Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 65

Intrinsic vs.

Extrinsic Value
First published Tue Oct 22, 2002; substantive revision Wed Feb 7, 2007

Intrinsic value has traditionally been thought to lie at the heart of ethics. Philosophers
use a number of terms to refer to such value. The intrinsic value of something is said
to be the value that that thing has “in itself,” or “for its own sake,” or “as such,” or “in
its own right.” Extrinsic value is value that is not intrinsic.

Many philosophers take intrinsic value to be crucial to a variety of moral judgments.


For example, according to a fundamental form of consequentialism, whether an action
is morally right or wronghas exclusively to do with whether its consequences are
intrinsically better than those of any other action one can perform under the
circumstances. Many other theories also hold that what it is right or wrong to do has at
least in part to do with the intrinsic value of the consequences of the actions one can
perform. Moreover, if, as is commonly believed, what one is morally responsible for
doing is some function of the rightness or wrongness of what one does, then intrinsic
value would seem relevant to judgments about responsibility, too. Intrinsic value is
also often taken to be pertinent to judgments about moral justice(whether having to do
with moral rights or moral desert), insofar as it is good that justice is done and bad
that justice is denied, in ways that appear intimately tied to intrinsic value. Finally, it
is typically thought that judgments about moral virtue and vice also turn on questions
of intrinsic value, inasmuch as virtues are good, and vices bad, again in ways that
appear closely connected to such value.

All four types of moral judgments have been the subject of discussion since the dawn
of western philosophy in ancient Greece. The Greeks themselves were especially
concerned with questions about virtue and vice, and the concept of intrinsic value may
be found at work in their writings and in the writings of moral philosophers ever
since. Despite this fact, and rather surprisingly, it is only within the last one hundred
years or so that this concept has itself been the subject of sustained scrutiny, and even
within this relatively brief period the scrutiny has waxed and waned.

• 1. What Has Intrinsic Value?


• 2. What Is Intrinsic Value?
• 3. Is There Such a Thing As Intrinsic Value At All?
• 4. What Sort of Thing Can Have Intrinsic Value?
• 5. How Is Intrinsic Value to Be Computed?
• 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
• Bibliography
o Cited works
o Other works
• Other Internet Resources
• Related Entries

1. What Has Intrinsic Value?

The question “What is intrinsic value?” is more fundamental than the question “What
has intrinsic value?,” but historically these have been treated in reverse order. For a
long time, philosophers appear to have thought that the notion of intrinsic value is
itself sufficiently clear to allow them to go straight to the question of what should be
said to have intrinsic value. Not even a potted history of what has been said on this
matter can be attempted here, since the record is so rich. Rather, a few representative
illustrations must suffice.

In his dialogue Protagoras, Plato [428-347 B.C.E.] maintains (through the character
of Socrates, modeled after the real Socrates [470-399 B.C.E.], who was Plato's
teacher) that, when people condemn pleasure, they do so, not because they take
pleasure to be bad as such, but because of the bad consequences they find pleasure
often to have. For example, at one point Socrates says that the only reason why the
pleasures of food and drink and sex seem to be evil is that they result in pain and
deprive us of future pleasures.[1] He concludes that pleasure is in fact good as such and
pain bad, regardless of what their consequences may on occasion be. In the Timaeus,
Plato seems quite pessimistic about these consequences, for he has Timaeus declare
pleasure to be “the greatest incitement to evil” and pain to be something that “deters
from good.”[2] Plato does not think of pleasure as the “highest” good, however. In
the Republic, Socrates states that there can be no “communion” between
“extravagant” pleasure and virtue;[3] and in the Philebus, where Philebus argues that
pleasure is the highest good, Socrates argues against this, claiming that pleasure is
better when accompanied by intelligence.[4]

Many philosophers have followed Plato's lead in declaring pleasure intrinsically good
and pain intrinsically bad. Aristotle [384-322 B.C.E.], for example, himself a student
of Plato's, says at one point that all are agreed that pain is bad and to be avoided,
either because it is bad “without qualification” or because it is in some way an
“impediment” to us; he adds that pleasure, being the “contrary” of that which is to be
avoided, is therefore necessarily a good.[5] Over the course of the more than two
thousand years since this was written, this view has been frequently endorsed. Like
Plato, Aristotle does not take pleasure and pain to be the only things that are
intrinsically good and bad, although some have maintained that this is indeed the case.
This more restrictive view, often called hedonism, has had proponents since the time
of Epicurus [341-271 B.C.E.].[6] Perhaps the most thorough renditions of it are to be
found in the works of Jeremy Bentham [1748-1832] and Henry Sidgwick [1838-
1900];[7] perhaps its most famous proponent is John Stuart Mill [1806-1873].[8]

Most philosophers who have written on the question of what has intrinsic value have
not been hedonists; like Plato and Aristotle, they have thought that something besides
pleasure and pain has intrinsic value. One of the most comprehensive lists of intrinsic
goods that anyone has suggested is that given by William Frankena [1908-1994]. It is
this: life, consciousness, and activity; health and strength; pleasures and satisfactions
of all or certain kinds; happiness, beatitude, contentment, etc.; truth; knowledge and
true opinions of various kinds, understanding, wisdom; beauty, harmony, proportion
in objects contemplated; aesthetic experience; morally good dispositions or virtues;
mutual affection, love, friendship, cooperation; just distribution of goods and evils;
harmony and proportion in one's own life; power and experiences of achievement;
self-expression; freedom; peace, security; adventure and novelty; and good reputation,
honor, esteem, etc.[9] (Presumably a corresponding list of intrinsic evils could be
provided.) Almost any philosopher who has ever addressed the question of what has
intrinsic value will find his or her answer represented in some way by one or more
items on Frankena's list. (Frankena himself notes that he does not explicitly include in
his list the communion with and love and knowledge of God that certain philosophers
believe to be the highest good, since he takes them to fall under the headings of
“knowledge” and “love.”) One conspicuous omission from the list, however, is the
increasingly popular view that certain environmental entities or qualities have intrinsic
value (although Frankena may again assert that these are implicitly represented by one
or more items already on the list). Some find intrinsic value, for example, in certain
“natural” environments (wildernesses untouched by human hand); some find it in
certain animal species; and so on.

Suppose that you were confronted with some proposed list of intrinsic goods. It would
be natural to ask how you might assess the accuracy of the list. How can you tell
whether something has intrinsic value or not? On one level, this is an epistemological
question about which this article will not be concerned. (See the entry in this
encyclopedia on moral epistemology.) On another level, however, this is a conceptual
question, for we cannot be sure that something has intrinsic value unless we
understand what it is for something to have intrinsic value.

2. What Is Intrinsic Value?

The concept of intrinsic value has been characterized above in terms of the value that
something has “in itself,” or “for its own sake,” or “as such,” or “in its own right.”
The custom has been not to distinguish between the meanings of these terms, but we
will see that there is reason to think that there may in fact be more than one concept at
issue here. For the moment, though, let us ignore this complication and focus on what
it means to say that something is valuable for its own sake as opposed to being
valuable for the sake of something else to which it is related in some way. Perhaps it is
easiest to grasp this distinction by way of illustration.

Suppose that someone were to ask you whether it is good to help others in time of
need. Unless you suspected some sort of trick, you would answer, “Yes, of course.” If
this person were to go on to ask you why acting in this way is good, you might say
that it is good to help others in time of need simply because it is good that their needs
be satisfied. If you were then asked why it is good that people's needs be satisfied, you
might be puzzled. You might be inclined to say, “It just is.” Or you might accept the
legitimacy of the question and say that it is good that people's needs be satisfied
because this brings them pleasure. But then, of course, your interlocutor could ask
once again, “What's good about that?” Perhaps at this point you would answer, “It just
is good that people be pleased,” and thus put an end to this line of questioning. Or
perhaps you would again seek to explain the fact that it is good that people be pleased
in terms of something else that you take to be good. At some point, though, you would
have to put an end to the questions, not because you would have grown tired of them
(though that is a distinct possibility), but because you would be forced to recognize
that, if one thing derives its goodness from some other thing, which derives its
goodness from yet a third thing, and so on, there must come a point at which you
reach something whose goodness is not derivative in this way, something that “just is”
good in its own right, something whose goodness is the source of, and thus explains,
the goodness to be found in all the other things that precede it on the list. It is at this
point that you will have arrived at intrinsic goodness.[10] That which is intrinsically
good is nonderivatively good; it is good for its own sake. That which is not
intrinsically good but extrinsically good is derivatively good; it is good, not (insofar as
its extrinsic value is concerned) for its own sake, but for the sake of something else
that is good and to which it is related in some way. Intrinsic value thus has a certain
priority over extrinsic value. The latter is derivative from or reflective of the former
and is to be explained in terms of the former. It is for this reason that philosophers
have tended to focus on intrinsic value in particular.
The account just given of the distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic value is
rough, but it should do as a start. Certain complications must be immediately
acknowledged, though. First, there is the possibility, mentioned above, that the terms
traditionally used to refer to intrinsic value in fact refer to more than one concept;
again, this will be addressed later (in this section and the next). Another complication
is that it may not in fact be accurate to say that whatever is intrinsically good is
nonderivatively good; some intrinsic value may be derivative. This issue will be taken
up (in Section 5) when the computation of intrinsic value is discussed; it may be
safely ignored for now. Still another complication is this. It is almost universally
acknowledged among philosophers that all value is “supervenient” on certain
nonevaluative features of the thing that has value. Roughly, what this means is that, if
something has value, it will have this value in virtue of certain nonevaluative features
that it has; its value can be attributed to these features. For example, the value of
helping others in time of need might be attributed to the fact that such behavior has
the feature of being causally related to certain pleasant experiences induced in those
who receive the help. Suppose we accept this and accept also that the experiences in
question are intrinsically good. In saying this, we are (barring the complication to be
discussed in Section 5) taking the value of the experiences to be nonderivative.
Nonetheless, we may well take this value, like all value, to be supervenient on
something. In this case, we would probably simply attribute the value of the
experiences to their having the feature of being pleasant. This brings out the subtle but
important point that the question whether some value is derivative is distinct from the
question whether it is supervenient. Even nonderivative value (value that something
has in its own right; value that is, in some way, not attributable to the value of
anything else) is usually understood to be supervenient on certain nonevaluative
features of the thing that has value (and thus to be attributable, in a different way, to
these features).

To repeat: whatever is intrinsically good is (barring the complication to be discussed


in Section 5) nonderivatively good. It would be a mistake, however, to affirm the
converse of this and say that whatever is nonderivatively good is intrinsically good.
As “intrinsic value” is traditionally understood, it refers to aparticular way of being
nonderivatively good; there are other ways in which something might be
nonderivatively good. For example, suppose that your interlocutor were to ask you
whether it is good to eat and drink in moderation and to exercise regularly. Again, you
would say, “Yes, of course.” If asked why, you would say that this is because such
behavior promotes health. If asked what is good about being healthy, you might cite
something else whose goodness would explain the value of health, or you might
simply say, “Being healthy just is a good way to be.” If the latter were your response,
you would be indicating that you took health to be nonderivatively good in some way.
In what way, though? Well, perhaps you would be thinking of health as intrinsically
good. But perhaps not. Suppose that what you meant was that being healthy just is
“good for” the person who is healthy (in the sense that it is in each person's interest to
be healthy), so that John's being healthy is good for John, Jane's being healthy is good
for Jane, and so on. You would thereby be attributing a type of nonderivative interest-
value to John's being healthy, and yet it would be perfectly consistent for you to deny
that John's being healthy is intrinsically good. If John were a villain, you might well
deny this. Indeed, you might want to insist that, in light of his villainy, his being
healthy is intrinsically bad, even though you recognize that his being healthy is
good for him. If you did say this, you would be indicating that you subscribe to the
common view that intrinsic value is nonderivative value of some peculiarlymoral sort.
[11]

Let us now see whether this still rough account of intrinsic value can be made more
precise. One of the first writers to concern himself with the question of what exactly is
at issue when we ascribe intrinsic value to something was G. E. Moore [1873-1958].
In his book Principia Ethica, Moore asks whether the concept of intrinsic value (or,
more particularly, the concept of intrinsic goodness, upon which he tended to focus) is
analyzable. In raising this question, he has a particular type of analysis in mind, one
which consists in “breaking down” a concept into simpler component concepts. (One
example of an analysis of this sort is the analysis of the concept of being a vixen in
terms of the concepts of being a fox and being female.) His own answer to the
question is that the concept of intrinsic goodness is not amenable to such analysis.
[12]
In place of analysis, Moore proposes a certain kind of thought-experiment in order
both to come to understand the concept better and to reach a decision about what is
intrinsically good. He advises us to consider what things are such that, if they existed
by themselves “in absolute isolation,” we would judge their existence to be good; in
this way, we will be better able to see what really accounts for the value that there is
in our world. For example, if such a thought-experiment led you to conclude that all
and only pleasure would be good in isolation, and all and only pain bad, you would be
a hedonist.[13] Moore himself deems it incredible that anyone, thinking clearly, would
reach this conclusion. He says that it involves our saying that a world in which only
pleasure existed — a world without any knowledge, love, enjoyment of beauty, or
moral qualities — is better than a world that contained all these things but in which
there existed slightly less pleasure.[14] Such a view he finds absurd.
Regardless of the merits of this isolation test, it remains unclear exactly why Moore
finds the concept of intrinsic goodness to be unanalyzable. At one point he attacks the
view that it can be analyzed wholly in terms of “natural” concepts — the view, that is,
that we can break down the concept of being intrinsically good into the simpler
concepts of being A, being B, being C…, where these component concepts are all
purely descriptive rather than evaluative. (One candidate that Moore discusses is this:
for something to be intrinsically good is for it to be something that we desire to
desire.) He argues that any such analysis is to be rejected, since it will always be
intelligible to ask whether (and, presumably, to deny that) it is good that something
be A, B, C,…, which would not be the case if the analysis were accurate.[15]Even if this
argument is successful (a complicated matter about which there is considerable
disagreement), it of course does not establish the more general claim that the concept
of intrinsic goodness is not analyzable at all, since it leaves open the possibility that
this concept is analyzable in terms of other concepts, some or all of which are not
“natural” but evaluative. Moore apparently thinks that his objection works just as well
where one or more of the component concepts A, B, C,…, is evaluative; but, again,
many dispute the cogency of his argument. Indeed, several philosophers have
proposed analyses of just this sort. For example, Roderick Chisholm [1916-1999] has
argued that Moore's own isolation test in fact provides the basis for an analysis of the
concept of intrinsic value. He formulates a view according to which (to put matters
roughly) to say that a state of affairs is intrinsically good or bad is to say that it is
possible that its goodness or badness constitutes all the goodness or badness that there
is in the world.[16]
Eva Bodanszky and Earl Conee have attacked Chisholm's proposal, showing that it is,
in its details, unacceptable.[17]However, the general idea that an intrinsically valuable
state is one that could somehow account for all the value in the world is suggestive
and promising; if it could be adequately formulated, it would reveal an important
feature of intrinsic value that would help us better understand the concept. We will
return to this point in Section 5. Rather than pursue such a line of thought, Chisholm
himself responded in a different way to Bodanszky and Conee.[18] He shifted from
what may be called an ontologicalversion of Moore's isolation test — the attempt to
understand the intrinsic value of a state in terms of the value that there would be if it
were the only valuable state in existence — to an intentionalversion of that test — the
attempt to understand the intrinsic value of a state in terms of the kind of attitude it
would be appropriate to have if one were to contemplate the valuable state as such,
without reference to circumstances or consequences. This new analysis in fact reflects
a general idea that has a rich history. Franz Brentano [1838-1917], C. D. Broad [1887-
1971], W. D. Ross [1877-1971], and A. C. Ewing [1899-1973], among others, have
claimed, in a more or less qualified way, that the concept of intrinsic goodness is
analyzable in terms of the worthiness of some attitude.[19] Such an analysis is
supported by the mundane observation that, instead of “good,” we often use the term
“valuable,” which itself just means: worthy of being valued. It would thus seem very
natural to suppose that for something to be intrinsically good is simply for it to be
worthy of being valued for its own sake. (“Worthy” here is often understood to signify
a particular kind of moral worthiness, in keeping with the idea that intrinsic value is a
particular kind of moral value. The underlying point is that those who value for its
own sake that which is intrinsically good thereby evince a kind of moral sensitivity.)
Though undoubtedly attractive, this analysis can be and has been challenged. Brand
Blanshard [1892-1987], for example, argues that the analysis is to be rejected because,
if we ask whysomething is worthy of being valued for its own sake, the answer is that
this is the case precisely because the thing in question is intrinsically good; this
answer indicates that the concept of intrinsic goodness is more fundamental than that
of the worthiness of being valued, which is inconsistent with analyzing the former in
terms of the latter.[20] Ewing and others have resisted Blanshard's argument,
maintaining that what grounds and explains something's being valuable is not its
being good but rather its having whatever non-value property it is upon which its
goodness supervenes; they claim that it is because of this underlying property that the
thing in question is “both” good and valuable.[21] Thomas Scanlon calls such an
account of the relation between valuableness, goodness, and underlying properties a
buck-passing account, since it “passes the buck” of explaining why something is
worthy of being valued from its goodness to some property that underlies its
goodness.[22] Whether such an account is acceptable has recently been the subject of
intense debate. Many, like Scanlon, endorse passing the buck; some, like Blanshard,
object to doing so. If such an account is acceptable, then Ewing's analysis survives
Blanshard's challenge; but otherwise not. (Note that one might endorse passing the
buck and yet reject Ewing's analysis for some other reason. Hence a buck-passer may,
but need not, accept the analysis. Indeed, there is reason to think that Moore himself is
a buck-passer, even though he takes the concept of intrinsic goodness to be
unanalyzable.)[23]

Even if Blanshard's argument succeeds and intrinsic goodness is not to be analyzed in


terms of the worthiness of being valued, it could still be that it is necessarily true that
whatever is intrinsically good is worthy of being valued for its own sake, and vice
versa. If this were the case, it would reveal an important feature of intrinsic value,
recognition of which would help us to improve our understanding of the concept.
However, this thesis has also been challenged. Some argue that there can be reason to
value something for its own sake even if that thing is not intrinsically good. A
relatively early version of this argument was again provided by Blanshard.[24] Recently
the issue has been brought into stark relief by the following sort of thought-
experiment. Imagine that an evil demon wants you to value him for his own sake and
threatens to cause you severe suffering unless you do. It seems that you have reason to
do what he wants — it is appropriate or fitting to value him, so that he is, in some way
at least, worthy of being valued — even though he is clearly not intrinsically good.
[25]
This issue, too, has attracted a lot of attention lately. Some have been persuaded
that the challenge succeeds, while others have sought to undermine it.

One final cautionary note. It is apparent that some philosophers use the term “intrinsic
value” and similar terms to express some concept other than the one just discussed. In
particular, Immanuel Kant [1724-1804] is famous for saying that the only thing that is
“good without qualification” is a good will, which is good not because of what it
effects or accomplishes but “in itself.”[26] This may seem to suggest that Kant ascribes
(positive) intrinsic value only to a good will, declaring the value that anything else
may possess merely extrinsic, in the senses of “intrinsic value” and “extrinsic value”
discussed above. This suggestion is, if anything, reinforced when Kant immediately
adds that a good will “is to be esteemed beyond comparison as far higher than
anything it could ever bring about,” that it “shine[s] like a jewel for its own sake,” and
that its “usefulness…can neither add to, nor subtract from, [its] value.” For here Kant
may seem not only to be invoking the distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic value
but also to be in agreement with Brentano et al. regarding the characterization of the
former in terms of the worthiness of some attitude, namely, esteem. (The term
“respect” is often used in place of “esteem” in such contexts.) Nonetheless, it becomes
clear on further inspection that Kant is in fact discussing a concept quite different
from that with which this article is concerned. A little later on he says that all rational
beings, even those that lack a good will, have “absolute value”; such beings are “ends
in themselves” that have a “dignity” or “intrinsic value” that is “above all
price.”[27] Such talk indicates that Kant believes that the sort of value that he ascribes
to rational beings is one that they possess to an infinite degree. But then, if this were
understood as a thesis about intrinsic value as we have been understanding this
concept, the implication would seem to be that, since it contains rational beings, ours
is the best of all possible worlds.[28] Yet this is a thesis that Kant, along with many
others, explicitly rejects elsewhere.[29] It seems best to understand Kant, and other
philosophers who have since written in the same vein,[30] as being concerned not with
the question of what intrinsic value rational beings have — in the sense of “intrinsic
value” discussed above — but with the quite different question of how we ought to
behave toward such creatures.[31]

3. Is There Such a Thing As Intrinsic Value At All?

In the history of philosophy, relatively few seem to have entertained doubts about the
concept of intrinsic value. Much of the debate about intrinsic value has tended to be
about what things actually do have such value. However, once questions about the
concept itself were raised, doubts about its metaphysical implications, its moral
significance, and even its very coherence began to appear.
Consider, first, the metaphysics underlying ascriptions of intrinsic value. It seems safe
to say that, before the twentieth century, most moral philosophers presupposed that
the intrinsic goodness of something is a genuine property of that thing, one that is no
less real than the properties (of being pleasant, of satisfying a need, or whatever) in
virtue of which the thing in question is good. (Several dissented from this view,
however. Especially well known for their dissent are Thomas Hobbes [1588-1679],
who believed the goodness or badness of something to be constituted by the desire or
aversion that one may have regarding it, and David Hume [1711-1776], who similarly
took all ascriptions of value to involve projections of one's own sentiments onto
whatever is said to have value.)[32] It was not until Moore argued that this view implies
that intrinsic goodness, as a supervening property, is a very different sort of property
(one that he called “nonnatural”) from those (which he called “natural”) upon which it
supervenes, that doubts about the view proliferated.

One of the first to raise such doubts and to press for a view quite different from the
prevailing view was Axel Hägerström [1868-1939], who developed an account
according to which ascriptions of value are neither true nor false.[33] This view has
come to be called “noncognitivism.” The particular brand of noncognitivism proposed
by Hägerström is usually called “emotivism,” since it holds (in a manner reminiscent
of Hume) that ascriptions of value are in essence expressions of emotion. (For
example, an emotivist of a particularly simple kind might claim that to say “A is
good” is not to make a statement about A but to say something like “Hooray for A!”)
This view was taken up by several philosophers, including most notably A. J. Ayer
[1910-1989] and Charles L. Stevenson [1908-1979].[34] Other philosophers have since
embraced other forms of noncognitivism. R. M. Hare [1919-2002], for example,
advocated the theory of “prescriptivism” (according to which moral judgments,
including judgments about goodness and badness, are not descriptive statements about
the world but rather constitute a kind of command as to how we are to act),[35] and
Simon Blackburn and Allan Gibbard have since proposed yet other versions of
noncognitivism.[36]

Hägerström characterized his own view as a type of “value-nihilism,” and many have
followed suit in taking noncognitivism of all kinds to constitute a rejection of the very
idea of intrinsic value. But this seems to be a mistake. We should distinguish
questions about value from questions about evaluation. Questions about value fall into
two main groups, conceptual (of the sort discussed in the last section)
and substantive (of the sort discussed in the first section). Questions about evaluation
have to do with what precisely is going on when we ascribe value to something.
Cognitivists claim that our ascriptions of value constitute statements that are either
true or false; noncognitivists deny this. But even noncognitivists must recognize that
our ascriptions of value fall into two fundamental classes — ascriptions of intrinsic
value and ascriptions of extrinsic value — and so they too must concern themselves
with the very same conceptual and substantive questions about value as cognitivists
address. It may be that noncognitivism dictates or rules out certain answers to these
questions that cognitivism does not, but that is of course quite a different matter from
rejecting the very idea of intrinsic value on metaphysical grounds.

Another type of metaphysical challenge to intrinsic value stems from the theory of
“pragmatism,” especially in the form advanced by John Dewey [1859-1952].
[37]
According to the pragmatist, the world is constantly changing in such a way that
the solution to one problem becomes the source of another, what is an end in one
context is a means in another, and thus it is a mistake to seek or offer a timeless list of
intrinsic goods and evils, of ends to be achieved or avoided for their own sakes. This
theme has been elaborated by Monroe Beardsley, who attacks the very notion of
intrinsic value.[38] Denying that the existence of something with extrinsic value
presupposes the existence of something else with intrinsic value, Beardsley argues
that all value is extrinsic. (In the course of his argument, Beardsley rejects the sort of
“dialectical demonstration” of intrinsic value that was attempted in the last section,
when an explanation of the derivative value of helping others was given in terms of
some nonderivative value.) A quick response to Beardsley's misgivings about intrinsic
value would be to admit that it may well be that, the world being as complex as it is,
nothing is such that its value is wholly intrinsic; perhaps whatever has intrinsic value
also has extrinsic value, and of course many things that have extrinsic value will have
no (or, at least, neutral) intrinsic value. Far from repudiating the notion of intrinsic
value, though, this admission would confirm its legitimacy. But Beardsley would
insist that this quick response misses the point of his attack, and that it really is the
case, not just that whatever has value has extrinsic value, but also that nothing has
intrinsic value. His argument for this view is based on the claim that the concept of
intrinsic value is “inapplicable,” in that, even if something had such value, we could
not know this and hence its having such value could play no role in our reasoning
about value. But here Beardsley seems to be overreaching. Even if it were the case
that we cannot know whether something has intrinsic value, this of course leaves open
the question whether anything does have such value. And even if it could somehow be
shown that nothing doeshave such value, this would still leave open the question
whether something could have such value. If the answer to this last question is “yes,”
then the legitimacy of the concept of intrinsic value is in fact confirmed rather than
refuted.

As has been noted, some philosophers do indeed doubt the legitimacy, the very
coherence, of the concept of intrinsic value. Before we turn to a discussion of this
issue, however, let us for the moment presume that the concept is coherent and
address a different sort of doubt: the doubt that the concept has any great moral
significance. Recall the suggestion, mentioned in the last section, that discussions of
intrinsic value may have been compromised by a failure to distinguish certain
concepts. This suggestion is at the heart of Christine Korsgaard's “Two Distinctions in
Goodness.”[39] Korsgaard notes that “intrinsic value” has traditionally been contrasted
with “instrumental value” (the value that something has in virtue of being a means to
an end) and claims that this approach is misleading. She contends that “instrumental
value” is to be contrasted with “final value,” that is, the value that something has as an
end or for its own sake; however, “intrinsic value” (the value that something has in
itself, that is, in virtue of its intrinsic, nonrelational properties) is to be contrasted with
“extrinsic value” (the value that something has in virtue of its extrinsic, relational
properties). (An example of a nonrelational property is the property of being round; an
example of a relational property is the property of being loved.) As an illustration of
final value, Korsgaard suggests that gorgeously enameled frying pans are, in virtue of
the role they play in our lives, good for their own sakes. In like fashion, Beardsley
wonders whether a rare stamp may be good for its own sake;[40]Shelly Kagan says that
the pen that Abraham Lincoln used to sign the Emancipation Proclamation may well
be good for its own sake;[41] and others have offered similar examples.[42] Notice that
in each case the value being attributed to the object in question is (allegedly) had in
virtue of some extrinsic property of the object. This puts the moral significance
of intrinsic value into question, since (as is apparent from our discussion so far) it is
with the notion of something's being valuable for its own sake that philosophers have
traditionally been, and continue to be, primarily concerned.

There is an important corollary to drawing a distinction between intrinsic value and


final value (and between extrinsic value and nonfinal value), and that is that, contrary
to what Korsgaard herself initially says, it may be a mistake to contrast final value
with instrumental value. If it is possible, as Korsgaard claims, that final value
sometimes supervenes on extrinsic properties, then it might be possible that it
sometimes supervenes in particular on the property of being a means to some other
end. Indeed, Korsgaard herself suggests this when she says that “certain kinds of
things, such as luxurious instruments,...are valued for their own sakes under the
condition of their usefulness.”[43] Kagan also tentatively endorses this idea. If the idea
is coherent, then we should in principle distinguish two kinds of instrumental value,
one final and the other nonfinal.[44] If something A is a means to something elseB and
has instrumental value in virtue of this fact, such value will be nonfinal if it is merely
derivative from or reflective of B's value, whereas it will be final if it is nonderivative,
that is, if it is a value that A has in its own right (due to the fact that it is a means to B),
irrespective of any value that B may or may not have in its own right.

Even if it is agreed that it is final value that is central to the concerns of moral
philosophers, we should be careful in drawing the conclusion that intrinsic value is not
central to their concerns. First, there is no necessity that the term “intrinsic value” be
reserved for the value that something has in virtue of its intrinsic properties;
presumably it has been used by many writers simply to refer to what Korsgaard calls
final value, in which case the moral significance of (what is thus called) intrinsic
value has of course not been thrown into doubt. Nonetheless, it should probably be
conceded that “final value” is a more suitable term than “intrinsic value” to refer to
the sort of value in question, since the latter term certainly does suggest value that
supervenes on intrinsic properties. But here a second point can be made, and that is
that, even if use of the term “intrinsic value” is restricted accordingly, it is arguable
that, contrary to Korsgaard's contention, all final value does after all supervene on
intrinsic properties alone; if that were the case, there would seem to be no reason not
to continue to use the term “intrinsic value” to refer to final value. Whether this is in
fact the case depends in part on just what sort of thing can be valuable for its own
sake — an issue to be taken up in the next section.

In light of the matter just discussed, we must now decide what terminology to adopt.
It is clear that moral philosophers since ancient times have been concerned with the
distinction between the value that something has for its own sake (the sort of
nonderivative value that Korsgaard calls “final value”) and the value that something
has for the sake of something else to which it is related in some way. However, given
the weight of tradition, it seems justifiable, perhaps even advisable, to continue,
despite Korsgaard's misgivings, to use the terms “intrinsic value” and “extrinsic
value” to refer to these two types of value; if we do so, however, we should explicitly
note that this practice is not itself intended to endorse, or reject, the view that intrinsic
value supervenes on intrinsic properties alone.

Let us now turn to doubts about the very coherence of the concept of intrinsic value,
so understood. In Principia Ethicaand elsewhere, Moore embraces the
consequentialist view, mentioned above, that whether an action is morally right or
wrong turns exclusively on whether its consequences are intrinsically better than those
of its alternatives. Some philosophers have recently argued that ascribing intrinsic
value to consequences in this way is fundamentally misconceived. Peter Geach, for
example, argues that Moore makes a serious mistake when comparing “good” with
“yellow.”[45] Moore says that both terms express unanalyzable concepts but are to be
distinguished in that, whereas the latter refers to a natural property, the former refers
to a nonnatural one. Geach contends that there is a mistaken assimilation underlying
Moore's remarks, since “good” in fact operates in a way quite unlike that of “yellow”
— something that Moore wholly overlooks. This contention would appear to be
confirmed by the observation that the phrase “x is a yellow bird” splits up logically (as
Geach puts it) into the phrase “x is a bird and x is yellow,” whereas the phrase “x is a
good singer” does not split up in the same way. Also, from “x is a yellow bird” and “a
bird is an animal” we do not hesitate to infer “x is a yellow animal,” whereas no
similar inference seems warranted in the case of “x is a good singer” and “a singer is a
person.” On the basis of these observations Geach concludes that nothing can be good
in the free-standing way that Moore alleges; rather, whatever is good is
good relative to a certain kind.

Judith Thomson has recently elaborated on Geach's thesis.[46]Although she does not
unqualifiedly agree that whatever is good is good relative to a certain kind, she does
claim that whatever is good is good in some way; nothing can be “just plain good,” as
she believes Moore would have it. Philippa Foot, among others, has made a similar
charge.[47] It is a charge that has recently been rebutted by Michael Zimmerman, who
argues that Geach's tests are less straightforward than they may seem and fail after all
to reveal a significant distinction between the ways in which “good” and “yellow”
operate.[48] He argues further that Thomson mischaracterizes Moore's conception of
intrinsic value. According to Moore, he claims, what is intrinsically good is not “just
plain good”; rather, it is good in a particular way, in keeping with Thomson's thesis
that all goodness is goodness in a way. He maintains that, for Moore and other
proponents of intrinsic value, such value is a particular kind of moral value.

4. What Sort of Thing Can Have Intrinsic Value?

Among those who do not doubt the coherence of the concept of intrinsic value there is
considerable difference of opinion about what sort or sorts of entity can have such
value. Moore does not explicitly address this issue, but his writings show him to have
a liberal view on the matter. There are times when he talks of individual objects (e.g.,
books) as having intrinsic value, others when he talks of the consciousness of
individual objects (or of their qualities) as having intrinsic value, others when he talks
of the existence of individual objects as having intrinsic value, others when he talks of
types of individual objects as having intrinsic value, and still others when he talks of
states of individual objects as having intrinsic value.

Moore would thus appear to be a “pluralist” concerning the bearers of intrinsic value.
Others take a more conservative, “monistic” approach, according to which there is just
one kind of bearer of intrinsic value. Consider, for example, Frankena's long list of
intrinsic goods, presented in Section 1 above: life, consciousness, etc. To
what kind(s) of entity do such terms refer? Various answers have been given. Some
(such as Panayot Butchvarov) claim that it is properties that are the bearers of
intrinsic value.[49] On this view, Frankena's list implies that it is the properties of being
alive, being conscious, and so on, that are intrinsically good. Others (such as
Chisholm) claim that it is states of affairs that are the bearers of intrinsic value.[50] On
this view, Frankena's list implies that it is the states of affairs of someone (or
something) being alive, someone being conscious, and so on, that are intrinsically
good. Still others (such as Ross) claim that it isfacts that are the bearers of intrinsic
value.[51] On this view, Frankena's list implies that it is the facts that someone (or
something) is alive, that someone is conscious, and so on, that are intrinsically good.
(The difference between Chisholm's and Ross's views would seem to be this: whereas
Chisholm would ascribe intrinsic value even to states of affairs, such as that of
everyone being happy, that do not obtain, Ross would ascribe such value only to states
of affairs that do obtain.)

Ontologists often divide entities into two fundamental classes, those that are abstract
and those that are concrete. Unfortunately, there is no consensus on just how this
distinction is to be drawn. Most philosophers would classify the sorts of entities just
mentioned (properties, states of affairs, and facts) as abstract. So understood, the
claim that intrinsic value is borne by such entities is to be distinguished from the
claim that it is borne by certain other closely related entities that are often classified as
concrete. For example, it has recently been suggested that it is tropes that have
intrinsic value.[52] Tropes are supposed to be a sort of particularized property, a kind of
property-instance (rather than simply a property). (Thus the particular whiteness of a
particular piece of paper is to be distinguished, on this view, from the property of
whiteness.) It has also been suggested that it is states, understood as a kind of instance
of states of affairs, that have intrinsic value.[53]

Those who make monistic proposals of the sort just mentioned are aware that intrinsic
value is sometimes ascribed to kinds of entities different from those favored by their
proposals. They claim that all such ascriptions can be reduced to, or translated into,
ascriptions of intrinsic value of the sort they deem proper. Consider, for example,
Korsgaard's suggestion that a gorgeously enameled frying pan is good for its own
sake. Ross would say that this cannot be the case. If there is any intrinsic value to be
found here, it will, according to Ross, not reside in the pan itself but in the fact that it
plays a certain role in our lives, or perhaps in the fact that something plays this role, or
in the fact that something that plays this role exists. (Others would make other
translations in the terms that they deem appropriate.) On the basis of this ascription of
intrinsic value to some fact, Ross could go on to ascribe a kind of extrinsic value to
the pan itself, in virtue of its relation to the fact in question.

Whether reduction of this sort is acceptable has been a matter of considerable debate.
Proponents of monism maintain that it introduces some much-needed order into the
discussion of intrinsic value, clarifying just what is involved in the ascription of such
value and simplifying the computation of such value — on which point, see the next
section. (A corollary of some monistic approaches is that the value that something has
for its own sake supervenes on the intrinsic properties of that thing, so that there is a
perfect convergence of the two sorts of values that Korsgaard calls “final” and
“intrinsic” — on which point, see the last section.)[54] Opponents argue that reduction
results in distortion and oversimplification; they maintain that, even if there is
intrinsic value to be found in such a fact as that a gorgeously enameled frying pan
plays a certain role in our lives, there may yet beintrinsic, and not merely extrinsic,
value to be found in the pan itself and perhaps also in its existence. [55] Some propose a
compromise according to which the kind of intrinsic value that can sensibly be
ascribed to individual objects like frying pans is not the same kind of intrinsic value
that is the topic of this article and can sensibly be ascribed to items of the sort on
Frankena's list.[56](See again the cautionary note in the final paragraph of Section 2
above.)

5. How Is Intrinsic Value to Be Computed?

In our assessments of intrinsic value, we are often and understandably concerned not
only with whether something is good or bad but with how good or bad it is. Arriving
at an answer to the latter question is not straightforward. At least three problems
threaten to undermine the computation of intrinsic value.

First, there is the possibility that the relation of intrinsic betterness is not transitive
(that is, the possibility that something A is intrinsically better than something else B,
which is itself intrinsically better than some third thing C, and yet A is not intrinsically
better than C). Despite the very natural assumption that this relation is transitive, it has
recently been argued that it is not. [57] Should this in fact be the case, it would seriously
complicate comparisons, and hence assessments, of intrinsic value.

Second, there is the possibility that certain values are incommensurate. For example,
Ross at one point contends that it is impossible to compare the goodness of pleasure
with that of virtue. Whereas he had suggested in The Right and the Goodthat pleasure
and virtue could be measured on the same scale of goodness, in Foundations of
Ethics he declares this to be impossible, since (he claims) it would imply that pleasure
of a certain intensity, enjoyed by a sufficient number of people or for a sufficient time,
would counterbalance virtue possessed or manifested only by a small number of
people or only for a short time; and this he professes to be incredible. [58] But there is
some confusion here. In claiming that virtue and pleasure are incommensurate for the
reason given, Ross presumably means that they cannot be measured on the
same ratio scale. (A ratio scale is one with an arbitrary unit but a fixed zero point.
Mass and length are standardly measured on ratio scales.) But incommensurability on
a ratio scale does not imply incommensurability on every scale — an ordinal scale, for
instance. (An ordinal scale is simply one that supplies an ordering for the quantity in
question, such as the measurement of arm-strength that is provided by an arm-
wrestling competition.) Ross's remarks indicate that he in fact believes that virtue and
pleasureare commensurate on an ordinal scale, since he appears to subscribe to the
arch-puritanical view that any amount of virtue is intrinsically better than any amount
of pleasure. This view is just one example of the thesis that some goods are “higher”
than others, in the sense that any amount of the former is better than any amount of
the latter. This thesis can be traced to the ancient Greeks, [59] and it has been endorsed
by many philosophers since, perhaps most famously by Mill.[60] Interest in the thesis
has recently been revived by a set of intricate and intriguing puzzles, posed by Derek
Parfit, concerning the relative values of low-quantity/high-quality goods and high-
quantity/low-quality goods.[61] One response to these puzzles (eschewed by Parfit
himself) is to adopt the thesis of the nontransitivity of intrinsic betterness. Another is
to insist on the thesis that some goods are higher than others. Such a response does not
by itself solve the puzzles that Parfit raises, but, to the extent that it helps, it does so at
the cost of once again complicating the computation of intrinsic value.

To repeat: contrary to what Ross says, the thesis that some goods are higher than
others implies that such goods are commensurate, and not that they are
incommensurate. Some people do hold, however, that certain values really are
incommensurate and thus cannot be compared on any meaningful scale. (Isaiah Berlin
[1909-1997], for example, is often thought to have said this about the values of liberty
and equality. Whether he is best interpreted in this way is debatable.) [62] This view
constitutes a more radical threat to the computation of intrinsic value than does the
view that intrinsic betterness is not transitive. The latter view presupposes at least
some measure of commensurability. If A is better than B andB is better than C,
then A is commensurate with B and B is commensurate with C; and even if it should
turn out that A is not better than C, it may still be that A is commensurate with C,
either because it is as good as C or because it is worse than C. But if Ais
incommensurate with B, then A is neither better than nor as good as nor worse than B.
(Some claim, however, that the reverse does not hold and that, even if A is neither
better than nor as good as nor worse than B, still A may be “on a par” with B and thus
be roughly comparable with it.)[63] If such a case can arise, there is an obvious limit to
the extent to which we can meaningfully say how good a certain complex whole is
(here, “whole” is used to refer to whatever kind of entity may have intrinsic value);
for, if such a whole comprises incommensurate goods A and B, then there will be no
way of establishing just how good it is overall, even if there is a way of establishing
how good it is with respect to each of A and B.

There is a third, still more radical threat to the computation of intrinsic value. Quite
apart from any concern with the commensurability of values, Moore famously claims
that there is no easy formula for the determination of the intrinsic value of complex
wholes because of the truth of what he calls the “principle of organic
unities.”[64] According to this principle, the intrinsic value of a whole must not be
assumed to be the same as the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts.[65] As an
example of an organic unity, Moore gives the case of the consciousness of a beautiful
object; he says that this has great intrinsic value, even though the consciousness as
such and the beautiful object as such each have comparatively little, if any, intrinsic
value. If the principle of organic unities is true, then there is scant hope of a
systematic approach to the computation of intrinsic value. Although the principle
explicitly rules out only summation as a method of computation, Moore's remarks
strongly suggest that there is no relation between the parts of a whole and the whole
itself that holds in general and in terms of which the value of the latter can be
computed by aggregating (whether by summation or by some other means) the values
of the former. Moore's position has been endorsed by many other philosophers. For
example, Ross says that it is better that one person be good and happy and another bad
and unhappy than that the former be good and unhappy and the latter bad and happy,
and he takes this to be confirmation of Moore's principle.[66] Broad takes organic
unities of the sort that Moore discusses to be just one instance of a more general
phenomenon that he believes to be at work in many other situations, as when, for
example, two tunes, each pleasing in its own right, make for a cacophonous
combination.[67] Others have furnished still further examples of organic unities.[68]

Was Moore the first to call attention to the phenomenon of organic unities in the
context of intrinsic value? This is debatable. Despite the fact that he explicitly invoked
what he called a “principle of summation” that would appear to be inconsistent with
the principle of organic unities,[69] Brentano appears nonetheless to have anticipated
Moore's principle in his discussion of Schadenfreude, that is, of malicious pleasure; he
condemns such an attitude, even though he claims that pleasure as such is intrinsically
good. Certainly Chisholm takes Brentano to be an advocate of organic unities,
ascribing to him the view that there are many kinds of organic unity and building on
what he takes to be Brentano's insights (and, going further back in the history of
philosophy, the insights of St. Thomas Aquinas [1225-1274] and others).[70]

Recently, a special spin has been put on the principle of organic unities by so-called
“particularists.” Jonathan Dancy, for example, has claimed (in keeping with
Korsgaard and others mentioned in Section 3 above), that something's intrinsic value
need not supervene on its intrinsic properties alone; in fact, the supervenience-base
may be so open-ended that it resists generalization. The upshot, according to Dancy, is
that the intrinsic value of something may vary from context to context; indeed, the
variation may be so great that the thing's value changes “polarity” from good to bad,
or vice versa.[71] This approach to value constitutes an endorsement of the principle of
organic unities that is even more subversive of the computation of intrinsic value than
Moore's; for Moore holds that the intrinsic value of something is and must be
constant, even if its contribution to the value of wholes of which it forms a part is not,
whereas Dancy holds that variation can occur at both levels.

Not everyone has accepted the principle of organic unities; some have held out hope
for a more systematic approach to the computation of intrinsic value. However, even
someone who is inclined to measure intrinsic value in terms of summation must
acknowledge that there is a sense in which the principle of organic unities is obviously
true. Consider some complex whole, W, that is composed of three goods, X, Y, and Z,
which are wholly independent of one another. Suppose that we had a ratio scale on
which to measure these goods, and that their values on this scale were 10, 20, and 30,
respectively. We would expect someone who takes intrinsic value to be summative to
declare the value ofW to be (10 + 20 + 30 =) 60. But notice that, if X, Y, and Z are
parts of W, then so too, presumably, are the combinations X-and-Y, X-and-Z, and Y-
and-Z; the values of these combinations, computed in terms of summation, will be 30,
40, and 50, respectively. If the values of these parts of W were also taken into
consideration when evaluating W, the value of W would balloon to 180. Clearly, this
would be a distortion. Someone who wishes to maintain that intrinsic value is
summative must thus show not only how the various alleged examples of organic
unities provided by Moore and others are to be reinterpreted, but also how, in the sort
of case just sketched, it is only the values of X, Y, and Z, and not the values either of
any combinations of these components or of any parts of these components, that are to
be taken into account when evaluating W itself. In order to bring some semblance of
manageability to the computation of intrinsic value, this is precisely what some
writers, by appealing to the idea of “basic” intrinsic value, have tried to do. The
general idea is this. In the sort of example just given, each of X, Y, and Z is to be
construed as having basic intrinsic value; if any combinations or parts of X, Y,
and Z have intrinsic value, this value is not basic; and the value of W is to be
computed by appealing only to those parts of W that have basic intrinsic value.

Gilbert Harman was one of the first explicitly to discuss basic intrinsic value when he
pointed out the apparent need to invoke such value if we are to avoid distortions in our
evaluations.[72]However, he offers no precise account of the concept of basic intrinsic
value and ends his paper by saying that he can think of no way to show that nonbasic
intrinsic value is to be computed in terms of the summation of basic intrinsic value.
Several philosophers have since tried to do better. Many have argued that nonbasic
intrinsic value cannot always be computed by summing basic intrinsic value. Suppose
that states of affairs can bear intrinsic value. Let X be the state of affairs of John being
pleased to a certain degree x, and Y be the state of affairs of Jane being displeased to a
certain degree y, and suppose that X has a basic intrinsic value of 10 and Y a basic
intrinsic value of −20. It seems reasonable to sum these values and attribute an
intrinsic value of −10 to the conjunctive state of affairs X&Y. But what of the
disjunctive state of affairs XvY or the negative state of affairs ~X? How
are their intrinsic values to be computed? Summation seems to be a nonstarter in these
cases. Nonetheless, attempts have been made even in such cases to show how the
intrinsic value of a complex whole is to be computed in a nonsummative way in terms
of the basic intrinsic values of simpler states, thus preserving the idea that basic
intrinsic value is the key to the computation of all intrinsic value. [73] (These attempts
have generally been based on the assumption that states of affairs are the sole bearers
of intrinsic value. Matters would be considerably more complicated if it turned out
that entities of several different ontological categories could all have intrinsic value.)

Suggestions as to how to compute nonbasic intrinsic value in terms of basic intrinsic


value of course presuppose that there is such a thing as basic intrinsic value, but few
have attempted to provide an account of what basic intrinsic value itself consists in.
Fred Feldman is one of the few.[74] Subscribing to the view that only states of affairs
bear intrinsic value, Feldman identifies several features that any state of affairs that
has basic intrinsic value in particular must possess. He maintains, for example, that
whatever has basic intrinsic value must have it to a determinate degree and that this
value cannot be “defeated” by any Moorean organic unity. In this way, Feldman seeks
to preserve the idea that intrinsic value is summative after all. He does not claim that
all intrinsic value is to be computed by summing basic intrinsic value, but he does
insist that the value of entire worlds is to be computed in this way.
Despite the detail in which Feldman characterizes the concept of basic intrinsic value,
he offers no strict analysis of it. Others have tried to supply such an analysis. For
example, by noting that, even if it is true that only states have intrinsic value, it may
yet be that not all states have intrinsic value, Zimmerman suggests (to put matters
somewhat roughly) that basic intrinsic value is the intrinsic value had by states none
of whose proper parts have intrinsic value.[75] On this basis he argues that disjunctive
and negative states in fact have no intrinsic value at all, and thereby seeks to show
how all intrinsic value is to be computed in terms of summation after all.

Two final points. First, we are now in a position to see why it was said above (in
Section 2) that perhaps not all intrinsic value is nonderivative. If it is correct to
distinguish between basic and nonbasic intrinsic value and also to compute the latter
in terms of the former, then there is clearly a respectable sense in which nonbasic
intrinsic value is derivative. Second, if states with basic intrinsic value account for all
the value that there is in the world, support is found for Chisholm's view (reported in
Section 3) that some ontological version of Moore's isolation test is acceptable.

6. What Is Extrinsic Value?

At the beginning of this article, extrinsic value was said simply — too simply — to be
value that is not intrinsic. Later, once intrinsic value had been characterized as
nonderivative value of a certain, perhaps moral kind, extrinsic value was said more
particularly to be derivative value of that same kind. That which is extrinsically good
is good, not (insofar as its extrinsic value is concerned) for its own sake, but for the
sake of something else to which it is related in some way. For example, the goodness
of helping others in time of need is plausibly thought to be extrinsic (at least in part),
being derivative (at least in part) from the goodness of something else, such as these
people's needs being satisfied, or their experiencing pleasure, to which helping them is
related in some causal way.

Two questions arise. The first is whether so-called extrinsic value is really a type of
value at all. There would seem to be a sense in which it is not, for it does not add to or
detract from the value in the world. Consider some long chain of derivation. Suppose
that the extrinsic value of A can be traced to the intrinsic value of Z by way
of B, C, D… Thus A is good (for example) because of B, which is good because of C,
and so on, until we get to Y's being good because of Z; when it comes to Z, however,
we have something that is good, not because of something else, but “because of
itself,” i.e., for its own sake. In this sort of case, the values of A, B, …, Y are all
parasitic on the value of Z. It is Z's value that contributes to the value there is in the
world; A, B, …,Y contribute no value of their own. (As long as the value of Z is the
only intrinsic value at stake, no change of value would be effected in or imparted to
the world if a shorter route from A to Zwere discovered, one that bypassed some
letters in the middle of the alphabet.)

Why talk of “extrinsic value” at all, then? The answer can only be that we just do say
that certain things are good, and others bad, not for their own sake but for the sake of
something else to which they are related in some way. To say that these things are
good and bad only in a derivative sense, that their value is merely parasitic on or
reflective of the value of something else, is one thing; to deny that they are good or
bad in any respectable sense is quite another. The former claim is accurate; hence the
latter would appear unwarranted.
If we accept that talk of “extrinsic value” can be appropriate, however, a second
question then arises: what sort of relation must obtain between A and Z if A is to be
said to be good “because of” Z? It is not clear just what the answer to this question is.
Philosophers have tended to focus on just one particular causal relation, the means-
end relation. This is the relation at issue in the example given earlier: helping others is
a means to their needs being satisfied, which is itself a means to their experiencing
pleasure. The term most often used to refer to this type of extrinsic value is
“instrumental value,” although there is some dispute as to just how this term is to be
employed. (Remember also, from Section 3 above, that on some views “instrumental
value” may refer to a type of intrinsic, or final, value.) Suppose that A is a means to Z,
and that Z is intrinsically good. Should we therefore say that A is instrumentally good?
What if A has another consequence, Y, and this consequence is intrinsically bad?
What, especially, if the intrinsic badness of Y is greater than the intrinsic goodness
of Z? Some would say that in such a case A is both instrumentally good (because of Z)
and instrumentally bad (because of Y). Others would say that it is correct to say
that A is instrumentally good only if all of A's causal consequences that have intrinsic
value are, taken as a whole, intrinsically good. Still others would say that whether
something is instrumentally good depends not only on what it causes to happen but
also on what it prevents from happening.[76] For example, if pain is intrinsically bad,
and taking an aspirin puts a stop to your pain but causes nothing of any positive
intrinsic value, some would say that taking the aspirin is instrumentally good despite
its having no intrinsically good consequences.

Many philosophers write as if instrumental value is the only type of extrinsic value,
but that is a mistake. Suppose, for instance, that the results of a certain medical test
indicate that the patient is in good health, and suppose that this patient's having good
health is intrinsically good. Then we may well want to say that the results are
themselves (extrinsically) good. But notice that the results are of course not a means
to good health; they are simply indicative of it. Or suppose that making your home
available to a struggling artist while you spend a year abroad provides him with an
opportunity he would otherwise not have to create some masterpieces, and suppose
that either the process or the product of this creation would be intrinsically good. Then
we may well want to say that your making your home available to him is
(extrinsically) good because of the opportunity it provides him, even if he goes on to
squander the opportunity and nothing good comes of it. Or suppose that someone's
appreciating the beauty of the Mona Lisa would be intrinsically good. Then we may
well want to say that the painting itself has value in light of this fact, a kind of value
that some have called “inherent value.”[77](“Inherent value” may not be the most
suitable term to use here, since it may well suggest intrinsic value, whereas the sort of
value at issue is supposed to be a type of extrinsic value. The value attributed to the
painting is one that it is said to have in virtue of its relation to something else that
would supposedly be intrinsically good if it occurred, namely, the appreciation of its
beauty.) Many other instances could be given of cases in which we are inclined to call
something good in virtue of its relation to something else that is or would be
intrinsically good, even though the relation in question is not a means-end relation.

One final point. It is sometimes said that there can be no extrinsic value without
intrinsic value. This thesis admits of several interpretations. First, it might mean that
nothing can occur that is extrinsically good unless something else occurs that is
intrinsically good, and that nothing can occur that is extrinsically bad unless
something else occurs that is intrinsically bad. Second, it might mean that nothing can
occur that is either extrinsically good or extrinsically bad unless something else occurs
that is either intrinsically good or intrinsically bad. On both these interpretations, the
thesis is dubious. Suppose that no one ever appreciates the beauty of Leonardo's
masterpiece, and that nothing else that is intrinsically either good or bad ever occurs;
still his painting may be said to be inherently good. Or suppose that the aspirin
prevents your pain from even starting, and hence inhibits the occurrence of something
intrinsically bad, but nothing else that is intrinsically either good or bad ever occurs;
still your taking the aspirin may be said to be instrumentally good. On a third
interpretation, however, the thesis might be true. That interpretation is this: nothing
can occur that is either extrinsically good or extrinsically neutral or extrinsically bad
unless something else occurs that is either intrinsically good or intrinsically neutral or
intrinsically bad. This would be trivially true if, as some maintain, the nonoccurrence
of something intrinsically either good or bad entails the occurrence of something
intrinsically neutral. But even if the thesis should turn out to be false on this third
interpretation, too, it would nonetheless seem to be true on a fourth interpretation,
according to which the concept of extrinsic value, in all its varieties, is to be
understood in terms of the concept of intrinsic value.

Bibliography

Cited works

Note: Numbers in square brackets indicate to which of the above sections the
following works are especially relevant.
• Anderson, Elizabeth, 1993, Value in Ethics and Economics,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press [2, 3, 4]
• Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (several editions) [1]
• Ayer, A. J., 1946, Language, Truth, and Logic, second edition,
London: Victor Gollancz [3]
• Beardsley, Monroe C., 1965, “Intrinsic Value”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 26: 1-17 [3, 4]
• Bentham, Jeremy, 1789, An Introduction to the Principles of
Morals and Legislation (several editions) [1]
• Berlin, Isaiah, 1969, Four Essays on Liberty, Oxford: Oxford
University Press [1, 5]
• Blackburn, Simon, 1984, Spreading the Word, Oxford: Oxford
University Press [3]
• Blanshard, Brand, 1961, Reason and Goodness, London: Allen
and Unwin [2]
• Bodanszky, Eva and Conee, Earl, 1981, “Isolating Intrinsic
Value”, Analysis, 41: 51-53 [2]
• Bradley, Ben, 1998, “Extrinsic Value”, Philosophical Studies,
91: 109-26 [6]
• –––, 2006, “Two Concepts of Intrinsic Value”, Ethical Theory
and Moral Practice, 9: 111-30 [2]
• Brentano, Franz, 1969 (originally published in 1889), The
Origin of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul [1, 2, 5]
• Broad, C. D., 1930, Five Types of Ethical Theory, London:
Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner [2, 5]
• –––, 1985 (originally presented as lectures in 1952-53), Ethics,
Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff [2, 5]
• Butchvarov, Panayot, 1989, Skepticism in Ethics, Indianapolis:
Indiana University Press [1, 3, 4]
• Carlson, Erik, 1997, “The Intrinsic Value of Non-Basic States of
Affairs” Philosophical Studies, 85: 95-107 [5]
• Chang, Ruth, 1997, “Introduction”, in Incommensurability,
Incomparability, and Practical Reason, Ruth Chang (ed.),
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press [5]
• –––, 2002, “The Possibility of Parity”, Ethics, 112: 659-88 [5]
• Chisholm, Roderick, 1968-69, “The Defeat of Good and
Evil”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical
Association, 42: 21-38 [5]
• –––, 1972, “Objectives and Intrinsic Value”, in Jenseits von Sein
und Nichtsein, R. Haller (ed.), Graz: Akademische Druck- und
Verlagsanstalt [4]
• –––, 1975, “The Intrinsic Value in Disjunctive States of
Affairs”, Noûs, 9: 295-308 [4, 5]
• –––, 1978, “Intrinsic Value”, in Values and Morals, A. I. Goldman
and J. Kim (ed.), Dordrecht: D. Reidel [2, 4]
• –––, 1981, “Defining Intrinsic Value”, Analysis, 41: 99-100 [2, 4]
• –––, 1986, Brentano and Intrinsic Value, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press [1, 2, 4, 5]
• Conee, Earl, 1982, “Instrumental Value without Intrinsic
Value?”, Philosophia, 11: 345-59 [3, 6]
• Dancy, Jonathan, 2000, “The Particularist's Progress”, in Moral
Particularism, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (ed.), Oxford:
Clarendon Press [5]
• Dewey, John, 1922, Human Nature and Conduct, New York: H.
Holt [3]
• Epicurus, 1926, Letter to Menoeceus, in Epicurus: The Extant
Remains, Oxford: Oxford University Press [1]
• Ewing, A. C., 1948, The Definition of Good, New York:
Macmillan [2]
• Feldman, Fred, 1997, Utilitarianism, Hedonism, and Desert,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [1, 4, 5, 6]
• –––, 2000, “Basic Intrinsic Value”, Philosophical Studies, 99:
319-46 [4, 5]
• Foot, Philippa, 1985, “Utilitarianism and the Virtues”, Mind, 94:
196-209 [3]
• Frankena, William K., 1973, Ethics, second edition, Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice Hall [1, 6]
• Geach, Peter, 1956, “Good and Evil”, Analysis, 17: 33-42 [3]
• Gibbard, Alan, 1990, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, Cambridge,
Mass: Harvard University Press, [3]
• Hägerström, Axel, 1953, Inquiries into the Nature of Law and
Morals, Uppsala: Uppsala University Press [3]
• Hare, Richard M., 1952, The Language of Morals, Oxford:
Oxford University Press [3]
• Harman, Gilbert, 1967, “Toward a Theory of Intrinsic
Value”, Journal of Philosophy, 64: 792-804 [5]
• Hobbes, Thomas, 1651, Leviathan (several editions) [3]
• Hume, David, 1739, A Treatise of Human Nature (several
editions) [3]
• Hurka, Thomas, 1998, “Two Kinds of Organic Unity”, Journal of
Ethics, 2: 299-320 [5]
• Kagan, Shelly, 1998, “Rethinking Intrinsic Value”, Journal of
Ethics, 2: 277-97 [3, 4]
• Kant, Immanuel, 1785, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of
Morals (several editions) [2]
• –––, Lectures in Ethics (notes taken by some of Kant's students
in the latter half of the eighteenth century; several editions) [2]
• Korsgaard, Christine, 1983, “Two Distinctions in
Goodness”, Philosophical Review, 92: 169-95 [3, 4]
• Lemos, Noah, 1994, Intrinsic Value, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press [1, 2, 4, 5]
• –––, 1998, “Organic Unities”, Journal of Ethics, 2: 321-37 [5]
• Lewis, Clarence I., 1946, An Analysis of Knowledge and
Valuation, La Salle: Open Court [2, 6]
• Mill, John Stuart, 1863, Utilitarianism (several editions) [1, 5]
• Moore, G. E., 1903, Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press [1-6]
• –––, 1912, Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press [1-6]
• –––, 1922, Philosophical Studies, New York: Harcourt, Brace [2]
• Oldfield, Edward, 1977, “An Approach to a Theory of Intrinsic
Value”, Philosophical Studies, 32: 233-49 [5]
• Olson, Jonas, 2006, “G. E. Moore on Goodness and
Reasons”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84: 525-34 [2]
• Parfit, Derek, 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon
Press [5]
• Plato, Philebus (several editions) [1]
• –––, Protagoras (several editions) [1]
• –––, Republic (several editions) [1]
• –––, Timaeus (several editions) [1]
• Quinn, Warren S., 1974, “Theories of Intrinsic Value”, American
Philosophical Quarterly 11: 123-32 [5]
• Rabinowicz, Wlodek and Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, 1999, “A
Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and For Its Own
Sake”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 100: 33-52 [3,
4]
• –––, 2003, “The Tropic of Value”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 66: 389-403 [3, 4]
• –––, 2004, “The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes
and Value”, Ethics, 114: 391-423
• Rachels, Stuart, 1998, “Counterexamples to the Transitivity
of Better Than”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76: 71-83
[5]
• Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, 2002, “Instrumental Values – Strong
and Weak”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 5: 23-43 [1, 3, 4,
6]
• Ross, W. D., 1930, The Right and the Good, Oxford: Oxford
University Press [1-6]
• –––, 1939, Foundations of Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University
Press [1-6]
• Scanlon, Thomas M., 1998, What We Owe to Each Other,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press [2]
• Sidgwick, Henry, 1907, The Methods of Ethics (seventh
edition), London: Macmillan [1]
• Stevenson, Charles L., 1944, Ethics and Language, New Haven:
Yale University Press [3]
• Temkin, Larry S., 1987, “Intransitivity and the Mere Addition
Paradox”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 16: 138-87 [5]
• –––, 1997, “A Continuum Argument for
Intransitivity”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 25: 175-210 [5]
• Thomson, Judith, 1997, “The Right and the Good”, Journal of
Philosophy, 94: 273-98 [3]
• Zimmerman, Michael J., 2001, The Nature of Intrinsic Value,
Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield [1-6]

Other works

• Allen, Julie, 2003, “G. E. Moore and the Principle of Organic


Unity”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 37: 329-39
• Alm, David, 2004, “Atomism about Value”, Australasian Journal
of Philosophy, 82: 312-31
• Anderson, C. Anthony, 1997, “Chisholm and the Logic of
Intrinsic Value”, in The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm, L.
E. Hahn (ed.), Chicago: Open Court
• Anderson, Elizabeth, 1997, “Practical Reason and
Incommensurable Goods”, in Chang, 1997
• Aquinas, St. Thomas, Summa Theologiae (several editions)
• Åqvist, Lennart, 1968, “Chisholm-Sosa Logics of Intrinsic
Betterness and Value”, Noûs, 2: 253-70
• Arrhenius, Gustaf, 2000, “An Impossibility Theorem for
Welfarist Axiologies”, Economics and Philosophy, 16: 247-66
• –––, 2005, “Superiority in Value”, Philosophical Studies, 123:
97-114
• Arrhenius, Gustaf, and Rabinowicz, Wlodek, 2005a, “Millian
Superiorities”, Utilitas, 17: 127-46
• –––, 2005b, “Value and Unacceptable Risk: Temkin's Worries
about Continuity Reconsidered”, Economics and Philosophy,
21: 177-97
• Attfield, Robin, 1987, A Theory of Value and Obligation, New
York: Croom Helm
• –––, 1991, The Ethics of Environmental Concern, Athens:
University of Georgia Press
• Audi, Robert, 1997a, “Intrinsic Value and Moral
Obligation”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 35: 135-54
• –––, 1997b, Moral Knowledge and Ethical Character, Oxford:
Oxford University Press
• –––, 1998, “The Axiology of Moral Experience”, Journal of
Ethics, 2: 355-75
• –––, 2003a, “Intrinsic Value and Reasons for Action”, Southern
Journal of Philosophy, 41: 30-56
• –––, 2003b, “Intrinsic Value, Inherent Value, and Experience: A
Reply to Stephen Barker”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 61:
323-27
• –––, 2004, The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and
Intrinsic Value, Princeton: Princeton University Press
• Baldwin, Thomas, 2003, “The Indefinability of Good”, Journal of
Value Inquiry, 37: 313-28
• Barker, Stephen, 2003, “The Experiential Thesis: Audi on
Intrinsic Value”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 41: 57-61
• Baron, Marcia, 1986, “On Admirable Immorality”, Ethics, 96:
557-66
• Baron, Marcia, et al., 1997, Three Methods of Ethics, Oxford:
Blackwell
• Baylis, Charles A., 1958, “Grading, Values, and Choice”, Mind,
67: 485-501
• Beardsley, Elizabeth L., 1957, “Moral Worth and Moral
Credit”, Philosophical Review, 66: 304-28
• Benson, Paul, 1987, “Moral Worth”, Philosophical Studies, 51:
365-82
• Bernstein, M., 2000, “Intrinsic Value”, Philosophical Studies,
102: 329-43
• Bradley, Ben, 2001, “The Value of Endangered
Species”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 35: 43-58
• –––, 2002, “Is Intrinsic Value Conditional?”, Philosophical
Studies, 107: 23-44
• Brandt, Richard, 1959, Ethical Theory, Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice-Hall
• –––, 1963, Value and Obligation, New York: Harcourt, Brace,
and World
• –––, 1979, A Theory of the Good and the Right, Oxford:
Clarendon Press
• Brännmark, Johan, 2001, “Good Lives: Parts and
Wholes”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 38: 221-31
• Broad, C. D., 1942, “Certain Features in Moore's Ethical
Doctrines”, in Schilpp, 1942
• Broome, John, 1991, Weighing Goods, Oxford: Blackwell
• –––, 1999a, Ethics out of Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press
• –––, 1999b, “Normative Requirements”, Ratio, 12: 398-419
• –––, 2004, Weighing Lives, New York: Oxford University Press
• Brülde, Bengt, 1998, The Human Good, Gothenburg: Acta
Universitatis Gothoburgensis
• Callicott, J. Baird, 1986, “The Intrinsic Value of Nonhuman
Species”, in Bryan Norton (ed.), The Preservation of Species,
Princeton: Princeton University Press
• Card, Robert F., 2004, “Consequentialist Teleology and the
Valuation of States of Affairs”, Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice, 7: 253-65
• Carlson, Erik, 1995, Consequentialism Reconsidered,
Dordrecht: Kluwer
• –––, 1997, “A Note on Moore's Organic Unities”, Journal of
Value Inquiry, 31; 55-59
• –––, 2001, “Organic Unities, Non-Trade-Off, and the Additivity
of Intrinsic Value,” Journal of Ethics, 5: 335-60
• –––, 2006, “Incomparability and Measurement of Value”, in The
Good, the Right, Life and Death, Kris McDaniel et al. (ed.),
Aldershot: Ashgate Press
• Carson, Thomas L., 2000, Value and the Good Life, South Bend:
University of Notre Dame Press
• Carter, Robert Edgar, 1968, “The Importance of Intrinsic
Value”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 28: 567-
77
• –––, 1974, “Intrinsic Value and the Intrinsic Valuer”, Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research, 34: 504-14
• Castañeda, Hector-Neri, 1969, “Ought, Value, and
Utilitarianism”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 6: 257-75
• Chang, Ruth, (ed.), 1997, Incommensurability, Incomparability,
and Practical Reason, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press
• –––, 2002, Making Comparisons Count, New York: Routledge
• –––, 2005, “Parity, Interval Value, and Choice”, Ethics, 115:
331-50
• Cheney, Jim, 1992, “Intrinsic Value in Environmental Ethics:
Beyond Subjectivism and Objectivism”, Monist, 75: 227-35
• Chisholm, Roderick M., 1974, “Practical Reason and the Logic
of Requirement”, in Practical Reason, Stephan Körner (ed.),
Oxford: Blackwell
• Chisholm, Roderick M. and Sosa, Ernest, 1966a, “Intrinsic
Preferability and the Problem of Supererogation”, Synthese,
16: 321-31
• –––, 1966b, “On the Logic of ‘Intrinsically Better’”, American
Philosophical Quarterly, 3: 244-49
• Crisp, Roger, 2005, “Value, Reasons and the Structure of
Justification: How to Avoid Passing the Buck”, Analysis, 65: 80-
85
• –––, 2006, Reasons and the Good, Oxford: Clarendon Press
• Dancy, Jonathan, 1993, Moral Reasons, Oxford: Blackwell
• –––, 1999, “On the Logical and Moral Adequacy of
Particularism”, Theoria, 65: 212-24
• –––, 2000, “Should We Pass the Buck?”, in Anthony O'Hear
(ed.), Philosophy, the Good, the True, and the Beautiful,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
• –––, 2003, “Are There Organic Unities?”, Ethics, 113: 629-50
• –––, 2004, Ethics without Principles, Oxford: Clarendon Press
• Danielsson, Sven, 1997, “Harman's Equation and the Additivity
of Intrinsic Value”, Uppsala Philosophical Studies, 46: 23-34
• –––, 1998, “Harman's Equation and Non-Basic Intrinsic
Value”, Uppsala Philosophical Studies, 47: 11-19
• –––, 2001, “The Supervenience of Intrinsic Value”, Uppsala
Philosophical Studies, 50: 93-103
• D'Arms, Justin and Jacobson, Daniel, 2000a, “Sentiment and
Value”, Ethics, 110: 722-48
• –––, 2000b, “The Moralistic Fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’ of
Emotions”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61:
65-90
• –––, 2006, “Anthropocentric Constraints on Human Value”,
in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 1, Russ Shafer-Landau
(ed.), New York: Oxford University Press
• Darwall, Stephen, 1977, “Two Kinds of Respect”, Ethics, 88: 36-
49
• –––, 2003, “Moore, Normativity, and Intrinsic Value”, Ethics,
113: 468-89
• DePaul, Michael R., 2002, “A Half Dozen Puzzles regarding
Intrinsic Attitudinal Hedonism”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 65: 629-35
• Dewey, John, 1939, Theory of Valuation, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press
• Dreier, Jamie, 2003, “Gibbard and Moore”, Southern Journal of
Philosophy, suppl. vol. 41: 158-64
• Ducasse, C. J., 1968, “Intrinsic Value”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 28: 410-12
• Duncan-Jones, Austin, 1958, “Intrinsic Value: Some Comments
on the Work of G. E. Moore”, Philosophy, 33: 240-73
• –––, 1966, “Good Things and Good Thieves”, Analysis, 26: 113-
18
• Edwards, Rem B., 1979, Pleasures and Pains, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press
• Egonsson, Dan, 1998, Dimensions of Dignity, Dordrecht:
Kluwer
• Elliot, Robert, 1992, “Intrinsic Value, Environmental Obligation
and Naturalness”, Monist, 75: 138-60
• Ewing, A. C., 1973, Value and Reality, London: George Allen
and Unwin
• Feit, Neil, 2001, “The Structure of Higher Goods”, Southern
Journal of Philosophy, 39: 47-57
• Feldman, Fred, 1986, Doing the Best We Can, Dordrecht: D.
Reidel
• –––, 1992, Confrontations with the Reaper, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
• –––, 1998, “Hyperventilating about Intrinsic Value”, Journal of
Ethics, 2: 339-54
• –––, 2002a, “The Good Life: A Defense of Attitudinal
Hedonism”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65:
604-28
• –––, 2002b, “Comments on Two of DePaul's
Puzzles”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 636-
39
• –––, 2004, Pleasure and the Good Life, New York: Oxford
University Press
• Findlay, J. N., 1963a, Language, Mind, and Value, London: Allen
and Unwin
• –––, 1963b, Meinong's Theory of Objects and Values, Oxford:
Oxford University Press
• –––, 1968, Values and Intentions, London: Allen and Unwin
• Finnis, John, 1983, Fundamentals of Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon
Press
• Flanagan, Owen, 1986, “Admirable Immorality and Admirable
Imperfection”, Journal of Philosophy, 83: 41-60
• Foot, Philippa, 1961, “Goodness and Choice”, Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 35: 45-60
• –––, 1978, Virtues and Vices, Berkeley: University of California
Press
• Frankfurt, Harry G., 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
• Freeman, James B., 1973, “Fairness and the Value of
Disjunctive Actions”, Philosophical Studies, 24: 105-11
• Fried, Charles, 1970, An Anatomy of Values, Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press
• Frondizi, Robert, 1963, What Is Value?, La Salle: Open Court
• Garcia, J. L. A., 1987, “Goods and Evils”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 47: 385-412
• Gardiner, P. L., 1964, “Pain and Evil”, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 38: 107-24
• Gaus, Gerald F., 1990, Value and Justification, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
• Geach, Peter, 1977, The Virtues, New York: Cambridge
University Press
• Gert, Joshua, 2004, “Value and Parity”, Ethics, 114: 492-520
• Gibbard, Alan, 2003, “Normative Properties”, Southern Journal
of Philosophy, suppl. vol. 41: 141-57
• Goldstein, Irwin, 1989, “Pleasure and Pain: Unconditional,
Intrinsic Values”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
50: 255-76
• –––, 1996, “Pain's Intrinsic Badness and Ethical Anti-Realism”,
in The Problematic Reality of Values, Jan Bransen and Marc
Slors (ed.), Assen: Van Gorcum
• –––, 2002, “The Good's Magnetism and Ethical
Realism”, Philosophical Studies, 108: 1-14
• –––, 2003, “Malicious Pleasure Evaluated: Is Pleasure an
Unconditional Good?”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 84: 24-
31
• Grice, Paul, 1991, The Conception of Value, Oxford: Clarendon
Press
• Griffin, James, 1986, Well-Being, Oxford: Clarendon Press
• –––, 1997, “Incommensurability: What's the Problem?”, in
Chang, 1997
• Hall, Everett, 1952, What Is Value?, New York: Humanities
Press
• –––, 1961, Our Knowledge of Fact and Value, Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press
• Hansson, Bengt, 1968a, “Fundamental Axioms for Preference
Relations”, Synthese, 18: 423-42
• –––, 1968b, “Choice Structures and Preference
Relations”, Synthese, 18: 443-58
• Hansson, Sven Ove, 1998, Structures of Value, Lund: Lund
Philosophy Reports
• Hare, R. M., 1964, “Pain and Evil”, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 38: 91-106
• Hargrove, Eugene C., 1992, “Weak Anthropocentric Intrinsic
Value”, Monist, 75: 183-207
• Harman, Gilbert, 2000, Explaining Value, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
• Harman, Gilbert, and Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1996, Moral
Realism and Moral Objectivity, Oxford: Blackwell
• Harris, George W., 2001, “Value Vagueness, Zones of
Incomparability, and Tragedy”, American Philosophical
Quarterly, 38: 155-76
• Hartmann, Nicolai, 1932, Ethics, London: George Allen and
Unwin
• Haybron, Daniel M., 1999, “Evil Characters”, American
Philosophical Quarterly, 36: 137-48
• Henson, Richard G., 1979, “What Kant Might Have Said: Moral
Worth and the Overdetermination of Dutiful
Action”, Philosophical Review, 88: 304-28
• Herman, Barbara, 1981, “On the Value of Acting from the
Motive of Duty”, Philosophical Review, 90: 359-82
• Hieronymi, Pamela, 2005, “The Wrong Kind of Reason”, Journal
of Philosophy, 102: 437-57
• Holtug, Nils, 2003, “Good for Whom?”, Theoria, 69: 3-20
• Hospers, John, 1961, Human Conduct, New York: Harcourt,
Brace, and World
• Hurka, Thomas, 2001, Virtue, Vice, and Value, New York:
Oxford University Press
• –––, 2002, “The Common Structure of Virtue and
Desert”, Ethics, 112: 6-31
• –––, 2003, “Moore in the Middle”, Ethics, 113: 599-628
• Jackson, Frank, 2003, “Cognitivism, A Priori Deduction, and
Moore”, Ethics, 113: 557-75
• Johnston, Mark, 1989, “Dispositional Theories of
Value”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary
Volume 63: 139-74
• Kagan, Shelly, 1988, “The Additive Fallacy”, Ethics, 99: 5-31
• –––, 1992, “The Limits of Well-Being”, in Paul, 1992
• Korsgaard, Christine, 1996, Creating the Kingdom of Ends,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
• –––, 1997, “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason”, in Ethics
and Practical Reason, Garrett Cullity and Berys Kraut (ed.),
Oxford: Oxford University Press
• –––, 1998, “Motivation, Metaphysics, and the Value of the Self:
A Reply to Ginsborg, Guyer and Schneewind”, Ethics, 109: 49-
66
• Kupperman, Joel J., 1999, Value...And What Follows, Oxford:
Oxford University Press
• –––, 2005, “The Epistemology of Non-Instrumental
Value”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70: 659-
80
• Lemos, Noah M., 2006, “Indeterminate Value, Basic Value, and
Summation”, in The Good, the Right, Life and Death, Kris
McDaniel et al. (ed.), Aldershot: Ashgate Press
• Lemos, Ramon, 1991, “Bearers of Value”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 51: 873-89
• Lewis, David, 1989, “Dispositional Theories of
Value”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary
Volume 63: 113-37
• Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper, 2003, “Measuring the Disvalue of
Inequality over Time”, Theoria, 69: 32-45
• Magendanz, Douglas, 2003, “Conflict and Complexity in Value
Theory”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 37: 443-53
• Magnell, Thomas, 1993a, “Evaluations as Assessments, Part I:
Properties and Their Signifiers”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 27: 1-
11
• –––, 1993b, “Evaluations as Assessments, Part II: Distinguishing
Assertions and Instancing Good of a Kind”, Journal of Value
Inquiry, 27: 151-63
• Mayerfeld, Jamie, 1999, Suffering and Moral Responsibility,
Oxford: Oxford University Press
• McCarty, Richard, 1994, “Are There ‘Contra-Moral
Virtues’?”, Metaphilosophy, 25: 362-75
• Montefiore, Alan, 1961, “Goodness and Choice”, Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 35: 61-80
• Moore, G. E., 1942, “A Reply to My Critics”, in Schilpp, 1942
• –––, 1959, Philosophical Papers, London: Allen and Unwin
• Mulligan, Kevin, 1998, “From Appropriate Emotions to
Values”, Monist, 81: 161-88
• Murdoch, Iris, 1991, The Sovereignty of Good, London:
Routledge
• Nagel, Thomas, 1979, Mortal Questions, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
• Norton, Bryan G., 1992, “Epistemology and Environmental
Values”, Monist, 75: 208-26
• Nozick, Robert, 1981, Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press
• –––, 1993, The Nature of Rationality, Princeton: Princeton
University Press
• Nussbaum, Martha C., 1984, The Fragility of Goodness,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
• Oddie, Graham, 2001a, “Axiological Atomism”, Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, 79: 313-32
• –––, 2001b, “Recombinant Values”, Philosophical Studies, 106:
259-92
• –––, 2005, Value, Reality, and Desire, Oxford: Clarendon Press
• Olson, Jonas, 2003, “Revisiting the Tropic of Value”, Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research, 67: 412-22
• –––, 2004a, “Buck-Passing and the Wrong Kind of
Reasons”, Philosophical Quarterly, 54: 295-300
• –––, 2004b, “Intrinsicalism and Conditionalism about Final
Value”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 7: 31-52
• O'Neill, John, 1992, “The Varieties of Intrinsic
Value”, Monist 75: 119-37
• Österberg, Jan, 1996, “Value and Existence”, Uppsala
Philosophical Studies, 45: 94-107
• Parfit, Derek, 1986, “Overpopulation and the Quality of Life”,
in Applied Ethics, Peter Singer (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University
Press
• –––, 2001, “Rationality and Reasons”, in Exploring Practical
Philosophy, Dan Egonsson et al. (ed.), Aldershot: Ashgate Press
• Parsons, Charles, 1970, “Axiomatization of Åqvist's CS
Logics”, Theoria, 36: 43-64
• Parsons, Josh, 2002, “Axiological Atomism”, Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, 80: 137-47
• Pasquerella, Lynn, 1985, “Brentano and Organic Unities”,
in From Bolzano to Wittgenstein, J. C. Nyiri (ed.), Vienna:
Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky
• Pastin, Mark, 1975, “The Reconstruction of Value”, Canadian
Journal of Philosophy, 5: 375-93
• Paton, H. J., 1942, “The Alleged Independence of Goodness”, in
Schilpp, 1942
• Patton, Thomas E. and Ziff, Paul, 1964, “On Vendler's Grammar
of ‘Good’”, Philosophical Review, 73: 528-37
• Paul, E. F., (ed.), 1992, The Good Life and the Human Good,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
• Perrett, Roy W., 1997, “Preferring More Pain to
Less”, Philosophical Studies, 93: 213-26
• –––, 2003, “Recognizing and Reacting to Value”, Journal of
Value Inquiry, 37: 51-58
• Perry, R. B., 1918, General Theory of Value, New York:
Longmans, Green
• Persson, Ingmar, 1996, “Benevolence, Identification and
Value”, Uppsala Philosophical Studies, 45: 58-71
• –––, 1997, “Ambiguities in Feldman's Desert-adjusted
Values”, Utilitas, 9: 319-27
• –––, 2003, “The Badness of Unjust Inequality”, Theoria, 69:
109-24
• Pettit, Philip, 1993, “Consequentialism”, in A Companion to
Ethics, Peter Singer (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell
• Phillips, David, 2003, “Thomson and the Semantic Argument
against Consequentialism”, Journal of Philosophy, 100: 475-86
• Pitcher, George, 1970, “The Awfulness of Pain”, Journal of
Philosophy, 67: 481-92
• Quinn, Philip, 1977, “Improved Foundations for a Logic of
Intrinsic Value”, Philosophical Studies, 32: 73-81
• –––, 1978, Divine Commands and Moral Requirements, Oxford:
Clarendon Press
• Quinn, Warren S., 1990, “The Puzzle of the Self-
Torturer”, Philosophical Studies, 59: 79-90
• Rabinowicz, Wlodek, (ed.), 2000, Value and Choice, vol. 1,
Lund: Lund Philosophy Reports
• –––, (ed.), 2001, Value and Choice, vol. 2, Lund: Lund
Philosophy Reports
• –––, 2003a, “Ryberg's Doubts about Higher Pleasures – Put to
Rest?”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 6: 231-35
• –––, 2003b, “The Size of Inequality and Its Badness: Some
Reflections around Temkin's Inequality”, Theoria, 69: 60-84
• Rabinowicz, Wlodek, and Österberg, Jan, 1996, “Value Based
on Preferences”, Economics and Philosophy, 12: 1-27
• Rabinowicz, Wlodek, and Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, (ed.),
2003, Patterns of Value, vol. 1, Lund: Lund Philosophy Reports
• –––, (ed.), 2004, Patterns of Value, vol. 2, Lund: Lund
Philosophy Reports
• –––, 2006, “Buck-Passing and the Right Kind of
Reasons”, Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 114-20
• Rachels, Stuart, 2003, “A Defense of Two Optimistic Claims in
Ethical Theory”, Philosophical Studies, 112: 1-30
• Rashdall, Hastings, 1907, The Theory of Good and Evil, London:
Oxford University Press
• Raz, Joseph, 1999, Engaging Reason, Oxford: Oxford University
Press
• –––, 2001, Value, Respect and Attachment, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
• Regan, Donald H., 2002, “The Value of Rational
Nature”, Ethics, 112: 267-91
• –––, 2003, “How to Be a Moorean”, Ethics, 113: 651-77
• Regan, Tom, (ed.), 1984, Earthbound: New Introductory Essays
in Environmental Ethics, Philadelphia: Temple University Press
• –––, 1986, Bloomsbury's Prophet, Philadelphia: Temple
University Press
• –––, 1992, “Does Environmental Ethics Rest on a
Mistake?”, Monist, 75: 161-82
• Rescher, Nicholas, 1967, “Semantic Foundations for the Logic
of Preference”, in The Logic of Decision and Action, Nicholas
Rescher (ed.), Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press
• –––, 1993, The Validity of Values, Princeton: Princeton
University Press
• Rolston, Holmes, III, 1992, “Disvalues in Nature”, Monist, 75:
250-78
• Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, 2002, “Hedonism, Preferentialism,
and Value Bearers”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 36: 463-72
• Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni and Zimmerman, Michael J., (ed.),
2005, Recent Work on Intrinsic Value, Dordrecht: Springer
• Rosati, Connie, 2003, “Agency and the Open Question
Argument”, Ethics, 113: 490-527
• Ryberg, Jesper, 2002, “Higher and Lower Pleasures – Doubts on
Justification”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 5: 415-29
• Schaber, Peter, 1999, “Value Pluralism: Some
Problems”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 33: 71-78
• Schilpp, P. A., (ed.), 1942, The Philosophy of G. E. Moore,
Evanston: Northwestern University Press
• Schroth, Jörg, 2003, “Particularism and
Universalizability”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 37: 455-61
• Schumm, George, 1987, “Transitivity, Preference and
Indifference”, Philosophical Studies, 52: 435-37
• Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, 2003, “For Goodness'
Sake”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 41: 83-91
• Slote, Michael, 1983, Goods and Virtues, Oxford: Clarendon
Press
• Smith, Holly M., 1991, “Varieties of Moral Credit and Moral
Worth”, Ethics, 101: 279-303
• Smith, James Ward, 1948, “Intrinsic and Extrinsic
Good”, Ethics, 58: 195-208
• Smith, Michael, 2003, “Neutral and Relative Value after
Moore”, Ethics, 113: 576-98
• Smith, Tara, 1998, “Intrinsic Value: Look-Say Ethics”, Journal of
Value Inquiry, 32: 539-53
• Sobel, David, 2002, “Varieties of Hedonism”, Journal of Social
Philosophy, 33: 240-56
• Sobel, J. Howard, 1970, “Utilitarianisms: Simple and
General”, Inquiry, 13: 394-449
• Stocker, Michael, 1990, Plural and Conflicting Values, Oxford:
Clarendon Press
• Stratton-Lake, Philip, 2000, Kant, Duty, and Moral Worth,
London: Routledge
• –––, 2005, “How to Deal with Demons: Comment on Rabinowicz
and Rønnow-Rasmussen”, Ethics, 115: 788-98
• Stratton-Lake, Philip and Hooker, Brad, 2006, “Scanlon versus
Moore on Goodness”, in Metaethics after Moore, Terence
Horgan and Mark Timmons (ed.), New York: Oxford University
Press
• Sturgeon, Nicholas, 1996, “Anderson on Reason and
Value”, Ethics, 106: 509-24
• –––, 2003, “Moore on Ethical Naturalism”, Ethics, 113: 528-56
• Sumner, L. W., 1996, Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics, Oxford:
Clarendon Press
• Swanton, Christine, 1995, “Profiles of the Virtues”, Pacific
Philosophical Quarterly, 27: 335-44
• Tännsjö, Torbjörn, 1996, “Classical Hedonistic
Utilitarianism”, Philosophical Studies, 81: 97-115
• –––, 1999, “A Concrete View of Intrinsic Value”, Journal of Value
Inquiry, 33: 531-36
• Taylor, Paul, 1961, Normative Discourse, New York: Prentice-
Hall
• Temkin, Larry S., 1993, Inequality, Oxford: Oxford University
Press
• –––, 1994, “Weighted Goods: Some Questions and
Comments”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23: 361-63
• –––, 1997, “Rethinking the Good, Moral Ideals and the Nature of
Practical Reasoning”, in Reading Parfit, Jonathan Dancy (ed.),
Oxford: Blackwell
• –––, 2003a, “Personal versus Impersonal Principles:
Reconsidering the Slogan”, Theoria, 69: 21-31
• –––, 2003b, “Determining the Scope of Egalitarian Concern: A
Partial Defense of Complete Lives Egalitarianism”, Theoria, 69:
46-59
• –––, 2003c, “Measuring Inequality's Badness: Does Size Matter?
If So, How, If Not, What Does?”, Theoria, 69: 85-108
• –––, 2003d, “Exploring the Roots of Egalitarian
Concerns”, Theoria, 69: 125-51
• Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1992, “On Some Ways in Which a Thing
Can Be Good”, in Paul, 1992
• –––, 1994, “Goodness and Utilitarianism”, Proceedings and
Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 67: 7-21
• –––, 2001, Goodness and Advice, Princeton: Princeton
University Press
• –––, 2003a, “The Legacy of Principia”, Southern Journal of
Philosophy, 41: 62-82
• –––, 2003b, “Reply to Sinnott-Armstrong”, Southern Journal of
Philosophy, 41: 92-94
• Tolhurst, William, 1983, “On the Nature of Intrinsic
Value”, Philosophical Studies, 43: 383-95
• Vallentyne, Peter and Kagan, Shelly, 1997, “Infinite Value and
Finitely Additive Value Theory”, Journal of Philosophy, 94: 5-26
• Väyrynen, Pekka, 2006, “Resisting the Buck-Passing Account of
Value”, in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 1, Russ Shafer-
Landau (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press
• Vendler, Zeno, 1963, “The Grammar of
Goodness”, Philosophical Review, 72: 446-65
• Wallace, James D., 1978, Virtues and Vices, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press
• Weston, Anthony, 1985, “Beyond Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism
in Environmental Ethics”, Environmental Ethics, 7: 321-39
• –––, 1992, “Between Means and Ends”, Monist, 75: 236-49
• Wielenberg, E., 1998, “Goodness without Qualification”, Journal
of Value Inquiry, 32: 93-104
• Williams, Bernard, 1972, Morality, New York: Harper and Row
• Willigenburg, T. van, 1999, “Is the Consumer Always Right?
Intrinsic Value and Subject-Relativity”, in Ethics and the
Market, R. Norman (ed.), Aldershot: Ashgate Press
• Wolf, Susan, 1982, “Moral Saints”, Journal of Philosophy, 79:
419-39
• –––, 1997, “Happiness and Meaning: Two Aspects of the Good
Life”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 14: 207-25
• Wright, Georg Henrik von, 1963, The Varieties of Goodness,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
• –––, 1972, “The Logic of Preference Reconsidered”, Theory and
Decision, 3: 140-69
• Yarnell, Patrick H., 2001, “The Intrinsic Goodness of Pain,
Anguish, and the Loss of Pleasure”, Journal of Value Inquiry,
35: 449-54
• Zimmerman, Michael J., 1983, “Mill and the Consistency of
Hedonism”, Philosophia, 13: 317-35

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi