Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 15

BEHAVIORALISM:

Origins of the Concept

1. Behavioralism and the History of American Political Science


In the short history of American academic political science, behavioralism has played an important role. Even most contemporary historians of the discipline have agreed with Waldo's statement above (e.g., Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 150; Farr 1995: 198). Behavioralism has, indeed, haunted the discipline for half of its existence now. And although behavioralism is a product of an American political science and must be understood in that context, the impact of behavioralism on political science may have been as big in some other countries as it was in the United States. (1) In that sense the 'story' should have relevance fo all political scientists. To write about behavioralism today is important at least for three reasons. First, the question is about the identity. Although the present state of the discipline is usually labeled as postbehavioralism, "the present postbehavioral era can be understood only with reference to behavioralism and that, even then, the behavioral revolution is open to different interpretations" (Farr 1995: 221). But the strong identity is also based on conflict, and although "political scientists have quarreled over many matters in the contemporary period...the most divisive issue by far has been behavioralism" (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 173). Only conflicts reveal important issues. Secondly, behavioralism is one of the best research objects to understand the nature of political science and conceptual change within the discipline. The period following the Second World War was actually one of the two significant moments of academic reform in the United States, the first one being the rise of the research university after the Civil War (Bender 1997: 4). This academic reform touched also political science. The 1950s and the early 1960s were the golden days for the support of modern social science (Warren E. Miller in Baer 1991: 242). In fact, the prestige of social science has clearly declined in the United States since that time (Lindblom 1997: 227). And behavioralism brought passion for many. It has even be claimed that none of the contemporary tendencies "has caught the imagination of the discipline as whole and swept it along with the sense of a common and compelling purpose" (David Easton in Baer 1991: 213; cf. also Lindblom 1997: 230) the way behavioralism did. The reasons for passion were many, but passion there was. Thirdly, from time to time it is useful to look back at history to see, if there is something to learn from history. Social sciences are eager to adopt new ideas, research topics and approaches. Many times these new ideas may sweep important topics into the dustbin of history. Maybe it is time to save something important.

2. An Intellectual Matrix of Political Science

To analyse the history of political science it is useful to understand the development as a discursive practice. What is usually referred to as discursive practice (Berndtson 1983; Berndtson 1987; Gunnell 1993: 1) refers to a scholar's attempt to work intellectually within the scientific and social discourse in given society society. A scholar tries to answer problems which the society poses, but he does so through theoretical debate. A good example is conceptual change within a discipline. As James Farr points out: "Conceptual change is one imaginative consequence of political actors criticizing and attempting to resolve the contradictions which they discover or generate in the complex web of their beliefs, actions, and practices as they try to understand and change the world around them" (Farr 1989: 25). To understand the nature and history of behavioralism I will use the following simple intellectual matrix of political science as a framework for discursive practice: An Intellectual Matrix of Political Science Political science is an endeavor between science and society. As a study of politics, political science lives off the social, and above all, political development. This is self-evident, but apparently one must remind of it once in a while (e.g., Lowi 1992; Ball 1995: 41-41). The discipline is always a part of politics, in three different senses. First, social development offers problems to study; secondly, it has a socializing effect; and thirdly, political scientists have to cope with society in order to pursue their interests, whether in obtaining resources for research or even in being allowed to do research. Scholars must deal with organizations. Governments, foundations and corporations are important financiers of research. There may be direct demands for research or at least indirect ones. Contacts with society usually lead into bureaucratic rhetorics within the discipline (Ball 1995). Scholars have to convince influential outsiders about the relevance of their research. Bureaucratic rhetorics is always a part of a general metadiscourse of the discipline, other part being an internal criticism among scholars. In reality these two forms of metadiscourse often get mixed and it is hard to separate them. Goals of the discipline belong partly to a general metadiscourse of the discipline (bureaucratic rhetorics or internal criticism), but they are also part of scientific practice (discourse on methodology). In that sense they are an important link between metadiscourse and scientific practice itself. In regard to the latter it is useful to make a distinction between research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology (Berndtson 1983). In short: what to study, existing knowledge systems, perspectives and methods. The division of the focus of political science into research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology ahas an affinity with research programs (Lakatos) and with research traditions (Laudan) as they have been used in political science (Ball 1976; Dryzek 1986). Laudan, for instance, defines research traditions as "a set of general assumptions about the entities and processes in a domain of study, and about the appropriate methods to be used for investigating the problems and constructing the theories in that domain." (Laudan 1977: 81; Dryzek 1986: 305) Without going into a discussion about the usefulness of research programs or research traditions in the study of political science (see Dryzek 1986), I will use the term of a research

tradition to refer to the web of research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology. As an example of research traditions one can take, for instance, rational choice theories, functionalism and Marxism (Ball 1976; although Ball calls them research programs). It is important to point out that in order to qualify as a research tradition research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology must form a logical system of thought. Political science organizations include universities, associations, think tanks, etc. In a given society these organizations reflect the general culture of that society. An important feature of these organizations is their degree of academic freedom, which, again, is very much dependent on the prevailing degree of democracy and freedom in society in general. Individual scholars may be divided into the elite, the mandarins, and the mass. The mandarins may belong to the elite or to the mass, but for the purposes of the present article, it is useful to understand them as a category of their own. A last dimension is the impact of other disciplines. Social sciences have always developed in close contact with each other. In the case of political science it has been common that the discipline has received more impulses from other disciplines than the other way around. It is also important to notice that relations between academic disciplines are continuously changing. To study the history of political science is also to study relations between disciplines.

3. Definitions of Behavioralism
Most histories of political science agree on one thing: the concept of behavioralism has always been somewhat unclear. As Dwight Waldo stated while writing about the emergence of behavioralism, "what happened was...complicated - and somewhat obscure" (Waldo 1975: 58). Almost all those trying to define behavioralism have confessed that "every man puts his own emphasis and thereby becomes his own behavioralist" (Easton 1962: 9) and "attempts at coming to any complete definition of behavioralism are probably futile given the diversity of those who followed its banner" (Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 151). And also David Truman has warned that it is a mistake to overstandardize the definition of behavioralism, because "it was a kind multifaceted expression of dissatisfaction with the constraints and formalities of the conventional political science" and "that impulse, was the only thing that was in common among really a quite diverse series of efforts" (David Truman in Baer, et al., eds. 1991). The problem in trying to interpret the meaning of behavioralism simply seems to be that we can always find "authorities to whom we can turn to press our interpretation" (Easton 1962: 9). This seems to indicate that there has been no behavioralism, but many behavioralisms. Accordingly, the first conclusion is that behavioralism is not a research tradition, but something else. To find out what, a short history of conceptual change is useful. Behavioralism as a concept dates from the mid-1950s. As far as I have been able to detect the first one to use it in writing was Dwight Waldo in his 1956 book "Political Science in the United States" (Waldo 1956: 24) which was an introductory text written mainly for foreign audiences under UNESCO auspices. The term may have been used earlier, especially at the University of Chicago (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 183), but it became into general use only after 1956 (e.g. Hacker 1959). Furthermore, the concept seems to have received a wider popularity only after the publication of "The Limits of Behavioralism in Political Science" (Charlesworth, ed. 1962). The first time the concept appeared in the pages of the American

Political Science Review was in 1963 (Mendelson 1963: 593). Mendelson's article "The Neobehavioral Approach to the Judicial Process: A Critique" was, as its name indicates, a critique of behavioralism. In the next issue of the Review the concept appeared again in Albert Somit's and Joseph Tanenhaus's survey of the trends in American political science, now in the form of a neutral research field (Somit and Tanenhaus 1963). In the beginning of the 1950s the concept of behavioralism was not used. Instead, the concept of political behavior was very common from the beginning of the 1940s having spread since Charles E. Merriam's call for its study in the 1920s. The next step, accordingly, was to identify those studying political behavior, behavioralists. This happened at the beginning of the 1950s (e.g. Easton 1953: 151), although, instead of behavioralists, many used the term 'behaviorist'. It was above all David Easton, who stressed the importance of distinguishing behavioralists from behaviorists (Easton 1953: 151). The conceptual development seems to coincide with Albert Somit's and Joseph Tanenhaus's periodization of the history of emerging behavioralism (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 185): 1) from the end of the Second World War to 1949 there were only scattered signs of what was coming, political behavior as a new research area began to be propagated, 2) from 1950 to the mid-1950s was the emerging period, and, 3) from the mid-1950s to the mid-1960s behavioralism began to claim hegemony within the discipline, at the same time when its opponents launched a determined counter-attack. This seems to indicate that behavioralism was used first either in a neutral introductory meaning (Waldo; Somit and Tanenhaus) or in a critical fashion (Mendelson). David Easton has also pointed out that: "behavioralism was not a clearly defined movement for those who were thought to be behavioralists. It was more clearly definable by those who were opposed to it, because they were describing it in terms of the things within the newer trends that they found objectionable. So some would define behavioralism as an attempt to apply the methods of natural sciences to human behavior. Others would define it as an excessive emphasis upon quantification. Others as individualistic reductionism. From the inside, the practioners were of different minds as what it was that constituted behavioralism...few of us were in agreement." (David Easton in Baer et al., eds. 1991: 207) It was no wonder that those identifying themselves as behavioralists were more apt to speak about the study of political behavior as an approach and used the concepts of revolution, mood, movement, persuasion or protest to describe what political behavior research indicated. From the beginning behavioralism was a political, not a scientific concept. However, when behavioralists rised to an hegemonic position within American political science at the beginning of the 1960s the concept became more general. Behavioralists accepted it (Easton 1962) and it became even to designate the stage in the history of American political science (Easton 1985), while the critics continued to use it in a pejorative sense. Because behavioralism cannot be considered as a research tradition, but a political movement to advance something, definitions of behavioralism give an idea of what the behavioralists wanted. Most introductions to the subject stress methodology and goals of the discipline (value free research).

One of the most "influential" definitions of behavioralism has been David Easton's list of its characteristics: 1) search for regularities, even with explanatory and predictive value, 2) verification with testable propositions, 3) self-conscious examination for rigorous techniques, 4) quantification for precision when possible and relevant, 5) keeping values and empirical explanations analytically distinct, 6) systematization as an intertwining of theory and research, 7) pure science preceding the application of knowledge, and 8) integration of the social sciences (Easton 1962: 7-8; Easton 1965: 7). Other commentators have agreed. Somit and Tanenhaus present actually the same eight tenets of behavioralism (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 177-179) and many critics of behavioralism have also focused on methodology as a key element of behavioralism (e.g., Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 151-152.) But behavioralism has been understood also as dealing with something more than only methodology and goals of the discipline. James Farr has recently analysed behavioralism through three key problem areas: 1) a research focus on political behavior, 2) a methodological plea for science, and 3) a political message about liberal pluralism (Farr 1995). Although a focus on political behavior is self-evident in behavioralism, it has been somehow forgotten by those who are more interested in techniques than in actual problems. Maybe one reason has also been that behavioralists have been eager to demonstrate that the behavioral study of politics can be applied to all kinds of research areas (Eulau 1962). Political message about liberal pluralism refers to a new theory of democracy that was developed by American political scientists after the Second World War. Especially radical critics of behavioralism have taken a pluralist theory of American politics as their target, claiming that it has accepted the social and political system uncritically (e.g., McCoy and Playford, eds. 1967). Locigally behavioralism and pluralism are two distinct phenomena, but, if behavioralism is a political concept or, if it would like to present itself as a research tradition, pluralism could be understood as a tenet of behavioralism.

4. Explanations for the Rise of behavioralism


In order to understand behavioralism better as an internally heterogenous movement, it is necessary to focus on different explanations about its birth. The nature of behavioralism has been a topic of many articles, but systematic research on its development has been rare. There are general explanatory descriptive studies (Somit and Tannehaus 1982; Waldo 1975; Ricci 1984), historical interpretations of the period through some key scholars (Crick 1959; Seidelman and Harpham 1985), genealogical studies of the birth of research fields (Gunnell 1993) and countless articles (Dahl 1961; Ball 1993; Farr 1995). Although many of these studies are very systematic and thorough in their own ways, they give, however, only a partial picture of the problem. No full scale attempt to outline factors behind the behavioral movement exists. Using the intellectual matrix of political science, given explanations thus far may be presented as follows: Society Social development. Deep social crises have made political scientists more keen to realism. Students of the history of the discipline have mainly referred to three "big things": The Great Depression of the 1930s and the New Deal (Ball 1993), the World War II (Dahl 1961: Waldo

1975; Ball 1993; Farr 1995) and the Cold War (Ball 1993; Farr 1995). The socializing effect seems to have been most important in connection with the Great Depression, while it was Second World War that really forged a new relation between academia and politics. The Cold War marked the whole era of behavioralism and in that way its general effect on behavioralism was maybe more important than anything else. All three crisis led to a deep dissatisfaction with the "state of the discipline" (Somit and Tannehaus 1982: 184) and to behavioralism as an answer. Organizations. One of the most given explanations for the rise of behavioralism has been a reference to the role of foundations (2), mainly the emergence of the Ford Foundation as an important provider of funds (Dahl 1961; Somit and Tanenhaus 1982; Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 154). Many have even argued that the whole concept of behavioralism came into use only because of the policy of foundations (Geiger 1988: 329). And Bernard Berelson seems to agree: "What happened to give rise to the term? The key event was the development of a Ford Foundation program in this field. The program was initially designated 'individual behavior and human relations' but it soon became known as the behavioral sciences program and, indeed, was officially called that within the foundation. It was the foundation's administrative action, then, that led directly to the term and to the concept of this particular field of study." (Berelson 1968: 42) (3) The foundation money created also a self-generating process which led to the recruitment of behavioralists. Because behavioralist projects were funded better than traditional ones, there were a larger supply of behavioralists up for recruitment than others (Hacker 1959: 39-40). It is no wonder that some of the key practioners of behavioralism have been willing to admit, that "it was almost single-handedly the Ford Foundation that did so much to legitimate empirical social science" (Warren E. Miller in Baer, et al., eds. 1991: 242). And David Easton has argued that "in its orgins it may well be that the concept can be considered an accident" (Easton 1965: 12). Easton explains this accident with the convergence of the founding of the Behavioral Sciences Division of the Ford Foundation and the story of some congressmen attacking social sciences as socialist sciences (Easton 1965: 22; cf. Ball 1993). Foundations played a key role in financing research at the beginning of the 1950s, but the Ford Foundation terminated its behavioral program in 1957. One of the reasons was the attack towards foundations. There had already been the House of Representatives Select Committee (Cox Committee) investigating tax-exempt foundations in 1952, and the foundations were increasingly criticized as being too liberal (actually it was in the hearings of Cox Committee when social sciences were termed as socialist sciences). After the foundations began to diminish their financing of the behavioral sciences, the National Science Foundation stepped in. The original bill for the establishment of a National Science Foundation, which was given to the Congress in 1945, contained the establishment of a Social Science Division. Social Sciences came under attack from politicians, however, already then, because some congressmen saw them representing values foreign to Anmericans. Social scientists counterattacked with rhetorics stressing the values of science, neutral pursuance of truth, and distancing themselves from social reform. All the values that

had helped to win the Second World War (Ball 1993). But to no avail. The National Science Foundation was established in 1950 without the Division of Social Sciences. The Foundation began to search for opportunies to finance the social sciences, however, already in 1953. In 1958 it founded the Office of Social Sciences, which was changed into the Division alredy a year later (Lyons 1969: 272). Social sciences were accepted by politicians at last. As these examples show, political science was deeply dependent on the state of democracy in society. A general political climate had an impact also on individual scholars and universities as organizations. Political Science Scientific Culture. Scientific culture is tied to many ways to the general social, economic and political culture and development of a given country. Bernard Crick's thesis that American political science is based on a four-fold relationship between a common notion of science, the idea of a citizenhip training, the habits of democracy and a common belief in an inevitable progress (Crick 1959: xv) still merits attention. On the other hand, comparing the American and British political science, Andrew Hacker pointed out in the 1950s, how behavioralism was more natural for an American political scientist than for his/her British counterpart. British political scientists were at that time mainly library researchers. They could ignore the public, because they were judged by what they were rather than by what they did. On the contrary, in the United States there has always been a cultural requirement that the professor must "do" something. Although this is bound to lead to "productive scholarship" or as Benjamin Lippincott once remarked, to work which reminds "the compilation of a telephone directory" (Lippincott 1993: 157), the seeds for behavioral study of politics can be found in American culture. Organizations and Resources. Different universities played a different role in the rise of behavioralism. Usually one refers to the University of Chicago. The 'Chicago School of Political Science' led by Charles E. Merriam has been seen by many as a founder of the behavioralist movement in political science (Dahl 1961). Another kind of impact of the University of Chicago came after the World War II, when scholars from various disciplines joined together to develop an interdisciplinary behavioral science. Other forms of behavioral study of politics were developing elsewhere at the same time. The University of Michigan became a center for survey research. An important factor was the foundation the Survey Research Center in 1946, which became the Institute for Social Research in 1948 (Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 153). Later an event of utmost importance was the foundation of the Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research in 1962 Michigan as its homebase. It is important to notice, however, that the development was very uneven in different places and the spreading of behavioralism as dominant ideology of research was a long political process. Other organizations than universities played a major role in this process. A special importance has been given to the Social Science Research Council and its Committee on Political Behavior (Dahl 1961; Farr 1995). The Committee was founded in 1949 V.O. Key as its first chairman. The President of the Social Science Research Council at that time, Pendleton

Herring, has simply stated later that there was a spectrum of changing attitudes about the role of political science and the group "had an opportunity to articulate ideas that were developing, and it had the means to encourage and reward people who chose to work along lines that the committee was concerned with" (Pendleton Herring in Baer et al., eds. 1991: 34). The American Political Science Association as a peak organization of the discipline did also play an important role. Its impact was strengthened by the growth of the profession. In 1946 APSA had a membership of 4 000 which had risen to 14 000 in 1966 (Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 154). This growth in itself transformed a learned society to a professional organization. The result was that political scientists were now able to concentrate more easily on their own problems leaving social problems outside the profession (Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 151; 185). A good example is the attendance at the annual meetings of APSA. In the 1920s the registrants ranged between 127 and 292 and it was only in 1939 when there were over 1000 participants. Academic freedom. McCarthyism had a severe effect on the moulding of behavioralism (Easton 1985: 139-140; Farr 1995: 211). Some political scientists referred to this already in the 1950s, claiming that behavioralism provided a convenient escape from pressure from public appraisal and, because a behavioralist was "a liberal in his politics, but timid in his personality" he was ready to plunge into the behavioral stream, because he "who has not stuck his neck out cannot be attacked. And if he does question dominant values, he frequently does it in technical jargon and to a limited audience" (Hacker 1959: 40). These personal statements of scholars experiencing the everyday politics of the 1950s may also be corroborated by referring to studies on the impact of McCarthyism on academia. Paul F. Lazarsfeld's and Wagner Thielens, Jr.'s book "The Academic Mind: Social Scientists in a Time of Crisis" (1958) was a survey of over 2000 social scientists. Its results showed that "McCarthyism" really had an impact on academia. Many felt themselves under pressure (see also Diamond 1992). Individuals. The role of individuals is more complicated. Behavioralists have presented their own pedigree, which usually starts with Graham Wallas and Arthur F. Bentley, takes notice of Charles A. Beard and Walter Lippman, and then comes to Charles E. Merriam and the Chicago School of Political Science. However, there have also been conflicting arguments. The first one concerns the role of Charles E. Merriam and his younger colleagues Harold D. Lasswell and Harold F. Gosnell. For instance, Raymond Seidelman and Edward Harpham (1985) don't count Merriam and Lasswell as behavioralists, but as representatives of reform political science which was criticized by behavioralists at the beginning of the behavioral era. Another case with conflicting interpretations concerns the role of the migr scholars during the Second World War. Dahl (1961) and Somit and Tanenhaus (1982) have claimed that they provided the theoretical background for behavioralism, while John G. Gunnell (1993) has recently argued for a much more complex relationship between the migr scholars and American political science. Many of those who escaped from Europe became leading critics of empirical science of politics. Other Disciplines

The success of behavioralism would hardly have been possible without the development of survey methods, interviewing techniques and techniques of measurement (Truman 1955: 204209; Dahl 1961; Somit and Tanenhaus 1982; Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 152). On the other hand, many American universities were organized so that political scientists had an easy access to representatives of other disciplines, sociologists, social psychologists, etc. Compared to situation in other countries these other social sciences were well organised and intellectually developed. It was no wonder that interdisciplinary work took root in American universities, at least to some degree (Hacker 1959).

5. Explaining the Nature and Rise of Behavioralism


After the brief survey of the meaning of behavioralism and of major explanations for its birth, the concept still seems elusive. It is also hard to determine the exact weight of different explanations. It seems reasonable to agree with David Easton, however, that the concept of behavioral sciences was due both to the policy of the Ford Foundation (3) and to the conservative climate suspicious of anything reminding of socialism. On the other hand, it must be remembered that the concept of behavioralism was first used either in neutral or critical way, and it was only later that also behavioralists adopted it. Political climate shaped also the discourse on goals of the discipline. The debate on values became important when political scientists had to defend themselves (being liberal but neutral) against the threat both from the Right and from the Left (Gunnell 1993). But many of the tenets of behavioralism would have developed as well under some other label than behavioralism. The thirties and the New Deal, the Second World War and the Cold War had created the soscial context of American political science, behavioralist or not. And if we look at research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology of political science, all these basic components of any research tradition, were already pointing towards what came to be called behavioralism. A focus on an individual as a basic unit of analysis as well as an interest in empirical study of observable facts are both goals deeply grounded in American culture. The growing individualism of American society has nurtured methodological individualism and research areas dealing with the political behavior. The scientific study of politics is also a part of American culture. Important forerunners of behavioralism were the national conferences on the science of politics already in the 1920s. It was only that the development of statistical techniques gave new ammunition to this endeavor (4). And, as was pointed out earlier, behavioralism really was only a loose collection of different research traditions which converged in a number of points in order to advance their own special interests (5). As Evron M. Kirkpatrick wrote: "the term served as a sort of umbrella, capacious enough to provide a temporary shelter for heterogenous group united only by dissatisfaction with traditional political science" (Kirkpatrick 1962: 13). It has even been claimed that it was often difficult to distinguish true card-carriers in the behavioral movement from fellow-travelers, tolerant sympathizers, occasional supporters, or ambivalent critics (Easton 1962: 5). And recently Heinz Eulau has argued that:

"It seems to me that the practioners are less inclined than the bystanders to see this (behavioralism, E.B.) as a great divide in the discipline's history and tend to be more sensitive to the coexistence of novelties and continuities....I felt at the time, the historical, legal, or doctrinal approaches to the study of politics 'will persist....I have never believed that behavioralism occupied the hegemonic position attributed to it by some of its own advocates and by latter-day interpreters. The undue emphasis on behavioralism as 'revolution' has led to a biased neglect of theory and research that was not behavioral, though done in the 'behavioral era.'" (Eulau 1997: 585) It cannot be denied that in the 1950s and at the beginning of the 1960s the majority of American political scientists were doing something else than behavioral political science. International relations, American politics and government, comparative government, public administration and public law were all strong fields, and most of the scholars in those fields were not behavioralists. A good example is the Department of Political Science at the University of California (Berkeley), whose chairman from 1948 to 1956 was Peter Odegard. Odegard was a member of the Ford Foundation Study Committee from 1948 to 1950, but Odegard's own department was very strong in comparative politics and even in political theory (Watson 1961: 315-343). Although it is good to remember that most of the money from Ford Foundation went actually to international relations and comparative politics. How can all this be accounted for? The obvious paradox may be explained by the fact that most political scientists in the 1950s and the early 1960s occupied a position somewhere in the middle between behavioralism and traditionalism, but they were intuitively drawn more towards behavioralism. Albert Somit's and Joseph Tanenhaus's survey of the profession at the beginning of the 1960s shows this well. Using factor analysis to study the attitudes among political scientists, the single most important factor dividing the discipline was "behavioralism". However, only 10 percent of respondents identified themselves as behavioralists, although 22.6 percent felt that the most significant work within the discpline was being done by behavioralists. The other side of the coin was that there were 12.3 percent identifying themselves as political theorists, but only 9.9 percent felt political theory being a field of the most significant work. Furthermore, when asked which was the field of the least significant work, 7.8 percent said it was behavioral political science, but 32.4 percent thought that political theory had least significance in the discipline (Somit and Tanenhaus 1963: 939-942). The American political Science Review published also in 1956 a report on a Conference on Political Theory and the Study of Politics (Eckstein 1956), which indicated that there were a group of 'behaviorists' and 'anti-behaviorists' in the discipline, but a large majority were moderates between these two extreme groups. Much of the discussion in the conference dealt with a question of "how and why had the political 'philosophers' and the political 'scientists' managed to drift so far apart in their work when most of them were eager to concede that they had much to learn from one another?" and in the final analysis "our villain...was simply the 'behaviorist' - 'theorist' dichotomy" (Eckstein 1956: 486-487). Of course, there were real differences of opinion concerning methods of political science (explanation vs. understanding), its social role (training vs. cultivating) and its ultimate goal (scientific discipline vs. learned wisdom), but the underlying problem in many cases seemed

to be psychological and practical. People were interested in different problems and there was no real interest in the study of politics in totality. The problem was a political rather than an intellectual problem: "how to persuade the practioners in the field to develop a healthy interest and to acquire a healthy preparation in both political science and political philosophy." The 'behaviorists' were too current-events-conscious and the 'theorists' were not genuinely interested in political behavior. It seemed to be difficult to reach a compromise "between the study of Plato and the study of local government in Illinois" (Eckstein 1956: 485). Anyone familiar with political scientists knows that this is a real problem. Partly it is an ontological and epistemological problem. There are political scientists who are convinced that there exists "immortal" questions of politics, such as, freedom, equality and welfare, which can be studied out of historical context. And there are political scientists who are more interested in the immediate practical issues of politics which they confront in the everyday life. But one must distinguish the elite and the mass. The mass of American political scientists were doing what they had done before. It is no wonder that Charles E. Lindblom has recently noted that in the 1950s there was an amazing discrepancy between accepted scientific ideals and actual practice (Lindblom 1997: 233). The elite was defining the discourse. But the elite was not unanimous. Behavioralism consisted of at least two (still internally divided) research traditions: empirical theory and general theory. Empirical theory could be divided into those focusing on individuals proper (voting, public opinion) and those adhering to group approach. Those adhering to general theory, on the other hand, could be divided into various forms of systems theory - general systems theory, cybernetics, systems analysis, functionalism. This internal division in the ranks of behavioralism has not always been understood by all those writing about it (see, however, Farr and Seidelman, eds. 1993: 203). The division can be personalized using David Truman and David Easton as examples. Easton spoke mainly for the general theorists who found the established political science wanting. David Truman, on the other hand, spoke for those more empirically oriented researchers who had been influenced by Charles E. Merriam (Eulau 1969: 5). At the end, it was Truman's side who took command of the behavioral research. This was due to two things. First, Truman was a representative of a true elite within the discipline during behavioral era. For a number of reasons this elite was able to rise in the ranks of the profession in the 1950s and especially at the beginning of the 1960s (Waldo 1975: 61). Through their strategic positions, this key group of behavioralists was able to raise behavioralism into a legitimate and hegemonic position within the discipline at the beginning of the 1960s. Who should be counted as a member of this core group (elite), is a question which should be studied more carefully, but I would suggest that at least the following persons should be included: Pendleton Herring, Peter Odegard, V.O.Key, Jr., David Truman, Angus Cambell, Oliver Garceau, Alexander Heard, Avery Leiserson and Samuel J. Eldersveld. Many of them were members of the Committee on Political Behavior, while Herring and Odegard acted as key links to foundations. Herring was an executive associate of the Carnegie Corporation from 1846 to 1948 and Odegard was a member of the Ford Foundation Study Committee (1948-1950), which planned the Foundation's new activity for the social sciences. Both served also as President of the American Political Science Association (Odegard 1950-51, Herring 1952-53). Herring was also President of the Social Science Research Council over twenty

years (beginning in 1948). In many respects, however, the key person was V.O. Key, the first chairman of Social Science Research Council's Committee on Political Behavior. His good friends David B. Truman, Alexander Heard and Oliver Garceau still strengthened his position. It is good to point out two things. Most of these people were what is called empirical theorists and secondly, many of them had studied pressure groups (or parties). Another interesting thing is that those who wrote the most influencial writings about behavioralism (Robert A. Dahl, David Easton and Heinz Eulau) were somehow outside the core group (although Dahl was a close friend of Key). Maybe they were too much general theorists to fit in: "those who were particularly interested in quantification and the use of survey research were very critical of the work I was doing, which was very theoretical. They saw me as a person who was articulating a defense for them, but not as a practioner. And, although they accepted the importance of empirical theory, for them theory meant a much lower level of generalization than I was seeking. So those who criticized me as a behavioralist incarnate were driving me into the arms of the behavioralists, yet the behavioralists didn't have their arms wide open." (David Easton, in Baer et al., eds. 1991: 207) The division seems to have been also a question of different generations. Some of the oral histories of American political scientists (Baer, et. al., eds. 1991) point to this. Those born during the first decade of the 20th century were the first real generation of empirical students of politics (Charles Hyneman, Pendleton Herring, Belle Zeller, etc.). A generation born in the 1910s became, however, more theoretically oriented (e.g., Gabriel Almond, Robert A. Dahl and David Easton). A common experience for them was the depression of the 1930s. The generation born in the 1920s was again more empirical (and conservative) than the previous generation (e.g., Austin Ranney and Warren E. Miller). But the second fact has to be taken into account, too. The reason Truman's side became the core of behavioralism was due to the attitudes and opinions of the mass. And with the growth of the discipline the mass has become important organizationally (Ricci 1984). Positive towards behavioralism, but doing very traditional political science, these ordinary political scientists felt more close to Key's and Truman's concerete studies on American politics than to Easton's theoretical analysis. If I would have to make a summary of my argument about the nature of behavioralism and about its rise into an hegemonic position within American political science, I would use an analogy of American party politics. As American party politics consists of two major parties which are loose coalitions of different interests, so American political science has tended to create two opposing parties, whether it is traditionalists vs. behavioralists or behavioralists vs. postbehavioralists does not matter. These parties have been as undefinable as their counterparts in real political life. But they have caught the imagination of American political scientists, because American culture is dialectical. They have also formed identities as well as they have been vehicles in pursuing material interests. To better understand the nature and history of political science, it might be better, however, to forget behavioralism and postbehavioralism and look at the development of the discipline through different research traditions competing with each other.

6. The Legacy of Behavioralism

Terence Ball has recently (1993: 220-221) argued that behavioralism succeeded in the short run, because of succesful self-promotion, but in the long run it failed, because promises were made that could not be met. But, if the analysis in the previous chapter is correct, it doesn't matter whether behavioralism succeeded or not. An interesting thing to look, however, is which aspects of behavioralism have survived in the postbehavioral era and which have been lost. A few years ago Theodore Lowi (1992) claimed that American political science was dominated by three subfields of the discipline, public opinion, public choice and public policy. Of these only public opinion represented the old behavioral study of politics. If Lowi is correct, the first conclusion is that it is the individualistic perspective inherent in behavioralism that has been one of the survivors. Although the early behavioralism understood the importance of studying governmental structures and understood also socialization as an important element in moulding a person's attitudes and behavior, the basic methodological starting point was methodological individualism, because it was assumed that "collectivities do not exist apart from the conduct of their individual members" and "political behavior analysis is pre-eminently interested in determining the consequences of individual political behavior for the functioning of political institutions" (Eulau 1968: 205). A focus on individuals has also nurtured quantitative techniques. The early behavioralists were alraedy worried about this trend and, for example, V.O.Key used to warn that there is a danger that people stop asking good questions when methods are overemphasized (David Truman in Baer et al, eds., 1991: 148; cf. also David Easton in Baer et al., eds., 1991: 209). Both quantitative and qualitative analysis had their own place in research: "the approach cannot be limited to areas where the possibility of quantification is immediate. The student of political behavior cannot escape the obligation and must not deny himself the opportunity to ask important questions...simply because his answers must be more or less qualitative...he is obliged to perform his task in quantitative terms if he can and in qualitative terms if he must" (Truman 1951: 39). In regard to analyzing data with different nethods, American political science has really went into a wrong direction. Partly this may be due to the untheoretical nature of contemporary research. This untheoretical nature is tied to the major loss in behavioral legacy, forgetting the need for the integration of social knowledge. The idea has curiously disappeared. Here again the bureaucracy and special interests have been more powerful. The interdisciplinary idea never went through the ranks of ordinary political scientists (Geiger 1988: 332). At the beginning of the century there were also attempts to maintain close relations with all the social sciences, but already then the drift went away from this goal. As Albert Lepawsky has noted the new social science associations entered the twentieth century seeking to counteract their separateness. There were requests to a possible federation of associations, but "it was too late. The centrifugal forces in this phase of American life were stronger than the centripetal" (Lepawsky 1964: 52). And this has been the case ever since (the only success being the founding of the Social Science Research Council in 1924). This has galvanized also behavioralism. It is logical that the integration of the social sciences was not the major issue for the true behavioralist elite:

"The student of political behavior is concerned with the methods and concepts in other disciplines only to the extent that such tools contribute directly to a more meaningful statement of the phenomena of politics. The ultimate goal of the student of political behavior is the development of a science of the political process, logically complete within itself. Given the tremendous range and complexity of political data, such specialization is a continuing need...Many of the concerns of the other behavioral sciences are not thus relevant" (Truman 1951: 38-39). This attitude is completely different than David Easton's argument for the unity of behavioral sciences, which was, according to him, the real core of behavioralism. Arguing for the behavioral study of politics, Easton wrote that, "if all that behavioralists are arguing for is the introduction of scientific method and nothing more, why are we not content with calling a spade a spade?" (Easton 1965 :9) And Easton goes on to argue that the real meaning of behavioralism is (besides attention to empirical theory) "in locating stable units of analysis" (Easton 1965: 13) and "the key idea behind this approach has been the conviction that there are certain fundamental units of analysis relating to human behavior out of which generalizations can be formed and that these generalizations may provide a common sense on which the specialized sciences of man in society could be built" (Easton 1965: 14-15). Referring to attempts to find the most fruitful unit for a general social theory, Easton (1965: 15-21) refers to concepts such as action, the decision, functions, systems, power and groups. Although noting that in his own work he has "been exploring the utility of the system as the major unit, focusing on political life as a system of behavior operating within and responding to its social environment as it makes binding allocations of values" (Easton 1965: 21), he still leaves a door open for the best unit of analysis. Easton's real concern is a search for unified social knowledge. Easton has not dropped the idea. In his 1969 APSA presidential address he argued again that "social problems do not come neatly packaged as economic, psychological, political and the like. Our crises arise out of troubles that involve all aspects of human behavior" (Easton 1969: 1060). This time Easton proposed also the establishment of a Federation of Social Scientists to advance the integration of the social sciences. But no one seemed to notice this aspect of the new revolution in political science. The same has been the case with Easton's article on "The Political Science in the United States" in which Easton wrote: "in emphasizing the need to apply whatever knowledge we have to the solution of urgent social issues, we have already run into major difficulties in trying to reintegrate the various highly specialized disciplines....Application of knowledge to the social problems...requires the reassembly of the specialized knowledge of the various social sciences". (Easton 1985: 151) The need for integration of social sciences is a major legacy of behavioralism, but it has been forgotten as well by the majority of behavioralists as those criticizing it. The result has been the acceptance of the fragmentation of social knowledge as in the case of postmodernism. But the integration of social knowledge is as timely as it has always been. And this task doesn't require of finding any single concept that could unite the social sciences. It only requires that political, economic and social aspects of human behavior are theoretically linked together.

Individualism, quantification and fragmentation are the three major problems of social sciences today. Some have even claimed that they are behind our social crisis today (Dimock 1987; cf. also Bay 1965). To fight these tendencies of modern social science may be futile, but to be aware of these tendencies is the first requirement of forming ones's identity as a political scientist. To understand our identity we need a pluralist theory of scientific development.

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi