Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 20

[ PM L A

Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature


of Exhausted Justiication

andre furlani

S AMUEL BECKETT’S HOMAGE TO THE ARTIST JACK YEATS RIVALS


Ludwig Wittgenstein’s notorious prohibition “Whereof one
cannot speak, thereof one must be silent” (Tractatus 89 [pt. 7]):1

Gloss? In images of such breathless immediacy as these there is no


occasion, no time given, no room let, for the lenitive of comment.
None in this impetus of need that scatters them loose to the beyonds of
vision. None in this great inner real where phantoms quick and dead,
nature and void, all that ever and that never will be, join in a single
evidence for a single testimony. None in this inal mastery which sub-
mits in trembling to the unmasterable.
No.
Merely bow in wonder. (“Homage”)

Whereof one cannot speak, thereto one must bow. Beckett rebukes the
insistence on interpreting what is open to view and what is not avail-
able at all. Like the author of Tractatus logico-philosophicus, Beckett
airms the arts’ privileged access to “the beyonds of vision”; like the
author of Philosophical Investigations (Philosophische Untersuchungen),
he airms that interpretation is neither inexorable nor always desirable.
his contrasts with both the poststructuralism that enlists the
later work of Beckett and the neopragmatism that enlists the later
Associate professor in the Department work of Wittgenstein. Like Jacques Derrida, Wittgenstein sees that
of English at Concordia University, Sir if no sign by itself can determine a meaning, neither will any sup-
George Williams Campus, ANDRE FUR- plementary ones; no interpretation could ensure accord between
LANI is the author of Guy Davenport:
sign and referent: “Every interpretation hangs in the air along with
Postmodern and After (Northwestern UP,
2007). His book-length manuscript “Beck-
what is interpreted, and cannot serve as its support.” Wittgenstein,
ett after Wittgenstein” is under consider- however, declines the deconstructive deduction: “Interpretations by
ation at Northwestern University Press. themselves do not determine meaning” (Philosophische Untersu-

38 [ © 2012 by the moder n language association of america ]


1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 39

chungen 344 [no. 198]). What does determine To “execute” an interpretation (the
meaning is the context; the sign “by itself ” verb Beckett uses sardonically in Watt [73])
is a misleading philosophical abstraction at- depends on a rule-following competence
tached to a vestigial metaphysical demand. that permeates our actions (Wittgenstein,
Wittgenstein denies, Martin Stone writes, Bemerkungen über die Farben 102 [pt.  3,
“that we can intelligibly consider a bit of sign- no. 303]). Here Wittgenstein’s spade turns. he
involving behaviour in abstraction from its philosopher told his Cambridge students in
surrounding circumstances and nonetheless 1939 that grasping a rule is not an interpreta-
still have sign-involving behaviour in view” tion but a “consensus of action” (Wittgenstein’s
(“Wittgenstein” 106; see 100–12). Lectures on the Foundations 183–84). Lan-
In Investigations meaning is ungrounded guage itself rests on this “Übereinstimmung
and yet securely tied by outward criteria to im Handeln,” which, unlike C. S. Peirce’s ap-
ordinary social practices, whereas for Derrida peal to consensus, is not based on opinion
these practices obscure the extent to which (Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Ma-
their agreement with meaning is an entitle- thematik 342 [pt. 6, no. 39]). “But the ground,
ment only. For the author of Investigations, the justiication of the evidence, comes to an
interpretation is reserved for exceptions; end; yet the end is not that certain proposi-
for Derrida, plain meaning is a special case. tions strike us immediately as true—i.e., is not
Where Derrida identiies a necessary possi- a kind of seeing on our part; rather, it is our
bility of doubt about a sign’s meaning, this is acting, which lies at the basis of the language
only because, from Wittgenstein’s perspec- game” (Über Gewißheit 160–61 [no. 204]).
tive, he has severed the sign from its enabling he mental intermediary of interpreta-
circulation within the congruent behaviors tion between expression and application re-
composing a “form of life” (Lebensform)— quired by Derrida is for Wittgenstein by no
that is, the sum of the tacit agreements bound means compulsory.4 Interpretation, Robert
together in our communal activities, “what Fogelin notes, must be “understood as a spe-
has to be accepted, the given” (Philosophische cial kind of activity that takes place within
Untersuchungen 572). language and not as something that lies at its
“If I have exhausted the justiications, I foundation” (19). According to Wittgenstein,
have now reached bedrock, and my spade is “[t]he diicult thing here is not to dig down to
turned. I am then inclined to say, ‘his is just the ground but to recognize the ground lying
how I go about it.’”2 his is just how Beckett before us as the ground. For the ground keeps
goes about it. “here is an end to the tempta- projecting the illusion of a greater depth to
tion of light, its polite scorching & consola- us, and when we try to reach this we ind our-
tions,” he writes to Mary Manning Howe on selves once again at the old level. Our alic-
30 August 1937, insisting, “here is an end of tion is that of wanting to explain.”5
making up one[’s] mind, like a pound of tea” Beckett deeply shares what Fogelin calls
(Letters 546). “The difficulty is here: to put Wittgenstein’s “defactoism,” which is neither
a halt” to explanation (Wittgenstein, Zettel a symptom of pessimism nor an expression of
346 [no. 314]). That this halt should betray defeat but “a fundamental challenge to the le-
no deficiency or delinquency, that indeed gitimacy of the philosophical enterprise as it is
explanation should end and yet our practice commonly pursued” (Fogelin 11). Beckett told
rightly continue,3 discloses an abiding Witt- the scholar Lawrence Harvey in the early 1960s
gensteinian complement to Beckett’s uncom- that there was “no revolt at all” in his work:
promising yet phlegmatic representations of “He used the terms ‘complete submission’ and
exhausted justiication. said that he was ‘revolted but not revolting.’ He
40 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

was using the word in its etymological sense über die Grundlagen der Mathematik), fol-
of turning way from but not active opposition lowed by over a dozen major posthumous
to” (137). Elsewhere, Beckett celebrates the works before Beckett’s death, in 1989.
van Velde brothers’ “peinture d’acceptation” he irst of the following sections identi-
‘painting of acceptance’ (“Peintures” 137), fies Beckett’s allusions to Wittgenstein and
praises the “dispassionate acceptance that is applies the philosopher’s concept of “family re-
beyond tragedy” in Jack Yeats (“To Cissie Sin- semblance” (Familienähnlichkeit) to establish
clair”; 14 Aug. 1937; Beckett, Letters 536), and the nature and signiicance of the two writers’
recommends the “quietism” of his conidant, affinities. Each of the subsequent three sec-
the Catholic Irish poet Thomas McGreevey tions isolates a related instance of these aini-
(“Humanistic Quietism” 68). ties. he second section concerns Beckettian
Exposure during his German sojourn in alterity and places my argument within schol-
1936–37 to the captiously self-legitimating arship that eschews nihilist readings to gauge
science sponsored by Nazi ideology conirmed instead the activity of sense making in Beckett.
Beckett’s disdain for generalized elucidation, While much of that work follows from post-
as his unpublished German diaries report: “I structuralist categories of sense making as dif-
say I am not interested in a ‘uniication’ of the ferentiation,6 mine follows from Wittgenstein’s
historical chaos any more than I am in the account of sense making as rule following, not
‘clariication’ of the individual chaos, + still least because Beckett himself insistently re-
less in the anthropomorphisation of the inhu- turns to the protocols of rule following.
man necessities that provoke the chaos. What he third section situates rule following
I want is the straws, f lotsam, etc., names, and meaning in Beckett not in discourses
dates, births & deaths, because that is all I of deferral, undecidability, and instability
can know” (“German Diaries,”15 Jan. 1937). but in the convergent behaviors of a “form
Beckett’s brand of defactoism unites the mel- of life.” While scholars and audiences may
ancholy and resistance that Andrew Gibson not always recognize that “interpretation
identiies as going “hand in hand” in these di- comes to an end” or need not necessarily be-
aries and other writings (Samuel Beckett 81). gin (Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der
Alain Badiou identiies the late 1950s as Mathematik 342 [pt. 6, no. 38]), rehearsing
transitional for Beckett, especially in Beck- theater companies must. My concluding sec-
ett’s representations of solipsism and alterity tion shows that staging his plays in French,
(On Beckett). Despite Beckett’s rehabilitation English, and German enabled Beckett to re-
from nihilist reception, however, Badiou hy- strain the interpretative impulse.7 Indeed, as
postatizes into moral entities what Beckett he faced an often baffled audience directly
treats as pious obfuscations, such as amity, and thus more vulnerably as a stage direc-
unity, plurality, and ininity. Little sanctions tor—to protect himself, he avoided curtain
Badiou’s imposition on Beckett of Neopla- calls, irst nights, and press junkets—Beckett
tonic and Pauline notions of love remote from could draw clarifying philosophical conir-
the interactions of the Irish author’s calloused mation of his aesthetic practice from Witt-
characters. Yet the late 1950s, as John Fletcher genstein’s thought. Wittgenstein’s thinking
points out, is when Beckett acknowledged recommends itself here because for Wittgen-
reading Wittgenstein (Novels [1964] 88–89), stein the theater afforded exemplary dem-
who drated Investigations partly in Ireland. onstrations of the nature of self hood and
The stature of Investigations was enhanced alterity, rule following, and interpretation.
by the publication in 1956 of Remarks on the Wittgenstein’s account of rule follow-
Foundations of Mathematics (Bemerkungen ing, in which understanding is normative
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 41

and interpretation remedial, and his corol- activities and states of mind. If for instance
lary appeal to critical description over ex- I expect B to come to tea, what happens may
planation elucidate Beckett’s procedures and be this: At four o’clock I look at my diary and
diverge from Derridean theory, in which in- see the name “B” against today’s date; I pre-
terpretation is constitutive and understand- pare tea for two; I think for a moment “does B
smoke?” And put out cigarettes; towards 4.30
ing wrested from an ultimately undecidable
I begin to feel impatient; I imagine B as he will
realm of unlimited possibility. Since decon-
look when he comes into my room. All this is
struction shows that “one cannot refer to called “expecting B from 4 to 4.30.” And there
[the] real except in an interpretive experi- are endless variations to this process which
ence” (Derrida 148), it attends in Beckett’s we all describe by the same expression. If one
texts to purported hermeneutic aporias for asks what the diferent processes of expecting
what, as Beckett’s dramaturgy underscored, someone to tea have in common, the answer
oten belongs properly to the surface—an in- is that there is no single feature in common to
structively unproblematic surface Wittgen- all of them, though there are many common
stein wants recuperated from philosophy. features overlapping. These cases of expec-
tation form a family; they have family like-
nesses which are not clearly deined. (20)
Family Resemblance
In a description of rule following, Wittgen- The title of Beckett’s play, as well as its key
stein asks, “When someone promises from exchanges, similarly treats waiting not as a
one day to the next, ‘I’ll visit you tomorrow,’ uniform state but as a loosely related array of ac-
is he saying the same thing every day or every tivities. En attendant Godot declares as its sub-
day something diferent?” (Philosophische Un- ject only what is done “while awaiting Godot”:
tersuchungen 352 [no. 226]). En attendant Go-
VLADIMIR. What do we do now?
dot (Waiting for Godot), which premiered in
ESTRAGON. Wait.
1953, just as Philosophical Investigations post-
VLADIMIR. Yes, but while waiting.
humously appeared, poses the same question. ESTRAGON. What about hanging ourselves? (22)
Godot daily sends word to expect him tomor-
row, but is he saying the same thing every Simply to wait is not a possibility, because
day? And what kind of action is expectation? waiting takes on multiple guises, which have
Wittgenstein did not live to see a play no one feature in common. he play concerns
like Godot, largely conined to inconsequen- not waiting but the many ways the pair do not
tial routine, though almost a quarter century wait, while waiting. Waiting in Godot is pre-
before the premiere of Godot he foresaw such text and prayer, pastime and pensum, an asce-
a play’s potentially mesmeric quality and sis and a mode of inertia, but above all waiting
concluded in a notebook entry that it “would is a blanket term for the various means of or-
have to be uncanny and wondrous at the same ganizing the pair’s dilatory passage to vespers.
time” (Vermischte Bemerkungen 456). In he Beckett, like Wittgenstein, so parses the verb
Blue and Brown Books he sketches a scenario to wait that it sheds its spurious resemblance
of waiting as a drama of “family likenesses”: to a simple, homogenous action. Waiting has
no more an essence than does Godot, the
What happens if from 4 till 4.30 A expects B
to come to his room? In one sense in which vacuum out of which Vladimir and Estragon
the phrase “to expect something from 4 to generate minimal possibility.
4.30” is used it certainly does not refer to one Expressions of expectation are instances
process or state of mind going on throughout of language’s collusion in the perpetuation of
that interval, but to a great many different misleading a priori concepts. his contributes
42 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

to making it impossible to use language to proofs to deinitive conclusions; Saul Kripke


transcend language. “I cannot get beyond lan- stresses that Investigations “is written as a
guage by means of language,” Wittgenstein perpetual dialectic, where persisting worries,
declares;8 Tractatus proposes that we are con- expressed by the voice of the imaginary inter-
stituted by a language in which being cannot locutor, are never deinitively silenced” (3).11
be stated. “Mistrust of grammar is the irst While Beckett’s exposure to Wittgen-
condition of philosophizing,” Wittgenstein stein’s ideas cannot yet be precisely dated, tex-
says in his 1913 “Notes on Logic” (“Aufzeich- tual and anecdotal evidence permits inference.
nungen über die Logik” [206]). “Being is not Fletcher reports Beckett’s avowal of reading
syntactical,” Beckett proclaimed while direct- Wittgenstein since 1958, when the prelimi-
ing the German version of Godot in West Ber- nary studies for Investigations were published
lin in 1975 (Cohn, “Ruby Cohn” 129). as he Blue and Brown Books (Novels [1964]).
The limitations of language are not, in Beckett told André Bernold in 1984 that Witt-
this view, invitations to interpretation, which genstein was unheard of in Dublin when
is understood as a mode of substitution (Phi- Beckett permanently departed for France in
losophische Untersuchungen 345 [no. 201]). 1938 and that he had been obliged to study
Beckett and Wittgenstein expressed funda- his works unaided in recent years (Bernold 22;
mental misgivings about the interpretivist Pilling, Samuel Beckett Chronology 223). he
mandate assumed in philosophy and literary philosopher E. M. Cioran, Beckett’s friend
studies, and they not surprisingly objected since the early 1960s, compared him with
to much of their work’s reception.9 They Wittgenstein in a 1976 memoir, suggesting
questioned too the merits of institutional that had Beckett overlooked the parallels, Cio-
frameworks for the creation, support, and cus- ran was ready to remind him of them (135).
todianship of philosophical and literary texts. The consonances are equally striking
Wittgenstein’s work ater Tractatus (1922) fa- where the possibility of allusion does not ob-
vors examples over properties, practices over tain, as in the treatment of expectation. Mar-
principles and abstraction, and attends less jorie Perlof proposes that the issue “is less one
to encapsulating generalization than to vari- of inluence than of a peculiar symbiosis be-
ety and impurity, an impurity that is also the tween the Austrian philosopher and the Irish
acknowledged condition of the work itself. writer” (Wittgenstein’s Ladder 135). Particu-
Hence, Tractatus carries a force for those with larly germane here is Wittgenstein’s concept
reservations regarding critical theory.10 of family resemblance. Whereas the essential-
Such a stance would recommend itself to ist criteria and abstract categories of analytic
Beckett, who already in his 1931 monograph definitions subsume diverse entities under
Proust denounces synoptic system building, general rubrics, Wittgenstein recognizes that
depth models, exegesis, and abstraction. It a distinct entity may share a property with
would also recommend to him Wittgenstein’s another without satisfying necessary and suf-
style, about which Stanley Cavell notes, “he icient conditions of identity. He remarks that
first thing to be said in accounting for his the strength of a rope “does not lie in some
style is that he writes: he does not report, he one fiber running through its entire length
does not write up results” (“Availability” 70). but rather in many ibers overlapping” (Phi-
Both writers identiied their work as “precipi- losophische Untersuchungen 278 [no. 67]).
tates” and favored provisional titles for them The Wittgensteinian overlappings per-
(Wittgenstein, Philosophische Untersuchungen ceptible in Beckett’s work imply the fam-
231; Beckett, Echo’s Bones 142). Wittgenstein ily resemblances that Wittgenstein himself
does not argue deductively from theses and stressed between philosophy and literature:
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 43

“one really ought only write philosophy as While no direct evidence indicates that
poetry” (Vermischte Bemerkungen 483).12 Al- Beckett read Investigations before the late
ready in his 1929 essay on Finnegans Wake, 1950s, earlier familiarity with the argument
Beckett extols Giambattista Vico’s insight of Tractatus would be difficult to discount.
that “poetry is a prime condition of philos- Translating Murphy into French between 1939
ophy.”13 Wittgenstein, whose work Badiou and 1940, Beckett placed a Wittgensteinian
aligns with Arthur Rimbaud’s and Stéphane seal on the ladder Murphy draws up into his
Mallarmé’s (Wittgenstein’s Antiphilosophy garret: “Ticklepenny had unscrewed the lad-
156–57, 169), counters philosophy’s Hege- der, so that now he could draw it up ater him.
lian supersession of art by viewing literature Do not come down the ladder, they have taken
as privileged, because correctively ordinary it away,” the omniscient narrator irrelevantly
and yet, since it may show what nomination commands (188), as though strictly to allude
prohibits, exempt from the restrictions on to the discarded ladder of Tractatus. Now,
analytic discourse. Submitting Tractatus to as irst noted by Ruby Cohn (“Philosophical
a literary press, Wittgenstein in an undated Fragments” 174), Beckett adds a Gallic Lud-
1919 letter to the publisher Ludwig von Ficker wig (“Louis”), who otherwise never appears
called it “strictly philosophical and at the in either version of the novel: “Ticklepenny
same time literary” (Briefe 33). avait dévisée la base de l’échelle, de sort que
he concept of family resemblance ofers a maintenant il pouvait la ramener derrière
means for assessing literary and philosophical lui. Ne descendez pas par l’échelle, Louis, ils
interactions without the annexation of one to l’ont enlevée” (137). Within two years Beckett
the other. Wittgenstein and Beckett are partic- began Watt, a novel whose Wittgensteinian
ularly well served by it. “My propositions elu- analogues have been extensively discussed,
cidate in this way,” Wittgenstein writes, “that including Arsene’s account of his climacteric
he who understands me recognizes them at vision: “What was changed was existence of
last as senseless when he has climbed through the ladder. Do not come down the ladder, Ifor,
them—on them—over them. (He must, so to I haf taken it away” (44).16
speak, discard the ladder ater he has climbed Watt was largely completed before the
up on it)” (Tractatus 85 [pt. 6, no. 54]). In end of World War II. In 1946 Beckett drated
Worstward Ho (1981), Beckett declares, “Said is his irst original French novel, Mercier et Ca-
missaid” (108), the axiomatic, self-consuming mier (Mercier and Camier), in which Witt-
logic of the phrase akin to the self-invalidating genstein’s call for silence on matters deemed
performative that concludes—and paradoxi- inexpressible is the basis of a comic exchange:
cally vindicates—Tractatus.14
If we have nothing to say, said Camier, let
Beckett and Wittgenstein share what
us say nothing.
F. H. Bradley calls the critical capacity “to
We have things to say, said Mercier.
get within the judgement the condition of hen why don’t we say them? said Camier.
the judgement” (265). he paired quotations We can’t, said Mercier.
above are judgments, certainly, and equally hen let us be silent, said Camier.
they are trenchant instances of a commit- But we try, said Mercier. (144)
ment to retain and harness the conditions
of those judgments. Such resemblances be- A yet more explicit and sardonic (though
tween the authors of the deeply philosophical equally unremarked) reference to the Tracta-
Worstward Ho and the highly literary Investi- tus interdiction “Whereof one cannot speak,
gations invite reappraisal of the conventions thereof one must be silent” appears in the
that isolate them generically.15 opening paragraph of L’innommable (The
44 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

Unnamable), written between 1949 and 1950: tesian method, Beckett concisely exposes its
“he fact would seem to be, if in my situation foundational contradiction: doubt is certain,
one may speak of facts, not only that I shall indeed presumes certainty. Beckett’s typically
have to speak of things of which I cannot antonymic jest encapsulates Wittgenstein’s
speak, but also, which is even more interest- refutation of Cartesian skepticism: “Only he
ing, but also that I, which is if possible even who has learned something for certain can
more interesting, that I shall have to, I forget, begin to doubt” (Zettel 368 [no. 410]). Doubt
no matter” (4). No sooner resolve to speak entails certainty; one would otherwise have to
l’innommable than fail to speak it. he sen- begin by doubting the very language in which
tence appropriately fractures and falls silent doubt is voiced. “Who is certain of no fact
on the matter of defying silence. “I shall have could not even be certain of the sense of his
to speak of things of which I cannot speak” words” (Über Gewißheit 144 [no. 114]).
may serve as the caption to Wittgenstein’s Claims to knowledge are meaningful only
paradoxical book, which ultimately would where doubt is possible, but a stable network
speak—by failing to speak—the unspeakable.17 of implicit communal beliefs and practices
In an undated 1919 letter to Ficker, Witt- necessarily underlies doubt (Über Gewißheit
genstein writes: 141 [no. 105]). his is why Beckett’s later texts,
for all their igmentary phenomena and mo-
I should like to write that my work emerges in lecular verbal residua, deny the void from its
two parts: in what is put forward here, and in verge. There abides what in Worstward Ho
all I have not written. And precisely this sec- Beckett calls an “unnullable least” (106), forms
ond part is the important one. hat is, the ethi-
of life bewilderingly immune to final nega-
cal is delineated by my book from within; and I
tion: “All gnawing to be naught. Never to be
am convinced that it is strictly to be delineated
only in this way. In short, I believe: All that so naught” (115). A “system of relations” (Bezugs-
many blow hot air about these days I in my system) stands fast for all (Über Gewißheit 141
book have delineated by being silent about it. [no. 105])—one that guarantees the coherence
(Briefe 35) of Beckett’s increasingly elliptical, compressed
syntax and that encourages a lexicon with lit-
From an ethics of inaudibilities one readily ar- tle speciic semantic content (Banield 16–22).
rives at what Beckett in his 1932 novel Dream In their later works Wittgenstein and
of Fair to Middling Women, whose publication Beckett pursue the limitations on doubt
he postponed until ater his death, vaunts as rather than those on certainty. Both focus on
an “aesthetics of inaudibilities,” a program solipsism, which the rule-governed activity of
drawing on Rimbaud and Beethoven, “whose speech afronts. his predicament impels the
audibilities are no more than punctuation in 1980 text Company, to which I now turn with
a statement of silences” (141, 102). reference to Wittgenstein’s last work, On Cer-
tainty (Über Gewißheit [published in 1969]).
Wittgenstein defends the sanguine tol-
Private Languages
erance for doubt typical of Beckett’s mono-
When attention to a clock’s dial in Beckett’s logists: “(My) doubts constitute a system”
novel Ill Seen Ill Said reveals the Wittgenstei- (Über Gewißheit 146 [no. 126]). The condi-
nian point that any description of time is a tions of doubt belong to a given “picture of
function of the language game in which it is the world” (Weltbild) that is neither true nor
used (Wittgenstein, Blue and Brown Books false but the basis of all inquiry and assertion
106–10), the narrator concludes, “hen doubt (153 [no. 162]). his picture neither enjoys nor
certain” (77). Far from vindicating the Car- requires more justification than as an “un-
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 45

grounded way of acting” (143 [no. 110]; see abolishes the very terms of solipsism, the tau-
also 158 [no. 192]). It is a picture common in tology of pronominal notation. “What the so-
Beckett, who reduces human “ways of acting” lipsist wants is not a notation in which the ego
to their nucleus in an ontologically unguar- has a monopoly, but one in which the ego van-
anteed consensus prior to experience. ishes,” Wittgenstein said in the same lecture.
What underlies and enables doubt is The solipsism of Company’s narrator
then language itself. Doubt may be certain, involves just this evasion of the personal
but language precedes it. Thus, it threatens pronoun. He puts words in the hearer’s
the solipsism typically cherished by Beckett’s mouth—that is, in his own—only to rescind
narrators, such as of Company. “And you,” he them immediately, aware that this interven-
tells himself, “as you always were. Alone” (46). tion of a speaking ego does not conform with
And yet there is a lot of company in Beckett’s the solipsism that he hopes may aford sanc-
strikingly polyvocal and populous story. tuary from the pains of engagement: “the irst
here is a world of it: the world of speech. person singular and a fortiori plural pronoun
In Beckett’s later prose one is oten alone, had never any place in your vocabulary”
with words. Yet one is never alone with words: (45). “he word ‘I’ is one symbol among oth-
language keeps company. he pathos of Beck- ers having a practical use,” Wittgenstein told
ett’s later narrators and protagonists inheres his students, “and could be discarded when
not only in their isolation but also in the be- not necessary for practical speech. It does
deviling embeddedness of their language in not stand out among all other words we use
a world they would deny and the embedded- in practical life unless we begin using it as
ness of their world in a language they cannot Descartes did” (Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cam-
transcend. he third person is insinuated into bridge, 1932–1935 63).18 Company manipulates
the text, acting contrary to solipsism as Witt- the practical uses for and the tactical omission
genstein describes in his refutation of Carte- of the irst-person-singular pronoun.
sianism—acting in and on language. he voice he narrator of Company strives to com-
that spontaneously “comes to one in the dark” mand all the elements of the narrative, in-
may be a specter, a custodian, a self-projection, cluding his own impotence. he irst person
or a paraclete, but it is always irst and fore- is denied access to voice. “Could he speak to
most speech (Beckett, Company 3; cf. Wittgen- and of whom the voice speaks there would be
stein, Über Gewißheit 132 [nos. 61–65]). a irst,” he neutrally reports. “But he cannot.
“Getting into the solipsistic mood means He shall not.” he shit to the impersonal im-
not using the word ‘I’ in describing a personal perative betrays his imperiousness, as does
experience,” Wittgenstein told his Cambridge the biblical modulation: “You cannot. You
students in 1932 (Wittgenstein’s Lectures, shall not” (4). Like the self-entangling mar-
Cambridge, 1932–1935 22). he solipsist ren- tinet of What Where, the narrator wishes to
ders pronominal speciicity superluous. he do all the disposing. he most important pre-
irst-person pronoun is excluded from Com- rogative is to assert that the subject is alone.
pany, whose protagonist projects an omni- His solipsism requires this. The language,
scient third-person voice that addresses him however, disposes otherwise.
in the second and assigns memories the lis- Language gives the “deviser” of the story
tener denies: “To murmur, Yes I remember. the means to establish prior exterior entities
What an addition to company that would be! through the use of second- and third-person-
A voice in the irst person singular. Murmur- singular imperatives and indicatives, which
ing now and then, Yes I remember” (10). he installs him among relations. He can fabricate
I paradoxically generates company because it these relations but not the principles of their
46 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

coordination. he characters and situations of use of that name. Self-consciousness perpetu-


the narrative may be plastic and efaceable, but ates the illusion that the authority for the ego’s
the condition of narrative itself is not. Speech statements derives from experiences known
is public, subjecting the speaker to codes and exclusively to the ego, when they could not be
their consequences. The deviser of company intelligible were they private mental events.
wants no company, in reality. he story is about he assault on the epistemic criteria af-
how he gets it regardless. He cannot quarantine forded by the irst person does not eradicate
his language from this baneful efect. certainty but displaces it onto the third per-
The first-person singular can be omit- son. Contrary to Émile Benveniste, for whom
ted from Company but not “that cankerous the third-person pronoun is the sign of the
other” the third (4). This other dispels the “non-person” (228), Wittgenstein urges that,
soothing mirage of solipsistic seclusion in far from being evacuated, the third person
the dark recesses of consciousness. his other is the precondition for any statement of self-
proves that the narrative’s speaker is not identity, mutuality, or alterity. he existence
“alone” absolutely or necessarily but by ob- of the external world is presumed by any
stinate choice, like the monologist of Krapp’s statement made with respect to it, and so
Last Tape. Except in the sense of a routine ex- fundamental doubt inally must devour itself.
istential pathos that Beckett’s texts refuse (in- Such a displacement and reintegration of the
deed, mock), the “you” of Company cannot be self are pervasive in Beckett, however much
“as you always were. Alone.” he third person, his monologists may combat them.
invoked here by a irst person masquerading he terms of this company place Beckett’s
as a second, objectively secures company. deviser in the logic of pronominal mutuality
he pronominal oscillations are syntac- and reception. he conditions of his isolation
tic maneuvers in an exclusively linguistic are a fortiori communal, since verbal. In the
space, but, as Wittgenstein (following Gott- language of company, the third person con-
lob Frege) demonstrates, language depends fers plurality and facilitates exchange. “You”
on a world antecedent to the irst person. he may be alone on your back in the dark, as the
camoulaged irst-person narrator can only narrator imagines, but you are never alone in
devise a third person (and vice versa) because your language. his is a source of anguish to
of the priority of the third. Even projected many a Beckett character. Beckett’s readers
as a iction, the third person of Company is do not share this anguish because “leasten-
summoned, instantiated—and instantiating. ing words” like you do not merely displace or
Its priority is the guarantee of speech, world, postpone but affront the “so-said void. The
and self. Language does not simply make so-missaid” (Beckett, Company 106, 101).
company possible; it makes company. Badiou has inluentially detected in Beck-
For the Cartesian priority of the irst per- ett a maturation “from a programme of the
son Wittgenstein substitutes precedence of the One—obstinate trajectory or interminable
third, and he locates it in language itself. “I monologue—to the pregnant theme of the
have tried to convince you of just the opposite Two, which opens out onto ininity” (On Beck-
of Descartes’ emphasis on the ‘I,’” he told his ett 17). He inds in Company and other texts
students (Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge, from the late 1950s onward a redeeming en-
1932–1935 63). “I does not name a person,” counter with alterity: “the Two of love as the
he declares in Investigations (Philosophische passage from the One of solipsism to the in-
Untersuchungen 409 [no. 410]). Reference is inite multiplicity of the world” (31). Whereas
necessarily public, an agreement not between Badiou perceives an emerging emphasis on al-
name and object but between parties on the terity in Beckett, however, the later texts usu-
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 47

ally present the other as more phantasmagoric connected to an area increasingly important
than do the earlier ones. Language rather than to Beckett from the early 1960s, rule follow­
mutuality sponsors alterity in Beckett; lan­ ing. Following a rule is a practice, not an in­
guage is encounter—makes encounter. It is far terpretation (Philosophische Untersuchungen
from always welcome in Beckett (the narrator 345 [no. 202]). he special experiences of in­
of Company would gladly rid himself of it), but trospection supposed to secure understand­
it is certainly more welcome than love, a word ing of a rule are, like the more general notion
scrupulously omitted as irrelevant even from of a private language, chimerical, for there is
his play Enough, his tart distillation of he Old neither an inner process nor a metaphysical
Curiosity Shop on which Badiou dwells. mechanism involved in the ability to obey
It is in language that Beckett will capture an order correctly. Understanding is not the
the “all but uninane” deposits of being that consequence of a correct interpretation of
remain (Company 107). This is where alter­ the meaning of an order but is instead the
ity stumps solipsism. Badiou needs “event,” satisfactory demonstration of an inculcated
“love,” and “infinity” as the bases of a dis­ technique: “To follow a rule, convey a mes­
cursive ethics that Beckett resists and whose sage, give an order, play a game of chess are
legitimacy Wittgenstein denies (see, e.g., On customs (uses, institutions). To understand a
Beckett 17, 31, 65). Language precedes and con­ sentence means to understand a language. To
ditions these concepts. he cogito is confuted understand a language means to command a
by language well before the other assails it. technique” (Philosophische Untersuchungen
In Company Beckett follows a Wittgen­ 344 [no. 199]).
steinian route out of what he regarded as the In Endgame Clov grudgingly obeys
impasse of The Unnamable, whose narrator Hamm’s order to survey the earth through
lails against a language that, in constituting the telescope: “There’s one thing I’ll never
him, alienates him (hiher 84). For the speaker understand. (He gets down.) Why I always
of Company, enlistment into the plurality of obey you. Can you explain that to me?”
language is both coercion and complicity—a (75–76). Hamm surmises Clov’s unconscious
kind of inadvertent connivance with conniv­ motivation to be compassion (76), while crit­
ing speech. he story shows the habits of a so­ ics have adduced the mutual dependency of
lipsism wracked by the inveterate mutuality of the master­slave dialectic, or entropic iner­
speech; yet communication of solipsism, Beck­ tia, or the metatheatrical machinery that in
ett’s narration emphasizes, abolishes the cap­ repertory must restore Clov to servitude by
tious ontological basis of that condition and the next performance. Harder to see is the
generates instead encounter, one that textuality simplicity of a dramatic situation in which
multiplies. In challenging the doctrine of the rule following and obeying commands are
cogito, Wittgenstein makes a resounding phil­ behaviors justiied not by reason but by their
osophical statement of a condition fundamen­ recognized accord with instructions—Witt­
tal to Beckett’s later texts. “Does he who talks genstein’s “consensus of action.” As Saul
when no one else is there speak to himself?” Kripke notes, “Eventually the process must
(Philosophische Untersuchungen 362 [no. 260]). stop—‘justifications come to an end some­
No, Investigations and Company reply. where’—and I am left with a rule which is
completely unreduced to any other” (17).
In one of the many dramaticules in In-
Rule Following
vestigations, an interlocutor objects to Witt­
Wittgenstein’s examination of the idea that genstein’s example of teaching the rules for
no private realm of meaning should exist is addition by even numbers: “‘However you
48 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

instruct him to pursue the serial pattern, the command be veriied; and here, as oten
how can he know how he is to continue it by in the play, Hamm’s acknowledgment is tacit,
himself?’ Well, how do I know? If that means, a matter of subtle or displaced gestures of
‘Have I reasons?,’ the answer is: my reasons agreement encapsulating the form of life he
will soon give out on me. And then I will act shares with Clov.
without reasons” (Philosophische Unter su- Clov’s primitive reaction at the window is
chungen 349 [no. 211]). Without psychologi­ the result of training in particular paradigms,
cal inlation (i.e., causal motivations), Beckett without which no agreement about the con-
shows the point where reasons for following a cept of a rule could even arise. he reasons for
rule end. Clov wants to “understand” why he following rules, and for the conviction that
always obeys Hamm, but Endgame crisply de- they are correctly followed, come only later.
lineates that Wittgensteinian threshold where Obedience in Beckett is neither contingent nor
understanding becomes an accompaniment to metaphysical but instead a prerational relation.
an act that derives its meaning from its appli- Clov’s protestations and threats are the
cation (Zettel 343 [nos. 305–06]). marks of a primitive and unreasoned obedi-
Following rules and commands rests on ence. He follows the intricate rules of the end-
a basis outside language, where the shared game with aplomb. he repeated resolutions
criteria of a “form of life” establish agree- to quit Hamm’s service are expressions more
ment. As epitomized by his 1978 West Berlin of submission than deiance, for Clov must
production of Endgame (Endspiel), Beckett’s ind a way not to leave but to stay. Defection
dramaturgy shifted focus from dialogue to is in the script; Clov’s departure, in the guise
kinetics (spatial interaction, gesture, rhythm of a seasoned Edwardian rambler, is literally
and pacing, etc.). “Look at the earth,” Hamm pure theater: “his is what we call making an
commands, and Clov climbs the ladder to exit” (81). his is what actors, not servants,
peer through a window: call it. It is let to Hamm to discharge Clov:
“It’s the end, Clov, we’ve come to the end. I
CLOV. Christ, she’s under water! (He looks.) How don’t need you any more” (78). he masquer-
can that be? (He pokes forward his head, his hand ading is not a deception but another device
above his eyes.) It hasn’t rained. (He wipes the
for maintaining the game, “[s]ince that’s the
pane, looks. Pause.) Ah what a fool I am! I’m on
way we’re playing it” (84). It is another tac-
the wrong side! (He gets down, takes a few steps
towards the window right.) What a fool I am! (He tic of staying—not staying the same way, not
carries ladder towards window right.) Sometimes staying put, but staying in a way that may af-
I wonder if I’m in my right senses. hen it passes ford Clov a dignifying glint of possibility.
of and I’m as intelligent as ever. (73) Wittgenstein’s account of rule following
is an antidote to the temptation to psycholo-
Wittgenstein invokes the same situation: gize the two characters’ relationship narrowly.
“The absent-minded man who on the or- Clov’s grasp of rules and commands depends
der ‘Right turn!’ turns let, and then clutch- inally not on interpretation—on hypotheses
ing his forehead says, ‘Oh!—right turn’ and concerning their application—but on acquired
makes a right.—What has occurred to him? and unrelective response to them. Rule fol-
An interpretation?” (Philosophische Unter- lowing here accords not with inner processes
suchungen 434 [no. 506]). hus he dispatches but with outward criteria of a form of life—
the notion that interpretation inheres in acts that is, circumstances perceptibly agreeing
of rule following and obeying. Only when with an avowal, as collectively endorsed.
Hamm acknowledges that Clov has obeyed he play’s import is less the psychology
his command can Clov’s understanding of of Clov’s servitude or its perceived symbolic
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 49

innuendoes than the imperturbable adher- orders blind. hey do not question or assess
ence to the dynamics of rule and command the commands they follow, even when they in
following. his is part of what Beckett means turn become victims of the commands’ logic.
when, in a 29 December 1957 letter to Alan Eliminating every superluity from the logic of
Schneider, director of the American premiere rule following, Beckett shows how use rather
of Endgame, he characteristically urges “the than interpretation determines the meaning
extreme simplicity of dramatic situation and of the command. he criterion is simply cor-
issue. If that’s not enough for them [critics], rect understanding of an order. he lackeys’
and it obviously isn’t, or they don’t see it, it’s behavior initially accords with Bam’s com-
plenty for us, and we have no elucidations to mand, but Bam accuses each in turn of false
ofer of mysteries that are all of their making” report—a failure to obey. he subsequent cri-
(Beckett and Schneider 24). sis functions like a remorseless demonstration
His later plays and dramaturgy increase of Wittgenstein’s claim that following an or-
this insistence on outward criteria. In In- der is a practice independent of private under-
vestigations, Wittgenstein hypothesizes a standing: “‘to obey the rule’ is a practice. And
language made up exclusively of four com- to believe one is obeying the rule is not to obey
mands; Beckett, in his last performance piece, the rule. And hence one cannot ‘privately’
What Where, imagines a language consisting obey the rule, because otherwise to believe one
of one. Wittgenstein writes that “[o]ne can is obeying the rule would be the same thing
readily imagine a language that consists only as obeying the rule” (Philosophische Untersu-
of commands and reports in battle. Or a lan- chungen 345 [no. 202]). Belief cannot provide
guage that consists only of questions and an the criterion for obeying a command; once
expression of airmation and negation. And again, meaning is not some specter emerg-
innumerable others. And imagining a lan- ing from one’s head. What Where mordantly
guage means imagining a form of life” (Phi- stages what Anthony Kenny calls the “primi-
losophische Untersuchungen 245–46 [no. 19]). tive, unreasoned reaction on which the system
Whereas Endgame pays vestigial attention of rules and reasons is grated” (176).
to the psychology of asymmetrical relations, As rule following does not rest on in-
What Where concentrates on the formulas of terpretation, so in closing the Voice of Bam
rule following. It is a work at ease with con- mocks the viewer’s inclination to interpret
cepts of rule following that many early read- the action: “hat is all. Make sense who may.
ers of Investigations found baling. I switch of” (316). If rule following does not
What Where is a round of interrogations, require interpretation, neither does the action
conducted by and on three indistinguish- of What Where. Beckett stages not a riddle
able lackeys, under the empirical rule of Bam but an elemental interaction. It may appear
and the transcendent rule of Voice of Bam. as though the characters are disturbing ex-
The characters alternate in issuing futile ceptions who betray no more than a slavish,
commands to wrest information from one subhuman obedience (emphasized in the
another: “He didn’t say it? . . . He didn’t say director Damien O’Donnell’s 2000 version
where?” (312). As orchestrated by the disem- but not in Beckett’s own 1985 Süddeutscher
bodied Voice, rule following structures and Rundfunk television production [Beckett,
deines the action. Theatrical Notebooks IV]); yet they simply
“When I follow a rule, I don’t choose. I display what following a command funda-
follow the rule blind,” Wittgenstein writes mentally entails, the performance of an order.
(Philosophische Untersuchungen 351 [no. 219]). Beckett separates this performance from
Bem, Bim, and Bom follow Bam’s identical psychology to isolate its role in a minimal
50 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

form of life. He avoids arrogating to rule fol- the slick logical abstraction of the early work
lowing misleading notions of inner process to the corduroy traction of ordinary language
or judgment, mental states that by deinition in his later thinking. Thus, Investigations
stage and screen action withholds, nowhere maintains a view that Wittgenstein held since
more than in Beckett’s plays and ilms. Shorn drating “Notes on Logic,” in 1913: “In phi-
from the dialogue is the least suggestion losophy there are no deductions: it is purely
of interiority. For this reason Wittgenstein descriptive” (“Aufzeichnungen” 206).
views theatrical performance as an exemplary Only what is described has changed: the
instance of meaningful speech: it establishes irreducible “logical form” that any verbal
contexts and does not encourage the ascrip- “picture” must share with its referent has been
tion of private mental states to stage charac- replaced by actual verbal practices, which
ters. “he contexts in which a sentence stands have an unfixed logical order. “Philosophy
are best represented in a drama; thus, the best simply lays it all out and explains and deduces
example for a sentence with a speciic mean- nothing. Since everything lies open to view,
ing is a quotation from a drama. And who there is also nothing to explain. For whatever
asks a person in a drama what he’s experi- is hidden does not interest us” (Philosophische
encing while he’s speaking?” (Letzte Schriten Untersuchungen 303 [no. 126]). Wittgenstein
356–57 [no. 38]). views the arts the same way, noting in 1930,
In What Where Beckett imagines a “hings lie directly there before our eyes, no
unique form of life and the restrictive yet via- veil over them—Here religion and art part
ble language that constitutes it. Beckett seizes company” (Vermischte Bemerkungen 458).
upon the great diversity of verbal practices, so his is equally Beckett’s conviction. “One
that what may appear to be a pitiless reduc- can only speak of what is in front of one’s
tion of speech to mere commands, queries, eyes, and that now simply is the mess,” Beck-
and monosyllabic reports becomes conirma- ett told Tom Driver in 1961. “he only chance
tion of the fertility of language games, which of renovation is to open our eyes and see the
preserve their cohesion well ater the justii- mess. It is not a mess you can make sense of”
cations for them have been exhausted. (Driver 219, 220). Already in a preamble to
the irst radio broadcast of Godot in 1953, he
eschewed interpretation, “loftier meaning”
Description over Explanation
(“Who Is Godot?” 136).
Rule following, and thus the meaningfulness Investigations vindicates surfaces, showing
of concepts, is not inherently interpretive: “how it is” with us and leaving it as it is (Philo­
“there is a way of grasping a rule that is not sophische Untersuchungen 302 [no. 124]—an-
an interpretation but that expresses itself in ticipated in Tractatus 18 [pt. 3, no. 221]), a view
what we call ‘following the rule’ and ‘going that coincides with Beckett’s own defactoism,
against it’ from case to case of use” (Philoso­ not least in his novel How It Is. “Out with all
phische Untersuchungen 345 [no. 201]; see explanation, description alone must take its
also Über Gewißheit 132 [no. 62]). Because place” (Philosophische Untersuchungen 298–99
rule following shows that interpretation is [no. 109]; see also Perlof, “Poetics”). Making
not ubiquitous but remedial, it may serve as a this also a primary claim about aesthetics,
synecdoche for Beckett’s theater. Wittgenstein maintained in 1932 that explana-
Like the continuities in Beckett’s art tion simply substitutes one symbol for another
between affectless abstraction and visceral (Lectures and Conversations 1–40); pursued
proscenium practicalities, important conti- outside the hypothetico-deductive sciences,
nuities in Wittgenstein’s writing extend from explanation is liable to concoct “a new myth,”
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 51

such as psychoanalysis.19 “Our mistake is to he diicult production of Film in 1964


search for an explanation where we should appears to have enhanced Beckett’s confi-
have seen the facts as ‘protophenomena.’ hat dence in the self-sufficiency of the artistic
is, where we should have said, his language entity and in the value of its surface. The
game is being played [Dieses Sprachspiel wird initially dismaying gestation of one of his
gespielt]” (Philosophische Untersuchungen 476 most programmatic scripts into an elusive,
[no. 654]). autonomous film eventually gratified him.
Beckett’s postwar work solicits the ac- Inspired by Bishop Berkeley’s claim that “to
knowledgment that explanation is coun- be is to be perceived” (esse est percipi), Film
terproductive, though his insistence on follows (literally) Buster Keaton as he shuns
eschewing interpretation is oten met with in- in vain a perceiving agent coinciding first
credulity. “Do try and see the thing primarily with the camera perspective and inally with
in its simplicity, the waiting, the not knowing self-consciousness. While the ilm was being
why, or where, or when, or for what,” Beckett edited, Beckett airmed to its director, Alan
wrote on 1 April 1956 to Desmond Smith, who Schneider, in a 29 September 1964 letter that
hoped to produce Godot in Toronto. “Confu- it had escaped its “purely intellectual schema”:
sion of mind and of identity is an indispens- “I now begin to feel that this is unimportant
able element of the play and the efort to clear and that the images obtained probably gain
up the ensuing obscurities, which seems to in force what they lose as ideograms, and that
have exercised most critics to the point of the whole idea behind the film, while suf-
blinding them to the central simplicity, strikes iciently expressed for those so minded, has
me as quite nugatory” (Beckett, “Who Is Go- been chiely of value on the formal and struc-
dot?” 136). When, ater the 1953 West Berlin tural level” (Beckett and Schneider 166).
premiere of Wir Warten auf Godot (the Wir he lesson of Film curtailed the tempta-
was soon dropped from the title), the journal- tion to illustrate an intention. Beckett learned
ist Friedrich Lut asked Beckett to expostulate to trust the image; the aim was now to get it
on its signiicance, “he let me know evasively onto the stage, page, and screen. By the time
(as it seemed to me then): It’s just a play (Spiel). Jessica Tandy sought authorial intention
He had by no means intentionally added to clarify the role of Mouth in Schneider’s
deeper meaning or any hidden meaning at all American premiere of Not I, Beckett could
to his play. Only in performance (Spiel) itself write the director, on 16 November 1972,
should it elucidate itself. Did that not suice?” “I no more know where she is or why thus
(40). Dieses Spiel wird gespielt. than she does. All I know is in the text. ‘She’
Staging gave Beckett efective means to is purely a stage entity, part of a stage image
mule the symbolic reverberations that the and purveyor of a stage text. he rest is Ibsen”
extensive exegesis of his work had ampliied. (Beckett and Schneider 283).
He omitted from the English translation of “We lead words back again from their
Fin de partie (Endgame), as well as from his metaphysical to their everyday use,” Witt-
subsequent French and German productions genstein proclaims (Philosophische Untersu-
of the play, even the preposterous symbolism chungen 300 [no. 116]). Just as Wittgenstein
Hamm and Clov attach to the youth rumored grappled with the philosophical treatment of
to live outside the shelter—to Hamm he is a language, so did Beckett with the reception
Mount Pisgah Moses, to Clov a navel-gazing of his own work. Ruby Cohn concludes that
Narcissus (Fin 103–05). hough this passage Beckett’s production notebook for Endspiel
travesties hermeneutics, it had nevertheless is “concerned with the physical rather than
incited solemn commentary. the metaphysical” (Just Play 238). “Ohne
52 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

Metaphysik” ‘without metaphysics’ became poetry perhaps.’ hen he closes with surpris-
his watchword as a dramaturge, as the ac- ing inality, forestalling any objection: ‘he
tor Horst Bollmann recollected of the 1965 piece is interesting here exclusively as stage
West Berlin production of Warten auf Godot, entity [Spielvorlage]’” (Haerdter 92).20
which Beckett assisted: “When Beckett came “Don’t think but look!” Wittgenstein in-
the sun was rising for us, everything became structs himself and his readers (Philosophische
so clear and we were altogether very content, Untersuchungen 277 [no. 66]), while Beckett
you know. Ohne Metaphysik—genau richt writes in his Godot production notebook,
[“Without metaphysics—just right”]. The “[Z]uerst Wahrnehmen dann Kommentieren”
first night was a huge success.” Bollmann’s ‘[F]irst observe then comment’ (Theatrical
counterpart Klaus Herm recalled of Beckett’s Notebooks I 202). he notebook’s editors point
assistance on the production: “Until his ar- out that this is “one of Beckett’s instructions
rival, they were searching and digging to get to himself and to his actors” (403).
at the deeper sense of it and Beckett said, ‘But Beckett led his plays back from their
why? It’s so simple. It’s just a play.’ his helped metaphysical to their everyday use. Directing
them very much to accept it as such—as just a gave the playwright the opportunity not only
play” (Knowlson and Knowlson 180). to reconceptualize his dramas but also to pro-
Help like Beckett’s was not something duce an authorial anticommentary on works
criticism supplied, beyond such rare excep- already encrusted with explication (Gontar-
tions as Stanley Cavell’s “Ending the Waiting ski, “Staging” 87). Having declared himself
Game” (1969), which identiied the “ordinari- incapable of producing an introduction to his
ness” of Endgame and its “hidden literality”: work (Völker 60; see also Gontarski, “Grey-
“he words strew obscurities across our path ing” 144), he used staging as a superior—be-
and seem wilfully to thwart comprehension; cause purely expository—substitute.
and then time after time we discover that Aspiring to Jack Yeats’s “breathless im-
their meaning has been missed only because mediacy,” Beckett inds traction in the rough
it was so utterly bare—totally, therefore un- ground of exhausted justiication. His program
noticeably, in view” (119–20). Not coinci- note to the German premiere of Endspiel com-
dentally, Cavell’s essay relected his epochal plements Wittgenstein’s claim that “[t]here’s
engagement with Wittgenstein’s thought, no riddle. If a question can be put at all, then
employing his notion of “critical description” it can also be answered” (Tractatus 84 [pt. 6,
to temper the mystiications of hermeneutic no. 5]). Beckett insists that “Endspiel wird
responses to the play (128). bloßes Spiel sein. Nichts weniger. Von Rätseln
Wittgenstein’s stated aim was not the und Lösungen also kein Gedank” ‘Endgame
promulgation of doctrine but what Badiou, will be just play. Nothing less. So no thought
following Jacques Lacan, calls an antiphi- to riddles and solutions’ (“On Endgame” 110).
losophy eliminating misleading ideas, false Wittgenstein insisted the same, referring to
problems, and interpretations that obstruct the interpretive mandate of dream psychology:
the view of “how it is” with us (Wittgenstein’s “Such a riddle [Rätsel] does not have to have a
Antiphilosophy 75–81). This aim informed solution. It intrigues us. It is as though there
Beckett’s dramaturgy, as when he addressed were a riddle here. his could be a primitive
the cast of his production of Endspiel: “‘I reaction” (Letzte Schriten 378 [no. 195]).
don’t want to talk about my play. It has to be Published a year before the homage to
taken purely dramatically, to take shape on Yeats, Investigations was available to corrobo-
the stage. It doesn’t concern itself with philos- rate Beckett’s critique and endorse his drama-
ophy,’ he says with emphasis and adds, ‘with turgy: description over explanation. It ofered
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 53

coinciding philosophical sustenance, even a Wittgenstein’s method invites closer


vindication of methods that had aroused ex- attention to Beckett’s mode of critical self-
asperation and suspicion. Beckett refrained exposition. The prestige of Investigations
from explaining his enigmatically obvious supplied a credible philosophical riposte to,
plays in favor of describing them through or relief from, the excesses of hermeneutics.
stage directions. he results, as many critics he philosopher’s antidote was congenial to
have attested, were transformative versions of Beckett’s principles and consonant with his
his work and should transform its reception practice, both of which retain their urgency
(Füger; Bradby). The theater notebooks ac- as hermeneutical excesses persist in literary
centuate inlections of embodiment at the ex- and other kinds of theory.
pense of metaphysical innuendo. In Beckett’s
1975 production of Godot, the play became a
rhythmic geometry of balance and counter-
point, symmetry and antithesis, vectors of
approach and departure (Beckett, heatrical
NOTES
Notebooks I; Ross 72–73). Beckett used his I gratefully acknowledge the collaboration of David Sher-
man, David Rudrum, Darragh Languay, Brian Jones,
production to restore the kinetic logic of a Todd Hopkins, and Suzanne Bufam and the support of
play mired in what he disparaged as exegeti- the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of
cal “undertones” (Beckett and Schneider 29). Canada. his essay is for my teacher Charles Lock.
Beckett before his acting company was 1. All unattributed translations are mine.
not unlike Wittgenstein before his class. In 2. Philosophische Untersuchungen 350 (no. 217); see
also Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathematik
his 1931 lectures Wittgenstein objected to 199–200 (pt. 3, no. 74), Zettel 342 (nos. 300–02), and Be­
James Frazer’s interpretive approach to re- merkungen über die Farben 28 (pt. 1, no. 74).
ligion in The Golden Bough: “Here one can 3. Philosophische Untersuchungen 372 (no. 289) and
only describe and say: this is what human life Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathematik 406–
07 (pt. 7, no. 40).
is like” (“Remarks” 120). Beckett told Lau-
4. Derrida writes that “the essential and irreducible
rence Harvey, “he function of the critic—all possibility of mis-understanding . . . must be taken into
he can do—is to say ‘here is a poor devil in account in the description of those values said to be posi-
this situation’” (Harvey 134). tive” (126). Wittgenstein’s contrasting view is contrary
to Stanley Fish’s doctrine of the authority of interpretive
As Wittgenstein attempts to demystify
communities (Stone, “On the Old Saw”; Sedivy) and in-
language, philosophy, and his own writing, compatible with Richard Rorty’s reduction of all inter-
so too does Beckett. “We want to understand pretation to questions of use.
something that already lies open to view,” 5. Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathematik
Wittgenstein writes. “For this, in some sense, 333 [pt. 6, no. 31]; see also Zettel 345–46 (no. 314).
6. Connor; Locatelli; Hill; Begam. See also Badiou,
is what we appear not to understand” (Philo­
On Beckett, and those who engage his thought—e.g., Gib-
sophische Untersuchungen 291 [no. 89]). Beck- son, “Beckett” and Beckett; Weller, “Anethics,” Beckett,
ett’s writing and dramaturgy are intent on and Taste; Critchley, “Demanding” and On Humour.
restoring the supericies to view, thus assuring 7. Pascale Casanova similarly sees in Beckett’s texts
his audience both of the primacy of the im- “no meaning beyond the textual surface, no message
to be deciphered under the manifest appearance.” She
mediate theatrical event and of what Carla Lo- insists, however, that they “merely recount the process
catelli characterizes as “the ineliminability of of their begetting, or the exhaustion of the logical and
the object of representation” in his work (235). formal possibilities and consequences of a proposition
No European writer of Beckett’s generation arbitrarily given as motor and principle of the writing”
(74). Casanova would thus evacuate his texts of the rich
more fully shares Wittgenstein’s respect for surface sense Beckett recovers beyond exhaustion.
surfaces and his perception that meaning does 8. Philosophische Bemerkungen 54 (pt. 1, no. 6); see
not depend inescapably on interpretation. also Tractatus 12 (pt. 3, no. 332); Bouwsma 24.
54 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

9. Beckett did not permit even himself to explain his 18. See also Wittgenstein, Philosophische Unter su­
work; the actor Jack MacGowran recalled his saying, “I chungen 409 (no. 410) and Philosophical Occasions 228,
will feel superior to my own work if I try to explain it” 269; Guetti, “Monologic” 264; Scruton 288–94.
(Gussow 23; see also Bair 557). 19. Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge, 1930–1932
10. See esp. Altieri, “Tractatus” and “Wittgenstein”; 62–63 and Lectures and Conversations 51; see also Philo­
also Guetti, Wittgenstein; Perlof, Wittgenstein’s Ladder; sophische Untersuchungen 253–54 (no. 29) and Tractatus
Stone, “Wittgenstein”; Allen and Turvey; Schroeder. For 23 (pt. 3, no. 332).
a rebuttal, see Szafraniec 76–97. 20. See also Arikha 143; Asmus; Bair 557; Beckett,
11. See also Certeau 11; Dauber and Jost, “Varieties” heatrical Notebooks II xxi; Bernold 65; Cioran 132–33;
xix; Wittgenstein, “To J. M. Keynes.” Federman 302; Gussow 177; Simpson 119; Völker 146.
12. Scholars have struggled to ind an adequate trans­
lation of the original German phrase: “Philosophie dürte
man eigentlich nur dichten.” See Winch’s translation in
Culture and Value 24e, which is modiied by Gould 76
WORKS CITED
and Perlof, “But Isn’t the Same?” 38, 53. Acheson, James. “A Note on the Ladder Joke in Watt.”
13. “Dante” 24; see also “To Thomas McGreevey”; Journal of Beckett Studies 2.1 (1992): 115–16. Print.
21 Sept. 1937; Beckett, Letters 550. Allen, Richard, and Malcolm Turvey. “Wittgenstein’s
14. Where all philosophical statements are considered Late Philosophy: A Prophylaxis against Theory.”
senseless, as Tractatus, part 6, number 53, concludes, per­ Wittgenstein, heory, and the Arts. Ed. Allen and Tur­
force too are those of the Tractatus—including part 6, num­ vey. New York: Routledge, 2001. 1–35. Print.
ber 53 (85). Conant, “Method” and “Philosophy”; Diamond; Altieri, Charles. “Tractatus Logico­poeticus.” Critical In­
and Sass (137), who are refreshingly willing to take Witt­ quiry 33.3 (2007): 527–42. Print.
genstein at his word rather than accuse him of inadvertent ———.“Wittgenstein on Consciousness and Language: A
contradiction, cogently propose that Wittgenstein seeks Challenge to Derridean Literary heory.” MLN 91.6
only to give an illusion of what Beckett in Watt calls “ef­ (1976): 1397–423. Print.
ing the inefable” (62) and works by ironic self­distancing Arikha, Avigdor. “Avigdor Arikha on Beckett and Art.”
to disqualify positive transcendental statements. Knowlson and Knowlson 143–45.
15. Robinson observes that Wittgenstein eliminates Asmus, Walter D. “Im Theater­Alltag tut man sich
ontological or categorical obstacles considered as “distin­ schwerer. Beckett inszeniert Warten auf Godot.” Ma­
guishing philosophy as a kind of writing from literature as te rialien zu Samuel Becketts Warten auf Godot. Ed.
another,” while Beckett shows the “falseness of such a sep­ Hartmut Enelhardt und Dieter Mettler. Vol. 2. Frank­
aration by creating a philosophical literature” (157–58). furt: Suhrkamp, 1979. 312–24. Print.
16. See, e.g., Hoefer 74–76; Cohn, “Philosophical Badiou, Alain. On Beckett. Ed. Nina Power and Alberto
Fragments” 175; Coe 103–04. For a rebuttal, see Fletcher, Toscano. Trans. Bruno Bosteels, Power, and Toscano.
Novels (1964) 88–89, Novels (1970) 87–88, and Samuel Manchester: Clinamen, 2003. Print.
Beckett’s Art 136; Acheson; for a counterrebuttal, see Per­ ———. Wittgenstein’s Antiphilosophy. Trans. Bruno Bo­
lof, Wittgenstein’s Ladder 134–35. For the possible prov­ steels. London: Verso, 2011. Print.
enance of the ladder analogy in the work of Wittgenstein’s
Bair, Deirdre. Samuel Beckett: A Biography. New York:
Viennese contemporary Fritz Mauthner, see Ben­Zvi,
Harcourt, 1978. Print.
“Fritz Mauthner” and “Samuel Beckett.” For a rebuttal, see
Banield, Ann. “Beckett’s Tattered Syntax.” Representa­
Pilling, “From a (W)horoscope” and “Beckett”; Feldman.
tions 84 (2004): 6–29. Print.
Crucially, an analogy that arrested both Wittgenstein and
Beckett, Samuel. Company. Beckett, Nohow On 1–46.
Beckett entered their work for kindred reasons. Note that
in Dream of Fair to Middling Women Beckett substitutes ———. “Dante . . . Bruno . Vico . . Joyce.” Beckett, Disjecta
the phonetic “f ” for the written “v” to mimic a German 19–33.
pronunciation of English: “I think of Beethofen” (139). ———. Disjecta: Miscellaneous Writings and a Dramatic
17. Beckett “fervently disagreed” with Tractatus, Fragment. London: Calder, 1983. Print.
part 7, according to Duncan Scott, who worked as a light­ ———. Dream of Fair to Middling Women. Ed. Eoin O’Brien
ing engineer at London’s Royal Court heatre on several and Edith Fournier. London: Calder, 1993. Print.
of Beckett’s productions in the 1970s. “‘hat’s the whole ———. Echo’s Bones and Other Precipitates. Collected Po­
point,’ he said, ‘We must speak about it’” (218). Of course, ems in English and French. New York: Grove, 1977.
Wittgenstein fervently agreed that poets, not philoso­ 1–36. Print.
phers, can and should speak about the unspeakable. Both ———. Endgame. Endgame and Act without Words. New
the thesis and the style of Tractatus engaged Beckett, up York: Grove, 1958. 3–85. Print.
through the 1970s (e.g., Fizzles, no. 5). ———. Fin de partie. Paris: Minuit, 1957. Print.
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 55

———. Fizzles. he Complete Short Prose, 1929–1989. Ed. Bouwsma, O. K. Wittgenstein: Conversations, 1949–1951.
S. E. Gontarski. New York: Grove, 1995. 224–46. Print. Ed. J. L. Crat and Ronald E. Hustwit. Indianapolis:
———. “German Diaries.” N.d. MS. U of Reading Lib., Hackett, 1986. Print.
Reading. Bradby, David. “Beckett’s Production of Waiting for Godot
———. “Homage to Jack B. Yeats.” Beckett, Disjecta 148–49. (Warten auf Godot).” Gontarski, Companion 329–46.
———. “Humanistic Quietism.” Beckett, Disjecta 68–69. Bradley, F. H. Essays on Truth and Reality. Oxford: Clar-
———. Ill Seen Ill Said. Beckett, Nohow On 47–86. endon, 1914. Print.
———. he Letters of Samuel Beckett. Vol. 1 (1929–40). Casanova, Pascale. Samuel Beckett: Anatomy of a Liter-
Ed. Martha Dow Fehsenfeld and Lois More Overbeck. ary Revolution. Trans. Gregory Elliot. London: Verso,
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2009. Print. 2006. Print.
———. Mercier and Camier. London: Picador, 1988. Print. Cavell, Stanley. “he Availability of Wittgenstein’s Later
———. Murphy. Paris: Minuit, 1965. Print. Trans. of Mur- Philosophy.” Cavell, Must We Mean 44–72.
phy. New York: Grove, 1970. ———. “Ending the Waiting Game: A Reading of Beckett’s
———. Nohow On: Company, Ill Seen Ill Said, Worstward Endgame.” Cavell, Must We Mean 115–62.
Ho. New York: Grove, 1996. Print. ———. Must We Mean What We Say? Cambridge: Cam-
———. “On Endgame.” Beckett, Disjecta 106–10. bridge UP, 1976. Print.
———. “Les peintures de l’empêchement.” Beckett, Dis- Certeau, Michel de. he Practice of Everyday Life. Trans.
jecta 133–37. Steven Rendall. Berkeley: U of California P, 1984. Print.
———. Proust. New York: Grove, 1957. Print. Cioran, E. M. “Beckett: Some Meetings.” Anathemas and
———. The Theatrical Notebooks of Samuel Beckett I: Admirations. Trans. Richard Howard. New York:
Waiting for Godot, with a Revised Text. Ed. Dougald Arcade-Little, 1991. 129–36. Print.
McMillan and James Knowlson. London: Faber, 1993. Coe, Richard. “God and Samuel Beckett.” Twentieth
Print. Century Interpretations of Molloy, Malone Dies,
———. he heatrical Notebooks of Samuel Beckett II: End- he Unnamable. Ed. J. D. O’Hara. Englewood Clifs:
game. Ed. S. E. Gontarski. London: Faber, 1992. Print. Prentice, 1970. 91–113. Print.
———. The Theatrical Notebooks of Samuel Beckett IV: Cohn, Ruby. Just Play: Beckett’s Theater. Princeton:
he Shorter Plays. Ed. S. E. Gontarski. London: Faber, Princeton UP, 1980. Print.
1999. Print. ———. “Philosophical Fragments in the Work of Samuel
———. he Unnamable. New York: Grove, 1958. Print. Beckett.” Esslin 169–77.
———. Waiting for Godot. New York: Grove, 1982. Print. ———. “Ruby Cohn on the Godot Circle.” Knowlson and
———. Watt. New York: Grove, 1953. Print. Knowlson 125–30.
———, dir. What Where. By Beckett. Süddeutscher Rund- Conant, James. “The Method of the Tractatus.” From
funk, 1985. Television. Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives in Early Analytic
———. What Where. he Collected Shorter Plays of Sam- Philosophy. Ed. Erich H. Reck. New York: Oxford UP,
uel Beckett. New York: Grove, 1984. 307–16. Print. 2002. 374–462. Print.
———. “Who Is Godot?” Trans. Edith Fournier. New ———. “Philosophy and Biography.” Klagge 16–50.
Yorker 24 June 1996: 136–37. Print. Connor, Steven. Samuel Beckett: Repetition, heory and
———. Worstward Ho. Beckett, Nohow On 87–116. Text. Oxford: Blackwell, 1988. Print.
Beckett, Samuel, and Alan Schneider. No Author Better Critchley, Simon. “Demanding Approval: On the Eth-
Served: The Correspondence of Samuel Beckett and ics of Alain Badiou.” Radical Philosophy 100 (2000):
Alan Schneider. Ed. Maurice Harmon. Cambridge: 16–27. Print.
Harvard UP, 1998. Print. ———. On Humour. London: Routledge, 2002. Print.
Begam, Richard. “Beckett and Postfoundationalism; or, Dauber, Kenneth, and Walter Jost, eds. Ordinary Lan-
How Fundamental Are hose Fundamental Sounds?” guage Criticism: Literary Thinking after Cavell after
Lane 11–39. Print. Wittgenstein. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 2004. Print.
Benveniste, Émile. Problèmes de linguistique générale. ———. “he Varieties of Ordinary Language Criticism.”
Vol. 1. Paris: Gallimard, 1966. Print. Introduction. Dauber and Jost xi–xxii.
Ben-Zvi, Linda. “Fritz Mauthner for Company.” Journal Derrida, Jacques. Limited, Inc. Trans. S. Weber. Evan-
of Beckett Studies 9 (1984): 65–89. Print. ston: Northwestern UP, 1988. Print.
———. “Samuel Beckett, Fritz Mauthner, and the Limits Diamond, Cora. he Realist Spirit. Cambridge: MIT P,
of Language.” PMLA 95.2 (1980): 183–200. Print. 1991. Print.
Bernold, André. L’amitié de Beckett: 1979–1989. Paris: Driver, Tom. “Columbia University Forum.” Graver and
Hermann, 1992. Print. Federman 217–23.
56 Beckett after Wittgenstein: The Literature of Exhausted Justiication [ PM L A

Esslin, Martin, ed. Samuel Beckett: A Collection of Criti­ Klagge, James C., ed. Wittgenstein: Biography and Phi­
cal Essays. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice, 1965. Print. losophy. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2000. Print.
Twentieth Century Views. Knowlson, James, and Elizabeth Knowlson, eds. Beck­
Federman, Raymond. “Sam’s Git of Words.” Knowlson ett Remembering, Remembering Beckett. London:
and Knowlson 300–04. Bloomsbury, 2006. Print.
Feldman, Matthew. Beckett’s Books. London: Continuum, Kripke, Saul A. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Lan­
2006. Print. guage. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1982. Print.
Fletcher, John. The Novels of Samuel Beckett. London: Lane, Richard, ed. Beckett and Philosophy. New York:
Chatto, 1964. Print. Palgrave, 2002. Print.
———. he Novels of Samuel Beckett. Rev. ed. New York: Locatelli, Carla. Unwording the Word: Samuel Beckett’s
Barnes, 1970. Print. Prose Works ater the Nobel Prize. Philadelphia: U of
———. Samuel Beckett’s Art. London: Chatto, 1971. Print. Pennsylvania P, 1990. Print.
Fogelin, Robert J. Taking Wittgenstein at His Word. Luft, Friedrich. “Wir warteten auf Godot zum ersten
Princeton: Princeton UP, 2009. Print. Mal.” Völker 38–40.
Füger, Wilhelm. “he First Berlin Godot: Beckett’s Debut O’Donnell, Damien, dir. What Where. By Samuel Beck-
on the German Stage.” Samuel Beckett Today / Au­ ett. RTÉ; Channel 4; Irish Film Board, 2000. Film.
jourd’hui 11 (2002): 57–63. Print.
Perlof, Marjorie. “‘But Isn’t the Same at Least the Same?’:
Gibson, Andrew. “Beckett and Badiou.” Lane 93–107. Wittgenstein and the Question of Poetic Translatabil-
———. Beckett and Badiou: he Pathos of Indeterminacy. ity.” Gibson and Huemer 34–54.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 2006. Print.
———. “he Poetics of Description: Wittgenstein on the
———. Samuel Beckett. London: Reaktion, 2010. Print. Aesthetic.” Dauber and Jost, Ordinary Language Crit­
Gibson, John, and Wolfgang Huemer, eds. he Literary icism 231–44.
Wittgenstein. New York: Routledge, 2004. Print.
———. Wittgenstein’s Ladder. Chicago: U of Chicago P,
Gontarski, S. E., ed. A Companion to Samuel Beckett. Ox- 1996. Print.
ford: Wiley, 2010. Print.
Pilling, John. “Beckett and Mauthner Revisited.” Gontar-
———. “Greying the Canon: Beckett in Performance.” ski and Uhlmann 158–66.
Gontarski and Uhlmann 141–57.
———. “From a (W)horoscope to Murphy.” he Ideal Core
———. “Staging Himself; or, Beckett’s Late Style in the
of the Onion. Ed. Pilling and Mary Brydon. Reading:
Theater.” Samuel Beckett Today / Aujourd’ hui 6
Beckett Intl. Foundation, 1992. 1–20. Print.
(1997): 87–97. Print.
———. A Samuel Beckett Chronology. Basingstoke: Pal-
Gontarski, S. E., and Anthony Uhlmann, eds. Beckett
grave, 2006. Print.
ater Beckett. Gainsville: UP of Florida, 2006. Print.
Robinson, Christopher C. Wittgenstein and Political
Gould, Timothy. “Restlessness and the Achievement of
heory: he View from Somewhere. Edinburgh: Edin-
Peace: Writing and Method in Wittgenstein’s Philo­
burgh UP, 2009. Print.
sophical Investigations.” Gibson and Huemer 75–91.
Graver, Lawrence, and Raymond Federman, eds. Samuel Rorty, Richard. “he Pragmatist’s Progress.” Interpreta­
Beckett: The Critical Heritage. London: Routledge, tion and Overinterpretation. Ed. Stefan Collini. Cam-
1979. Print. bridge: Cambridge UP, 1992. 89–108. Print.
Guetti, James. “Monologic and Dialogic: Wittgenstein, Ross, Ciaran. “Beckett’s Godot in Berlin: New Coordi-
Heart of Darkness, and Linguistic Skepticism.” Gib- nates of the Void.” Samuel Beckett Today / Aujour­
son and Huemer 251–66. d’hui 11 (2002): 64–73. Print.
———. Wittgenstein and the Grammar of Literary Experi­ Sass, Louis. “Deep Disquietudes: Relections on Wittgen-
ence. Athens: U of Georgia P, 1993. Print. stein as Antiphilosopher.” Klagge 98–155.
Gussow, Mel. Conversations with (and about) Beckett. Schroeder, Severin. “he Coded-Message Model of Lit-
London: Hern, 1996. Print. erature.” Wittgenstein, heory, and the Arts. Ed. Rich-
Haerdter, Michael. “Proben- Notate zum Endspiel.” ard Allen and Malcolm Turvey. New York: Routledge,
Völker 92–98. 2001. 210–28. Print.
Harvey, Lawrence E. “Lawrence E. Harvey on Beckett, Scott, Duncan. “London.” Knowlson and Knowlson 214–19.
1961–2.” Knowlson and Knowlson 133–37. Scruton, Roger. A Short History of Modern Philosophy.
Hill, Leslie. Beckett’s Fiction: In Diferent Words. Cam- 2nd ed. London: Routledge, 2002. Print.
bridge: Cambridge UP, 1990. Print. Sedivy, Sonia. “Wittgenstein against Interpretation.”
Hoefer, Jacqueline. “Watt.” Esslin 62–76. Gibson and Huemer 165–85.
Kenny, Anthony. Wittgenstein. Harmondsworth: Pen- Simpson, Alan. Beckett and Behan and a heatre in Dub­
guin, 1973. Print. lin. London: Routledge, 1962. Print.
1 2 7. 1 ] Andre Furlani 57

Stone, Martin. “On the Old Saw, ‘Every Reading of a Text Is Smythies, Rush Rhees, and James Taylor. Ed. Cyril
an Interpretation.’” Gibson and Huemer 186–208. Barrett. Berkeley: U of California P, 1966. Print.
———. “Wittgenstein on Deconstruction.” he New Witt­ ———. Letzte Schriten über die Philosophie der Psycholo­
genstein. Ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read. London: gie. Wittgenstein, Werkausgabe 7: 347–488.
Routledge, 2000. 83–117. Print. ———. Philosophical Occasions, 1912–1951. Ed. James
Szafraniec, Asja. Beckett, Derrida, and the Event of Lit­ Klagge and Alfred Nordmann. Indianapolis: Hack-
erature. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2007. Print. ett, 1993. Print.
hiher, Allen. “Wittgenstein, Heidegger, the Unnamable, ———. Philosophische Bemerkungen. Wittgenstein, Werk­
and Some houghts on the Status of Voice in Fiction.” ausgabe, vol. 2.
Samuel Beckett: Humanistic Perspectives. Ed. Morris ———. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Wittgenstein,
Beja, S. E. Gontarski, and Pierre Astier. Columbus: Werkausgabe 1: 220–580.
Ohio State UP, 1982. 80–90. Print.
———. “Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough.” Wittgen-
Völker, Klaus, ed. Beckett in Berlin: Zum 80ten Geburts­
stein, Philosophical Occasions 119–55.
tag. Berlin: Hentrich; Fröhlich, 1986. Print.
———. “To J. M. Keynes.” 8 Feb. 1939. Cambridge Letters.
Weller, Shane. “he Anethics of Desire: Beckett, Racine,
Ed. Brian McGuinness and G. H. von Wright. Ox-
Sade.” Beckett and Ethics. Ed. Russell Smith. London:
ford: Blackwell, 1995. Print.
Continuum, 2008. 102–17. Print.
———. Tractatus logico­ philosophicus. Wittgenstein,
———. Beckett, Literature, and the Ethics of Alterity. Bas-
Werkausgabe 1: 7–85.
ingstoke: Palgrave, 2006. Print.
———. A Taste for the Negative: Beckett and Nihilism. Ox- ———. Über Gewißheit. Wittgenstein, Werkausgabe 8:
ford: Legenda, 2005. Print. 113–257.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. “Aufzeichnungen über die Logik.” ———. Vermischte Bemerkungen. Wittgenstein, Werkaus­
Wittgenstein, Werkausgabe 1: 188–208. gabe 8: 449–573.
———. Bemerkungen über die Farben. Wittgenstein, ———. Werkausgabe. Ed. Rush Rhees. 8 vols. Frankfurt:
Werkausgabe 8: 3–112. Suhrkamp, 1984. Print.
———. Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathema­ ———. Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge, 1930–1932.
tik. Wittgenstein, Werkausgabe, vol. 6. Notes by John King and Desmond Lee. Ed. Lee. Chi-
———. The Blue and Brown Books. 2nd ed. New York: cago: U of Chicago P, 1980. Print.
Harper, 1960. Print. ———. Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge, 1932–1935.
———. Briefe an Ludwig von Ficker. Ed. Georg Henrik von Notes by Alice Ambrose and Margaret Macdonald.
Wright. Salzburg: Müller, 1969. Print. Ed. Ambrose. Amherst: Prometheus, 2001. Print.
———. Culture and Value. Ed. G. H. von Wright. Trans. ———. Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of
Peter Winch. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1980. Print. Mathematics. Ed. Cora Diamond. Ithaca: Cornell UP,
———. Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psy­ 1989. Print.
chology, and Religious Belief. Notes taken by Yorrick ———. Zettel. Wittgenstein, Werkausgabe 8: 259–445.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi