes that the argument presented above for the con- Although ens and v e r u m are convertible, they are not
vertibility between being and the true (CBT1) has only synonymous. It is not redundant to say that every being
limited validity. It pertains exclusively to the relation is true. 63 'True' expresses something that is not ex-
between the secondary true, that is the ontological true pressed by the name 'being'; it adds something to being,
(T2), and B1. They are interchangeable s e c u n d u m namely, a relation to the intellect. Thomas always takes
s u b s t a n t i a m , the usual type of convertibility. But the seriously the relational character of ontological truth:
primary true that is in the intellect (T1) cannot be "Truth of things", he emphasizes, includes in its concept
interchangeable in this way with B1. Thomas introduces not only the entity of things but also the relation of con-
for their relation a new type of convertibility (CBT2). formity to the intellect.64 The true is a relational tran-
168 J A N A. A E R T S E N

scendental. The question which remains is, what is the however, a problem arises to which several scholars
nature of the relation that truth adds to being. have called attention. 67 One may wonder whether in this
The problem of this addition to being is one of the way truth can still be regarded as intrinsic to things. If
main questions in the medieval doctrine of the tran- "things are called true in virtue of the truth in an intel-
scendentals. Since Philip the Chancellor there had been lect", 68 it follows from this that being is called true only
a consensus that that which the other transcendentals by extrinsic denomination. This conclusion seems to
add to being cannot be a distinct reality or nature. For conflict, however, with Thomas's own basic intuition of
such an addition would limit being, with the consequence the correlation between being and spirit. His argument
that the transcendentals would lose their transcendental for the convertibility of ens and verum is that being is
character and would no longer express a general mode knowable by virtue of its actuality, and that the human
of being. What the transcendentals add to being is not soul is "in a sense all things". How can Thomas hold the
something secundum rein, but secundum rationem. The view that truth is a transcendental mode of being and at
relation that truth adds to being is therefore a relation of the same time assert that being is called true by extrinsic
reason. Thomas's additional argument for this conclu- denomination?
sion is that every real relation is categorial, and that, in It seems to me that Thomas's distinction between the
the Aristotelian system of categories, the relation is an two modes of truth is crucial for the solution to this
accident that comes to a substance. But truth cannot add difficulty. Being is called true because it "is apt to bring
such a relation to being, since this relation needs to be about a true idea of itself"; truth is conceived here as
transcendental. It cannot therefore be real and must be knowability. It is noteworthy that Thomas constantly
purely a relation of reasonY Thomas never entertained formulates ontological truth in terms of "aptitude".
the possibility of a real transcendental relation. Being is knowable through itself, on the basis of its act of
In De veritate 21, 1, Thomas deals extensively with being. Knowability is the possibility for truth, but it is
the problem of the addition and gives a more precise not yet truth in the formal sense, which is a conformity.
description of the relation of reason that truth adds to Truth in the formal sense is primarily in the intellect,
being. This type of relation occurs when the relation and secondarily in the thing insofar as it is known.
consists in a dependency and is nonmutual. The subject Thomas himself recognizes that a thing is not essentially
of the relation does not really depend upon that to (essentialiter) called true in relation to the human
which it is related, but the converse does not hold. intellect. 69
Thomas illustrates this by appealing to the relation From this a further conclusion follows necessarily.
between scientific knowledge (scientia) and its object. The same example that Thomas uses to elucidate the
Whereas science depends upon the object, the object relation of reason that truth adds to being, the relation
does not depend upon science. The relation of science of an object to science, he also employs to indicate a
to its object is real, but that of the object to science is a third feature of the relation between the modes of being.
relation of reason, because the object is only thought in Because extramental being is not dependent on the
relation to science. Thomas goes on to give this example knowledge which the intellect has of it, being as what is
a general import. The same holds in all cases where true (B2) is accidental to B1. Likewise, the relation to
things are related as measure and that which is meas- the intellect must be accidental to the truth of a thing.
ured. 66 What is measured is really related to that which Thomas explicitly draws this conclusion. A thing is
measures, but the measure is not dependent on what is related in an accidental way to the intellect for which it
measured. Such a nonreciprocal relation is the relation is knowable because the thing, in its being, is not
of truth, for the thing is the measure of the truth of the dependent upon this intellect. 7°
intellect. The thing is thought to be in relation, not At this point the limits of Thomas's anthropocen-
because the thing itself is really related to the intellect trism become clearly discernible. His thought does not
that understands it, but because the intellect is really manifest an anthropocentrism in the modern sense that
related to the thing. Metz attributes to the term. A good example of this is
The relation to the intellect that truth adds to being is Thomas's attitude toward Augustine's definition of
a relation of reason, which is like the nonmutual relation truth: "the true is that which is". Earlier we saw that in
between a measure and what is measured. At this point, De veritate 1, 1, he criticizes this definition because it
TRUTH AS TRANSCENDENTAL IN THOMAS AQUINAS 169

concerns only the foundation of truth and does not to its origin: the world is created, that is, m a d e by the
express the complete concept of truth, which consists in divine art. Essential for the truth of things is the relation
the conformity of thing and intellect. Yet at other places to the divine Logos. Ontological truth has a divine
he offers a certain justification for Augustine's defini- ground.
tion. In this definition of truth, the relation to the h u m a n F o r T h o m a s the ultimate meaning of adaequatio rei et
intellect has been eliminated, because what is accidental intellectus as the definition of truth is: the conformity of
(per accidens) is excluded f r o m every definition. 71 the thing with the divine intellect. At the close of De
If truth adds to being a relation to the intellect but the veritate 1, 2, he concludes that natural things have been
relation to the h u m a n intellect is not "essential" for placed between two intellects, the divine and the human,
things, then the unfortunate consequence seems to be and that they are said to be true in virtue of the
that being is called true only per accidens. Essential for conformity with each of the two: with the divine intellect
the truth of things can only be a real relation to the insofar as they fulfill that to which they are ordered by
intellect, a relation of dependence. 72 This conclusion this intellect; with the h u m a n intellect insofar as they are
compels T h o m a s to a further consideration of the apt to bring about true ideas of themselves. But the first
relation between thing and intellect. relation is m o r e fundamental for the truth of things than
The concept of truth presupposes a measure. At the is the latter one. 75
end of De veritate 1, 1, the various definitions of truth Things are called true per se in relation to the divine
were arranged according to a scheme in which the entity intellect. 76 Given this foundation of truth, T h o m a s can
(entitas) of a thing was the foundation of the conformity also advance a different version of the thesis of the
to the intellect. The way in which this scheme was convertibility of being and the true (CBT3). All natural
presented suggested that it has universality, but in De things are related to the divine intellect as artifacts to
veritate 1, 2, T h o m a s in fact acknowledges that the art. Therefore each thing is said to be true insofar as it
situation is m o r e complex. The measure of truth can be has its own form, according to which it imitates divine
located in either term of the adaequatio formula. T h e art. "It is in this way that being and the true are
criterion for the relation is twofold, namely, either the convertible, since any natural thing is conformed to
res or the intellectus. Sometimes the intellect is that divine art through its form. ''77 This third version of the
which measures. That is the case with practical reason, convertibility thesis contains two elements: every being
that is, the intellect directed at making s o m e t h i n g . is true (in the sense of knowable) on the basis of its own
Practical reason is the cause of things and is therefore form; every being is true (in the formal sense) on the
the measure of artifacts. They are called true insofar as basis of its relation to the divine practical intellect. This
they acquire the likeness of the f o r m in the mind of the last element expresses the ultimate consequence of
maker. The relation to the practical intellect is essential Thomas's thought on the true as a relational transcen-
for the truth of artifacts, for they are dependent u p o n it. dental
Sometimes, however, the relation is reversed, and the
thing is the measure of truth. That is the case with
theoretical reason. The thing is that which measures, Notes
because it is prior to the knowledge the intellect has of
it. It is in this way that natural things are related to the * I am grateful to Jorge Gracia, Scott MacDonald and Rudi te Velde
intellect; they are the measure of man's theoretical for their valuable comments on an earlier draft.
1 The critical edition of De veritate (DV) can be found in the
reason. 73
Leonine edition of Thomas's works (Aquinas, 1882--), vol. 22.
Yet the relation to the h u m a n intellect is accidental There is an English translation by Mulligan (1952).
for the truth of things, because this intellect is not the 2 See Muckle (1933). The definition may be derived from Islamic
cause of things. Therefore, T h o m a s now takes a further Aristotelians, such as Averroes, to whom the editors of Bonaven-
step based on the model of practical reason. The ture's works point as a possible source (Bonaventure, 1882--, vol. 1,
p. 707, n. 5).
measure for the truth of things can only be a productive
3 Albert the Great, De bono I, q. 1, a. 8 (Albert, 1951), p. 15;
intellect, as practical reason is for artifacts. A n d it is in Alexander of Hales, Summa theologiae I, 1, 3, 2 (Alexander, 1924),
this way that the creative intellect of G o d relates to all n. 88; Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaemeron IV, 2 (Bonaventure,
things. 74 T h o m a s traces the intelligibility of reality back 1891b), p. 349.
170 J A N A. A E R T S E N

4 Cf. Pouillon (1939). 28 Cf. In I X Metaph., lect. 11, 1898: " . . . fundamentum et causa
Summa de bono, prol. (Philip, 1985), p. 4. veritatis."
6 Ibid., q. 2 (Philip, 1985), p. 15: "Verum enim dicitur sine respectu 29 D V 1, 1: " . . . adaequatio intellectus et rei dicitur, et in hoc
ad intellectum." formaliter ratio veil perficitur."
7 Soliloquia II, 5 (Augustine, 1877). 3o Super I Sent. 19, 5, 1: "In ipsa operatione intellectus . . .
8 Summa de bono q. 2 (Philip, 1985), p. 10. completur relatio adaequationis, in qua consistit ratio veritatis."
9 Albert the Great, De bono I, q. 1, a. 8 (Albert, 1951), p. 15. 31 D V 21, 1: "Et ideo omnes recte diffinientes verum ponunt in eius
10 In what follows in q. 2 (Philip, 1985), p. 13, Philip says that the diffinitione intellectum." Cf. In I Perihermeneias, lect. 3, 29: "Unde
definition "sumitur a philosophis." de quocumque dicatur verum, oportet quod hoc sit per respectum ad
11 Summa de bono q. 2 (Philip, 1985), p. 8: "Diffinitio enim boni intellectum."
prima . . . est data . . . per differentiam in negatione consistentem: 32 D V 2 1 , 1.
per hunc enim modum oportet prima determinari, ut unum." 33 D V 1, 5: "Veritas adaequationem quandam et commensura-
12 Boethius, De hebdomadibus, prop. VIII (Boethius, 1973), p. 42. tionem importat."
13 See Albert the Great, De bono (Albert, 1951); Bonaventure, 34 Super I Sent. 19, 5, 2 ad 2: "Cum veritas sit quaedam rectitudo et
Breviloquium I, 6 (Bonaventure, 1891a), p. 215. commensuratio, oportet quod in ratione veritatis intelligitur men-
14 Super I Sent. 19, 5, 1; D V 1, 2 sed contra and Resp.; Summa sura."
theologiae I, 16, 1 sed contra. 35 Cf. In IPerih., lect. 7, 84: "Sicut in subiecto est verum vel falsum
15 Aristotle's text does not quite say what Thomas suggests, but in mente, ut dicitur in VI Metaph., in re autem sicut in causa."
Thomas's reading is taken from the medieval Latin translation of the 36 See Thomas's own formulation in In V Metaph., lect. 9, 895:
Arabic text. Cf. Wippel (1989), p. 297, n. 5. "Unde veritas propositionis potest dici veritas rei per causarn. Nam
16 In VI Metaph., lect. 4, 1234, esp.: "Sicut ergo bonum et malum ex eo quod res est vel non est, oratio vera vel falsa est."
designant perfectiones, quae sunt in rebus: ita verum et falsum 37 D V 1 , 1 ad 1; 1, 10 ad 1; SuperlSent. 19, 5, 1 ad 1.
designant perfectiones cognitionum"; 1240: "Apparet etiam ex his 38 Vande Wiele (1954), p. 549.
quae hic dicuntur, quod verum et falsum, quae sunt obiecta 39 D V 1, 1: "Sicut in demonstrabilibus oportet fieri reductionem in
cognitionis, sunt in mente." Cf. D V 1, 2: "Motus autem cognitivae aliqua principia per se intellectui nota, ita investigando quid est
virtutis terminatur ad a n i m a m . . , sed motus appetitivae terminatur unumquodque. Alias utrobique in infinitum iretur, et sic periret
ad res . . . . Et qnia bonum dicit ordinem entis ad appetitum, verum omnino scienfia et cognitio rerum."
autem dicit ordinem ad intellectum; inde est quod Philosophus dicit 40 Ibid. 1, 1: "l]lud autem quod primo intellectus concipit quasi
in VI Metaph. quod bonum et malum sunt in rebus, verum autem et notissimum et in quod conceptiones omnes resolvit est ens." Cf. S.th.
falsum sunt in mente"; S.th. I, 16, 1. For the contrast between the I--II, 94, 2: "Illud quod primo cadit sub apprehensione est ens, cujus
acts of knowledge and appetite see, f. i., De virtutibus in communi a. intellectus includitur in omnibus quaecumque quis apprehendit."
9: "Actio intellectus . . . est seeundum quod aliqualiter assimilatur 41 D V 1, 1: "Sed enti non possunt addi aliqua quasi extranea per
eognoscibili;.., actio autem virtutis appetitivae consistit in quadam modum quo differentia additur generi vel accidens subiecto, quia
inclinatione ad appetibile." quaelibet natura est essentialiter ens. Unde probat efiam Philoso-
17 In VIMetaph., lect. 4, 1239. phus in III Metaph. (c. 8) quod ens non potest esse genus."
is In VI Metaph., lect. 4, 1242: "Et i d e o . . , est praetermittendurn 42 Cf. D V 2 1 , 1: " . . . per modum contrahendi et determinandi."
, .. ens quod significat v e r u m . . . Et ideo pertinet ad scientiam de 43 For instance in D V 21, 3.
intellectu." Cf. In IVMetaph., lect. 17, 736: "Verum autem et falsum 44 D V 1 , 1.
pertinent proprie ad considerationem logici; consequuntur enim ens 45 SuperlSent. 25, 1, 4; SuperllSent. 37, 1, 1.
in ratione de quo considerat logicus: nam verum et falsum sunt in 46 D V 1, 1: "Hoc autem est anima, quae 'quodam modo est omnia',
mente." ut dicitur in III De Anima. In anima autem est vis cognitiva et
19 De ente et essentia, ch. 1; S.th. I, 3, 4 ad 2; 48, 2 ad 2; Summa appetitiva. Convenientiam ergo entis ad appetitum exprimit hoc
contra gentiles III, 9; De potentia 7, 2 ad 1; De malo 1, 1 ad 19; nomen 'bonum', . . . convenientiam veto entis ad intellectum
Quodl. IX, 2, 2; SuperlSent. 19, 5, 1 ad 1; Super l I Sent. 34, 1, 1. Cf. exprimit hoc nomen 'verum'."
Veres (1970). 47 Metz (1962).
2o In VMetaph., lect. 9, 896. 48 S.th.I, 8 2 , 4 a d 1 .
21 S.th. I, 16, 3: "Sed contra est quod dicit Philosophus quod eadem 49 In III De anima, lect. 13,790.
est dispositio rerum in esse et veritate." 50 S.th.I, 14, 1.
22 Thomas carefully articulates Aristotle's argument in his Com- sl Summa contra gentiles III, 112: "Naturae autem intellectuales
mentary: In H Metaph., lect. 2, 292--298. majorem habent affinitatem ad totum quam aliae naturae, nam
23 See S.th. I, 2, 3 ("the fourth way"); Depotentia 3, 5. unaquaeque intellectualis substantia est quodammodo omnia, in-
24 D V 1, 1 ad 5. Cf. Summa contragentiles I, 62. quantum totius entis comprehensiva est suo intellectu."
25 Superloannem c. 18, lect. 6, 2365. Cf. S.th I, 16, 3 ad 1: "Verum 52 D V 2 2 , 1 0 ; S . t h . I , 78,1.
est in rebus et in intellectu." 53 S.th. I, 16, 3: " . . . verum habet ordinem ad cognitionem.
26 This view seems to have regained support among modern Unumquodque autem inquantum habet de esse, intantum est
Aristotle scholars. See Owens (1984). cognoscibile. Et propter hoc dicitur in III De anima quod 'anima est
27 In IIMetaph., lect. 2, 298. quodammodo omnia' secundum sensum et intellectum. Et i d e o . . .
TRUTH AS TRANSCENDENTAL IN T H O M A S AQUINAS 171

convertitur cum ente . . . verum. Sed tamen . . . addit . . . verum . . . . Et ita est in omnibus aliis quae se babent ut mensura et
comparationem ad intellectum." mensuratum, vel perfectivum et perfectibile."
54 S.th. I, 87, 1. 67 See Vande Wiele (1954), p. 551; Aertsen (1984), pp. 10--11;
55 S.th. III, lO, 3. Wippel (1989), pp. 324--326.
56 In De causis, lect. 6, 168: "Probat autem Philosophus in IX 6~ S.th. I, 16, 8.
Metaph. (c. 9) quod u n u m q u o d q u e cognoscitur per id quod est in 69 In I Perih., lect. 3, 29. Cf. D V 1, 4: "In rebus autem [veritas est]
actu et ideo ipsa actualitas rei est q u o d d a m lumen ipsius." improprie et secundario."
57 S.th.I, 16,3obj. l. Cf. D V 1 , 2 o b j . 1. 7o S.th. I, 16, 1: "Per accidens autem [habet res ordinem] ad intel-
55 Heidegger (1967), pp. 80--81. lectum a quo cognoscibilis est." Cf. D V 1, 4: "Veritas autem quae
59 D V 1 , 2; S.th. I, 16, i a d 3. dicitur de rebus in comparatione ad intellectum humanum, est rebus
60 S.th. I, 16, 3 ad 1. In D V 1, 2 these types of convertibility are q u o d a m m o d o accidentalis"; D V 1, 10.
called per praedicationem and per consequentiam. 71 &th.I, 1 6 , 1 a d l . Cf. D V 1 , 2 a d 4 .
61 S.th.I, 16,3obj. 2. Cf. D V l , l obj. 7. 72 S.th. I, 16, 1: "Per se quidem habet [res] ordinem ad intellectum a
62 S.th. I, 16, 3 ad 2: "Non ens non habet in se unde cognoscatur, sed quo dependet secundum suum esse."
cognoscitur inquanmm intellectus facit iUud cognoscibile. U n d e 73 D V 1 , 2. Cf. InlPerih.,lect. 3, 29.
verum fundatur in ente, inquantum non ens est q u o d d a m ens 74 D V 1, 2: "Sed sunt mensuratae ab intellectu divino, in quo sunt
rationis, apprehensum scilicet a ratione." Super I Sent. 19, 5, 1 ad 5; omnia, sicut omnia artificiata in intellectu artificis."
D V l , l a d 7 . Cf. D V 1 , 5 a d 2 . 75 D V l, 2: "Prima autem ratio veritatis per prius inest rei quam
63 D V 1, 1 ad 1 (quae contra obiciuntur). secunda, quia prius est eius comparatio ad intellectum divinum quam
64 D V 1, 8. humanum."
65 Cf. D V 21, 1 ad 3: "Omnis relatio realis est in genere deter- 76 D V 1, 10: "Comparatio ad intellectum divinum est ei essentialis
minato, sed relationes non reales possunt circuire omne ens." et secundum earn per se dicitur vera."
66 D V 21, 1: "Illa autem r e l a t i o . . , invenitur esse rationis tantum, 77 InIPerih., lect. 3, 30.
secundum quam dicitur referri id quod non dependet ad id ad quod
refertur, sed e converso, cum ipsa relatio quaedam dependentia sit
Free University, A m s t e r d a m

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi