Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 4

EBSCO Publishing 

  Citation Format: MLA (Modern Language Assoc.):

NOTE: Review the instructions at http://support.ebsco.com/help/?


int=pov&lang=&feature_id=MLA and make any necessary corrections before using.
Pay special attention to personal names, capitalization, and dates. Always consult
your library resources for the exact formatting and punctuation guidelines.

Works Cited

Walter, Andrew. "Point: Euthanasia Should Be Legal." Points of View: Euthanasia


(2009): 2. Points of View Reference Center. EBSCO. Web. 27 Oct. 2010.

<!--Additional Information:
Persistent link to this record (Permalink): http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?
direct=true&db=pwh&AN=43283505&site=pov-live
End of citation-->

Point: Euthanasia Should Be Legal

Thesis: Euthanasia, and a common form of euthanasia, assisted suicide, should be


legal processes through which a terminally ill individual may voluntarily end his or
her own life.
1. MLA (7th ed.):

ProCon.org. "Should euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide only be allowed for the
terminally ill?" Euthanasia.ProCon.org. ProCon.org, 10 June 2008. Web. 27 Oct. 2010.

Should euthanasia and physician-


assisted suicide only be allowed for
the terminally ill?
PRO (yes) CON (no)

Compassion and Choices, the largest choice- Philip Nitschke, MD, Director and Founder of
in-dying organization in the United States, Exit International, an Australian voluntary
wrote in the "Frequently Asked Questions" euthanasia/physician-assisted suicide
portion of their website (accessed on Sep. organization, stated in a June 5, 2001
19, 2006): interview with the National Review:
"Suicide is never a good solution to a "If we are to remain consistent and we
problem. We believe that only people with believe that the individual has the right to
terminal conditions that severely impair the dispose of their life, we should not erect
quality of life should be able to end their artificial barriers in the way of sub-groups
suffering by hastening death." who don't meet our criteria.

Sep. 19, 2006 - Compassion & Choices  This would mean that the so-called 'peaceful
pill' should be available in the supermarket
so that those old enough to understand
death could obtain death peacefully at the
time of their choosing...

Any position other than this leads to


considerable debate about where exactly the
cut-off point should be. All the legislative
The Oregon Department of Human Services
models in existence (Oregon, the
gave a brief history of the Death with Dignity
Netherlands, and the past law in the
Act in their Mar. 2006 Eighth Annual Report
Northern Territory of Australia) have
on Oregon's Death with Dignity Act:
attempted to do just that--define this eligible
"The Death with Dignity Act allows terminally
sub-group — i.e., terminally ill, not
ill Oregon residents to obtain and use
depressed, over 18, articulate, and lucid,
prescriptions from their physicians for self-
etc., etc., and laws that attempt to do this
administered, lethal medications...
produce a great deal of confusion in the gray
To request a prescription for lethal areas of the cut-off. What about psychic
medications, the Death with Dignity Act suffering from mental illness? What about
requires that a patient must be...diagnosed teenagers with terminal cancer; why should
with a terminal illness that will lead to death they have to wait till they're 18? What about
within six months." the 95-year-old who is 'tired of life' but not
clinically depressed?"
Mar. 2006 - Oregon Department of Human Services
(DHS) 
June 5, 2001 - Philip Nitschke, MD 

Erich Loewy, MD, Professor at the University


Ludwig Minelli, founder of Dignitas, a Swiss
of California at Davis, wrote in the 1998
suicide clinic, stated in an Apr. 16, 2006
essay "Harming, Healing and Euthanasia,"
interview with the Times of London:
that appeared in his book Regulating How
We Die:
"I will argue that the time has come for us as "The idea of a terminal illness as a condition
a society to consider legitimizing active for assisted suicide is a British obsession...
voluntary euthanasia when it meets the
following conditions...it must be under We never say no. Even those suffering from
circumstances in which the death of the Alzheimer's will have lucid moments in which
individual is reasonably felt to be inevitable, they may choose to die...
shortly at hand, and, above all, in which the
time until death is filled with relentless We would never assist the death of someone
suffering." with acute depression... But if somebody
comes after 10 or 12 years of depression
1998 - Erich Loewy, MD  and says they do not want to prolong their
life under such conditions, then we might
help them to die...

We should not start from the premise that


suicide should not happen. "

Apr. 16, 2006 - Ludwig A. Minelli, LLM 

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy in


its entry, "Voluntary Euthanasia," last
updated April 25, 2006, stated that:
"Five Individually Necessary Conditions for
Candidacy for Voluntary Euthanasia:

Advocates of voluntary euthanasia contend


that if a person Gerald Dworkin, PhD, Professor of
Philosophy at the University of California at
(a) is suffering from a terminal illness; Davis, wrote in the chapter "Public Policy and
Physician-Assisted Suicide," that appeared in
(b) is unlikely to benefit from the discovery of the 1998 book Euthanasia and Physician-
a cure for that illness during what remains of Assisted Suicide:
her life expectancy; "Since one does not want to condone all
physician-assisted suicides, one needs
(c) is, as a direct result of the illness, either further criteria... The restriction to cases of
suffering intolerable pain, or only has terminal illness, while an effective way to
available a life that is unacceptably draw the line, does not allow relief to many
burdensome (because the illness has to be individuals who are suffering but not
treated in ways that lead to her being terminal. Someone with 'locked-in'
unacceptably dependent on others or on syndrome--totally paralyzed but fully
technological means of life support); conscious--is an example of this situation."

1998 - Gerald Dworkin, PhD 


(d) has an enduring, voluntary and
competent wish to die (or has, prior to losing
the competence to do so, expressed a wish
to die in the event that conditions (a)-(c) are
satisfied); and

(e) is unable without assistance to commit


suicide,
Felicia Ackerman, PhD, Professor of
then there should be legal and medical Philosophy at Brown University, wrote in her
provision to enable her to be allowed to die chapter "Assisted Suicide, Terminal Illness,
or assisted to die. Severe Disability, and the Double Standard,"
It should be acknowledged that these that appeared in the 1998 book Physician
conditions are quite restrictive, indeed more Assisted Suicide: Expanding the Debate:
restrictive than some would think "Appeals to privacy and autonomy are
appropriate. In particular, the conditions characteristic of assisted-suicide
concern access to voluntary euthanasia only advocates... But why not apply them to all
for those who are terminally ill. While that competent adults? If the issues are really
expression is not free of all ambiguity, for autonomy and privacy, then why legalize
present purposes it can be agreed that it suicide assistance only for the terminally ill?
does not include the bringing about of the Why not grant this right of privacy equally to
death of, say, victims of accidents who are the young and healthy--the very people our
rendered quadriplegic or victims of early society values most--if they come to decide,
Alzheimer's Disease." for whatever reason, that they do not want to
go on living? Such people could doubtless
Apr. 25, 2006 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy  use suicide assistance in the form of
prescriptions for lethal drugs, advice about
administration, etc. What factors could justify
granting this right of privacy only to the
terminally ill?"

1998 - Felicia Nimue Ackerman, PhD 

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi