Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 19

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 1 The Deadly Heart of Fiction: Ontological Intrusions between Poe and Heidegger Darren

Hutchinson

When I had waited a long time very patiently without hearing him lie down, I resolved to open a little -- a very, very little crevice in the lantern. So I opened it -- you cannot imagine how stealthily, stealthily -- until at length a single dim ray like the thread of the spider shot out from the crevice and fell upon the vulture eye. It was open, wide, wide open, and I grew furious as I gazed upon it. I saw it with perfect distinctness -- all a dull blue with a hideous veil over it that chilled the very marrow in my bones, but I could see nothing else of the old man's face or person, for I had directed the ray as if by instinct precisely upon the damned spot. --Edgar Allan Poe The Tell-Tale Heart

I. Heidegger never troubled himself with works of fiction. Even though 'Dichtung' in German includes fictional works of literature (though such works are also labeled with such terms as Fiktion, Bellatristik, or Geschichten), not merely poetry, Heidegger exclusively dedicated his later philosophical admiration of dichten to the works of poets, finding an uncanny resonance between the work of Hlderlin, Georg, and Trakl and the vibrations of a thinking-yet-to-come, an andenkendes Denken. He had nothing whatsoever to say, however, about the work of novelists such as Tieck or Mann. Even though in The Origin of the Work of Art he says, poesy is only one mode of the clearing of true, ie. Of poetic composition, finding all art to be essentially involved in poetic exposure, he nevertheless quickly follows that Nevertheless, the linguistic work, poetry in the narrower sense, has a privileged position in the domain of arts (Heidegger, Origin 198). In the same paragraph, he links the classical philosophically interesting examples of the arts, architecture, painting, and music, to the essence of poetry, but there is no word regarding the novel or the short story. Such neglect is grounded in the essential opening of Heidegger's thought. Even though Heidegger was the fundamental thinker of the thing in the last century, the one who first and foremost attempted to rescue things from their decimation through negation, representational annihilation, and technology (all of which were, for Heidegger, aspects of a single threat), there were certain relations to things which were for him too concrete, too specific, too ontic to brook philosophical notice, except perhaps to indicate their irrelevance to (post-)philosophical thinking or even the dangers they pose to the destiny of such thinking. Disciplines such as psychology, anthropology, and biology, for instance, fail to give an unequivocal and ontologically adequate answer to the question of the kind of being of this being that we ourselves are, even though Heidegger maintains no judgment is being made about the positive work of these disciplines (Heidegger, BT 46). Insofar as disciplines which describe (presumably) real feelings, real human relationships and histories, real pathologies and diseases, real lives lack the capacity to question at an appropriate level to resonate in an uncanny sameness with the task of thinking, what hope could a discipline which carries out such descriptions (though admittedly in a different manner)

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 2 in mere fantasy contribute to insight into fundamentally ontological concerns? For instance, the scene from Poe's story above details the machinations of the mind of a madman, obsessed with the cataracted eye of his elderly landlord and presents us with the plans of the murder plot, the surrounding rooms, the feelings, and the appearance of the eye, but it apparently poses no basic questions about the very possibility of the presentation of a scene, the engagement with the other, or the nature of description itself. For the purposes of fundamental ontology (and presumably for the thinking-to-come which would follow such ontology, since the work of fiction is never visited after fundamental ontology dies for Heidegger), like the empirical human sciences, fiction would begin much too late to be of philosophical/post-philosophical significance, already presupposing access to a world of beings (including other human beings), never revealing the opening of this access. Similarly to the manifold critiques of Heidegger's various neglects (of the animal, the body, sex, air, nearly everything) which have arisen over the years, the aim of the present essay is largely negative: to expose the limitations of Heidegger's commitments for the purposes of ontology (along with a certain genealogy of those commitments), commitments which lead him to choose one particular style over another (the poetic over the fictional) and consequently one approach to ontology over another. And yet, this aim comes with a caveat. It is only through following the path of Heidegger's thought towards a relation to things beyond metaphysics that the present exposure becomes possible. It will be another major contention of this essay that only at the limits of ontology and even post-ontological thinking, only where the language of ontology offers itself up to the oblivion of its capacity to address the being it would draw near can there occur a twisting of philosophy towards the deadly singularity of things, a twisting which manifests as a host of warping, morbid intrusions of fiction into the path of thinking. II. Heidegger takes as his dictum for his own phenomenological language in Being and Time Husserl's imperative To the things themselves!. But this is not all he takes from Husserl. Even though his phenomenological method in Being and Time is very different from Husserl's (since instead of bracketing the world and neutralizing the natural relation to it, to the contrary Being and Time begins with the world always already given for Da-sein), Heidegger adopts a certain sparse phenomenological prose for the discussion of examples which is remarkably similar to Husserl's prose. For instance, consider the following comparison:
Husserl: Let us start with an example. Constantly seeing this table and walking around it, changing my position in space in whatever way, I have constantly the consciousness of this one identical table factually existing in person and remaining unchanged. The tableperception, however, is a continually changing one; it is a continuity of changing perceptions. I close my eyes. My other senses have no relation to the table. I open my eyes and I have the perception again (Husserl 86). Heidegger: In accordance with their character of being usable material, useful things always are in terms of their belonging to other useful things: writing materials, pen, ink, paper, desk blotter, table, lamp, furniture, windows, doors, room. These things never show themselves initially by themselves, in order then to fill out a room as a sum of real

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 3


things. What we encounter as nearest to us, although we do not grasp it thematically, not as what it is between the four walls in a geometrical, spatial sense, but rather as material for living (Heidegger, BT 64).

On the one hand, these two passages seem phenomenologically distinct. Whereas Husserl finds the table given as a presentation (thus not totally given, only presented in adumbrations, facets which must be synthesized by the activity of the ego), Heidegger finds the table or the pen precisely not to be initially given as a presentation or even as a possible object of knowledge whether naive or scientific. Rather, Heidegger discovers the table, pen, etc. to be always already disclosed as a thing within an environment of relevance, all of the things within that environment interrelated through the interdependence of utilization. But on the other hand, the two passages seem remarkably related from another vantage. When the table (or any given item) appears in Heidegger's or Husserl's prose, it lacks all specificity and singularity. The hammer is never this hammer, my hammer, the hammer with a notch in the oak handle, the hammer I inherited from my father which I now notice that I grip in exactly the same fashion that he did, the hammer which throws rainbow glints from the surface of the head in the noonday sun, the hammer with bloodstains soaked in from where I missed and cut myself on a protruding nail. Rather, the hammer or table or whatever is neutralized through being put forward as a general example to be evaluated in philosophical discourse. And in such instances, as examples, the things are presented with a certain necessary incompleteness which is to be overcome with an appeal to the outside. For Husserl, the table-presentation is never of the whole table, only a facet, a side, and in order to encounter the table-as-such, as an intended object, I must continually move around it (bodily or in phantasy), seeing it from different perspectives, coordinating each incomplete moment within an ongoing activity of consciousness. For Heidegger, the given thing, for instance the hammer, is first disclosed to Da-sein in being handily used to hammer-in nails. But when it becomes a philosophical example, in order to be understood as what it is, the hammer must be coordinated in a context of relevance with other useful things around it (the house, the nails) along with the project for which it is used and with the general concern of Dasein of having a safe dwelling-space. Because of their being used as general examples of objects or even things, the hammer or the table are attributed a certain radical incompleteness in their being which must be overcome (or at least situated) through reference to transcending activity. In Husserl's case, the object such as the table is encountered as phenomenon only through the reductive loss of it as an immediate actuality, and one becomes responsible for its re-apprehension as a whole thing through ambulating around it (and doing so in phantasy) in order to be able to idealize it as an entire object so that one can restore it to the reality of objective sense. To carry out this procedure, the transcendental ego must be able to have access to itself in a Kantian fashion, maintaining a certain self-consciousness or auto-affection across time, such that the ego can retain an evidential relation to the object and not have it slip away into the fluctuations of mere fantasy. But as Derrida demonstrates in Voice and Phenomena, the phenomenological look does not abide (Derrida, SP 104). Transcendental consciousness cannot secure its own self-presence so that it can become a vehicle of the absolute evidence of the phenomenon: because, as Derrida says, this appearing of the Ideal as an infinite diffrance can only be produced within a relationship with death in general. Only a relation to my-death could make the infinite differing of presence appear (Derrida, SP 102). The fractured being of the phenomenon could only be

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 4 supplemented through a perpetually idealizing subject, but this very capacity for temporal idealization a priori fractures the subject from the inside, leaving both it and the phenomenon always to come, always incomplete. The subject is (beyond being) always already the living-dead and the thing itself always escapes. Both the phenomenon and consciousness are always already deconstructed because of their necessary relation to the writing which allows for their exemplification which puts them into an essential relationship with death in general. Such conclusions are no surprise to the careful student of Heidegger. Although Heidegger does not painstakingly allow for the deconstruction of the moment of presence central to phenomenology in the manner that Derrida does, he presupposes such a deconstruction in his account of Da-sein's essential relationship to the things which it confronts. Da-sein finds the things in the world with which it is involved disclosed precisely in its perpetually incomplete movement of being-towards-death. Da-sein is never complete, never has a possibility of full being, its essence is to have the no- essence of Wesung, to be always already beyond itself in being thrown projection, a siting of deathliness which could end only in an annihilation of all presence altogether. Heidegger's account of the ecstatic temporalization of Da-sein is wellknown and needs not be discussed further here. But the important point for our considerations is that the hammer, the nail, the house, as they are disclosed for Da-sein and then as they are exemplified in Heidegger's phenomenological discourse, manifest only in relation to this radical deathliness of the being-beyond-the-subject of Da-sein. The hammer is never this hammer, the one I am alongside of here and now, the thing together with me, with its fine grained handle and the blood stains of the past. Rather, the hammer gets to be disclosed as thing only through its utility or lack thereof, swept into the projecting of Da-sein and, as it were, made to resonate with Da-sein's essential incompleteness. It is important to note (and contrary to the work of many interpreters of Heidegger, especially in the Anglo-American community) that Heidegger has no account at all of the constitution of things. Although Husserl's phenomenologically-descriptive project at times becomes indistinguishable from a psycho-physics of the appearance of beings, drifting into the psychological and metaphysical explanations it formally eschews, Heidegger never explains where things come from or how they arise in their concrete being for the mind. In Being and Time, Heidegger presents only an order of disclosure, the way in which the world and the beings confronted in it (along with the being of those beings) gets encountered by Da-sein in and through its projections. Heidegger's work is the first and most substantial effort at merely revealing how things co-exist alongside one another in a world so near it even lacks the metaphysically posited status of immanence. There is in his texts a gentle moving of Da-sein from one engagement with beings to another: from one where in its fleeing from death, Da-sein has submitted the world and the things in it to a sort of presentational destruction (which will later be understood as technological enframing) and into another where Da-sein always already belongs together with the earthly things which are thrown from the abyss of Er-eignis. This new/old awareness (as the first opening of the Greek astonishment at things communicates a new astonishment, one beginning springing forth to play out in another fashion in an ecstatic temporality beyond the linearity of history) will involve encountering the equiprimordiality of things, projects, others, meanings, and actions outside the distorting force of representation, free from illusions of being as a set of beings (subjects, objects, God, matter, substance) to be placed

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 5 in a proper order through the challenged intellect. And yet, despite the fidelity of Heidegger's work to the things themselves, including the things of Da-sein and Mit-da-sein and Um-welt and the useful items encountered in contexts of relevance which have been historically destined, the concrete things of the world are given a deadly spin precisely through being incorporated in an account of Da-sein's deathly task. This happens in a three-fold manner. 1. Since things are disclosed primarily for Da-sein in contexts of caring utility, just as Da-sein is always already beyond itself, the things are always already beyond themselves at their core. When they are just lying around, it is because they are broken or obtruding into Da-sein's plans, and when disclosed as such, they are immediately cast once again beyond themselves. Concerning how one encounters random things with no use or purpose, or animals simply living as things beyond Da-sein's plans or needs, or the organs of the body as they autonomically function beyond control and notice, Heidegger has practically nothing to say. In order to be disclosed as a thing in the world, it seems, that thing must be placed in the wake of Da-sein's deathly projection. 2. Since the brokenness of presence-at-hand forms the paradigm for the presentation of any being as an object of interest, the aura of this brokenness pervades any thing which is given as an example of a thing in the world. When, for instance, the shoe or the watch or the piece of timber appear as objects of knowledge, they appear as already cut out of their context, as caricatures of their real useful being, and they are thereby determined as caricatures, mere objects which may or may not be restored to the flowing utilizations in which they were originally situated. Such caricature precludes, for instance, Heidegger or the reader from taking too much time on these objects in their non-functional being, for instance in attempting to describe the nuanced grain of the wood from the piece of timber, the frayed laces on the shoe, the odd smear of oil which marks the face of the watch. 3. Thus, the things of the world are presented as doubly incomplete, both devoid of characteristics which proceed into the endless depth of their singularity and insufficient in themselves without their being incorporated in the world of Da-sein's projects. Heidegger's style, the manner of exemplification he inherits from the history of philosophy, a history which has always neglected the mundane specificity of singular things thus comes to occlude other accounts of the beings of the world, accounts which would require an ontology beyond the life and death of Da-sein, at least insofar as that life and death only includes the goal of survival. Such accounts would even, perhaps, lead one beyond being itself, even beyond the pre-ontological projection which discloses all beings and into what might be called the (pre-)pre-ontological, the togetherness with things in their horrible (and sometimes wonderful, though never ideal) specificity, outside the dimensions of utility and care, and even outside the dimensions of Earth and Sky, Divinity and Mortals, and into the incredible specificity of their silent impingement. Thus, the preclusion of the empirical specificity of the things encountered by Da-sein is not merely a division between the ontic and the ontological, a passing from the shallow surface of factual description to the depths of being. Rather, this preclusion amounts to making an ontological decision, favoring an ontology of projection founded out of the thrown incompleteness of deathliness over an ontology arising from a non-projective encounter with the detailed richness of things without purpose or use, save perhaps the pleasure of merely coexisting with them in a laziness without aim (or the horror of co-existing with them in a suffering without cessation). One might say thus say that the style of exemplification inherited by Heidegger from Husserl who himself inherited from the Platonic-Cartesian philosophical

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 6 tradition is a genre of literature (which Heidegger will later label the poetic), not only because it essentially disavows a fundamental possibility (the fictional disclosure of being) through ignoring it (although such ignorance is always already a necessity whenever we speak, truth is always found in the manifold error of the erasure of the endless abyss in every thing) but also also because it provides for a fantastic sensibility whereby one can make sense of everything in the world in a situated context, rather than having merely to endure the useless beauty and complicated ugliness of mere things. III. In the midst of such concerns, we may return at this point to the exemplary story from Poe with which this essay began. The selection of this story is not merely fortuitous: The TaleTell Heart speaks of nothing other than the death of things, another death of things, beyond the deathly relations in which they are encountered in the work of Heidegger. The narrator of the story gives the motive for his accomplished murder:
It is impossible to say how first the idea entered my brain, but, once conceived, it haunted me day and night. Object there was none. Passion there was none. I loved the old man. He had never wronged me. He had never given me insult. For his gold I had no desire. I think it was his eye! Yes, it was this! One of his eyes resembled that of a vulture -- a pale blue eye with a film over it. Whenever it fell upon me my blood ran cold, and so by degrees, very gradually, I made up my mind to take the life of the old man, and thus rid myself of the eye for ever (Poe 295).

The first thing to be noticed in this passage is what might be called the fundamental relation to death of the speaker. Perhaps, in Heidegger's terms, one might be tempted to claim that this character is living in a radically inauthentic fashion, fleeing from the abyss in his own heart, denying his own temporal finitude through throwing himself into the project of murder. But such a supposition is nonsense, since the character in fact shows no concern for himself at all, not even the concern of enjoying himself in the activity he undertakes. In fact, the character rather opens himself up to the possibility of destruction, and even though the crime is perfectly carried out and there is no evidence, he ends up betraying himself, destroying his own life through his startling confession. However, here at the outset, in the course of examining what the story reveals about fundamental relation to the death of things, one might object that, at least for normal human beings, it reveals nothing whatsoever. The main character, after all, is mad. One might hear in such an objection a resonance with Descartes' response to the skeptical supposition that I, as meditator, might be mad: But such people are insane, and I would be thought equally mad if I took anything from them as a model for myself (Descartes 13). If I suppose that a character who wants to kill another human being merely because he is caused distress by the appearance of his diseased eye (giving a new meaning to: If an eye offends you, pluck it out) has anything to teach me about the basic human relation to the world or about the real nature of death, then perhaps I would have to be as mad as the character who would be my instructor. As if I had not had similar experiences throughout life, experiences which all human

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 7 beings undergo to varying degrees. Such experiences are certainly culturally conditioned and they are certainly different in different people and they are certainly manipulable to some degree, the achievement of such manipulation in certain cases representing a profound ethical achievement, but one would have to be mad to claim that such experiences are not as normal within the human condition as dreams. The experiences I refer to here are nothing other than those in which a certain repulsion or dread at the sight (or touch or smell) of the wounded or deformed or diseased body is undergone. A personal example: When I was in the cub scouts at 8 years old, there was a scoutmaster who brought about such feelings in me. This woman's husband (about whom I know only this, which is enough) had at some point, in a drunken rage, flung a pot of boiling water in her face. This event left her face severely disfigured and she was blind in one eye. I recall going to the scout meetings and having a difficult time looking at her, even though she was one of the most gentle and kind people I have ever encountered. At a certain point, I do not know how or when, during those two years I learned to look past her disfigurement, simply seeing her as Mrs. B, no longer avoiding her gaze. But I cannot deny that I went through this experience and it was sufficiently intense so that I remember it to this day. Despite his madness, Poe's character instantiates this quite normal condition, a condition which I will here term a desire for the death of death. Such a desire is not a fleeing from something as ethereal as the possibility of death, not a horror in the face of the nothingness of oblivion, not a deep anxiety concerning the perpetual erasure of presence as one (and others) become perpetually dead (changed, lost in memory, alien) through the passage inherent to the timeliness of life. Rather, the desire for the death of death arises from the repulsion at the dead thing, the dying thing, the wounded and rotting, the rend(er)ing of flesh in which it twisted beyond the health of the body. In the throes of such desire, one turns away from, avoids, winces at, wants to flee from the concrete being of oozing sores and scarred skin and mangled faces and limbs. One wishes that they simply did not exist. The dead eye of the narrator's victim is, indeed, vulture-like, not because it is animallike, not because it reminds the narrator of the bestiality of the human (the character reminds himself of that well enough through his deeds), but rather because it is connected to the decay of carrion, drawing an almost magical relation of osmosis between the predator and the dead bodies which it consumes. This eye, this concrete instance of death in life, a being-dead beyond all transcendence, even the transcendence of time, obsesses the narrator. The eye, the sign of life, the window to the soul, the grand metaphor of access to purely intelligible radiance, when it is encountered as a concrete thing, with its white film and burst veins and seeping fluid from the corners, has become a thing which he cannot take his eyes off of (including the eye of his mind) once he has seen it. Such a dead thing is beyond all conspicuousness or obtrusiveness which would be encountered in the dealing with the things of the world of Da-sein. Likewise, this thing is beyond the entire dialectic of materiality and spirituality which would belong to the movement of the negative. Such a dead eye has nothing to do with nihilation or annihilation or the void or sweeping fire of temporalization. It does not have full presence, since one cannot fully bring oneself to look at it, yet it is not absent either or even passing into absence. Rather, it is a dead and inert thing on the face of a living being, a thing which shows that at the bottom of things, everything is dead and inert, all bodies are things with eroded surfaces, stained sides, scratched

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 8 handles, broken grips, torn fabric, scabbed cuts, infected growths, etc. In such a light, the actions of Poe's character, while also extreme and psychopathic, seem also all-too-normal, all-too-human. They are the hyperbolic extension of the desire to turn away from the living-dead being of things and transform their death into an idealized memory of perfect being. IV. Heidegger: The full existential and ontological concept of death can now be defined as follows: As the end of Da-sein, death is the ownmost nonrelational and, as such, indefinite and not to be bypassed possibility of Da-sein. As the end of Da-sein, death is the being of this beingtowards-its-end (BT 239). According to such a concept, even though the dead body has a relatively special status among things, since it is not merely objectively present like a material thing but rather In it, we encounter something unliving, something which has lost its life, death properly understood cannot be accessed through any relation to the dying of others, or to the bodies left behind, or through the absence and memories associated with the passage of loved ones (Heidegger, BT 221). For Heidegger, death can never be a being, never one thing among others, not even a process or a property or a state. Death can only be the comingnihilation of temporal thrownness which is in each case mine, which is to say that the only death I truly encounter is my own death, my own possibility of impossibility. And even then, proximally and for the most part, I do not encounter this deathliness but rather flee from it through talking about it as a phenomenon and even through attempting to tranquilize myself regarding its very (perpetual) occurrence. Along these lines, perhaps an existential reading would require an analysis of the situation of the story as follows: in inauthentically attempting to deny the the perpetual comingof-death which is essential to his being, lacking the courage to own up to his essential Angst, the madman seeks to remove all traces which will remind him of dyingwhich will throw him back to the necessity of a decision regarding whether to authentically accept his being-towards-death as his own. Thus, the murderer, in attempting to take care of himself through fleeing into the world, kills the other in an act of radical inauthenticity. In effect, on this reading, the murderer would be the ultimate metaphysician of presence, since in his absolute denial of the temporality of being, he would slay the other in order to assure himself of his eternal present. But such a reading would fail to account for the details of Poe's story. The meticulousness of the murderer's reason, from the beginning, had indeed always been directed towards covering the evidence of the being of death. But contrary to Heidegger, from the vantage of Poe's fictional ontology, death is indeed something ontic, merely a being, merely a thing. Poe's narrator: If still you think me mad, you will think so no longer when I describe the wise precautions I took for the concealment of the body. The night waned, and I worked hastily, but in silence. I took up three planks from the flooring of the chamber, and deposited all between the scantlings. I then replaced the boards so cleverly so cunningly, that no human eye -- not even his -- could have detected anything wrong. There was nothing to wash out -- no stain of any kind -- no blood-spot whatever. I had been too wary for that (Poe 298).

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 9 At least from the madness of the murderer's perspective, not only is the body disposed of so the crime will not be discovered, but also and more primordially, the death of the eye, the deterioration associated with a pulse bound to fail, the wrinkles of age have also been eliminated, turned into an opaque surface of absolute smoothness, the smoothness of the polished floor. Just after his deed, the murderer congratulates himself that the victim is stone, stone dead. The horrible, deathly eye has been changed for him into a inert thing beyond living and dying. So imagine his surprise, when, while being interrogated by the officers who have been summoned on account of a shriek heard in the night (and is the shriek not just as much an emission from the dying body, as much as the flowing of blood and the excretion of pus? A shriek is not a sign of an internal state of awareness.), to begin (again) hearing the heart of the old man beating underneath the floorboards. He hears a low dull, quick soundmuch such a sound as a watch makes when enveloped in cotton (italics Poe's; Poe 300). The hideous heart of the old man as a living dead mechanism continues to beat from beyond the grave. There have been no end of facile analyses of the recurrence of the sound of the heart as the intrusion of subconscious guilt on the part of the narrator, and in a way, these analyses are true. But the madman's guilt is deeper than that of mortification over an evil deed. The madman has attempted to deny the death of things, the hideousness of the organ of the heart as it beats with cholesterol-plaqued arteries and half-ruptured chambers, awaiting its inevitable breakdown, and the madman is called back to reality out of his denial through the reappearance of death as a thing in the very room he sits, in and as the bodies of the surrounding men. The police officers are sitting to rest from their fatigues and chatting about familiar things. One can only imagine that one of the officers walks with a limp, the other has a rather unsightly scar on his nose, while the third one is balding, age spots already showing on his glistening scalp. Such signs of impending death show the narrator that he has been untruthful with himself, that he has in no way removed the dreadful eye and the hideous heart and the wrinkles of age and the deformities of disease from his presence, that death is always already at hand in the very event of social togetherness, even if one is alone with oneself and one's darkest thoughts. For Heidegger, Da-sein is also summoned out of its anxious fleeing in the face of death and back to itself through the guilty call of its care. Like the narrator, Da-sein has attempted to deny death and is now solicited to confess this denial and make amends, avowing the fundamental truth of human being. But this wanting to have a conscience for Heidegger is nothing other than the owning up to the nullity which is at the heart of Da-sein's caring being-inthe-world, which is the same as admitting that Da-sein has no heart. The essence of Da-sein does not essentially involve the heart of the body but rather the ownmost nihilation at the ground of the disclosure of all organic being. When the police of its guilt arrives, Da-sein is forced to exclaim not I admit the deed! -- tear up the planks! -- here, here! -- it is the beating of his hideous heart!" but rather that I have not projected myself on the null-basis of my be-ing, thus I am not an I but rather everyone and no one, fallen prey to the ontical distortions of my ontological condition! Let me shatter myself and stand free and ready to inherit the history which I will become when I authentically own up to and project from the vastation at the heart of my be-ing! Although when posed as an actual confession, such an announcement is comical (and one must ask why it is comical, why do we laugh when philosophy irrupts in inappropriate places?), for Heidegger such a confession is not supposed to be voiced in public but rather is to

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 10 be heard as the silent voice of Da-sein's thrown singularity. The uncanniness of my guilty condition disquiets me, disrupts me, deconstructs me, and when I testify that I have flown from the void(ing) of be-ing and into the absorption with the ontical things of the world, I privately bear witness to my flight and manifest the courage to bear death as death, which is always already my own. But to the contrary, for Poe's mad narrator, death is never my own. This is not so because I am not around when I die, so there is no owning of death possible at all, but rather because insofar as death always already involves dead and dying things, alien irruptions, protrusions, contusions, members and dismemberments, death calls me into a horrible awareness of the outside of everything. Not only is there no spirituality, no God, no soul, no transcendent reason, no subject can lie bleeding on the floor, but also there is not even a free space left behind in the absence of such divine things, no differencing opening of freedom, no rip in being, no work of the negative, not even the nihilation of time, but rather only one bloody thing after another, another ingrown fingernail, another shake of a Parkinsonian hand, another sign of blood in a bowel movement, along with the cracked handle of the hammer, and the traces of DNA left on the killing instrument. What the dead eye represented for the narrator was nothing other than there is no site of representation, not even an opening of disclosure, at least not insofar as such sites or openings involve another mode of being. The living dead narrator discovered that he was always already a dead and dying thing, even discovering that his own revelation would be classified as madness, merely the aberrant firing of certain neurons, a few biochemicals carrying him on his bad trip. And yet, he maintains, The disease had sharpened my senses, not destroyed, not dulled them. Above all was the sense of hearing acute. I heard all things in the heaven and in the earth. I heard many things in hell (Poe 295). Such radical sensation would include hearing that the very senses themselves were things, beside and among other things, even the heaven and hell of passion consisting only of earthly, ontic populations. Heidegger broaches and yet withdraws the possibility of such a mad reality (beyond the transcendence of possibility) in his lectures on Aristotle's Metaphysics: Is this one being (Sein) something before all unfolding, that is, something that exists for itself, whose independence is the true essence of being? Or is being in its essence never not unfolded so that the manifold and its foldings constitute precisely the peculiar oneness of that which is intrinsically gathered up? Is being imparted to the individual modes in such a way that by this imparting it in fact parts itself out, although in this parting out it is not partitioned in such a way that, as divided, it falls apart and loses its authentic essence, its unity? Might the unity of being lie precisely in this imparting, parting out? And if so, how would and could something like this happen? What holds sway in this event? (Heidegger, Metaphysics 25). On the one hand, if being is totally parted out, given as a plurality of things, totally exhausted in their multiplicity, granted as an exteriority without end, then there would be no space or place or site or region or even opening or coming forth. There would only be a mad manifold of beings without unity or sense. In confronting this mad manifold, assuming that one expected some beyond, some transcendence, some impetus otherwise which would dis-locate the immanence of the present (thus allowing it to be labeled as immanence of

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 11 the present), then the appropriate response to the mad awareness that there is neither an outside nor an inside, this is every thing, these bloody hands, this beating heart would be one of horror, not anxiety. Anxiety would happen with the confrontation of the no-thing-ness of be-ing as it emptily mimes the creative transcendence of God, as one finds an endlessly creative falling abyss as the basis of who one is, turning from this falling abyss incessantly (as one would anxiously flee from a cliff). But in a mad confrontation with the immanence of the present, then there would be nowhere to turn, except where one always already was, together with the brutal plurality of things. (On the other hand), Heidegger goes out of his way in the paragraph above to re-introduce the siting of transcendence in the heart of beings, effectively turning from them as he turns towards them. As his thought moves from foldings and modes towards the unity of being as the parting/opening of the manifold, he asks the quite metaphysical question how would and could something like this happen? In a sense, Poe's mad narrator is far beyond Heidegger at this point, since he knows better than to ask such a question. He finds himself confronted with the mad death of things, the plurality without the eternal transcendence of life, and he recoils in what might be called authentic horror at this death. While it is true he is mad and cannot bear his own insight, so he attempts to destroy the death of things with his blade, he possesses too much wisdom to ask such questions as what is the essence of deterioration?, how does aging come to pass?, or In what sense does history give us lives whose sense passes away along with it?. The narrator knows that there is no answer to these questions, that they are thus not even questions, that one cannot mitigate the horror of the death of things through thinking it through. V. Not even here. The present essay, of course, is not a work of fiction. At best, it is an attempt at thinking which is poised on the brink of failure, situated between the loss of things through conceptual annihilation and their promised return, inheriting their eidola through irruptions of Poe's prose. (At worst, it is merely a failure.) Insofar as it speaks from the depths, even if it speaks of the depths of singularity or mad specificity or endlessly concrete detail, thus even it attempts to stay with the essence of shallowness in the confrontation of dead and disfigured and stained and decomposing things which meet the gaze, touch the skin, whose odors intrude into the nose and whose shrieks carry one towards a body dying once and alone with a universe of imperfections constituting its morbid beauty, then (insofar as it successful as thinking) this essay speaks poetically and risks incorporating any fictional words into its poetic movement. Insofar as this prose essay speaks insightfully, it poetizes, bringing every thing of which it speaks into the dimension of pure saying. Heidegger: The opposite to the purely spoken, to the poem, is not prose. Pure prose is not 'prosaic.' It is as poetic and thereby as rare as poetry Heidegger, Poetry 208). But when the prose of thinking is thus purified, inflected towards the poetic, resonating with it in a strange disclosive sameness, there are advantages and disadvantages, gains and losses, insofar as such thought would attempt to bear witness to the truth of madness and death in their singular instantiations in the bodies of the earth. In his later thoughtful writing on poetry, language, madness, and death, Heidegger only attends to the advantages and gains, to the extent that the pure rarity of his thinking is formed entirely through this one-sided attentiveness, an

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 12 attentiveness which conceals as much as it reveals. For an essential instance, in precisely the place where he does address the madman and his relation to death, in Language and the Poem, later Heidegger follows his characteristic pattern of turning away from dead and dying things and towards the pure (dis)essence(ing) (Wesung) of their presentation. In his reading of a single line from Trakl's Psalm, everything about later Heidegger's continuing fundamental relationship to death is exposed. Trakl writes: Der Wahnsinnige ist gestorben (The madman is dead) (Heidegger, Language 173). Amazingly, about this dead madman, Heidegger makes a series of remarkable interpretive claims: 1. The madman is not really dead. The dead one lives in his grave. He lives in his chamber so quietly and pensively that he plays with his snakes. They cannot harm him. 2. The dead madman is not really a mentally-ill person (Geisteskranken). Madness (Wahnsinn) does not mean the sense that hallucinates the nonsensical. The madman senses, and he even senses as none has before. But he remains mad, without the sense of the others. He is of another sense. Heidegger draws the mad, separated one, the stranger who is departed, displaced in relation both to the boy Elis from Trakl's To the Boy Elis (Oh how long, Elis, have you been dead.) and to Nietzsche's Zarathustra, the one who projects beyond Platonism from the site of its overturning. But about Elis (and by implication the stranger, the madman, and even Zarathustra) Heidegger asserts Elis is not a dead one who deteriorates (verwest) into the lateness of dying life. Elis is rather the dead one who purifyingly moves (entwestone would want to say decontaminates) into earliness (Heidegger, Language 175) And with another astounding, macabre linking, Heidegger connects the dead, mad, stranger, by way of Elis (become Zarathustra's child) to the unborn. Heidegger recalls Trakl's line from Bright Spring,: The unborn tends its ownmost calm. This unborn protects and preserves the quiet childhood in the coming awakening of the human race. Thus, Heidegger concludes, the one who died early lives calmly. This stranger become madman become living corpse become (sexless) child become unborn lives quietly for the sake of the future, a perpetually posthumous being, perhaps even a philosopher of the future, one of the wicked which Nietzsche saw coming. Such conclusions seems incontrovertible at the distance from which Heidegger reads, a distance which allows for the purifying poetization of poetry itself, a distillation of its form into essential words. But if one looks at Trakl's words a bit more closely, with a more prosaic mind, one might notice equally astonishing occlusions in Heidegger's reading. To unearth these strange fossils, we only need to attend to the conclusion of Trakl's Psalm where the dead madman was first invoked: It is an empty boat which pushes down the black canal in evening. In the gloom of of the old asylum, human ruins deteriorate. Dead orphans lie at the garden wall. From gray rooms proceed angels with shit-flecked wings. Worms drop from their yellowed lids. The square before the church is dark and silent, as in the days of childhood. Earlier lives glide by on silver soles. And the shadows of the damned descend to sighing waters. In his grave, the white magician plays with his snakes.

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 13 Silently above the place of skulls open God's golden eyes. (Trakl 16-17) Here, one can easily see the amount of elision involved in Heidegger's dissociation of death (and madness) from bodily deterioration in Trakl's poetry. Even only taking into account the entirety of this one intervening stanza separating the madman from the magician in the grave, the magician who supposedly still lives (while noting the two other equally problematic stanzas with their mentions of bloody contagia, bats, blindness, poverty), one might come to an exactly opposite determination from Heidegger regarding the significance of the death of the madman: the madman does not live. Rather, he has magically transformed from a vibrant presence into a rotting corpse, playing with the snaking worms which eat his remnants. The ruins of the madman's mind deteriorated in the old asylum, drawing him down from heavenly transcendence and into a perverse relation with dead bodies (perhaps orphans he murdered), excrement; damned through a bio-fixation allowing no elevation from the sighing waters of the singular earth. The only future, the only one to come, the only unborn child of the body is the skull which rests on Golgotha, the skull which draws God's golden eyes and simultaneously shows this God that He has been as mad and dead all along as the madman to whom He can offer no salvation. The mystical divine vision of death (here) is drawn into a revelation of its impotence in the face of the contingent horror of no future at all. One might imagine Poe's madman from The Tell-Tale Heart carrying out such a perverse reading from the enlightened vantage of his asylum cell, perhaps encouraged by his anachronistic knowledge of Trakl's all-too-earthly (and psychopathological) death from depression and cocaine. Perhaps awaiting execution in the cell next to him, Poe's equally mad narrator from The Black Cat whispers through the walls, whispers of a spirit of perversenss he senses in Trakl's writing, the same spirit which led this narrator not only to do what he knew he should not (gouge his beloved cat's eye out, hang it from a tree, murder his wife with an ax) but also perpetually to obsess about every morbid detail of his actions. Like the Heart's narrator, the Cat's Narrator attempted to cover up his crime assiduously through disposing of the body: At one period I thought of cutting the corpse into minute fragments, and destroying them by fire. At another, I resolved to dig a grave for it in the floor of the cellar. Again, I deliberated about casting it in the well in the yard - about packing it in a box, as if merchandize, with the usual arrangements, and so getting a porter to take it from the house. Finally I hit upon what I considered a far better expedient than either of these. I determined to wall it up in the cellar - as the monks of the middle ages are recorded to have walled up their victims (Poe, 261). And also like the Heart's narrator, the Cat's narrator was undone by the re-intrusion of the corpse out of its hiddenness, in this case revealed by a cat which reminded him of the one he had killed, a cat whose cries brought the investigators to tear down the wall behind which his wife's body was immured: The corpse, already greatly decayed and clotted with gore, stood erect before the eyes of the spectators. Upon its head, with red extended mouth and solitary eye of fire, sat the

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 14 hideous beast whose craft had seduced me into murder, and whose informing voice had consigned me to the hangman. I had walled the monster up within the tomb! (Poe, 263). From such a vantage, a vantage of the specifics of fiction in resonance with the mortal detail of death and madness, one may well have disturbing suspicions about what lies hidden behind Heidegger's elisions in his poetic readings. Not only: what is essentially concealed is the opening disclosure of eventual speaking? But also: What is Heidegger intentionally concealing in his re-inscription of death and madness as projective promise? What torturous impulses, what violent images, what secret hatreds, what waves of nausea, what childhood horrors, what sexual fantasies, what racial antipathies, what impulses to power, what real abuses lie behind the walls of the enactment of the homecoming of the human race into the quiet beginning of its stiller swaying? (Heidegger, Language 191). Doubtlessly, such questions have no answers, and furthermore, they remain at the level of psychological interrogations. And yet, such questions, questions brought forth precisely by a curiosity towards the details of mere being do not merely call for the florid, journalistic description of the life of the thinker. Rather, they draw poetic thinking to the site of its necessary exclusions. In order for thinking to take place, there must be a withdrawal from (or even willful repression of) fixation on morbid impulses, perverse tendencies, violent fulminations (even here, in the midst of all these horrible references; words are not wounds): there is indeed a calm anticipation which constitutes the life of the mind. This calm anticipatory movement of disclosure which has here been termed the poetic is not to be found in the objective presence of the poem (even though the elegance of poetic economy and cadence draw it forth) but rather is the space in which the poem is received. Likewise, the morbid perversity, the obsessiveness, the fixation on detail of the fictional is not to be found in the objective presence of the short story or the novel (even though their intricate wanderings and imbricated constellations draw it forth) but rather is the space in which fiction is received. Certainly, in many places, the poetic distillations of Heidegger in regard to Trakl's work seem appropriate. But, as is demonstrated here, there is another space in which even the poem can be received. If Heidegger's thinking disavows such a space, if Heidegger's thinking is nothing other than a name for the future of thinking itself as the poetic, then this does not prove that such a space is of no relevance for an authentic relation to being. Rather, it would only indicate that thinking would be a name for a certain occurrence of purification, symbolization, essentialization, and gathering which allows be-ing to manifest within a dimension of projective hope. Through the lens of the other, half-blind fictive eye, being would appear quite differently; not as that which calls for thinking but rather as that which cannot be thought at all, that which can only be lingered with, endured, fugitively described, and acknowledged in its horror, even that which must be so acknowledged lest it return with the perverse force of deadly, exclusive violence. One might even say (reversing Heidegger's announcement cited earlier) that the opposite to the impurely spoken, to fiction, is not poetry. Impure poetry is not poetic. It is as fictional and thereby as common as fiction. Perhaps Heidegger's great foe Adorno should have written not that There is no poetry after Auschwitz but rather that there has never been any pure poetry, before or after Auschwitz, that is not the fantasy of a distilling projection which would entomb suffering, fragile, and deteriorating bodies (and the minds contained in psychopathological

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 15 brains) in silent crypts. The philosophical essay (which resonates in poetic sameness with the poem) would have to poise itself at the edge of deteriorating into unthought images of dead and dying bodies in order to even begin to bear witness to this silence: thus out of the opening propagated through the thinking of Heidegger, we would have to commence to tell stories. VI. This essay ends with the deaths of two women, recounted in two fictional presentations. But before I narrate these deaths, number them specifically, tell the tales of each woman's demise, singularly and without precedent, allow me to return to the opening theme of the essay for a brief re-emphasis, even though it has been continually in the background of my discussion. Philosophy can barely tolerate, if at all, literary specificity, the specificity of Dichtung als Belletristik. Philosophy has told itself that it deals with the concept or what comes after the concept in zones of quasi-transcendentality. It has told itself that it is of the essence of language to lose the things themselves, perpetually, to have them vanish in traces of imagined forms, metaphysical representations, historical ideas, scientific descriptions, and even traces themselves, doubled tracings which torsion beyond the name of being. And yet, when one attempts to acknowledge the death of things, the decaying and imperfect and deteriorating things of the world, things such as Socrates mentions in the Parmenides only to disavow, hair, mud, filth, and other things which are base and vile, and especially when one attempts to acknowledge the human body and the human mind as the locus of such things, then one is forced to enter into a language resistant to the generality of conceptualization and even resistant to the sublimation of singular figures into symbols (Plato 6). For instance, in the above paragraphs, each time I evoke the death of things beyond the determining disclosure of Heidegger's ontology, with appeals to the prose of Poe or autobiographical eruptions or even vague references which have for me all-too-concrete connotations (the horror towards the death of things is always operative in writing), I find myself moved into an idiom of specificity where the words magically fixate on singular beings, even beyond the language of being. Of course, all words, in being repeated and repeatable, in being cast forth, in being words at all, are always already generalities, transported outside the evidence of the immanent present. And yet, as the death of things is broached, as one is shocked into the eerie proximity of flea eggs on the neck of your cat, of the weird twitch of your bird's head, of the scar from the grill-burn which will always be there, from the pain in the throat from esophageal reflux, among other things, then one finds these general words to be pulled to these specific points through the weird gravity of the detail of singular life. Though much about this life can be disclosed through paraphrasing it as being-in-the-world which shares quite general, ontological structures with the lives of others and much can be learned about the whole of the life of (to use a phrase Heidegger would have found abhorrent) Da-sein as a species (where fundamental ontology could be redescribed as a sort of weird existential biology), there are things about life, occurrences of beings, a radically nominalized ontology which can only be avowed (at least within language) through the shocks, winces, raptures, and shrieks of fictive prose, even when this prose comes forth in the apparently non-fantastic realms of autobiography or commentary on the real.

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 16 1. then without those doors there did stand the lofty and enshrouded figure of the lady Madeline of Usher. There was blood upon her white robes, and the evidence of some bitter struggle upon every portion of her emaciated frame. For a moment she remained trembling and reeling to and fro upon the threshold - then, with a low moaning cry, fell heavily inward upon the person of her brother, and in her violent and now final death-agonies, bore him to the floor a corpse, and a victim to the terrors he had anticipated (Poe 219). There is a thematics of what has been called here the desire for the death of death which runs throughout Poe's work, not merely residing beneath the floorboards of The Tale-Tell Heart and behind the walls of The Black Cat. Along with this thematics, there is also a counter-movement of the return of such death from its attempted destruction or covering, a counter-movement of ghastly resurrection. Lady Madeleine, though she scarcely appears in The Fall of the House of Usher (much as the old man scarcely appears in The Tale-Tell Heart, or the wife scarcely appears in The Black Cat, as if there were a literary mimesis of this desire flowing through Poe's activity of composition, as if he almost could not bear the figure of death any more than his characters could) embodies this counter-movement in the eeriest and most provocative fashion possible. Suffering from a severe unexplainable state where she is dissolving into a condition of perpetual catatonia, Lady Madeleine apparently dies. It is almost as if, in her, Poe prophesied a natural occurrence of the entry of the body into the indistinct zone of Agamben's bare life, since in the story she exists neither as a biological being nor as a social presence, she only manifests as the living-dead, pure catalepsy, glimpsed merely as a ghostlike movement, a(n) (apparently) dead body, and in her horrible returning visitation. In the story, this woman has been reduced by her illness (and perhaps by her brother) to a gravelike silence. She (apparently) dies out of the sight of the narrator. He and Roderick Usher take her body and entomb it in the family crypt, (for mysterious reasons) preserving it for a later burial. (One familiar with Poe would also here recall the macabre entombment which takes place in The Cask of Amontillado, another site of the death of death in his work.) As they entomb her, they are confronted with her strange hovering between death and life: Our glances, however, rested not long upon the dead - for we could not regard her unawed. The disease which had thus entombed the lady in the maturity of youth, had left, as usual in all maladies of a strictly cataleptical character, the mockery of a faint blush upon the bosom and the face, and that suspiciously lingering smile upon the lip which is so terrible in death (Poe 213). The men, awed by the sight of the living-death of the thing her body has been exposed as, retreat after replacing and screwing down a lid upon it and sealing it behind an iron door. And yet, in the horrific conclusion, the body returns, returns to die, already dead in a way, the dead returning to kill the living who have attempted to seal her out of sight. But as anyone familiar with the story knows, she had already been returning, attempting to be heard out of the silence of her entombment. With his unnaturally heightened senses, Roderick Usher has heard her

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 17 scratching and moaning in the crypt for days. Yet he dared not remedy their error (if it was an error, if he had not somehow known she was still alive all along, if he had not already been responsible for her catatonia, perhaps having transformed her into the living-dead long ago through unspeakable acts of abuse), and while she scratched at the walls of her tomb, he discusses literature together with his friend, first reciting a poem of his own composition, The Haunted Palace, and then listening to the narrator read a tale of knightly conquests. As the narrator reads the story, a story whose uncouth and unimaginative prolixity he suspects will cause it to be of little interest to the refined sensibilities of Roderick, the sounds of Madeleine's escape echo through the house as an horrific counterpoint. While the narrator reads of the breaking of a door, he hears the same cracking and ripping sound reverberate through the mansion, as Madeleine tears off the wooden lid with her bare hands. While the narrator reads of the death shriek of a slain dragon, he hears an unusual screaming or grating sound vibrate through the walls, as Madeleine cries out from the madness of her condition. While the narrator reads of the falling of a great shield to the floor, a distinct, hollow, metallic, and clangorous, yet apparently muffled reverberation rings within the great house, as Madeleine opens the great iron door behind which she was left for dead. Such horrific sounds, unintentionally responding to the space of literature, as it describes and presents in its flowing cadences, would be nothing other than the sounds of the death of things, as they arise and return us to a horrible authenticity, exposing the intellectualized courage for death as a shallow heroism of the spirit, the precursor to any fascism. 2.
From the dark opening of the worn insides of the shoes the toilsome tread of the worker stares forth. In the stiffly rugged heaviness of the shoes there is the accumulated tenacity of her slow trudge through the far-spreading and ever-uniform furrows of the field swept by a raw wind. On the leather lie the dampness and richness of the soil. Under the soles slides the loneliness of the field-path as evening falls. In the shoes vibrates the silent call of the earth, its quiet gift of the ripening grain and its unexplained self-refusal in the fallow desolation of the wintry field. This equipment is pervaded by uncomplaining anxiety as to the certainty of bread, the wordless joy of having once more withstood want, the trembling before the impending childbed and shivering at the surrounding menace of death. This equipment belongs to the earth, and it is protected in the world of the peasant woman. From out of this protected belonging the equipment itself rises to its restingwithin-itself (Heidegger, Origin 159).

The peasant woman, of course, had no idea it would be her shoes (assuming they were hers, assuming they were a pair, to echo Derrida's concerns from Restitutions (TIP, 259)) (who also problematically engages Schapiro's critique of Heidegger) that would be immortalized and utilized as an example to show the way in which the work of art sets truth to work, allowing the things of the world to be disclosed against the background of the withdrawn recessing of earthliness, preserving through founding an awesome beginning. She had no idea that it would be her shoes which would be drawn from the painting and into communication with the erecting of the Greek temple, allowing passages between worlds, transitions between beginnings, as the opening of presence leaps into dark smudges of paint, allowing the cracks in classical architecture to be seen as inherent to its being. She had no idea that it would be her shoes which

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 18 both first shine forth as equipment while at the same time, in their being twisted beyond use on the painted surface, disclose the essence of equipmentality, the essence of the striving engagement allotted to mortals on the earth. If she had known this, before she sold them to the small shop in the village owned by her uncle who would later load them onto a train car where they would embark on an unremarkable journey which would eventually take them to the floor beneath Van Gogh's canvas, she would have perhaps (along with insisting on more of a profit for her sale) affixed a short note which afforded clearer understanding of their history. Certainly (on one hand) Heidegger was right, these were shoes which carried within them, in the dark recesses of their other interior, seasons and toil, worry and hope, birth and death. The nexus of the world radiated from the simple being of the things that the shoes persisted as. But on the other hand, she had sold the shoes and they were taken away, removed and detached from their being, and her life as a peasant, as a farmer, as one who lived in the midst of the richness and poverty of the granting of the earth had long ago passed. Perhaps her note would include the following details: She sold the shoes because she could not stand to have them in the house. She could not stand to have them in the house because she had been wearing these shoes when lightning struck the field where she was working alongside her husband, Roland. The bolt-from-the-darkening-clouds, the clouds they braved because of needing to secure enough food for the harsh winter, flashed to her right, surprising and blinding her. She was thrown to the ground in confusion and did not immediately comprehend what had happened. When she righted herself, she found her husband Roland lying of the crumbled earth clutching his chest, gasping, his clothes smoldering, the scent of his burned flesh in her nose. The rain had begun pouring and the wind roaring and the lightning sparked wildly in the heavens. She knew she had to get him back to the house. In a mad instant of decision, she ran to get her daughters to help transport him home through dragging his body on a burlap sack. But as she ran, her shoes caught in the roots and plants erupting in every row. So she took off the shoes and flung them to the ground and ran with bare feet. Weeks later, Roland was dead and in the dirt (he never awakened, but he twitched for hours before he died, his body still conducting the electricity which eventually killed it.) However, before she sold the farm and moved together with her oldest daughter and her husband, since it was all she could do, she wandered to the circle of dead plants where the terrible thing had happened, almost expecting to find him still lying there, twitching, but she found her shoes instead, half buried in mud and filled with rainwater. She shuddered as she held them in her hands and knew she would never wear them again, nor allow them to become keepsakes of tragedy. Thus, they went to her uncle's store, along with the farming tools and Roland's clothes and most of the other vestiges of her peasant existence. She died seven months later after crying nearly every night for her lost Mann. Would such an affixed note destroy the poetry of Van Gogh's art, and the poetry of Heidegger's reading of that art? Would such a detailed account draw the shoes from Heidegger's elegant yet completely banal and general account of the truth of equipmentality and the being of things into the irrelevance of journalism? Heidegger had to imagine the site of the shoes, the placement of the shoes, the life of the wearer, but by what standard did he license himself to stop imagining, to divide essence from singular accident? And according to what principle did he allow himself to turn the peasant woman into an icon, an exemplar, a model of Da-sein,

Phaenex: Spring 2012: Hutchinson 19 purified from the terrible contingent eccentricities of life? Such unanswerable questions would lie on the stone and root-filled other way towards the essence of truth, the shadowed path which runs through the valley of dead things. Works Cited Derrida, Jacques. Aporias. Trans. Thomas Dutoit. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993. Speech and Phenomena and Other Essays on Husserl's Theory of Signs (translation of Voix to Voice from Speech mine). Trans. David B. Allison. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973). Restitutions. Trans Geoff Bennington and Ian McCloud. The Truth in Painting. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. Descartes, Renee. Meditations on First Philosophy. Trans. John Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Heidegger, Martin. Aristotles Metaphysics 13: On the Essence and Actuality of Force. Trans. Walter Brogan and Peter Warnek. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995. Being and Time. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. Albany: SUNY Press, 1996. On the Way to Language. Trans. Peter D. Hertz. New York: Harper and Row, 1971. (emendations to the translation mine.) Poetry Language Thought. Trans. Albert Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row, 1971. The Origin of the Work of Art. Trans. Albert Hofstadter. Basic Writings. San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1993 Husserl, Edmund. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and a Phenomenological Philosophy. Trans. Fred Kersten. The Hague: Martinus Nijhof, 1983. Plato. The Parmenides. Trans. Benjamin Jowett. Maryland: Arc Manor, 2008. Poe, Edgar Allan. Tales of Mystery and Imagination. New York: Henry Frowde Press, 1903. Trakl, Georg. Poems and Prose: A Bilingual Edition. Trans. Alexander Stillmark. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2005. (translations in this essay mine).

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi