Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 48

Logic

2
What is logic?
Logic is an algebra for manipulating only two values:
true (T) and false (F)
Nevertheless, logic can be quite challenging
This topic will cover:
Propositional logic--the simplest kind
Predicate logic (a.k.a. predicate calculus)--an extension of
propositional logic
Resolution theory--a general way of doing proofs in predicate
logic
Possibly: Conversion to clause form
Possibly: Other logics (just to make you aware that they exist)
Propositional logic
4
Propositional logic
Propositional logic consists of:
The logical values true and false (T and F)
Propositions: Sentences, which
Are atomic (that is, they must be treated as indivisible units, with no
internal structure), and
Have a single logical value, either true or false
Operators, both unary and binary; when applied to logical
values, yield logical values
The usual operators are and, or, not, and implies
5
Useful binary operators
Here are the binary operators that are traditionally used:
Notice in particular that material implication () only
approximately means the same as the English word implies
All the other operators can be constructed from a combination
of these (along with unary not, )

X

Y
AND
X . Y
OR
X v Y
IMPLIES
X Y
BICONDITIONAL
X Y
T T T T T T
T F F T F F
F T F T T F
F F F F T T
6
Logical expressions
All logical expressions can be computed with some combination
of and (.), or (v), and not () operators
For example, logical implication can be computed this way:
Notice that X v Y is equivalent to X Y
X Y X X v Y X Y
T T F T T
T F F F F
F T T T T
F F T T T
7
Another example
Exclusive or (xor) is true if exactly one of its operands is true
Notice that (X.Y)v(X.Y) is equivalent to X xor Y
X Y X Y X . Y X . Y (X.Y)v(X.Y) X xor Y
T T F F F F F F
T F F T F T T T
F T T F T F T T
F F T T F F F F
8
Worlds
A world is a collection of prepositions and logical
expressions relating those prepositions
Example:
Propositions: JohnLovesMary, MaryIsFemale, MaryIsRich
Expressions:
MaryIsFemale . MaryIsRich JohnLovesMary
A proposition says something about the world, but
since it is atomic (you cant look inside it to see
component parts), propositions tend to be very
specialized and inflexible
9
Models
A model is an assignment of a truth value to each proposition, for
example:
JohnLovesMary: T, MaryIsFemale: T, MaryIsRich: F
An expression is satisfiable if there is a model for which the
expression is true
For example, the above model satisfies the expression
MaryIsFemale . MaryIsRich JohnLovesMary
An expression is valid if it is satisfied by every model
This expression is not valid:
MaryIsFemale . MaryIsRich JohnLovesMary
because it is not satisfied by this model:
JohnLovesMary: F, MaryIsFemale: T, MaryIsRich: T
But this expression is valid:
MaryIsFemale . MaryIsRich MaryIsFemale
10
Inference rules in propositional logic
Here are just a few of the rules you can apply when
reasoning in propositional logic:
From aima.eecs.berkeley.edu/slides-ppt, chs 7-9
11
Implication elimination
A particularly important rule allows you to get rid of the
implication operator, :
X Y X v Y
We will use this later on as a necessary tool for
simplifying logical expressions
The symbol means is logically equivalent to
12
Conjunction elimination
Another important rule for simplifying logical
expressions allows you to get rid of the conjunction
(and) operator, . :
This rule simply says that if you have an and operator at
the top level of a fact (logical expression), you can
break the expression up into two separate facts:
MaryIsFemale . MaryIsRich
becomes:
MaryIsFemale
MaryIsRich

13
Inference by computer
To do inference (reasoning) by computer is basically a search
process, taking logical expressions and applying inference
rules to them
Which logical expressions to use?
Which inference rules to apply?
Usually you are trying to prove some particular statement
Example:
it_is_raining v it_is_sunny
it_is_sunny I_stay_dry
it_is_rainy I_take_umbrella
I_take_umbrella I_stay_dry
To prove: I_stay_dry

14
Forward and backward reasoning
Situation: You have a collection of logical expressions
(premises), and you are trying to prove some additional
logical expression (the conclusion)
You can:
Do forward reasoning: Start applying inference rules to the
logical expressions you have, and stop if one of your results is
the conclusion you want
Do backward reasoning: Start from the conclusion you want,
and try to choose inference rules that will get you back to the
logical expressions you have
With the tools we have discussed so far, neither is
feasible
15
Example
Given:
it_is_raining v it_is_sunny
it_is_sunny I_stay_dry
it_is_raining I_take_umbrella
I_take_umbrella I_stay_dry
You can conclude:
it_is_sunny v it_is_raining
I_take_umbrella v it_is_sunny
I_stay_dry I_take_umbrella
Etc., etc. ... there are just too many things you can conclude!
Predicate Calculus
17
Predicate calculus
Predicate calculus is also known as First Order Logic
(FOL)
Predicate calculus includes:
All of propositional logic
Logical values true, false
Variables x, y, a, b,...
Connectives , , ., v,
Constants KingJohn, 2, Villanova,...
Predicates Brother, >,...
Functions Sqrt, MotherOf,...
Quantifiers , -
18
Constants, functions, and predicates
A constant represents a thing--it has no truth value,
and it does not occur bare in a logical expression
Examples: DavidMatuszek, 5, Earth, goodIdea
Given zero or more arguments, a function produces a
constant as its value:
Examples: motherOf(DavidMatuszek), add(2, 2),
thisPlanet()
A predicate is like a function, but produces a truth value
Examples: greatInstructor(DavidMatuszek),
isPlanet(Earth), greater(3, add(2, 2))
19
Universal quantification
The universal quantifier, , is read as for each
or for every
Example: x, x
2
> 0 (for all x, x
2
is greater than or equal to
zero)
Typically, is the main connective with :
x, at(x,Villanova) smart(x)
means Everyone at Villanova is smart
Common mistake: using . as the main connective with :
x, at(x,Villanova) . smart(x)
means Everyone is at Villanova and everyone is smart
If there are no values satisfying the condition, the result is true
Example: x, isPersonFromMars(x) smart(x) is true
20
Existential quantification
The existential quantifier, -, is read for some or
there exists
Example: -x, x
2
< 0 (there exists an x such that x
2
is less
than zero)
Typically, . is the main connective with -:
-x, at(x,Villanova) . smart(x)
means There is someone who is at Villanova and is smart
Common mistake: using as the main connective with -:
-x, at(x,Villanova) smart(x)
This is true if there is someone at Villanova who is smart...
...but it is also true if there is someone who is not at Villanova
By the rules of material implication, the result of F T is T
21
Properties of quantifiers
x y is the same as y x
-x -y is the same as -y -x

-x y is not the same as y -x
-x y Loves(x,y)
There is a person who loves everyone in the world
More exactly: -x y (person(x) . person(y) Loves(x,y))
y -x Loves(x,y)
Everyone in the world is loved by at least one person

Quantifier duality: each can be expressed using the other
x Likes(x,IceCream) -x Likes(x,IceCream)
-x Likes(x,Broccoli) x Likes(x,Broccoli)
From aima.eecs.berkeley.edu/slides-ppt, chs 7-9
22
Parentheses
Parentheses are often used with quantifiers
Unfortunately, everyone uses them differently, so dont be
upset at any usage you see
Examples:
(x) person(x) likes(x,iceCream)
(x) (person(x) likes(x,iceCream))
(x) [ person(x) likes(x,iceCream) ]
x, person(x) likes(x,iceCream)
x (person(x) likes(x,iceCream))
I prefer parentheses that show the scope of the quantifier
-x (x > 0) . -x (x < 0)
23
More rules
Now there are numerous additional rules we can apply!
Here are two exceptionally important rules:
x, p(x) -x, p(x)
If not every x satisfies p(x), then there exists a x that does
not satisfy p(x)
-x, p(x) x, p(x)
If there does not exist an x that satisfies p(x), then all x do
not satisfy p(x)
In any case, the search space is just too large to be
feasible
This was the case until 1970, when J. Robinson
discovered resolution
24
Interlude: Definitions
syntax: defines the formal structure of sentences
semantics: determines the truth of sentences wrt (with
respect to) models
entailment: one statement entails another if the truth of
the first means that the second must also be true
inference: deriving sentences from other sentences
soundness: derivations produce only entailed sentences
completeness: derivations can produce all entailed
sentences
Resolution
26
Logic by computer was infeasible
Why is logic so hard?
You start with a large collection of facts (predicates)
You start with a large collection of possible transformations
(rules)
Some of these rules apply to a single fact to yield a new fact
Some of these rules apply to a pair of facts to yield a new fact
So at every step you must:
Choose some rule to apply
Choose one or two facts to which you might be able to apply the rule
If there are n facts
There are n potential ways to apply a single-operand rule
There are n * (n - 1) potential ways to apply a two-operand rule
Add the new fact to your ever-expanding fact base
The search space is huge!
27
The magic of resolution
Heres how resolution works:
You transform each of your facts into a particular form,
called a clause (this is the tricky part)
You apply a single rule, the resolution principle, to a pair of
clauses
Clauses are closed with respect to resolution--that is, when you
resolve two clauses, you get a new clause
You add the new clause to your fact base
So the number of facts you have grows linearly
You still have to choose a pair of facts to resolve
You never have to choose a rule, because theres only one
28
The fact base
A fact base is a collection of facts, expressed in predicate
calculus, that are presumed to be true (valid)
These facts are implicitly anded together
Example fact base:
seafood(X) likes(John, X) (where X is a variable)
seafood(shrimp)
pasta(X) likes(Mary, X) (where X is a different variable)
pasta(spaghetti)
That is,
(seafood(X) likes(John, X)) . seafood(shrimp) .
(pasta(Y) likes(Mary, Y)) . pasta(spaghetti)
Notice that we had to change some Xs to Ys
The scope of a variable is the single fact in which it occurs

29
Clause form
A clause is a disjunction ("or") of zero or more literals,
some or all of which may be negated
Example:
sinks(X) v dissolves(X, water) v denser(X, water)
Notice that clauses use only or and notthey do
not use and, implies, or either of the quantifiers for
all or there exists
The impressive part is that any predicate calculus
expression can be put into clause form
Existential quantifiers, -, are the trickiest ones
30
Unification
From the pair of facts (not yet clauses, just facts):
seafood(X) likes(John, X) (where X is a variable)
seafood(shrimp)
We ought to be able to conclude
likes(John, shrimp)
We can do this by unifying the variable X with the constant
shrimp
This is the same unification as is done in Prolog
This unification turns seafood(X) likes(John, X) into
seafood(shrimp) likes(John, shrimp)
Together with the given fact seafood(shrimp), the final
deductive step is easy
31
The resolution principle
Here it is:
From X v someLiterals
and X v someOtherLiterals
----------------------------------------------
conclude: someLiterals v someOtherLiterals
Thats all there is to it!
Example:
broke(Bob) v well-fed(Bob)
broke(Bob) v hungry(Bob)
--------------------------------------
well-fed(Bob) v hungry(Bob)
32
A common error
You can only do one resolution at a time
Example:
broke(Bob) v well-fed(Bob) v happy(Bob)
broke(Bob) v hungry(Bob) happy(Bob)
You can resolve on broke to get:
well-fed(Bob) v happy(Bob) v hungry(Bob) v happy(Bob) T
Or you can resolve on happy to get:
broke(Bob) v well-fed(Bob) v broke(Bob) v hungry(Bob) T
Note that both legal resolutions yield a tautology (a trivially true
statement, containing X v X), which is correct but useless
But you cannot resolve on both at once to get:
well-fed(Bob) v hungry(Bob)
33
Contradiction
A special case occurs when the result of a resolution
(the resolvent) is empty, or NIL
Example:
hungry(Bob)
hungry(Bob)
----------------
NIL
In this case, the fact base is inconsistent
This will turn out to be a very useful observation in
doing resolution theorem proving
34
A first example
Everywhere that John goes, Rover goes. John is at
school.
at(John, X) at(Rover, X) (not yet in clause form)
at(John, school) (already in clause form)
We use implication elimination to change the first of
these into clause form:
at(John, X) v at(Rover, X)
at(John, school)
We can resolve these on at(-, -), but to do so we have
to unify X with school; this gives:
at(Rover, school)
35
Refutation resolution
The previous example was easy because it had very few
clauses
When we have a lot of clauses, we want to focus our
search on the thing we would like to prove
We can do this as follows:
Assume that our fact base is consistent (we cant derive NIL)
Add the negation of the thing we want to prove to the fact
base
Show that the fact base is now inconsistent
Conclude the thing we want to prove
36
Example of refutation resolution
Everywhere that John goes, Rover goes. John is at school.
Prove that Rover is at school.
1. at(John, X) v at(Rover, X)
2. at(John, school)
3. at(Rover, school) (this is the added clause)
Resolve #1 and #3:
4. at(John, X)
Resolve #2 and #4:
5. NIL
Conclude the negation of the added clause: at(Rover, school)
This seems a roundabout approach for such a simple example,
but it works well for larger problems
37
A second example
Start with:
it_is_raining v it_is_sunny
it_is_sunny I_stay_dry
it_is_raining I_take_umbrella
I_take_umbrella I_stay_dry
Convert to clause form:
1. it_is_raining v it_is_sunny
2. it_is_sunny v I_stay_dry
3. it_is_raining v I_take_umbrella
4. I_take_umbrella v I_stay_dry
Prove that I stay dry:
5. I_stay_dry



Proof:
6. (5, 2) it_is_sunny
7. (6, 1) it_is_raining
8. (5, 4) I_take_umbrella
9. (8, 3) it_is_raining
10. (9, 7) NIL
Therefore, (I_stay_dry)
I_stay_dry
Conversion to clause form
A nine-step process

Reference: Artificial Intelligence, by Elaine Rich and Kevin Knight
39
Running example
All Romans who know Marcus either hate Caesar or
think that anyone who hates anyone is crazy

x, [ Roman(x) . know(x, Marcus) ]
[ hate(x, Caesar) v
(y, -z, hate(y, z) thinkCrazy(x, y))]

40
Step 1: Eliminate implications
Use the fact that x y is equivalent to x v y

x, [ Roman(x) . know(x, Marcus) ]
[ hate(x, Caesar) v
(y, -z, hate(y, z) thinkCrazy(x, y))]

x, [ Roman(x) . know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v
(y, (-z, hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]
41
Step 2: Reduce the scope of
Reduce the scope of negation to a single term, using:
(p) p
(a . b) (a v b)
(a v b) (a . b)
x, p(x) -x, p(x)
-x, p(x) x, p(x)

x, [ Roman(x) . know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v
(y, (-z, hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]

x, [ Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v
(y, z, hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]
42
Step 3: Standardize variables apart
x, P(x) v x, Q(x)
becomes
x, P(x) v y, Q(y)
This is just to keep the scopes of variables from getting
confused
Not necessary in our running example
43
Step 4: Move quantifiers
Move all quantifiers to the left, without changing their
relative positions

x, [ Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v
(y, z, hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y)]

x, y, z,[ Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v
(hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]
44
Step 5: Eliminate existential quantifiers
We do this by introducing Skolem functions:
If -x, p(x) then just pick one; call it x
If the existential quantifier is under control of a universal
quantifier, then the picked value has to be a function of the
universally quantified variable:
If x, -y, p(x, y) then x, p(x, y(x))
Not necessary in our running example
45
Step 6: Drop the prefix (quantifiers)
x, y, z,[ Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v (hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]
At this point, all the quantifiers are universal quantifiers
We can just take it for granted that all variables are
universally quantified
[ Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v (hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]
46
Step 7: Create a conjunction of disjuncts
[ Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) ] v
[hate(x, Caesar) v (hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y))]

becomes

Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) v
hate(x, Caesar) v hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y)


47
Step 8: Create separate clauses
Every place we have an ., we break our expression up
into separate pieces
Not necessary in our running example
48
Step 9: Standardize apart
Rename variables so that no two clauses have the same
variable
Not necessary in our running example

Final result:
Roman(x) v know(x, Marcus) v
hate(x, Caesar) v hate(y, z) v thinkCrazy(x, y)

Thats it! Its a long process, but easy enough to do
mechanically

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi