Vous êtes sur la page 1sur 44

Cours d’Introduction à l’Histoire des Sciences 2022-2023 -Evaluation blanche

Sujet

Vous rédigerez un essai de synthèse critique sur le texte de Robert Westman extrait de The
Copernican Question. Prognostication, Skepticism, and Celestial Order, Presses de
l’Université de Californie, Berkeley, 2011. Le texte correspond au chapitre 3 de ce livre ; une
table des matières est fournie.

Vous trouverez un exemplaire imprimé de ce texte devant le bureau d’Annie Moulin, 4 e étage
du Bâtiment Olympe de Gouges.
Dégager > Thème du texte, Problématique(s) posée(s), Thèse(s) énoncée(s), corpus employé (sources et littérature qu'utilise l'auteur), Structure
Consignes de l'argumentation de la ou des thèses > comment les sources sont mobilisées, // pour la littérature.

L’objectif est de présenter les principaux arguments développés par l’auteur, de réfléchir aux
sources mobilisées et de vous interroger sur leur pertinence. C’est un exercice de synthèse et
de réflexion.

Votre essai doit être de l’ordre de 5 à 10 pages (entre 2.500 et 5.000 mots), rédigés en taille de
police 12, interligne 1,5. Vous l’enverrez au plus tard le 1er novembre 2022, aux adresses
mails suivantes : jb.grodwohl@gmail.com ; bonvoisin.clement@gmail.com

Conseils de méthode

Lisez le chapitre une première fois rapidement, en essayant de résumer chaque section en une
ligne afin de pouvoir ressaisir ensuite la progression générale de l’argumentation.

Reprenez ensuite les sections en détail afin d’isoler les éléments qui vous semblent
importants. Réfléchissez aux sources qui sont mobilisées et aux arguments que l’auteur
cherche à développer. Vos notes doivent vous permettre de dégager le thème du texte, la ou
les problématique(s) posée(s), la ou les thèse(s) énoncée(s), le corpus employé (quelles
sources ? quelles références ?), la structure de l'argumentation (résumer à grands traits les
arguments déployés pour étayer la thèse, ainsi que leur enchaînement ; ne pas oublier de
relever les pages où chaque argument est déployé), et comment le corpus est employé
(comment telle source est interprétée, comment le texte se positionne par rapport à la
littérature convoquée, etc.). Comparez les informations données dans les différentes sections.

Rédigez votre essai. Formellement, on attend :

1. Une introduction qui présente :


1.1. L’auteur, le texte ce qu'il a écrit, ou ce livre ce place dans sa carrière et par rapport aux autres ?
1.2. le thème du texte, la problématique posée, la thèse défendue par
l’auteur.
1.3. un plan du commentaire, qui expose la structure de votre
argumentation.

2. le commentaire en lui-même, qui est une sorte de résumé analytique du texte


: on explique (sans paraphraser) les arguments de l'auteur, sur quoi ils
s'appuient (sources ? références ?) et comment ils s'enchaînent
(éventuellement en rédigeant une partie par argument)
dans le commentaire, lorsque l'on fait des références à des argu précédents, préciser lignes/para pour
1 que ce soit clair pour le jury...
Si l'on veut intégrer la réflexion dans le commentaire au lieu de séparer en deux parties, on peut ... mais...à voir...

Liberté quant aux pronoms personnels utilisés dans le commentaire...


, et des comparaisons
personnelles avec d'autres auteurs
et d'autres époques passées et ou
difficultés d'approche futur...
3. une seconde partie réflexive qui identifie des difficultés, des aspects qui
mériteraient des développements ou des explications complémentaires. Cette
seconde partie vise à présenter ce que vous avez pensé du texte, si vous
identifiez des problèmes, des limites dans l'approche. Vous pourrez effectuer
des comparaisons avec d’autres textes sur le sujet (comme ceux qui sont vus
et discutés en cours) ou consulter les recensions critiques par les experts du
sujet dans la littérature spécialisée.

Gardez à l’esprit la règle : une idée (bien développée, bien étayée) par paragraphe, un
paragraphe par idée.

Pensez à bien illustrer votre propos à l’aide d’exemples.

Mettez vos sources en note de bas de page, avec le numéro de la page à laquelle vous vous
référez. On peut écrire le devoir à la main mais.. notes de bas de page...

Soignez votre expression (clarté, précision du vocabulaire, orthographe). Ce n’est pas un


exercice de restitution de connaissance : c’est un exercice qui doit permettre à votre lecteur de
comprendre le texte que vous présentez (ne supposez pas que le lecteur le connaît déjà), et de
suivre comment vous vous l’appropriez et le discutez.

Vous ne serez pas évalués sur votre capacité à avoir restitué tous les éléments du texte, mais
sur votre capacité à mettre en évidence les aspects essentiels à l’argumentation et à identifier
des aspects plus problématiques.

Ne soyez pas trop neutres dans votre exposé. C’est votre propos : c’est vous qui expliquez le
texte et le discutez.

2
Contents

List of Illustrations  /  xi ogers’ War  82  •  Pico against the As­t rol­
ogers  84  •  Domenico Maria Novara and
Preface and Acknowledgments  /  xv Copernicus in the Bologna Culture of Prog­
nostication  87  •  Prognosticators, Humanists,
Introduction  /  1 and the Sedici  93  •  Copernicus, Assistant
The Historical Problematic  1  •  Summary and Witness  96  •  The Averroists and the
and Plan of This Work  9  •  Categories of Order of Mercury and Venus  99  •  Coperni­-
Description and Explanation  17 cus’s Commentariolus or, Perhaps, the Theoric
of Seven ­Postulates  100  •  Copernicus, Pico,
and De Revolutionibus  103
i Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities
1. The Literature of the Heavens and the ii Confessional and Intercon­fessional
Science of the Stars  /  25 Spaces of Prophecy and Prognostication
Printing, Planetary Theory, and the Genres
of Forecast  25  •  Copernicus’s Exceptional- 4. Between Wittenberg and Rome
ism  28  •  Practices of Classifying Heavenly The New System, Astrology, and the End
Knowledge and Knowledge Makers  29  •  The of the World  /  109
Science of the Stars  34  •  The Career of the
Theorica/Practica Distinction  40  •  Theoretical Melanchthon, Pico, and ­Naturalistic Divina-
Astrology: From the Arabic to the Reformed, tion  110  •  Rheticus’s Narratio Prima in the
Humanist Tetrabiblos  43  •  The Order of the Wittenberg-Nuremberg Cultural Orbit  114  •
Planets and Copernicus’s Early Formation  48  • ​ World-Historical Proph­ecy and Ce­lestial Revolu-
Copernicus’s Problematic: The Unresolved tions  118  •  Celestial Order and Necessity  121  •
Issues  55 Necessity in the Con­sequent  122  • ​The Astron-
omy without Equants  126  •  Principles versus
Tables with­out Demonstrations  127  •  The
2. Constructing the Future  /  62 Publication of De Revolutionibus: Osiander’s “Ad
The Annual Prognostication  62  •  The ­Lectorem”  128  • ​Holy Scripture and Celestial
Popular Verse Prophecies  66  •  Sites of Order  130  •  De Revolutionibus: Title and ­Prefatory
Prognostication  70 Material  133  • ​The “Principal Consideration”  139

3. Copernicus and the Crisis of the Bologna 5. The Wittenberg Interpretation


Prognosticators, 1496–1500  /  76 of Copernicus’s Theory  /  141
The Bologna Period, 1496–1500: An Undisturbed Melanchthon and the Science of the Stars at
View  76  •  From the Krakow Collegium Maius Wittenberg  143  •  The Melanchthon Circle,
to the Bologna Studium Generale  77  • ​Bologna Rheticus, and Albertine Patronage  144  •  Rheti-
and the “Horrible Wars of Italy”  78  • ​The Astrol- cus, Melanchthon, and Copernicus: A Psycho­
dynamic Hypothesis  147  •  Erasmus Reinhold, cal and Eschatological Meanings of Comets  252  • ​
Albrecht, and the Formation of the Wittenberg The Language, Syntax, and Credibility of Com-
Interpretation  150  •  The Prutenic Tables, Pa­ etary Observation  253  • ​Place and Order, the
tronage, and the Organization of Heavenly Litera- Comet and the Cosmos: Gemma, Roeslin, Maest­lin,
ture  158  • ​The Consolidation of the Wittenberg and Brahe  254  • ​Con­c lusion  257
Interpretation  160  •  The Advanced Curriculum
at Wittenberg  164  •  Germany as the “Nursery 9. The Second-Generation Copernicans
of Mathematics”  168  •  Conclusion  169 Maest­lin and Digges  /  259
Michael Maest­lin: Pastor, Academic, Mathemati-
6. Varieties of Astrological
cus, Copernican  259  • ​Maest­lin’s Hesitations
Credibility  /  171
about Astrology  262  • ​The Practice of Theoriz-
Marking the Dangers of Human Foreknowl- ing: Maest­lin’s Glosses on Copernicus  264  • ​
edge  171  •  Becoming a Successful Prognosti­ Thomas Digges: Gentleman, Mathe­matical Prac­
cator  172  •  Multiplying Genitures  174  • ​From titioner, Platonist, Copernican  268  • ​Digges on
Wittenberg to Louvain: Astrological Credi­bility and Copernicus in Wings or Ladders  270  • ​(Re)Clas-
the Copernican Question  178  • ​John Dee and sifying the Star  272  • ​The Mathema­ticians’
Louvain: Toward an Optical Reformation of Astrol- Court  272  • ​Reorganizing Copernicus  273  • ​
ogy  183  •  Jofrancus Offusius’s Semi-Ptolemaic Thomas Digges’s Infinite Universe “Augmenta-
Solution to the Variation in Astral Powers  185  • tion” in Leonard Digges’s Prognosti­cation Euer-
Skirting the Margins of Dangerous Divination  190 lastinge  275  • ​The Plummet Passage  278  • ​
Conclusion  279
7. Foreknowledge, Skepticism, and Celestial
Order in Rome  /  194 10. A Proliferation of Readings  /  281
De Revolutionibus at the Papal Court: A Stillborn The Emergence of a Via Media  281  • ​Along
(Negative) Reaction  194  •  The Holy Index the Via Media: Tycho’s Progress  286  • ​Nego­
and the Science of the Stars  197  •  Making tiating the Spheres’ Ontology  288  • ​Rothmann’s
Orthodoxy: Learned Advice from Trent  199  • Transformation and the First Copernican Contro-
Astrology, Astronomy, and the Certitude of versy  290  • ​Giordano Bruno: “Accademico di
Mathematics in Post-Tridentine Heavenly Sci- nulla Accademia detto il Fastidito”  300  • ​Bruno’s
ence  202  •  The Jesuits’ “Way of Proceeding”: Visual, Pythagorean Reading of Copernicus  301  • ​
The Teaching Ministry, the Middle Sciences, Bruno and the Science of the Stars  305
Astrology, and Celestial Order  204  • ​Clavius
on the Order of the Planets  209  • ​Disciplinary iv Securing the Divine Plan
Tensions  213  • ​Astronomy in a Hexameral
Genre: Robert Bellarmine  217 11. The Emergence of Kep­ler’s Copernican
Representation  /  309
iii Accommodating Unanticipated, The Copernican Situation at the End of the
Singular Novelties 1580s  309  • ​Counterfactual Kep­ler  311  • ​
Kep­ler’s Copernican Formation at Tübingen,
8. Planetary Order, Astronomical Reform, 1590–1594  314  • ​Kep­ler’s Shift in the Astrono-
and the Extraordinary Course of mer’s Role  316  • ​Kep­ler’s Physical-Astro­logical
Nature  /  223 Problematic and Pico  320  • ​Dating Kep­ler’s
Encounter with Pico: A Tübingen Scenario?  321  • ​
Astronomical Reform and the Interpretation of
The Gold Nugget  323  • ​Prognosticating (and
Celestial Signs  223  • ​The New Piconians  226  • ​
Theorizing) in Graz  324  • ​Kep­ler’s Copernican
Mistrusting Numbers  228  • ​The Rise of the
Cosmography and Prognostication  325  • ​The
Theoretical Astronomer and the “Science” of the
Divine Plan, Archetypal Causes, and the Begin-
New Star of 1572  230  • ​The Generic Location of
ning of the World  328  • ​From Kep­ler’s Polyhe-
the New Star  234  • ​Court Spaces and Networks:
dral Hypothesis to the Logical and Astronomical
Uraniborg, Hapsburg Vienna and Prague  236  • ​
Defense of Copernicus  331
Hagecius’s Polemic on the New Star  240  • ​An
Emergent Role for a Noble Astronomer: Tycho
Brahe and the Copenhagen Oration  243  • ​Tycho 1 2. Kep­ler’s Early Audiences, 1596–1600  /  336
and Pico, Generic and Named Adversaries  245  • ​ The Mysterium Cosmographicum: The Space of
The Tychonian Problematic, 1574  247  • ​A Tychonic Reception  336  • ​The Tübingen Theologians
Solution to Pico’s Criticism? Naibod’s Circumsolar and the Duke  337  • ​The German Academic
Ordering of Mercury and Venus  248  • ​The Comet Mathematicians: Limnaeus and Praetorius  339  • ​
of 1577 and Its Discursive Space  250  • ​Astrologi- Kep­ler’s Mysterium and the Via Media Group  341
v Conflicted Modernizers at the Turn 17. Modernizing Theoretical Knowledge

of the Century Patronage, Reputation, Learned Sociability,


Gentlemanly Veracity  /  434
13. The Third-Generation Copernicans Theoretical Knowledge and Scholarly Reputa-
Galileo and Kep­ler  /  353 tion  434  • ​Patron-Centered Heavenly Knowl-
edge  436  • ​Patronage at the Periphery: Galileo
Galileo and the Science of the Stars in the Pisan and the Aristocratic Sphere of Learned Sociabil-
Period  353  • ​Galileo and the Wittenberg and Ura- ity  440  • ​Florentine Court Sociabilities  442  • ​
niborg-Kassel Networks  355  • ​Galileo on Coper- Galileo’s Decision to Leave Padua for Flor-
nicus: The Exchange with Mazzoni  356  • ​Galileo ence  447  • ​Stabilizing the Telescopic Novel-
and Kep­ler: The 1597 Exchange  357  • ​Galileo as ties  448  • ​Conclusion: Gentlemanly Truth
a “Maest­linian”  360  • ​Paduan Sociabilities: The Tellers?  454
Pinelli Circle and the Edmund Bruce Episode, 1599–
1605  362  • ​1600: Bruno’s Exe­cution  366  • ​1600:
18. How Galileo’s Recurrent Novelties
William Gilbert’s Project for a Magnetical Philoso-
phy  368  • ​The Quarrel among the Modernizers: Traveled  /  455
New Convergences at the Fin de Siècle  374  • ​ The Sidereus Nuncius, the Nova Controversies, and
Galileo’s Silence about Bruno  375  • ​Galileo’s First Galileo’s “Copernican Silence”  455  • ​Through
Run-In with the In­quisition  376  • ​The Coperni- a Macro Lens: The Reception of the Sidereus Nun-
can Problematic and Astrological Theorizing after cius and the Telescope, Mid-March to Early May
Bruno’s Trial  376  • ​Kep­ler’s Continuing Search 1610  457  • ​Kep­ler’s Philosophical Conversation
for Astrology’s Foundations  378 with Galileo and His Book  460  • ​Galileo’s Nego-
tiations with the Tuscan Court, May 1610  465  • ​
14. The Naturalist Turn and Celestial Order Virtual Witnessing, Print, and the Great Resis-
Constructing the Nova of 1604  /  382 tance  468  • ​Magini’s Strategic Retreat and the
7/11 Problem  476  • ​Galileo and Kep­ler: The
The Predicted Conjunction of the Three Superior Denouement  477  • ​Scottish Sci­entific Diplo-
Planets and the Unforeseen Nova of 1604  382  • ​ macy: John Wedderburn’s Confutatio  481  • ​
Galileo and the Italian Nova Controversies  384  • ​ Galileo’s Novelties and the Jesuits  481
Honor and Credibility in the Capra Contro-
versy  389  • ​Galileo and Kep­ler’s Nova  391  • ​
Conclusion. The Great
Celestial Natural Philosophy in a New Key: Kep­
ler’s De Stella Nova and the Modernizers  393  • ​ Controversy  /  485
The Possibility of a Reformed Astrological Theoric: Astrological Prognostication and Astronomical
Kep­ler for and against Pico (Again)  395  • ​The Revolution  486  • ​Copernicans and Master-
Copernican Question in the Stella Nova: Kep­ler Disciple Relations  487  • ​Seventeenth-Century
for Gilbert, against Tycho  398  • ​Making Room: Thoughts about Belief Change  488  • ​The End
Kep­ler between Wacker von Wackenfels and Tycho of the Long Sixteenth Century  489  • ​The Era
Brahe  399  • ​Generating the Nova: Divine Action of Consolidation: World Systems and Comparative
and Material Necessity  400  • ​Summary and Probability  492  • ​From Philosophizing Astro­
Conclusion  401 nomer-Astrologers to New-Style Natural Philoso-
phers  495  • ​Weighing Probables: The Via Mod-
15. How Kep­ler’s New Star Traveled erna versus the Via Media at Midcentury  499  • ​
to England  /  403 The Copernican Question after Midcentury  501  • ​
Robert Hooke, Isaac Newton, and the Crucial
Kep­ler’s Star over Germany and Italy  403  • ​ Experiment  504  • ​The Copernican Question:
Kep­ler’s English Campaign  404 Closure and Proof  510

vi The Modernizers, Recurrent Notes  /  515


­Novelties, and Celestial Order Bibliography  /  605
16. The Struggle for Order  /  419 Index  /  649
The Emergent Problematic of the Via Mo-
­­der­na  419  • ​Many Roads for the Modernizers:
The Social Disunity of Copernican Natural Phi-
losophy  423  • ​Along the Via Moderna  426  • ​
Conclusion  433
3

Copernicus and the Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators,


1496–1500

Copernicus was involved in a culture of astrological edge of astronomical theory, acquired at the feet
prognosticators during his student years in Bolo- of his Krakovian masters. During his four years
gna. Although not a single word about astrology has of study at Bologna, he made the acquaintance of
survived in his writings, a great deal can be said the astronomer Domenico Maria Novara (1454–
about the specific circumstances that framed his 1504).1 According to some historians, Copernicus
involvement with that subject as a local practice. In- studied with Novara and helped him (in some
deed, much can be learned about various elements unknown way) to make celestial observations.
that shaped his early problematic and that pertain Most significantly, Novara first acquainted the
to questions unresolved in chapter 1: his map of young Polish astronomer with difficulties in
knowledge domains, the cluster of major questions Ptolemy’s theories, notably an apparent shift in
that preoccupied him for the rest of his life, why the the direction of the terrestrial pole. This anomaly
ordering of Venus and Mercury became a matter is alleged to have stimulated his own ideas about
demanding of solution, and his concern with the moving the Earth.2 According to others, Novara’s
period-distance rule. The four years that Coperni- critique of Ptolemy arose from Neoplatonic and
cus spent in Bologna were a critical phase of his Neopythagorean sources to which he had been
formative intellectual period. During this time, the exposed through the Platonic Academy of Flor-
prognosticators were under serious pressure both ence.3 Copernicus’s complaints about the old
to justify their forecasts and to defend the theoreti- world system—both the Ptolemaic equant mech-
cal foundations of their practice against the massive anism and the ordering of the planets—were
criticisms of Pico della Mirandola. All the astronom- then thought to have arisen from the same intel-
ical and physical considerations that historians have lectual ground.4
emphasized are relevant to this account; but Coper- Given how little is known about Copernicus’s
nicus’s problematic makes more sense when one in­ short time in Bologna, it seems legitimate to ask
corporates astrological practice into the story. More how one can justify an entire chapter devoted to
broadly, these conclusions suggest how we might this period of his life. My first contention is that
make sense of the subsequent evolution of the Co- there is more to Copernicus’s relationship with
pernican question into the seventeenth century. Novara than hitherto has been appreciated. A
great deal of very admirable work has been done
The Bologna Period, 1496–1500 by positivist historians, such as Carlo Malagola,
An Undisturbed View Leopold Prowe, and Ludwik Birkenmajer. But
earlier historiographical presuppositions about
The usual story is that Copernicus went to Italy what was useful and “scientific” or dismissible
in 1496 to study law. He came with some knowl- and “superstitious” in Novara’s writings effec-

76
24. Domenico Maria Novara. Un-
known eighteenth-century artist and
cherub. Raccolta iconografica, vol. 12,
fascicle 13, no. 58. Courtesy Biblio-
teca Communale Ariostea, Ferrara.

tively hid a great deal of information about the From the Krakow Collegium
Bolognese master. These assumptions also seem Maius to the Bologna Studium
to have inhibited the study of Novara’s extant
Generale
writings, which were all astrological in charac-
ter. My second contention, which is far more Nicolaus Copernicus arrived in the fall of 1496 at
ambitious, is that Domenico Maria Novara—and the old Bologna studium generale—the medieval
through him, Copernicus—were part of a flour­ term by which the university was still known—
ishing community of prognosticators in Bologna.5 to receive instruction in “both laws,” civil and
A better appreciation of that culture is needed canon. With three years of arts study at Krakow
to understand the circumstances that framed between 1491 and 1494 (but no degree), he prob-
the motivation of Copernicus’s astronomical ably arrived with some competence in Peurbach’s
project. New Theorics. The main Krakovian teachers were

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 77


intimately familiar with theoric. John of Glogau from that of many Polish students in the fifteenth
had composed a commentary on the old Theorics century who attended the Italian universities to
of Gerard of Cremona; his pupil Albert of Bru­ pursue legal or medical studies, although there
d­zewo, as noted in chapter 1, was the first to com- was ample precedent for Krakow professors’ hav-
ment on Peurbach.6 Moreover, both Glogau and ing studied astronomy at Bologna.11 Copernicus’s
Brudzewo are known to have issued annual prog- uncle, Lukas Watzenrode (1447–1512), had him-
nostications; thus it would be very surprising if self studied canon law at Bologna between 1469
Copernicus had not been acquainted with one or and 1473, eventually receiving a doctorate in that
more of their forecasts.7 Whether Copernicus subject, and had then proceeded to amass a large
himself engaged in any prognosticatory activi- number of wealth-yielding prebends and sine-
ties at Krakow, however, is unknown. The only cures.12 Copernicus, however, showed no inclina-
extant book from his library that could date to tion to follow the same ambitious path even after
the Krakow period and that suggests direct fa- he returned to Poland. For the rest of his life, he
miliarity with astrological theory is Haly Aben- enjoyed the modest economic security of a can-
ragel’s In judiciis astrorum. Copernicus’s copy of onry and an absentee teaching post or scholastry
this work is bound with Euclid’s Elements.8 Fi- at Vratislavia (Wrocław) arranged by his uncle.
nally, just as Copernicus arrived in Bologna, Regio­ Soon after coming to the Bologna studium,
montanus’s Epitome of the Almagest was published however, Copernicus became associated with the
in Venice. senior master of astronomy in a capacity that pre-
Although both Krakow and Bologna were supposed astronomical competences in the
major sites of annual prognostication, Coperni- sphere and theorics acquired during his liberal
cus’s formal choice of curriculum at Bologna was arts training at Krakow. The most reliable state-
associated directly with his decision to follow in ment that we possess occurs in Rheticus’s Nar-
his uncle’s footsteps as a church administrator or ratio Prima, written during 1539 while he was
canon. The legal statutes of the Varmia chapter staying with Copernicus in Frombork (Frauen-
of the Church clearly decreed that any newly ad- berg). “My teacher made observations with the
mitted canon should receive at least three years’ utmost care at Bologna, where he was not so
training in one of the higher faculties of “some much the pupil as the assistant and witness of
preeminent studium,” unless he be already a the learned Dominicus Maria.”13 Precisely be-
“Master or Bachelor of Sacred Letters or a Doctor cause it was made in passing, Rheticus’s allusion
of Medicine or Licentiate in Physic or the Decre- should be taken very seriously. If Copernicus was
tals [i.e., Canon] or Civil law.”9 These stipulations an “assistant and witness” rather than a “pupil”
make sense when it is recalled that theology, law, of Novara, then his primary relationship to the
and medicine were the three superior faculties latter was not mainly an academic association in
beyond the bachelor of arts degrees in the medi- which texts were read and commented on but
eval university structure. rather some kind of joint practice. That associa-
In the pre-Reformation Italian city-states, how- tion is the main subject of this chapter.
ever, there were no theology faculties of the sort
to be found in the transalpine universities. The- Bologna and the
ology instruction occurred inside the houses of “Horrible Wars of Italy”
religious orders, usually mendicant orders (Do-
minicans and Franciscans), and sometimes at The city of Bologna at the end of the fifteenth
episcopal palaces or secular colleges. Although century was not a sleepy university town. Coper-
the corporations or universitates of law and medi- nicus arrived at a moment of extraordinary politi-
cine elected student rectors and therefore had a cal crisis for the delicately balanced Italian city-
significant role in university governance, the col- state system, of which the Church territories
legia theologorum were, at best, examining boards were a significant part. The city had a mixed gov-
run by mendicant friars, in which secular clergy ernment, ruled both by the Bentivoglio family
had no part.10 and by the pope through his legate. The Benti­
Copernicus and his uncle followed a curricu- voglio, like the rulers of other Italian city-states,
lar path that involved no formal degree in theol- such as Ferrara, Mantua, or Urbino, were a fam-
ogy. Indeed, their education was no different ily of mercenary captain-princes or condotierre.14

78 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


Only Giovanni I (d. 1402) had ruled legally. Sante alliance broke up as soon as the king retreated,
Bentivoglio (d. 1463) ruled de facto through a showing how weak and opportune were the ties,
small group of powerful patrician families known and Venice now joined the new French king,
as the Sedici Riformatori dello Stato di Libertà Louis XII (r. 1498–1515), in the same year.
or Regimento. This senatorial body, however, had A few years after Copernicus left Bologna, the
been forced to share power with papal suzer- governo misto collapsed. Pope Julius II (1503–13)
ainty.15 It was Giovanni II (1443–1508), the last exploited the French presence to undermine the
of the Bentivoglio despots, who maintained for independent states of Romagna and Ancona and
most of his reign a workable balance between to assert papal hegemony. Bologna’s mixed gov-
the commune’s republican institutions—which ernance and Bentivoglio despotic rule came
he controlled—and papal interests, represented under intense pressure.17 In October 1506, Julius
by its legate on the Sedici. This body met every exercised a prerogative already established by the
day in the Palazzo del Commune, with the legate medieval popes. He issued a bull putting Bolo-
and Giovanni present. Its broad functions in- gna under interdict, an action designed to foment
cluded appointing and communicating with dip- popular opposition by forbidding priests to ad-
lomatic envoys, hiring mercenaries, sentencing minister the sacraments. The senate protested,
exiles, balancing the budget, and regulating all but as the interdict took effect, the churches
matters associated with morals, public health, began to shut down, and the religious orders de-
commerce, building, and food supply. It also had parted. The handwriting was on the wall. The
the task of wooing professors to the university French now entered Bolognese territory at Castel-
from other institutions, making appointments, franco. Giovanni Bentivoglio was isolated; he
and establishing salaries.16 The ruler himself, received no support from either the dukes of
moreover, might intervene to settle intramural Ferrara or the Florentines. Julius II told Niccolò
political disputes at the university, rule on the Machiavelli that Giovanni Bentivoglio could ei-
granting of free degrees, or play a role in bring- ther surrender directly into papal hands or leave
ing scholars to Bologna from other places. the city. When the French king offered him asy-
Just prior to Copernicus’s arrival, these arrange­ lum in Milan, he accepted. On the morning of
ments were already under the shadow of threat- November 2, the Bentivoglio family and their sup­
ening clouds. In September 1494, the French porters gathered in the main piazza and, with
Valois king, Charles VIII (r. 1483–98), passed some five hundred horses (and, as a chronicler
into Italy, marching down the western coastal wrote, amid much weeping and sighing), rode
region at the head of a massive, tightly unified out of Bologna, with safe passage through the
army of thirty thousand men. It was the largest French lines.18
such military force to appear in centuries, and it On November 11, 1506, the pope made his tri-
assisted in promoting Charles’s imperial, messi- umphal entry. The Bentivoglio palace was razed,
anic image. Within a few months he had taken and the pope immediately began construction of
Milan and Pisa, and when he entered Florence, a new fortress, for which Michelangelo was called
the reigning Medici family fled. By January 1495, upon to make a large bronze statue of Julius.
Charles was advancing on Rome; by late Febru- The effect on the university was almost as severe
ary, he was in Naples. These French successes al- as on the palace. The university closed for two
lowed other Italian states to take advantage of the months. Many students left. A substantial num-
imbalance of power. Venice, already more power- ber of rhetoricians and poets, whose fate and sta-
ful than the other states, profited the most. It was tus had been tied to the Bentivoglio court, left for
involved in the formation of several military co- other universities.19 Shortly after the invasion, a
alitions. The first of these leagues joined the duke German student in Bologna wrote to a friend: “In
of Milan, the Venetian Republic, and pope Alex- Bologna I myself saw pestilence, an earthquake,
ander VI, together with the great foreign poten- high food prices, and every kind of distressing
tates Ferdinand, king of Aragon and Maximilian condition; and fortune spared me so that I might
I, the Hapsburg emperor. Reinforced by Spanish also see war, internal dissension, and three changes
and Venetian naval power, this so-called Holy of government of Bologna in as many days. I
League forced Charles to retreat north to Milan, hope that all of these things will at some time be
where he suddenly died of a stroke in 1498. The of no little use to me.”20

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 79


25. Italy at the time of the French
invasion, 1494. From Guicciardini
1969. Courtesy of Princeton Uni­
versity Press.

Copernicus had missed the worst of these papal military expeditions.21 Copernicus left Bo-
events. A humanistic culture centered on the logna in the spring of 1500 and, according to
Bentivoglio palace flourished throughout his stay Rheticus, appeared at Rome as a “public lecturer
in Bologna. But he would certainly have been on mathematical subjects before a large audience
aware of the threat of disorder during the entire of students and also to a circle of great men and
period of his studies. The time he spent in Bolo- to craftsmen skilled in this kind of learning.”22
gna was a time of considerable troop movements This is, unfortunately, all that we know of his
in the duchies of Milan and Ferrara and espe- visit. When Copernicus returned to pursue med-
cially in the Republic of Florence. It was also a ical studies at Padua between 1501 and 1503, the
period when the Bentivoglio were engaged in al- French were still consolidating their control of
most constant secret negotiations with the the north and the Spaniards claiming the south,
French, and Girolamo Savonarola was burned at and the situation in Bologna was already worsen-
the stake in Florence. The year 1500 was a jubilee ing. The final collapse occurred only after he had
or holy year, and Rome had throngs of visitors returned to Varmia and had finally obtained a
who came to buy indulgences, some of the pro- doctoral degree in canon law at the University of
ceeds from which were used to finance future Ferrara in May 1503.

80 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


The long-term consequences of the develop- macy. Writing retrospectively, Guicciardini said
ments that were just beginning during Coper- that the prognosticators’ correct predictions of
nicus’s student days were profound. Although the invasion agreed with the unnatural, mon-
class, family, and status rivalries already charac- strous effects associated with the disorderliness
terized the medieval Italian cities, within a few of the king’s body:
short years the French invasions significantly
changed the balance of power not only in Bologna The very heavens and mankind concurred in pre-
but in Italy and in Europe at large.23 The real victor dicting the future woes of Italy. For those whose
profession it is to foretell the future by means of
in the thirty-six-year “Italian wars” would be the
skilled knowledge or divine inspiration [o per scien-
Holy Roman Empire, which emerged in 1530 under
tia, o per afflato divino]29 unanimously affirmed that
Charles V (1519–56) with a dynastic union with more frequent and greater changes were in store,
Aragon and vastly larger resources of soldiers, and stranger and more horrible events were about to
equip­ment, and money than the French had.24 occur than had been seen in any part of the world
Francesco Guicciardini (1483–1540), the skilled for many centuries. With no less terror did rumors
Florentine diplomat, vividly captured these spread everywhere that in various parts of Italy
changes in his famed Storia d’Italia, composed in there had appeared things alien to the usual course
the late 1530s. The French passage into Italy, he of nature and the heavens. In Puglia one night,
said, “not only gave rise to changes of dominions, three suns appeared in the sky, surrounded by
subversions of kingdoms, desolation of countries, clouds, and with frightful thunder and lightning. In
destruction of cities and the cruelest massacres, the territory of Arezzo an infinite number of armed
but also [to] new fashions, new customs, new and men on enormous horses were seen for many days
bloody ways of waging warfare, and diseases [nota- passing through the air with a terrible clamor of
drums and trumpets. In many places in Italy the sa-
bly syphilis] which had been unknown up to that
cred images and statues had openly sweated. Every-
time. Furthermore, his [Charles VIII’s] incursion
where monsters of men and other animals were
introduced so much disorder into Italian ways
being born. Many other things beyond the usual
of governing and maintaining harmony, that we course of nature had happened in various sections:
have never since been able to re-establish order, whence the people were filled with unbelievable
thus opening the possibility to other foreign na- dread, frightened as they already were by the fame
tions and barbarous armies to trample upon our of French power and by the ferocity of that nation
institutions and miserably oppress us.”25 which had already marched across all of Italy.  .  .  .
Guicciardini attributed the great disorder that People were only surprised that amid so many prod-
Charles wrought to his monstrously unnatural igies there did not appear a comet which the an-
body and personal character: “Charles, from boy- cients reputed to be an unfailing messenger of the
hood on, was of very feeble constitution and un- mutation of kingdoms and states.30
healthy body, short in stature, very ugly (aside
from the vigor and dignity of his eyes), and his Guicciardini’s representation of the invasions
limbs so ill-proportioned that he seemed more made use of and elevated the importance of the
like a monster than a man. Not only was he with- prognosticators and their profession. But in addi-
out any learning and skill but he hardly knew the tion, Guicciardini, narrating his account many
letters of the alphabet; a mind yearning greedily years after the events, took for granted a distinc-
to rule but capable of doing anything but that, tion between two classes of prognosticators:
since he was always surrounded by courtiers over those who based their forecasts on learned disci-
whom he maintained neither majesty nor author- plines (per scientia) and those who claimed to
ity.”26 This trope of disorder served Guicciardini’s foretell the future by means of some special pro-
purposes as a historian by exposing the irony phetic gift ( per afflato divino). Domenico Maria
of Italian weakness at the hands of an unworthy No­vara’s forecasts belonged to the first genre.
conqueror.27 It was also a great exaggeration, as Gui­cciar­dini effortlessly appropriated the images
Charles was quite skilled at both war and diplo- and explanatory resources of the second genre,
macy.28 Yet the image of order and disorder (even­ the popular verse prophecies that made forecasts
tually deployed by Copernicus as a resource in without any quantitative apparatus and which
his proof of a new planetary order) was also sig­ were profusely available at the time of the initial
nificant for enhancing the prognosticators’ legiti- invasions.31

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 81


dictus Hectoris (Benedetto Ettore Faelli), one of
The Astrologers’ War
the five leading Bolognese publishers of the late
The heavenly forecasting literature functioned fifteenth century,35 published the crabbed, volu-
as a powerful resource of warning and consola- minous, unfinished manuscript of Giovanni Pico
tion. As opposed to the promiscuous prophecies della Mirandola’s disputations on astrology. It was
often read aloud in the streets, the learned genre Pico’s nephew, Gian Francesco Pico, who had as-
advocated engaging in or avoiding certain kinds sembled the manuscript for publication soon after
of actions based on a technical assessment of the the untimely death of his uncle on November 17,
convergence of celestial influences at specific mo- 1494, the very same day on which Charles VIII en-
ments. It was a form of advice literature that in- tered Florence. According to Gian Francesco Pico,
voked natural causes and effects; because it was his uncle’s aim was to safeguard the authority of
temporally grounded, it complemented the genres biblical prophecy and God’s preeminent agency in
of so-called mirrors, or advice to princes and ad- ruling the cosmos apart from the heavens. What-
vice to courtiers. Niccolò Machiavelli’s The Prince ever other personal motives may have driven him,
(1532) and Baldassare Castiglione’s The Book of Pico took aim precisely at the vast corpus of an-
the Courtier (Il cortegiano, 1528) are only the most cient Arabic and Jewish conjunctionist astrology
famous and influential examples of such aphoris- on which many of the prognosticators relied to
tic advice-giving practices.32 make their alarmist predictions. Hectoris’s repu-
If the prognosticators profited from the anxiety tation as a publisher of the celebrated Pico was
and uncertainty created by the invasions, they quickly established, because he now added the
were not without their own difficulties. By the work against the astrologers to the collection of
last decade of the fifteenth century, the many Pico’s other works and letters. As further evidence
producers of annual prognostications confronted of his prestige, soon thereafter, in 1498, a pirated
a dangerously changing situation that threatened edition of Pico-Hectoris was issued by the Vene-
to undermine the authority of their forecasts. tian publisher Bernardino Vitali—this in spite of a
Paul of Middelburg, physician and astrologer to formal testimonial granted by the duke of Milan,
the duke of Urbino, already felt it necessary in Ludovico Sforza, giving Hectoris exclusive privi-
1492 to defend the legitimacy of “the astrologer’s leges to publish Pico’s works.
office” against the “superstitious” prophecies of Em­ Meanwhile, in 1497, the opponents of astrology
peror Maximilian’s astrologer, Johannes Lichten­ opened a second front: Girolamo Savonarola, the
berger (see chapter 2). His fears were not base­ fiery, charismatic Dominican preacher, reconsti-
less. The verse prophets readily used carnival­esque tuted and radically abridged the learned, philo-
images to mock openly the learned astrological sophical diatribes against astrological authority
culture by transforming their instruments into by his close friend Pico della Mirandola. Savona­
common kitchenware: “These astrolabes of yours rola came from Ferrara, where Pico had studied
are frying pans, your spheres are juggling balls, briefly at the university (1479–80) and where the
the quadrant is a pot, a jar; your tables are a [din- Este dukes sustained and promoted a rich astro-
ing] tables set, where you put good things to logical culture at both court and university.36 Sa­
eat. Cuius, cuia, coioni, you are part prophet and vonarola had encouraged Pico’s attack on the as-
part diviner when you have drunk well of wine. trologers, and he now produced a vernacular
Go with your Almanac into the kitchens, to the work that condensed Pico’s arguments for a pop-
stoves in the back alley, where there is always a ular audience. He directed this work to all levels
flood of grease and fat.”33 Apart from this sort of of Florentine society, encouraging them to “casti-
popular belittling satire, which drew liberally gate and punish” greedy astrologers, satirizing
from the resources of carnival literature, Cicero’s the astrologers’ principles, and affirming the su-
On Divination provided the learned source that perior power of religious prophecy. As for the zo-
was used most widely in resisting astrologers’ diac, wrote Savonarola, it is a human construc-
claims.34 tion: “There is no man who, in such a multitude
At the end of the fifteenth century, however, a of stars, coupling them in various manners, can-
new assault on astrology appeared that coincided not imagine whatever figures he wants. . . . Just
with the ever-burgeoning literature of astrological as men have imagined animal figures, they could
theory and prognostication. In July 1496, Be­ne­ have imagined houses, or castles, or trees, or

82 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


26. Portrait of Giovanni Pico della
Mirandola by Christofano dell’Altis­
simo. Date unknown. Courtesy So-
printendenza Speciale per il Polo
Museale Fiorentino. (For full-color
version, see http://en.wikipedia.org/
wiki/File:Pico1.jpg.)

other similar things . . . but to believe that God philosophy.39 Bellanti modestly declared in his
and nature have drawn in the sky lions, dragons, “Letter to the Reader” that he had not written ei-
dogs, scorpions, vases, archers, and monsters is a ther of these two books “out of enmity or anger”
ridiculous thing.”37 On May 23, 1498, a year after for the “venerated Pico,” although his tone was
the appearance of Savonarola’s volume, at the biting, if not sarcastic.40 In the dedication, Bel-
urging of the pope, its author was hanged and lanti cast his justification for astrology on the
burned for preaching a reform of the Church, for grounds of its necessity for medicine (medicina
prophesying that both Florence and the Church scientia), especially the importance to the physi-
would be scourged and reformed, and for alleg- cian of “practical astrology (which authors call
edly plotting in secret against the ruling council judiciary),” but also on the basis of the higher au-
or Signoria.38 thority of the theologians John Duns Scotus and
Just as the Savonarola affair was reaching its the (frequently cited) “divine Thomas [Aquinas].”
climax, on May 8, 1498, the publisher Gherardus At this moment, the appeal to Rome and Catholic
de Haarlem put up for sale the trenchant Book of orthodoxy was as necessary for a proponent as for
Questions concerning Astrological Truth and Re- an opponent. Conscious of longstanding Church
plies to Giovanni Pico’s Disputations against the opposition to prediction based on the stars, Bel-
Astrologers by Lucio Bellanti (d. 1499), who identi­ lanti had to navigate a careful course between a
fied himself only as a “physicus et astrologus” good astrology of spiritual forces and a bad one
from Siena. The denomination physicus reflects controlled by demons.41 Astrology had nothing to
that of an author trained in scholastic natural add to revealed knowledge, but through “nature’s

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 83


light” it could still be “useful” in “avoiding er- a bad astrology that denied it.44 The good kind in-
rors” and “coming to know God.” His chapter-by- voked the Thomist formula Astra inclinant, sed
chapter rebuttal of Pico’s arguments, which non necessitant (The stars dispose but do not de-
makes up the second work, quickly became a rich termine). Walker is probably right that Pico pri-
resource for the astrological prognosticators. One vately held the Thomist position. But one would
testimony to its continuing appeal is the fact that be hard pressed to find this mitigated view
at least two further editions (each of two issues) maintained in the highly polemical Disputations
appeared in the sixteenth century.42 against Divinatory Astrology. In the last two years
Among Bellanti’s considerable range of topics, of his life, Pico’s position on astrology shifted
organized as for-and-against quaestiones (always dramatically from that of his earlier writings.
followed by the author’s resolutio), is the question And he made ample use of earlier critics, includ-
of where to locate astrology in the division of ing Nicole Oresme’s well-tempered fourteenth-
knowledge: “Whether astrology can be prognosti- century arguments.45
catory”; “Whether all astrology is useful for know-
ing the divine and for avoiding errors”; “Whether
Pico against the Astrologers
heaven is the universal or particular cause of
events in the lower world”; “Whether astrology is Pico’s attack radically questioned astrology’s the-
theorica or practica.” To the last question, Bellanti oretical and practical foundations and anticipated
responded that astrology is partly practical, partly the broader revival of Ciceronian and Pyrrhonian
theorical. For if theoric is a kind of knowledge skepticism in the sixteenth century, promoted by,
based on actions that have no object other than among others, his nephew Gian Francesco Pico.46
themselves (“intrinsic” or “speculative”), as for There is no need to rehearse here the entire bat-
example, the part of astrology that concerns the tery of arguments and replies generated by the
planetary distances and motions themselves (the- Piconian controversies, but it is important to ap-
orica planetarum) or the nature of planetary in­ preciate the work’s overall scope, tenor, and feroc-
fluence, and if practice is a kind of knowledge ity as well as aspects of Pico’s critique that have
that considers a mode of operation (modus ope- been largely misunderstood or simply overlooked.
randi) that has a transitive effect (actio transiens), The Disputations brought Pico’s new objections
such as promoting the good and minimizing the together with earlier ones into a single massive
bad (for example, medicine, military advice, eth- synthesis. “Our Pico,” wrote his nephew, “utterly
ics, and theology), then astrology is both practical burned up and reduced to ashes that unfortunate
and theoretical. tree [of divinatory astrology]—from the root to
Besides its critique of Pico, Bellanti’s treatment the trunk, from the trunk to the branches, and
went beyond the Tetrabiblos to include questions from the branches to the leaves. He did this by
dealing with the physical foundations of theoreti- means of his own incomparable natural talent
cal astronomy. Among these were “Whether the and by means of the most scorching fire of the
heaven is a fluid ( fluxibilis) or solid substance” true philosophy and the true theology.”47
and “Whether there are eight, nine, or ten ­moving In his table of chapter summaries, Pico said
spheres.” Yet, for all of his detailed arguments, that all major authorities “damn” astrology, for it
Bellanti was often cited in the sixteenth century weakens religion, encourages superstition, pro-
for claiming that astrologers had correctly pre- motes idolatry, makes people unhappy and mis-
dicted Pico’s death at the age of thirty-three—a erable, and transforms free beings into slaves.48
squib that, although false, became a convenient There is nothing weighty to be found in the books
way to disparage Pico’s objections.43 of the astrologers. In fact, “among their authors,
Bellanti’s negative representation of Pico leaves there is no authority; among their reasons, noth-
open a question (to which I shall only allude) of ing reasonable; in their experiences, nothing is
how Pico’s position evolved from an earlier es- established, nothing is constant, nothing true,
pousal of astrology to a condemnation of it. D. P. nothing credible, nothing solid. There is only con­
Walker has argued that Pico, like everyone else tradiction, falsehood, absurdity, and empty con-
at this time (including Pico’s friend Marsilio Fi- ceit so that you can scarcely believe what they
cino), distinguished between a good astrology write.” In his own books, then, he claims that he
that maintained human and divine free will and will expose the “uselessness, falsehood, and ig-

84 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


norance of the whole profession and the careless- In this theory of the heavens as the general con-
ness of the professors [of astrology] of our time. dition of motion and life in the terrestrial world,
Likewise, why they sometimes predict the truth Pico altogether ignored both Ptolemy’s and the
when the profession itself is false.” And in the Centiloquium’s standard qualifications about pre-
sixth book, astrology’s main boundary designa- dicting particulars. For Pico, these were mere lip
tors will be destroyed: “The house, the sign, the service: the problem was much more serious. The
aspect, the obsessions and combustions, the anti- astrologers could neither explain nor predict be-
sia, the retrogradations, the dragon’s head and cause change induced by the heavenly heat did
tail, the exaltations, trigons and triplicities, the not produce specific differences: “For who does not
faces, the termini, the dodecathemoria, the de- see that the heavens generate the horse with the
grees, the parts, and the climacteric year.”49 In horse and the lion with the lion and that there is
other words, none of astrology’s categories are re- no position of the stars under which the lion is not
liable. And furthermore, most damagingly, nei- born of the lion, and the horse from the horse?”51
ther astronomers who calculate planetary posi- But particulars were produced by different proxi-
tions nor astrologers who use these positions to mate (noncelestial) causes that varied as much as
establish the play of planetary influences on the their effects. For this reason, the same cause (the
lower terrestrial region agree among themselves heavens) could not explain the particularity of Ar-
about what is reliable. Pico constantly took the ab- istotle’s natural talent as a philosopher any more
sence of consensus as an indication of the fallibil- than it could explain divine miracles, such as the
ity of both astronomy and astrology. virgin birth of Christ.52 There are glimmerings
In natural philosophy it was otherwise for Pico; here of the central insight of the Duhem-Quine
there, different authorities were made to reign thesis: Pico’s theory of celestial influence underde-
harmoniously. Pico did not hesitate to bring into termined the production of specific differences
concordance the ancients (Aristotle, Plato, Ploti- and thus became an important basis for his rejec-
nus) and their many commentators (Averroës, tion of the astrologers’ authority.
Avi­cenna, Aquinas). Material and efficient causes In books 9 and 10 of the Disputations, which
received preference. The zodiac, he contended, have been either ignored or not well understood,
was a human construction. It was merely an ar- Pico brought together a mixture of astronomical
rangement of the stars that was useful for math- and astrological considerations that he took to be
ematicians. But, in themselves, the shapes of the further evidence of the uncertainty that divided the
constellations had no material essence, no inde- astrologers.53 For example, in book 9, chapter 7,
pendent capacity to induce effects. If the heavens he claimed that the astrologers were unsure how
did influence the terrestrial realm, then it was to divide up the houses. Should they use the method
because the celestial contained the “most perfect of Campanus of Novara or of Regiomontanus?54
of all natural bodies.” Commensurate with heav- And, if they were unsure about the house divi-
enly perfection was the most perfect kind of sions, how could they be sure exactly where the
motion (round or circular, orbicularis), and to the planets were in the houses? If they were unsure
senses no quality was more perfectly perceptible about the planets’ locations, then how could they
than light. Through circular motion and light, know the planets’ influences?
the heavens acted as a “universal, efficient cause” And more. The astronomers—on whom the
to generate change. Here light worked physically astrologers rely—did not agree on the length of
as a vital principle and logically as a necessary the tropical year (the time between two vernal
condition—although not itself alive, it prepared equinoxes, marked by the moment when the Sun
or disposed all bodies capable of life to receive it. crosses the equator northward). Hipparchus be-
Like the Stoic pneuma and Ficino’s spiritus, heat lieved that the Sun completed its annual revolu-
functioned as light’s emissary, a mediating con- tion in 3651⁄4 days. Ptolemy, 285 years later, deter-
tinuum between the soul and the body. Accord- mined the extra fraction to be 1⁄300 of a day.
ing to Pico, heat came from light, as though a Al-Battani, 743 years after Ptolemy, found the
property: “A heat that is not fire nor even air, but Sun to be moving more slowly, because the frac-
rather a celestial heat . . . the most efficacious and tional part was now 1⁄106. Then Thabit ibn-Qurrah
most salutary, which penetrates, warms, and or- (d. 901) said that the length of the year is 365
ders all things.”50 days, 6 hours, 9 minutes, and (mistakenly) 12 de-

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 85


grees.55 Some, like Ptolemy and King Alfonso, forms of arguments by astrologers that he found
thought all years to be of equal length, whereas to be weak and ineffective. One of these he called
others, like the medievals al-Zarqali (Arzachel), the argument “from the order of the numbers;” it
Henry Bate, and Isaac Israeli, believed them to concerned the arbitrariness of the “natural affin­
be unequal. They attributed this variation to the ity” between planetary order and the order of the
nonuniform motions of the eighth sphere. elements. Pico did not ascribe this position to any
To add insult to injury, Abraham ibn Ezra, in particular authorities. If Saturn, for example, is
the sixth book of his De revolutionibus nativita- the first in the order of the planets, it should have
tum, doubted that horoscopes could be cast with an affinity with fire, the first in the order of the
accuracy because no instrument could deter- elements. “And yet,” said Pico, “according to the
mine with sufficient precision the moment when astrologers, what could be more different from
the Sun enters the first degree of Aries (the con- Saturn than fire?”61 Similarly, Mars is the third
ventional starting point for measuring longi- planet and water the third element, yet “does not
tude).56 Likewise, Abraham Judaeus narrated a Mars differ from water as much as water from
sobering episode in his book on the composition fire?” The same was true of the signs: Aries is the
of astronomical tables: “Two astrolabes were con- first sign, yet the astrologers deny that Saturn has
structed with the greatest care and of such size any correspondence with it. The problem was not
that the diameter of each measured nine palms. so much the order in which the planets should be
Then the constructors of the instruments, the two numbered—whether beginning with Saturn and
brothers Bersechit, observed together the Sun’s counting down to the Moon or beginning with
altitude and its entry into Aries. The two instru- the Moon and counting up to Saturn—but that
ments, however, did not give the same results but “the place and order of the intermediate planets
differed between them by two minutes.”57 “The is entirely uncertain.”62
instruments are imprecise” was not quite an es- Pico, writing just before the appearance of Re-
tablished medieval trope, but it was certainly a well- giomontanus’s Epitome, was nevertheless well
established worry well before Thomas Hobbes aware of the fact that both the ancients and the
used it against Robert Boyle’s air pump in the moderns disagreed about the order of the planets
seventeenth century.58 with respect to the Sun. He used language antici-
Pico now pointed to the ripple of implications pating that of Regiomontanus, calling it an “an-
that followed from an error of even one degree. cient controversy” whether the Sun comes right
The planet found to be at the extreme limit of one after the Moon or whether the Sun is in the mid-
zodiacal sign would move to the next, so that dle of the other planets. The Egyptians thought
the Moon, happy in Taurus, would be unhappy in that the Sun was close to the Moon; the Chaldeans
Gemini. Further, a masculine quality would be- placed it among the planets, as did Ptolemy and
come feminine, a lucid one opaque, an opaque one the moderns. Others dissented: Geber, a most in-
shadowy, and so forth. Pico asked rhetorically: telligent mathematicus, and Theon, a Greek com-
“In whatever way the planet’s position varies— mentator on Ptolemy, as well as Plato and Aristotle,
whether by one degree or one minute—will not the placed the Sun immediately above the Moon. Not
stellar virtue or influxus be profoundly changed a surprise, said Pico, for many argu­ments were
by such an error?”59 In fact, Pico argued, the best borrowed and none could be thought certain, as
mathematicians acknowledged the uncertainties calculation could not establish which planet was
of their numbers. One of his examples was Paul above another.
of Middelburg. Pico described him as “a famous The same uncertainty held also for Venus and
mathematicus, who now lives with Guido, Duke Mercury. According to Ptolemy, the Sun was
of Urbino, the most cultivated prince,” and who placed aptly (convenienter) in the midst of the
denied that the tables of planetary latitudes were planets: Saturn, Jupiter, and Mars digress from it
trustworthy ( fideles).60 No trust in the numbers, in longitude, while Venus and Mercury closely
no trust in the prediction of effects. follow it. Pico dismissed this as a “frivolous and
In book 10, chapter 4, Pico came to a matter of inconsistent conjecture,” however, because the
crucial interest here: the order of the planets and Moon, like the superior planets, also digresses
the assignment of elemental qualities. The occa- from the Sun, and yet it is not thereby situated
sion for this discussion concerned five different between those planets that digress and those that

86 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


do not. An “equally weak” argument was that of of celestial causes and corresponding effects. Pi-
al-Bitruji (Alpetragius), who believed that the in- co’s questioning of Ptolemy’s ordering of Mer-
ferior planets should move the fastest of all the cury and Venus was itself not unprecedented—as
planets. But then he placed the allegedly inferior we have seen, it was already in the Almagest—but
planet Venus above the Sun and Mercury, thereby the context was strikingly new. Now, for the first
locating a supposedly fast-moving body where it time, an uncertainty about planetary order was
ought to have been moving more slowly. Conse- situated in the context of the assignment of quali-
quently, al-Bitruji adopted a view that no one ac- ties and powers to the individual planets. As a
cepted. Even the ancient view that placed the Sun consequence, an uncertainty about the order
close to the Moon was better than al-Bitruji’s, be- would put the whole scheme of astrological influ­
cause the Sun was thereby never lost to us by the ences at risk—including what young Copernicus
interposition of Venus and Mercury. But perhaps had learned just recently from Albert of Brudze-
there was another explanation why the Sun and wo’s commentary on Peurbach’s New Theorics of
Moon appeared to be contiguous while Mercury the Planets.
and Venus remained invisible: “Either Mercury
is very small or Venus, being close to the Sun, is Domenico Maria Novara and
enveloped and cut off by its rays, whence it could Copernicus in the Bologna
not obstruct the path by which the rays descend
­Culture of Prognostication
toward us whereas the more distant Moon could
do so. Thus, being very tenuous and not as Copernicus must have encountered Pico’s Dispu-
earthly as the lunar thickness, they do not resist tations sometime after arriving in Bologna with
the rays; moreover, they have their own light his brother Andreas. In fact, he encountered
which they send forth in the vicinity of the solar more than a book: he entered a cultural space
[light] They do not [so much] lose this light as where, because of the frequent and uncertain dis-
change it and, as a result, an eclipse [of the Sun] ruptions provoked by the movements of troops,
is not observed.”63 the prognosticators’ warnings were valued more
After criticizing these inadequate arrange- than ever. Copernicus moved into the house of
ments, Pico then cited a passage from Averroës’ Domenico Maria, known both by his city of an-
Paraphrase on Ptolemy’s Syntaxis as an apparent ex- cestral origin (Novara) and by the city where he
ception to his argument that Mercury and Venus was born and studied (Ferrara). We have it on
are usually lost in the Sun’s light. This work was the reliable authority of Copernicus’s disciple
available only in Hebrew, but Pico was something Rheticus that “he lived with Domenico Maria of
of a Hebraist; he had studied Hebrew at Florence Bologna, with whose ideas he was plainly ac-
with Elia del Medigo, who was also quite familiar quainted and with whose observations he as-
with Averroës’ writings.64 According to Pico, Aver- sisted.”67 Unfortunately, the house no longer ex-
roës said that “he had once observed two dark ists today. A plaque at no. 65 via Galliera in the
spots on the Sun, and having made a calculation, parish of San Giuseppe, erected in 1973, marks
he found that Mercury was opposite [or in line the spot where it is believed to have stood before
with] the Sun’s rays.”65 Here Pico introduced a the Risorgimento—“next to a bakery and along the
consideration that even Regiomontanus did not public road”—and where subsequent urban re-
mention: the question of transits of the Sun. He newal has produced an unassuming apartment
then concluded from this passage, as well as on building that now abuts, in an ironic postmodern
the authority of Moses the Egyptian and unnamed juxtaposition, onto an international hotel and car
“others,” that “the order of the Sun, Mercury, and park.68 Exactly how long Copernicus lived at this
Venus remains uncertain.”66 location and how he found it is not known. There
A serious problem followed from this discus- is some evidence that, either before or after his
sion: if there was disagreement on the order of residence in the house of Novara, he also lived
the planets, then the principles governing the near the Porta Nova in the parish of San Salva-
various associations of elemental qualities to the tore, not far away. It may have been as a young
planets would be gravely undermined. Beholden law student seeking lodging that he first encoun-
to the superior science of astronomy, astrology tered Novara. Such a connection would explain
could no longer be certain of its core association why Rheti­cus took care to dissociate his teacher

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 87


27. Sala di Bologna, Vatican Apostolic Palace. Detail of mural map of Bologna. Encircled area indicates location of
­Domenico Maria Novara’s residence, today via Galliera 65. Photo Vatican Museums.

from a strictly pedagogical relationship with the gin that the will had been drawn up just one
“learned Dominicus Maria.” month earlier by another notary, Ser Lorenzo de
But we have still another important clue to Benazzi. Novara, in fact, had probably lived for a
their relationship. The house in which Novara time in Benazzi’s house, because the inventory
lived was owned by the notary Francesco Calle- states: “He paid Lorenzo de Benazzi one hundred
gari. At the behest of Novara’s beneficiaries, Cal- pounds for two years’ rent of the house.” 70
legari had prepared an inventory of Novara’s pos- The Benazzi, like many of the Bolognese nota-
sessions at the time of his death on September 5, ries, were a noble family. Lorenzo’s son, Giacomo
1504. In 1920 Lino Sighinolfi, the Bologna city li- (1471–1548), was one of the three masters of astron­
brarian, published a small section of this inven- omy at the university from 1501 onward.71 Gia-
tory, bemoaning along the way the fact that the como announced in a prognostication published
twenty-six titles in Novara’s library had been in 1502 that he was a pupil of Novara.72 Lattanzio
omitted because the beneficiaries valued the fur- Benazzi (1499–1572), no doubt a younger relative
nishings more highly.69 Callegari noted in a mar- of the family and possibly the son of Giacomo,

88 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


held the astronomy professorship from 1537 to plex terrestrial world. Put otherwise, because the
1572 and issued numerous prognostications.73 same celestial cause could produce different ef-
Taken together, these details are highly sug- fects in different places, effective interpreters of
gestive of unsuspected cultural connections: at celestial forces and effects required good access
the time of Copernicus’s stay in Bologna, the to local knowledge.77 The credibility of their pre-
families of notaries and prognosticators were dictions required them to be politically and so-
closely bound together. In fact, as the notarial cially well-informed. We have seen evidence of
archives reveal, most of the native Bologna this kind of privileged knowledge in Avogario’s
prognosticators—Manfredi, Benazzi, Pietramel- candid letters to the duke of Ferrara. Behind the
lara, Scribanario, Vitali—came from prominent generalized language of Novara’s 1492 prognosti-
notarial families. The name Scribanario may de- cation we may detect a muffled echo:
rive from “someone who writes.” Probably No-
vara was something of an exception to this rule. Wishing to prognosticate the nature of the celestial
Novara’s grandfather Bartolino (or Bartolomeo) effects, it is necessary not only to contemplate the
forces of the celestial bodies, but it is also neces-
Ploti di Novara was an engineer and builder of
sary to understand how the subjects’ passive dis-
fortifications who designed the Castello di San
positions adapt to the natural agents, because the
Michele, the castle of the dukes of Ferrara.74 At
same celestial nature produces different effects in
any rate, our evidence permits the speculation different places. Therefore, ought not the rational
that the notarial profession—and perhaps even prognosticator to have also an understanding of
the profession of prognosticator—was passed that part of philosophy which concerns the [di-
down through generations. verse] locations of the entire world? That is to say,
The notaries were probably among the best-in- of all terrestrial and maritime things and the di-
formed people in the city.75 Notaries were con- versity of human customs, animals, plants, and
cerned with securing and managing personal also fruits which have such diversity throughout
capital and its transmission between individuals the universe.78
and generations. They made up wills and house-
hold inventories. They wrote contracts and com- Concerned as the prognosticators were with
posed letters. They had contacts with people at all the dispositions and future fate of members of
social levels. For example, they kept records of ar- different social groups, notarial contacts might
tisans’ meetings, recorded oaths of office, and have given them information about the immedi-
kept auditing records. They were also consum- ate distribution of social and political capital and
mate deal makers. Furthermore, in Bologna, the hence improved the quality of their local predic-
Palace of the Notaries (Palazzo dei Notai) was lo- tions. Little is known about astrological consid-
cated just across the main square from the pal­ erations in notarial practice, although Ottavia
ace where the senate held its weekly meetings. Niccoli has located direct evidence that notaries
Some notaries held seats in that body. Lorenzo in Piacenza, Cesena, and Udine were among the
de Be­nazzi himself was a member of the Sedici in transcribers and circulators of nonastrological
1460.76 The Church, the senate, and various uni­ prophecies.79
ver­sity structures were no more than two to three When Copernicus lived with Domenico Maria
minutes’ walking distance apart. Effectively, the Novara and acted as his “assistant and witness,”
relatively small geographical and social scale of we can speculate that he somehow participated
the city at the time of Copernicus’s student days in this network of prognosticators and notaries.
made much more probable all kinds of links That he never issued any prognostications of
among people that might not occur quite so read- his own at Bologna indicates one meaning of as-
ily in the city at its current size. sistant. Copernicus, for all his well-known talent,
Although it is difficult to document precisely was still something of an outsider. After all, he
what the prognosticators might have learned was formally obligated to the Varmia chapter.
from the notaries, the prognosticators were aware His uncle had already lined up a church sinecure
that an effective forecast required not only knowl- for him, which he accepted at Bologna by proxy
edge of how and when the planetary causes oper- and through a notary. Finally, he was neither a
ated but also how their effects might be received native of Bologna nor, like Novara, a member of
and distributed in the always variable and com- the faculty of arts and medicine. He came from

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 89


neither a noble family nor a family of notaries forecasts appeared either from his own press or
nor a family of prognosticators. He had no degree at his own expense and mostly in the vernacu-
of any kind, let alone a doctorate, with which to lar.82 They were generally dedicated to the ruling
announce his officium or public identity: thus family, the Bentivoglio, but in 1489, he addressed
he could not (yet) invoke the social authority of the legate and the senate as well. Therefore, by
the university as a warrant for his credibility. He 1482, when Novara received his appointment,
could not be a full-fledged academic prognostica- publication of the annual judgment had replaced
tor, but he could still assist in the production of the parchment requirements of the statutes as
the forecast and thereby contribute to the practice something of a stable practice.
of the prognosticators. Novara’s surviving prognostications were all
The formal authority to prognosticate at Bolo- printed and dedicated to the Bentivoglio. They
gna fell directly under academic jurisdiction. have consistently the same rhetorical structure.
Since 1404, it had been a requirement of the uni- Typically, they begin with a general exordium of-
versity statutes that the lecturer on spherics and fering some display of learning or general argu-
theorics issue an annual prognostication. The ment about heavenly influence. This brief section,
Bologna statutes specified a set of precise obliga- amounting to one or two pages, might have been
tions that the astrologer was supposed to meet. read publicly at the university. Perhaps it repre-
He must provide free to the university an annual sented the condensed summary of a disputation.
judgment ( judicium) and, in addition, he had the Whether the judgment that followed was deliv-
obligation to dispute (disputare). ered orally is also difficult to determine. It was
commonly divided into subsections that treated
Let the doctor elected to the salary of astrologer dis- major planetary conjunctions and eclipses, the
pute two questions (questiones) in astrology and
time of the Sun’s entry into Aries, the prospects
de­termine these not later than eight days before
for war and disease, and the specific fates of Bolo-
the said day of the disputation. And also, let him
gna, Venice, Florence, Pisa, the Turks, and vari-
dispute about any subject (quodlibet) in astrology
at least once. . . . And let the said questiones and ous rulers of other domains. Remarkably, I have
the said quodlibet be written down and sent to the found not one reference to the Bible in any of the
Stationer within fifteen days after the “determina- Bologna prognostications—an important differ-
tions,” and let it be done in good letters and on ence, so far as I can tell, between Italy and the
good, unshaved sheets of parchment. . . . And let transalpine north. The most commonly used au-
the said questiones remain continuously at the Sta- thorities were Greek, Jewish, and Arabic: Mes-
tioner so that copies may be made from them.80 sahalah, Albumasar, Ptolemy (Tetrabiblos; Centi-
loquium), Aristotle, and Haly Abenrodan’s com-
The statutes make clear that these scribal prog- mentary on the Tetrabiblos. At the end of each
nostications enjoyed only limited distribution in prognostication appeared a table of new and full
Bologna because access to the documents was moons—effectively the basic materials of an al-
restricted to the university’s stationer, where they manac, the elements of eclipse prediction. Occa-
would have been copied. The earliest Bologna sionally, as for the year 1500, Novara included a
prognostication that I have been able to locate is list of lucky and unlucky days.83
that of Johannes Paulus de Fundis (who lectured Domenico Maria Novara’s prognostications,
there from 1428 to 1473), written on February 7, ­issued between 1483 and 1504, were composed in
1435. It is evidently a copy, as it has been written Latin, although occasionally the same forecast ap-
not on unshaved parchment but on relatively thin, peared in Italian as well. The Latin versions were,
loosely sewn paper folio sheets (21.5 by 31 cm). It in all probability, the original texts, prepared by
is also considerably longer than the later printed the prognosticator himself, whereas the vernacu-
prognostications, which were typically eight ­folios lar version—which often dropped some technical
folded in quarto.81 references and expressions—might have been
The arrival of print, as the previous two chap- translated by someone else afterward, perhaps an
ters show, changed the possibilities of reader- assistant.84 Leading Bologna publishers produced
ship. At Bologna, active publication of the yearly all but the forecasts for 1484 and 1497: Ugo Rug-
prognostications began at least as early as 1475 gieri (1492), Caligola Bazilieri (1496), Giu­stiniano
with Girolamo Manfredi (1455–93). Manfredi’s da Rubiera (1500), and Benedetto di Ettore Faelli

90 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


(1501–4).85 The Bologna prognosticators’ annual trasting the wise and the ignorant. Constructing
predictions appeared simultaneously with those of an epideictic rhetoric of praise and blame, he
other members of the university: Manfredi until avoided mentioning specific names or parties,
1493, and then his successors, Antonio Arquato yet his account was undoubtedly aimed at an on-
(1493–94), Francesco de Papia (1493–97), Scipio going debate within the university faculty about
de Mantua (1484–98), and Giacomo Pietramel- the scope and legitimacy of what he called the
lara (1496–1536); Novara’s pupil Giacomo Be­nazzi “science of the stars” (scientia astrorum): How
(1500–1528), Luca Gaurico (1506–7), Marco Scriba­ should such knowledge be ranked among the lib-
nario (1513–30), Ludovico de Vitali (1504–54), Lat- eral arts? Of what practical or civil use is it? Who
tanzio de Benazzi (1537–72), and so forth.86 Inter- is competent to discourse about it? His prelimi-
estingly, Scribanario issued his judgments mostly nary answer was that there are few really wise
in Italian and addressed them all to the papal leg- men who understand the science of the stars and
ate, Cardinal Ascanio Sforza. Pietramellara made many who criticize and clumsily imitate its lan-
separate forecasts for the pope, the emperor, and guage. A correct use of (technical) language sep-
the kings of France and Spain.87 These important arates true astronomers from their imitators.90
differences suggest some kind of political division In the second, somewhat less rhetorical part of
of intended audiences among the university’s the prefatory section, Novara emphatically de-
prognosticators. Perhaps the existence of differ- veloped the position that astronomers do not
ent predictions for the same year assisted in pro- make claims of necessity in human affairs. Here,
tecting their general credibility: someone was he followed the customary two-cell Ptolemaic
bound to hit the mark. More likely, however, they division between the mathematical-astronomical
simply reflected the division of the governo misto: part of the prognostication that he regarded as
one set was directed to the secular princes, the certain (and whose subject matter and methods
other to the church. are described in Ptolemy’s Almagest) and the
The themes of Novara’s individual exordia re- judgmental part that was not as firm and strong.91
veal something of the changing concerns and On this occasion, he did not make explicit use
strategies of the forecasts. Prognosticators might of the Centiloquium, which said that “the ‘judg-
choose a scholarly text through which to display ment’ is in the middle between the necessary
their learning or begin with an aphorism drawn and the possible.”92 Instead, Novara shaped his
from the Centiloquium. In the 1489 prognostica- appeal explicitly on the authority of Galen, per-
tion, for example, Novara delivered a long com- haps because he was directing his remarks to
mentary on a passage from Ptolemy’s Geography, critics of astrological medicine in Bologna: “Galen
in which he conjectured that the Earth’s pole had distinguishes in several places two kinds of
shifted slightly since the time of Ptolemy. The knowledge in medical science. One kind is cer-
­entire passage was quoted by Giovanni Antonio tain; but the other is cunningly conjectural, ac-
Magini in 1585 from what he called “a certain old ceptable only insofar as its judgment is in the
prophecy made at Bologna in the year 1489” (quo- vicinity of the truth. Now, of these two kinds of
dam antiquo vaticinio anni 1489 Bononiae) that he knowledge, the astronomer’s is the first—both
claimed was difficult to find even at the time of certain and scientific93 —because he deduces nat-
his own writing!88 In the introduction to his 1496 ural inclinations in human affairs from celestial
forecast, Novara used an aphorism about love and causes. But again, the other [kind of knowledge]
hate from the Centiloquium as an occasion for a is conjectural because what it foretells by con-
didactic lecture on the moral value of seeking out sidering the natural inclination can vary with the
the mean between extremes. free will.”94
At least from 1499 onward, a more combative In this passage, Novara seems to be invoking a
and defensive tone is evident.89 Signs of Pico’s cri- version of the conventional formula that the stars
tique and the French invasion break into the pre- causally determine human dispositions but that
ambulatory material. The 1499 prognostication is knowledge of these dispositions does not guaran-
especially important because it appeared at exactly tee that the astronomer can predict exactly how a
the time that Copernicus was in Bologna and be- human agent or a nation will behave in a particu-
cause it has never been translated or analyzed. lar circumstance. Moreover, Novara did not use
Novara began the Latin prognostication by con- this occasion to deepen astronomy’s purchase on

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 91


demonstrative knowledge. For example, he did This passage appears to be more than a conven-
not claim that such knowledge conforms to Aris- tional defense of astrology. The science of the
totle’s stringent ideal of the scientific demonstra- stars (like that of genetic predispositions today)
tion, in which the major premises are “true, pri- was believed to produce knowledge of human dis-
mary, immediate, better known than, prior to, and positions and inclinations, and this knowledge
causative of the conclusion.”95 Nor did he take up was conditional on secure knowledge about the
any of Pico’s pointed astronomical criticisms positions of the stars. It also allowed room for
about the uncertainty of the Sun’s motion or the human volitional behavior. Once the astrologer
order of the planets. Because this was the intro- determined which celestial configurations gov-
duction to a prognostication, its aim was limited, erned particular classes of individuals, then state-
and the focus was appropriately on the conjec- ments of possible effects of a particular character
tural and conditional basis of the astronomer’s might be specified and annual prognostications
forecast. Novara revealed, in the process, how he drawn up. Such a pointed justifi­cation of the sta-
thought about the general logical structure of tus of astrological knowledge is not to be found in
predictions in human affairs. any previous forecast by Novara of which I am
His main example shows that military events aware.97 Its timing, some three years after the pub-
were a central preoccupation, in this case the lication of the Disputations against Divinatory As-
possible movements of the French armies. “The trology and just a few months after the appearance
astronomer predicts that, on account of the celes- of Lucio Bellanti’s book, strongly suggests that it
tial influence, this year the French are naturally represents Dome­nico Maria Novara’s reply to Pico
inclined to make war against the Italians. But pre- della Mirandola.
cisely here, [the astronomer] is not content with Novara’s defense of the logical status of prog-
this as a proper and certain prediction and so nostication shows that the fight for the status of
places it second, as a conjectural inquiry.” Now, if prognostication was a two-front war against both
the problem was “conjectural,” then what guesses Piconian skepticism and other claimants to fore-
could be made about French “inclinations” in casting competence. This is clear again from a
1499? Novara did not say directly, but instead of- prog­nostication by Giacomo Benazzi, a con­firmed
fered a decidedly philosophical disquisition about student of Novara. Benazzi used his very first
different kinds of inclinations: prog­nostication to set up a classification of oppo-
nents. He spelled out the distribution of author-
ity between the astronomical “school” of his
And he [the astronomer] says: “He who is most nat-
urally inclined to pursue some goal pursues it by
teacher Novara and several other genera of fore-
the greatest sensual appetite and natural inclina- cast. First, “men inspired by divine will or revela-
tion. For it appears that all desire the good.” How- tion” make “prophecies;” such works are based
ever, to us, it appears better [to say] that “the natural on faith alone. Second, physicians “imperfectly”
disposition inclines us,” since, especially in choos- prognosticate critical days and the course of
ing one of two possibilities, the mind does not [al- disease from individual bodily signs. Third, in a
ways] choose the more certain [even if all desire the likely reference to Marsilio Ficino, he remarked
good]. And so it appears to be more evident that it that “therapeutic physicians” speak profusely
is [the mind] whose natural disposition is pleased. (but without evident success) about “melanchol-
Hence, the astronomer says thus: . . . “If the French ics.” Benazzi used these barely articulated genera
attack Italy this year, then it will happen for the to dismiss what would appear to be a certain fac-
most part that the effect follows because the nat- tion in the medical faculty. Against this group, he
ural inclination was strong.” The astrologer thus
praised the “astronomers” and their methodus
banishes necessity in human actions. Indeed, [the
pronosticandi—obviously the group with which
astrologer] always infers the necessary as a condi-
he and his teacher were identified. The astrono-
tional, just as if I were to say that “the French will
surely fight against the Italians if they follow their mers’ method is “the more perfect” because it
natural inclinations.” You, magnanimous prince, moves deductively and swiftly to “harmonic ef-
will not be surprised, however, if we say that the fects” from celestial motions and virtues. Also, in
astronomer’s judgments are of this kind. If the nay- a barely veiled reference to Pico, Benazzi stated
sayers speak abusively, they do what they ought to that astronomy “does not reckon to be an inquiry
do, since they do not know how to speak well.96 of the demons, as certain people unwittingly bear

92 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


witness to in their publications.” Astronomy pro- circulated through the Bologna senate, the Benti­
vides us with powerful foreknowledge of good voglio palace, and the university? Next, how ex-
influences that we might follow and bad ones actly might Copernicus have assisted Novara in
that we might avoid. “As Ptolemy says, in the sa- the preparation of his annual judgments? And
gacious sayings of the Almagest: Sapiens domina- finally, how might Pico’s critique have entered
bitur astris [The wise man shall rule the stars]. into Copernicus’s hypothesis about the new or-
For astronomy shall be able to protect us from dering of the planets?
infinite misfortunes that can occur while manag-
ing and governing commonwealths. And, in ad- Prognosticators, Humanists,
dition, says Ptolemy, the astronomer shall protect and the Sedici
against many evils because the extraordinary and
special man knows very well beforehand the na- The Bologna prognosticators occupied an impor-
ture of these things from the stars.”98 Sapiens tant social position in the city, a status that traded
dominabitur astris was a topos among prognosti- on their familial connections to the notaries and
cators, but the phrase comes from pseudo-Ptole- their rank in both the medical and arts faculty
my’s Centiloquium rather than from the Almagest. at the university. Girolamo Manfredi and Dome­
As this casual citation shows, Ptolemy’s roles as nico Maria Novara, for example, were not only
astrologer and astronomer were easily blurred. teachers in the university but also members of
Benazzi here represented Ptolemy not as the au- both the medical and the arts faculties.99 The
thor of the Almagest but as an astrologer whose polymath Giovanni Garzoni (1419–1505)—a phi-
writings could help men to free themselves from lologist, moralist, historian, and one-time teacher
the baleful influences of the stars. of Savonarola—lectured on Avicenna’s Canon 3 in
Rheticus’s report that Copernicus was “plainly the chair of practical medicine for thirty years.100
acquainted with Domenico’s ideas” increases During this time, he also composed De Eruditi-
confidence that no later than 1499, and probably one Principum Libri Tres, a work in the evolving
earlier, Copernicus was familiar with Novara’s advice-to-princes genre that grew out of personal
retort to Pico’s charges against the hopeless un- discussions with Giovanni Bentivoglio.101 “I be-
certainty and allegedly deterministic dangers of lieve,” wrote Garzoni, “that anyone who does not
astrological knowledge. Moreover, the 1499 prog- know astrology cannot succeed in being a good
nostication elevates the likelihood that Coperni- philosopher, physician, or poet.”102
cus was already reading Pico’s book in Bologna Garzoni’s statement points to another source
and that it pushed him at that early date to think of the prognosticators’ influence: their discursive
about a strategy for defending the astronomical and explanatory resources were widely valued
foundations of astrology. In other words, even if and circulated beyond their local sphere of activ-
judiciary astrology could strive only for conjec- ity. The prognosticatory genre structured a repre-
tural knowledge in making the judgment, as- sentation of the immediate future for all social
tronomy could hope to achieve knowledge that is groups. Members of the highest cultural and po-
securely grounded, even if not fully demonstra- litical circles found their energizing tropes in the
tive in the strict Aristotelian sense. A defense of astrologers’ vocabulary of necessity and freedom
practical astrology grounded in the discipline of to act. An expression of this view appears, for ex-
theoretical astronomy would differ considerably ample, in one of the short stories that make up
from the sort offered both by Novara’s pupil Gia- Sabadino degli Arienti’s Le porretane. A Milanese
como Benazzi and by Lucio Bellanti because it nobleman, Gabriele Rusconi, receives the follow-
would be concerned with fixing the mathemati- ing advice: “Gabriel, I am persuaded that since you
cal principles on which the planetary tables were have arrived at the age where you thirst for writ-
constructed. And Copernicus’s skill at theorica ten books, you ought to agree and understand
must have been obvious to Novara when he took clearly—both through practice and theoric [per
him on as an assistant. pratica e per teorica]—that the stars, through their
In the remaining sections of this chapter, then, influences, entirely dispose and govern our active
I shall take up three questions. First, what could life.”103 The prognosticators’ language, drawing
Novara have communicated to the young Coper- its resources from learned treatises like the Tetra-
nicus about the Piconian critique as political news biblos, was not quite as malleable as the language

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 93


of verse prophecy; nonetheless, it helped to con- 1496 edition of Pico’s works.111 In fact, Hectoris
tain ruling-class anxieties about imminent de- published most of Beroaldo’s writings, and they
struction from external forces. Such high, astrol- stand as exemplars of Bolognese humanism.112
ogized discourse, in other words, bound together One of Codro’s most important pupils, Antonga-
the linguistic space of the poet, the physician, the leazzo Bentivoglio, became chancellor of the Col-
philosopher, and the astronomer with men in the lege of Jurists in 1491.113
world of political action. The major patron of the Bolognese humanists
Yet it seems that the Bologna prognosticators was Mino di Bartolomeo Rossi or Minus Roscius,
themselves did not enjoy the same intimate rela- the son of Bartolomeo (1455–1503). Beroaldo re-
tionship with the Bentivoglio as did their con- ferred to him frequently in his writings with
freres at the Este court in Ferrara. It was the hu- flattering phrases: “To me, no man was friend-
manists, rather, with positions as rhetoricians, lier, dearer or more close”; he was “the refuge
poets, or grammarians, who had special ties to of all lettered men” (“asilo di tutti i letterati”).114
the Bentivoglio court, sometimes as tutors of hu- Cayado also referred to him as “Dictator amplis-
manist subjects or as panegyrists. Francesco del simus.”115 And of Rossi’s writings Garzoni ex-
Pozzo of Parma (known as Puteolano), for exam- claimed: “You would have said that Cicero had
ple, lived at the Bentivoglio palazzo near the uni- been restored to life.”116 In fact, Rossi was a figure
versity for many years; he lectured on rhetoric central to the city’s political life both before and
and poetry from 1467 to 1477, published an edi- after the beginning of the French invasions. He
tion of Ovid’s works in 1471, and tutored the Ben- was made a member of the Sedici in 1482. He ac-
tivoglio sons. Puteolano was also involved in companied Giovanni II on two trips in 1485 and
setting up the first printing establishments at 1488. In 1492, he was part of the embassy sent to
Bologna and Parma.104 Giovanni Bentivoglio II Rome on the election of the new pope, Alexander
described him as “a person most learned in po- VI. Two years later, he was accompanied by Anto-
etry, oratory, and the liberal arts.”105 nio Urceo Codro and Alessandro Bentivoglio on a
The dominating Bolognese humanists of the mission to the duke of Milan. Again in 1499 he
end of the fifteenth century also had strong ties spent six to seven weeks with the king of France
to the court: Filippo Beroaldo the Elder (Phi­ in Milan negotiating the fate of Bologna. Bentivo-
lippus Beroaldus; 1453–1505) and his colleague glio confidence in Rossi was sufficiently high
and rival Antonio Codro Urceo, who held the chair that he was again sent in April 1500 to represent
of grammar, rhetoric, and poetry (1482–1500).106 the commune to the duke of Milan. And finally,
Beroaldo had been a pupil of Puteolano and lec- sometime in 1502, he departed on a diplomatic
tured on rhetoric and poetry at the university from mission to France, where he remained for nearly
1479 to 1503; he also tutored Annibale and Ales- six months.117
sandro Bentivoglio and dedicated a commentary Rossi was a man of political affairs, but his hu-
on Suetonius to the former.107 His political and manist sensibilities were no mere adornment:
intellectual connections were substantial. Gio­ both he and Beroaldo had studied with Francesco
vanni Bentivoglio described him as “persona vir- Puteolano. Throughout his writings, Beroaldo
tuosa e degna.”108 He was also a magnet for for- mixed laudatory with biographical references to
eign humanists. The Portuguese poet Hermico Rossi. In his commentary on Apuleius’s Golden
Cayado, later praised by Erasmus, was in Bologna Ass, published by Hectoris on August 1, 1500, he
between early 1495 and May 1497 in order to study engages in an extended digression praising the
with Beroaldo. The publisher Hectoris produced country villa of his friend Mino Rossi, with its
Cayado’s Aeclogae Epigrammata Sylvae.109 Cayado spacious gardens, fountains and staircases, which
and Beroaldo were linked in another way: both lay about seven miles from the city in the valley
sang the praises of a Polish nobleman, Pawel of the river Reno. Every year—no doubt in the
Szdłowiecki (Paulus Sidlovitius), who was proba- summer, as the palazzo was not well heated—
bly one of their patrons. It is possible that Coper- Gio­vanni Bentivoglio came to this villa with his
nicus came into contact with Beroaldo through sons to be royally entertained by Rossi.118 Cayado
Cayado and Szdłowiecki.110 Beroaldo was also a recited poetry there on at least one occasion.119 Be­
close friend of Pico della Mirandola; some of his roaldo was clearly part of this company, and it is
letters to Pico were published by Hectoris in the evident that being entertained at this level was

94 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


28. Mino Rossi (1455–1503), senator of Bologna, patron of Bologna humanists, friend and correspondent of Pico della
Mirandola, and dedicatee of at least two prognostications by Domenico Maria Novara. Courtesy of Marchese Ippolito
Bevilacqua Ariosti.

not unusual for him; of course, mention of it was prognostication literature, and there are no such
also a way of publicizing his own status by repre- references in any of Novara’s earlier (extant)
senting his social proximity to a patron. An ear- prognostications. Note what it achieved. First,
lier, informative reference can be found in a letter the prognosticator signals that his own status is
to Pico della Mirandola (April 10, 1486), where sufficiently important that it allowed him to
Beroaldo referred to having been entertained by engage in a “conversation” with a member of the
Pico together with Mino Rossi at the former’s resi- Sedici at his home (perhaps the Reno Valley
dence. Hectoris published this letter as part of villa). Second, he takes care both to indicate his
­Pico’s collected works in 1496.120 Again, as late as own lower status (Rossi interrupts him) and to
July 31, 1502, Beroaldo referred to a supper party reveal that the senator was the one who intro-
hosted by Rossi for Giovanni Bentivoglio.121 duced the question for debate (a dubium).122 Third,
There is no independent evidence that Do- he lets it be known not only that Rossi was knowl-
menico Maria Novara was ever invited to such a edgeable enough to make a significant objection
dinner, but he had been well received at one of (“worthy of philosophical inquiry”) but also that
Rossi’s residences. In 1501, he began the disputa- he knew how to do it in the right way, that is, in
tional part of his forecast with the report of an good Latin (the language of the university). Even
important conversation: “A few days ago, when if Novara did not partake of dinner with the
I was at the home of Mino Rossi, Senator of Bo- senator, they shared Latinity and serious philo-
logna, a man of course not ignorant of the Latin sophical argumentation. Together, these aspects
language, he brought forth for the public good of the meeting signal Novara’s access to the cen-
(interrupting, as we were discussing some things) ter of political power and afford legitimacy to the
a certain doubt about astronomical matters, a encounter.123
difficulty, in fact, not unworthy of philosophical The 1502 prognostication posed an interesting
inquiry.” This opening strategy is revealing and conundrum. Again, the prognostication begins
unusual because such references to personal with a scene of conversation, although this time
meet­ings with senators are exceptional in the without reference to “the home of Mino Rossi”:

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 95


“There is a common proverb among speakers: of all of Novara’s later prognostications even as
‘The imagination often causes an event,’ that is, he published the prestigious works of Pico. For
frequently something happens just as we have Hectoris, the major threat came from piracy by
imagined. From this puzzling proposition, the other printers. Two Lyonnais publishers, Jacobi-
mag­nanimous prince Mino Rossi, a man (like nus Suigus and Nicolaus de Benedictis, pirated
us) not ignorant of the Latin language, brought the first volume of his edition of Pico’s Works,
forth for the public good a single, certain diffi­ and the Disputations against the Astrologers was
culty while he discoursed about many and vari- appropriated by the Venetian printer-pirate Ber-
ous matters, such as befits senatorial dignity.” nardinus de Vitalibus on August 14, 1498.125
Again it is the senator, now referred to as a Prestige accrued to printers by virtue of their as-
“prince,” who initiates discussion of a difficulty sociation with authors of noble birth and some-
(arduum certe) that he knows the prognosticator times from authors’ provocative claims. With the
will use as an occasion, as in the previous year, publication of Pico, Hectoris had the advantages
for a published academic discourse. Again the ar- of both.
rows of mutual social legitimation fly in both di-
rections: Mino Rossi allows himself to be associ- Copernicus, Assistant
ated with the prognosticator and the university;
and Witness
Novara acquires a public association with a lead-
ing member of the senate. Perhaps there is also a A remarkable conjuncture of publications inter-
hint that something else is being exchanged: on sected Copernicus’s arrival in Bologna in the
the one hand, senatorial political gossip of value fall of 1496: at Milan, in 1495, a new issue of Al­
to the prognosticator in constructing his forecast; bert of Brudzewo’s Most Useful Commentary on
on the other hand, authoritative arguments de- the Theorics of the Planets from a different pub-
signed to quell doubts about the forecast’s causal lisher than the first issue; in August, from Simon
and epistemic foundations. Bevilacqua in Venice, another—indeed, the only
The strands of this investigation now come to- other—commentary on Peurbach, by the public
gether to form a new space of probable under- lecturer on astronomy at Padua, Francesco Ca­
standing and hypothesis. The prognosticators puano da Manfredonia; and also in Venice, at the
were part of system in which privileged informa- end of August 1496, Regiomontanus’s Epitome of
tion and political intelligence in Bologna circu- the Almagest. Finally, in July 1496, Pico’s Disputa-
lated through the notaries, the professoriate, and tions appeared at Bologna. In short, within one
certain members of the senate. The credibility of year, publishers in key north-central Italian ven-
the advice offered in the annual forecasts must ues had created a kind of mini-revival of Regio-
have relied, at least in part, on the quality of this montanus’s short-lived Nuremberg printing
information—it certainly could not have come project, some of it framed by Italian and Polish
entirely from the astrology manuals. Proper cal- interpreters. To these significant resources of the
culation of eclipses and important conjunctions science of the stars must also be added the
then furnished material for the causal, explana- slightly earlier 1493 edition of the Tetrabiblos.126
tory part of the judgment as well as the grounds Girolamo Salio of Faventino, a physician with
for specific advice on the timing of when to act or significant Bologna connections, explicitly dedi-
not. Although Cicero’s On Divination was a com- cated that work to Novara.127 Although the text
mon authority for questioning astrology, there reads “Domenico Maria of Anuaria, Doctor of
developed a deeper uneasiness, if not outright Arts and Medicine and Most Excellent Astrolo-
skepticism, about the dominion of the stars after ger,” “Anuaria” is not a known place name, and
the appearance of Pico’s Disputations. The exact- the designation was unquestionably a typograph-
ing placement of a dubium, attributed to Rossi, at ical error for “Nouaria.”128 Hence the 1493 Tetra-
the head of the 1501 and 1502 prognostications biblos, the principal resource of theoretical astrol-
suggests the possibility that Novara was respond- ogy of the late fifteenth century, must be the
ing directly to these patronal concerns.124 edition used by Domenico Maria Novara and
The printer and bookseller Benedictus Hecto- Nicolaus Copernicus, the young man who as-
ris did not hesitate to profit from both the believ- sisted him in his work. Indeed, the copy of the
ers and the doubters. Hectoris was the publisher 1493 Tetrabiblos in the University of Bologna Li-

96 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


29. Domenico Maria Novara’s signature in his copy of the omnibus edition of Ptolemy’s Tetrabiblos (1493).
By permission of Biblioteca Universitaria di Bologna. A.V.KK.VI.26.4. Further reproduction by any means is prohibited.

brary, which is bound together with the De Nati- chapter 27, Copernicus reports that he has seen
vitatibus of Albubather Alhasan (Abū Bakr) and the Moon eclipse “the brightest star in the eye of
the Summa Anglicana of John of Eschenden (Jo- the Bull,” namely Aldebaran (in the constellation
hannes Eschuid), strikingly supports this hy- Taurus). In 1543, he uses this observation to ad-
pothesis. The last page of the bundled collection vance a theoretical claim: that the Bologna obser-
contains Novara’s signature and is the only book vation confirmed exactly the size of the apparent
from his library currently known to survive.129 lunar diameter. Copernicus wrote: “These values
Copernicus had thus arrived in Bologna and was agree so thoroughly with the observation that no-
living in the home of one of its major astrological body need doubt the correctness of my hypothe-
practitioners just as Pico’s critique appeared amid ses and the statements based on them.”132 It is
a rapid-fire sequence of publications concerning curious that Copernicus chose to report an ob-
the science of the stars. servation represented as witnessed only by him-
Novara was also the likely source of Coperni- self and made forty-six years earlier when he
cus’s first knowledge of Regiomontanus’s Epit- might have used another, later observation. Noel
ome. Given everything now known, it would be Swerdlow and Otto Neugebauer comment that
surprising if the Novaran had not quickly ac- although Copernicus used this observation to test
quired a copy of that work. Novara’s motive would Ptolemy’s lunar parallax, “one cannot be certain
have been more than a concern with theoretical about what Copernicus did with [these observa-
astronomy: he referred to “Magister Joannes de tions] at so early a date.”133
Monte Regio Germanus: Praeceptor Meus” (Mas- Was Copernicus acting then on March 9, 1497,
ter John Regiomontanus the German, my as an assistant and witness to Novara? It would
teacher) in a manuscript concerning the Moon’s seem more likely that in this instance Copernicus
influence at the moment of human conception.130 was acting alone as an observer, as mention of
It seems clear that Novara, like Paul of Middel- Novara’s presence as a witness surely would have
burg, regarded Regiomontanus as the right kind enhanced the authority of the observation. But
of astrologer.131 And Novara may have owned certainly one reason why Copernicus might have
some of Regiomontanus’s manuscripts. been interested in new and full moons was to as-
Apart from these key intellectual referents, all sist in checking the lunar tables for Novara’s 1498
Copernicus’s known observations from his Bolo- prognostication. This concern with the reliability
gna period involve the Moon. For example, in the of the tables is entirely consistent with the usual
famous observation of De Revolutionibus, book 4, account that he was disturbed by Ptolemy’s theory

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 97


30. Table of contents showing full
list of works included in the omni-
bus edition containing Ptolemy’s
Tetrabiblos, 1493. Note additional
titles added by hand. By permission
of Biblioteca Universitaria di Bolo-
gna. A.V.KK.VI.26.1. Further repro-
duction by any means is prohibited.

of the Moon because he had read Regiomon­ta­ made at Rome on November 6, 1500. Copernicus
nus’s Epitome, book 5, proposition 22. But, as reported that he observed the eclipse at two hours
Jerzy Dobrzycki and Richard Kremer have shown after midnight. Novara’s prediction of that event,
in the case of the little-known Viennese physi- made on January 20, 1500, affords a rare oppor-
cian and ephemeridist Johann Angelus (Johann tunity to correlate a specific prognostication with
Engel; d. 1512), there is evidence for a more wide- an observation by Copernicus:
spread interest in improving the common Alfon-
sine-based almanacs by introducing innovations This year an eclipse of the moon will occur on the
into planetary theory.134 And the examples of An- fifth of November at night. And the moon will be
gelus and Copernicus begin to provide a different eclipsed around the northern node at 24 degrees of
Taurus and almost all of the moon’s body will fall
sort of reason for the turn to theory, a reason situ-
into the shadow. The beginning of the eclipse will
ated in the space of practical astrology.
be at 7:30 p.m.; the middle of the eclipse will be a
Consider the other Copernican observations
little later at 9 p.m., although some astronomers
about which there is some knowledge. Coperni- place the beginning of the eclipse at 7 p.m. or 8 p.m.
cus observed conjunctions of Saturn and the And so there is some error in the calculation: in-
Moon in Taurus on January 9 and March 4, 1500. deed, whoever makes a mistake in even one sixth
For the year 1500, both Novara and Marco Scri­ part of an hour [10'] in the equations will fall into
banario predicted a conjunction of Mars and Sat- error. An even more serious error concerns the
urn in Taurus in February, an ill omen. Novara’s motion of the eighth sphere because it is necessary
forecast for the year 1500 went to press on Janu- to acknowledge that the equinoxes are continually
ary 20, eleven days after Copernicus’s first ob- moving. . . . And whoever fails to notice this will
servation. We can only speculate that the second suppose one thing, but, in the conclusion, will
observation, two months later, might have been reach the opposite result.
made as a check on the first.
Perhaps the most interesting observation is Novara says no more about the eighth sphere but
that of a partial lunar eclipse that Copernicus concludes that “the effects of this eclipse will not

98 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


appear this year.” A wise conclusion indeed! His gna, the Averroist Alessandro Achillini (1463–
prediction was off by at least five hours, depend- 1512) was the most authoritative philosophical
ing on how one interprets Copernicus’s descrip- voice on this subject. He was well connected to
tion of his Rome observation: “I observed the . . . the Bentivoglio court and eventually became one
eclipse, also with great care, at Rome on 6 No- of the Sedici’s highest-paid professors at the uni-
vember 1500, two hours after the midnight which versity. In argument he was said to be so sharp
initiated 6 November . . . ten digits in the north that he merited the squib “It is either the Devil
were darkened.”135 Novara made no reference to or Achillini.”138 Benedictus Hectoris published
this discrepancy in the next year’s forecast; but it his enormously dense On the Orbs in 1498. As a
is clear that short-term inaccuracies of this mag- defen­der of the Averroist-Aristotelian system of
nitude offered no special difficulty for the credi- concentric orbs, Achillini regarded Ptolemy’s ec-
bility of the forecast. The discrepancy could ei- centrics and epicycles as absurd fictions; he was
ther be ignored (as in this case) or rolled over into also critical of Ptolemy’s handling of Mercury and
a long-term explanation of terrestrial effects. Venus. According to Achillini, Ptolemy contra-
It now seems reasonable to conclude that the dicted himself. In the Almagest, book 9, chapter 1,
late-fifteenth-century Bologna culture of prog- he said that he could not detect whether the infe-
nostication furnished an important context for rior planets ever eclipsed the Sun; hence he con-
Copernicus’s initial concerns about the lunar cluded that they must be above the Sun. Subse-
theory. As I have argued, Copernicus likely en- quently, however, Ptolemy conceded that Mercury
countered Regiomontanus’s Epitome at Bologna and Venus fell onto the same line that connected
through Novara. Both Copernicus and Novara the Sun and the observer—a position with which
would have had a keen interest in Regiomonta- Geber agreed.139 Achillini believed that this sec-
nus’s account of the Moon because the Moon had ond or “lower” ordering was correct. In its ­defense,
a crucial role in the computation of eclipses; and he inferred the presence of Mercury and Venus
eclipses, because of their long-term effects, were while explaining away their invisibility: the Sun’s
of great significance in the annual prognostica- brightness blots out the tiny planets when they
tions.136 Rheticus’s remark in the Narratio Prima are close; their transparency may not block the
contains more than an echo of Copernicus’s early Sun’s rays; moreover, their great distance from
problematic: “The theory of eclipses all by itself Earth causes the cone of the eclipse’s shadow to
seems to maintain respect for astronomy among be “lost in the air” or terminated before it reaches
uneducated people; yet we see daily how much it the Earth. These were the reasons why no one
differs nowadays from common calculation in had observed solar transits. Although Achillini’s
the prediction of both the duration and extent of commentary picked out for exegesis exactly the
eclipses.”137 same passage cited by Pico just three years earlier,
Achillini failed to mention Averroës’ claim that
The Averroists and the Order he had observed “dark spots” or to draw the Pico-
of Mercury and Venus nian moral that dissensus betokened uncertainty.
Rather, in the end, he heralded agreement: “It is
As we have seen, Copernicus was not alone in re- unnecessary to say that Aristotle supposed the op-
garding planetary order as disputed knowledge. posite from Ptolemy, as Averroës said.” In fact:
Ptolemy’s Almagest had already expressed doubts “Experience conforms to this order of the plan-
about the order of the inferior planets with respect ets  .  .  . it can be rationally conjectured through
to the Sun; in 1496, Regiomontanus renewed the exact instruments.”140
doubt by calling it a controversy. And Pico’s cri- Yet there was an Averroist answer to Pico’s
tique seriously aggravated the problem by con- complaint about the astronomers’ disagreement
necting these doubts to the general viability of concerning the order of the inferior planets and
astrological theory and practice. Together, these the arbitrary assignment of physical qualities. It
developments must have put some pressure on came from Lucio Bellanti, the Sienese philoso-
Sacrobosco and Tetrabiblos commentators as well pher and astrologer who had taken the trouble to
as natural philosophers for whom the order of answer—or at least to say something about—
Venus and Mercury was unproblematic. each and every one of Pico’s objections, including
Among Copernicus’s contemporaries at Bolo- the arguments in Disputations, book 10, chapter 4:

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 99


He [Pico] does not know that there is a clear dem- awkward and ineffective. Perhaps this confluence
onstration concerning the place of Mercury and of ideas, appearing in such rapid succession, set
Venus beneath the Sun, whether such [a demon- the twenty-five-year-old Copernicus to thinking
stration] be elicited from the size[s] of the epicycles about a different kind of approach to the ordering
or from the greater apparent size of these bodies; of the inferior planets.
[consequently] those who follow after him are un-
familiar with these [phenomena]. But Averroës
says that these things are of no moment, since he Copernicus’s Commentariolus,
asserts in Metaphysics XII that the appearances of or, Perhaps, the Theoric of
these planets can be saved by different poles in the Seven Postulates
same orb, while denying those very foolish epicy-
cles, which even now deceive philosophy. Never- Copernicus was not a systematic philosopher ei-
theless, he suffered from old age and could not ther in the traditional sense of a scholastic com-
learn astrology and thus did not understand either mentator like Achillini or in the later sense of a
that of the ancients or of his own time.141 Descartes.143 The Commentariolus more closely
resembles an astronomical theoric, a laying down
Bellanti was as imprecise on this matter as he of principles preparatory to a later work. It is,
was emphatic. He did not bother to supply his as Albert of Brudzewo characterized Peurbach’s
“clear demonstration,” nor did he describe Aver- work, descriptive or narrative rather than demon-
roës’ solution to the uncertain ordering. Did he strative, like the Almagest. It is compact and
mean that there are two planets within the same tightly argued, but it is also spare and unforth-
orb? To Ptolemaic-style astronomers like Coper- coming about what is prior or presupposed. By
nicus and Novara, Bellanti’s denial of the value contrast, De Revolutionibus and, even more, Rhe-
of epicycles could only have seemed superficial ticus’s Narratio Prima are more readily open in
and objectionable—perhaps one further source stating their assumptions, as one might expect,
of Copernicus’s notorious mistrust of natural because the former had many decades to ripen
philosophers. The proposed solution to the prob- on the vine. It is thus often tempting to use the
lem of order was no solution at all: even if one later works to interpret assumptions made in the
tinkered with the poles around which the (con- earlier one.
centric) orbs of Mercury and Venus were said to Sometime before 1514—perhaps in 1510, per-
revolve, such an approach did not address the haps much earlier—Copernicus composed this
controversy over their relative order. And to any- characteristically terse work, one whose list of
one who hoped to use planetary models to make basic postulates shows notable correspondences
astrological predictions, Bellanti’s reply would to the conclusiones of book 1 in Regiomontanus’s
have appeared entirely useless. Epitome of the Almagest.144 Historians commonly
Yet Bellanti’s argument with Pico provided a call it the Commentariolus, although Coperni-
striking textual locus that again called attention cus’s own title is unknown.145 For convenience, I
to one of Pico’s most important astronomical ob- follow the traditional designation. The Commen-
jections to the claims of astrology. Furthermore, tariolus presents a new “order of the orbs” in the
the Averroistic reference could have directed Co- form of a derivation: “If there be granted to us
pernicus’s attention to Achillini’s just-published some postulates [petitiones], which some call axi-
De Orbibus and to its unsatisfying treatment of oms.”146 There are seven of these postulates,
the ordering of Mercury and Venus. As Hectoris which together lay out the elements of a new ce-
published (and sold) not only Achillini’s work but lestial order. Copernicus relied here, it seems, on
also Pico’s Disputations and Domenico Maria No- Aristotle’s sense of a principle or petitio in the
vara’s prognostications, there is every likelihood Posterior Analytics: “any provable proposition that
that these volumes would have been found on is assumed and used without being proved”
the same shelf in Hectoris’s shop, or perhaps in rather than “that which is in itself necessarily
Novara’s home library.142 Copernicus and Novara, true and must be thought to be so.”147 It is in the
introduced to the Viennese initiative of Peurbach first sense that Copernicus may have intended
and Regiomontanus in its Italian incarnation, his remark that “anybody familiar with the art of
surely would have seen Bellanti’s Averroistic reply mathematics” (e quibus mathematicae artis non ig-
to Pico’s objections about planetary ordering as narus) ought to understand what he is doing.

100 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


Noel Swerdlow has aptly observed of the seven kind of book from the one that he ultimately pro-
postulates that only two of them (numbered 3 duced, a book much closer to the spirit of Osian-
and 6) function as logically prior, whereas four der, in which he argued simply that the Earth’s
(numbered 2, 4, 5, and 7) actually serve as con­ daily and annual motions, although unproven as-
sequences of the aforementioned two. Consider sumptions, actually save more appearances than
first the assumptions, then the consequences. had hitherto been imagined by the Pythagoreans?
Had he done so, he might have spared himself a
3. All orbs encircle the Sun, which is, so to speak, good deal of trouble. He could have dedicated
in the middle of all of them, and so that the center
such a book to an earlier pope, published it much
of the universe is near the Sun.148
sooner than 1543, and avoided the anonymous let-
ter to the reader, the defense of a seemingly ab-
I suggest that this postulate, and even more ex-
surd premise, and the search for any revisions of
plicitly number 6, can be read as Copernicus’s
natural philosophy and theology. Yet already in
resolution of Peurbach’s conundrum: the Earth’s
the Commentariolus it is clear that he had decided
annual motion explains the Sun’s apparent mo-
to advance the Earth’s motions as physical postu-
tions as a mirrored effect.
lates. Of course, whether the Earth is a point or
6. Whatever motions appear to us to belong to the a physical body, when the Earth and the Sun are
Sun are not due to [the motion of] the Sun but [to mutually transposed, then the period-distance re-
the motions of] our orb, [the orb of] the Earth, with lation nicely follows: “One [planet] exceeds an-
which we revolve around the Sun just as any other other in rapidity of revolution in the same order in
[moving] star. The Earth is thus possessed of sev- which they traverse the larger or smaller perime-
eral motions.149 ters of [their] circles.”154 Further, once the sidereal
periods of Venus and Mercury were determined
In a revealing comment at the very end of the separately from the Sun’s annual motion, then
postulates, Copernicus contended that both his the period-distance relationship definitively re-
own hypotheses and those of the natural phi- solved their ordering.155
losophers should be regarded as inferences from Thus, Copernicus’s insight left a dilemma: the
the appearances—from effects to causes—rather period-distance relation underdetermines the
than established by authority or by apodictic Earth’s status as either a mathematical point or a
demonstration.150 Copernicus’s assumptions fol- physical body. Although the period-distance en-
lowed the Pythagoreans, but, rather than being tailment might have satisfied his psychological
arbitrary, as theirs were, his were to be seen as intuition that he was right to make the mathe-
reasoned: “Lest anybody suppose that, with the matical assumption, it did not strictly authorize
Pythagoreans, we have asserted the Earth’s mo- the move to make the Earth’s annual motion a
tion rashly, he will find here strong evidence in physical premise. So, why did Copernicus choose
[our] explanation of the circles. For, the argu- the second, more difficult, alternative? I can
ments by which the natural philosophers try think of only one reason: If the Earth did not
above all to establish the Earth’s immobility rest ­really move, then one could not claim that the
for the most part upon appearances. But all their planets—and their associated powers—really
arguments are the first to collapse here, since we were ordered by their periods of revolution. To
overturn the Earth’s immobility also by means of uphold the conclusion, Copernicus somehow
an appearance.”151 Rheticus and Copernicus needed to persuade himself of the truth—or at
would later expand the claim: “This one move- least the likelihood—of the fundamental premise
ment of the Earth satisfies an almost infinite and its corollaries. Without such a demonstra-
number of appearances.”152 And they would rein- tion, he was in no position to answer Pico’s cri-
vent Plato and the Pythagoreans as “the greatest tique concerning the astronomical foundations
mathematicians of that divine age,” whom Co- of theoretical astrology.
pernicus followed “in judging that circular mo- Already in the Commentariolus, this dilemma
tions ought to be attributed to the Earth’s spheri- compelled Copernicus to address the physical
cal body in order to explain the appearances.”153 implications of the Earth’s motion. For example,
At this point, a counterfactual speculation may even if the Earth’s center is not the center of the
assist. What if Copernicus had written a different universe, it is still the center of gravity toward

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 101


which heavy things move (postulate 2). If the troducing humanist logical and persuasive re-
Earth rotates daily on its axis, explaining the ap- sources to defend the equivalents of the main
parent risings and settings of the stars, then the postulates from his earlier treatise. A further con-
three other contiguous elements must move to- sideration is that the Epitome also suited Coper-
gether with the Earth (postulate 5). Further, the nicus’s general approach. Although Copernicus
size of the universe must be much larger than combined geometrical and physical reasoning,
usually conceived, as the distance between the as one would obviously expect in a mixed sci-
Earth and the Sun is “imperceptible” compared ence such as optics, harmonics or astronomy,
with the distance to the fixed stars (postulate 4). his main practices were geometrical. His major
By starting from a mathematical rather than a claims about planetary order rested on geomet-
physical premise, Copernicus opened up prob- rical constructions to which was added time:
lems of physical justification and proof of a kind hence the periods of circular revolutions of
that his predecessors had never faced. points. In this sense, the weight of his stronger
The problems were daunting, and it is perhaps physical claims rested initially on the way that
no surprise that Copernicus remained silent he put together models of this sort. He was, as
about various other physical implications of his sixteenth-century writers often remarked, a “sec-
main assumption. For example, if he was follow- ond ­Ptolemy” (and not a second Aristotle, a second
ing Sacrobosco’s Sphere in the Commentariolus— Aver­roës, or even a second Peurbach). If Coper-
and it is by no means clear that he was—then the nicus intended to deliver true conclusions about
Earth and its elements would need to be embed- the world from a group of assumed premises,
ded in and continuous with a circularly mov- this was surely neither the practice followed by
ing celestial sphere that possessed qualities of the philosopher Pico nor the typical method of
an eternal, unchanging substance.156 In that philosophical disputations in which, like Achil-
case, how could it also be a “center of gravity”? lini, Bellanti, and Capuano, the disputant was ex-
Indeed, how could a perfect, revolving sphere pected to argue an exercise in utramque partem,
also contain diverse rectilinear motions, violent that is, from both sides of a proposition, before re-
weather events, and complex human behaviors? jecting the affirmative arguments and providing
And, in addition, by reordering the planets, how his own solution or reply to the question.159
could one justify upsetting the planets’ fixed ele- The abbreviated form, the succinct style, and
mental qualities? Further, how could one have the absence of prefatory material make it difficult
a traditional—or indeed any—astrology? Coper- to say from explicit references which audience
nicus’s characteristic silence on such matters— Copernicus hoped to reach in the Commentario-
his refusal to philosophize beyond the bare mini- lus. It was certainly not some hypothetical—
mum—both allows and encourages the view that and anachronistic—“scientific community.”160
he must have struggled with the physical status Our reconstruction of the Bologna period makes
of his primary assumption. credible a more exacting guess about the kind of
These considerations may also help to explain audience that Copernicus intended: academic
his choice of literary form. The organization of prognosticators (exemplified by Domenico Maria
the postulates, as Swerdlow plausibly suggests, Novara, Giacomo Benazzi, and Marco Scribana­
may simply indicate that this was a preliminary rio) and court astrologers (Paul of Middelburg,
draft. But if Jerzy Dobrzycki’s hypothesis is cor- Luca Gaurico); sympathetic fellow canons at Var­
rect, then the postulates were consciously mod- mia (Tiedemann Giese); former friends and
eled after corresponding topics in Regiomonta- teachers at Krakow (John of Glogau, Albert of
nus’s Epitome.157 This illuminating comparison Brudzewo); ephemeridists (like Johannes Stöffler
opens the possibility of viewing Copernicus as and Johannes Angelus); and opponents of Pico—
both imitating and rewriting Regiomontanus’s in short, those later referred to under the generic
Ptolemy rather than remaining within the frame- designation “mathematicians” in the preface to
work of authority delimited by the scholastic De Revolutionibus. Copernicus was consistently
practices of Sacrobosco and his commentators.158 dismissive of those whom he called “philoso-
Later, in De Revolutionibus, Copernicus ­developed phers,” even as he himself engaged in various
a further textual transformation, dropping the kinds of philosophical bricolage.
austere strategy of axioms and postulates and in- When, on May 1, 1514, Matthew of Miechów (1457–​

102 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


1523), a Krakow University physician, geographer, time, Pico would have had no opportunity, in
and historian, composed an entry in his personal his eighth and ninth books, of impugning not
library for a manuscript or a gathering of six merely astrology but also astronomy. For we see
leaves, he gave it the following title: “A Six-Folio daily how markedly common calculation departs
Theoric Asserting That the Earth Moves while from the truth.”166 This telling remark—the
the Sun Remains at Rest” (Sexternus Theorice sole explicit reference to Pico in the Copernican
­A sserentis Terram Moveri, Solem vero Quiescere).161 ­corpus—urges a more ambitious question: Was
For Matthew, and perhaps also for Copernicus, Pico’s objection about planetary order really a
the Commentariolus was a theoric—in the sense concern of the earlier work?
of a group of seven postulates or assumed propo-
sitions.162 The Commentariolus left full “mathe- Copernicus, Pico,
matical demonstrations” of the individual plane- and De Revolutionibus
tary models explicitly to “another volume.”163 It is
difficult to escape the impression that in assum- The Commentariolus is much less revealing of
ing these postulates, Copernicus hoped they its origins than either the Narratio Prima or the
would resolve disagreements among astrono- mature De Revolutionibus. Copernicus never
mers. Should the planets revolve around the cen- published the former, and it is not clear that he
ter of the universe on concentric orbs, as the ever intended to do so. His full vision of a Sun-
Averroists wished? Should they revolve around centered cosmos evolved over more than three
off-​center axes, as Ptolemy allowed? And was ­decades before it finally appeared in 1543. Rheti-
there a secure common principle by which to cus’s Narratio Prima, the first published state­
order the planets against the criticisms of Pico? ment of Copernicus’s theory, was richly inter-
The hope for consensus on these questions lay spersed with biographical references, citations of
not in the premises but in the power of the de- ancient and modern authorities, and the author’s
rived consequences. For Copernicus could not ap- own enthusiastic outbursts of praise for the
peal to the force of demonstrative reasoning in man to whom he always referred with undis-
which, as Aristotle held in the Topics, “things are guised adulation as “my teacher.” Not surpris-
true and primary which command belief through ingly, De Revolutionibus, the mature work, is also
themselves and not through anything else; for re- much closer to the Narratio Prima than to the Com­
garding the first principles of science it is unnec- mentariolus in its full engagement with support-
essary to ask any further question as to ‘why,’ but ing and opposing authorities. Traces and residues
each principle should of itself command belief.”164 from Copernicus’s early formative period show
At best, Copernicus could resort to dialectical up more clearly in the later works than in the ear-
strategies of argumentation, as André Goddu sug­ lier. It is to these later footprints that one must
gests; and this meant that he could show a prob- turn in order to illuminate the earlier tracks.
able world but not a necessary one.165 This brings us back to the famous book 1, chap-
Pico della Mirandola’s name did not show up ter 10, of De Revolutionibus, where Copernicus
either in Copernicus’s characteristically terse Com­ reviewed the ancient philosophers’ claims about
mentariolus or in De Revolutionibus. But there is the order of the planets. Some of his language
important evidence in the Narratio Prima that in- bears a strong resemblance to Pico’s account. For
creases our confidence that Copernicus was try- example, Copernicus, like Pico, grouped together
ing to answer Pico’s complaint. Rheticus, whose Plato, Ptolemy, “a good number of the moderns”
sympathetic testimony provides an unusually re- (bona pars recentiorum), and al-Bitruji. Of the last
liable firsthand acquaintance with Copernicus’s he wrote, in his characteris­tically compressed
thoughts, had composed his book in 1539 while way, that “al-Bitruji places Venus above the sun,
living with Copernicus in Frombork. Rheticus and Mercury below it.” Copernicus’s language
had consistently presented Copernicus as the does not carry quite the detail provided by Pico,
equal of Ptolemy and Regiomontanus, the true but the enumeration of authorities is strikingly
successor to Ptolemy. After reviewing Coperni- similar.167 Unlike Pico, however, Copernicus con-
cus’s solar theory, Rheticus noted with an air of sistently framed his problem and his criticism in
triumph that “if [my teacher’s] account of the ce- the discourse of theoretical astronomy. He did
lestial phenomena had existed a little before our not, like Pico, merely list authorities and their po-

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 103


sitions, nor did he simply dismiss the inconsis- idiom of the theorics. As Swerdlow has pointed
tencies between them. As would be expected, he out, when Copernicus said that all the planets are
introduced a different sort of reasoning when he “related to a single center,” he spoke of the “con-
said that “those who locate Venus and Mercury vex orb” of Venus’s sphere and the “concave orb”
below the Sun base their reasoning on the wide of Mars.172 This part of the account ended with
space which they notice between the Sun and the the famous dithyramb to the Sun, with its mix-
Moon.” Copernicus then provided values for the ture of pagan and Christian images, and the sug-
absolute distances that define the space between gestively poetic passage that echoes Giovanni
the Moon and Mercury, Mercury and Venus, and Pontano’s De Rebus Coelestis (1512): “Meanwhile,
Venus and the Sun. the Earth has intercourse with the Sun, and is
Immediately following this discussion, how- impregnated for its yearly parturition.”173 This
ever, Copernicus took up a question that Pico humanist admixture of theorics and poetics was
dealt with directly and about which he could have prelude to a final restatement of Copernicus’s
had no knowledge independently of Pico.168 In own aesthetic, already presaged in the preface
his critical editorial notes to De Revolutionibus, Ed­ to his work: “We discover a marvelous fitting to-
ward Rosen showed that Copernicus could have gether of the parts [symmetriam] of the universe,
known the previously cited Averroës passage only and an established harmonious linkage between
from the Disputations, because the Arabic text the motion of the spheres and their size, such as
did not exist and the work was available only in a can be found in no other way.” For the ordering
Hebrew translation.169 “In his Paraphrase of Ptol- of Mercury and Venus, then, Copernicus would
emy,” wrote Copernicus, “Averroës reports hav- not make an ad hoc appeal to authority but in-
ing seen something blackish when he found a voked a general structural principle that applied
conjunction of the Sun and Mercury indicated in uniformly to the entire planetary order.
the tables. And thus these two planets are judged That Copernicus’s new representation of the
to be moving below the Sun’s sphere.”170 Not sur- machina mundi avoided explicit reference to astro-
prisingly, Copernicus judged the Averroistic claim logical matters shows at least the persistent force
to be “weak and unreliable” (infirma sit et incerta). of ancient genres of writing in the sixteenth cen-
His argument was based on the space that would tury. “My teacher,” Rheticus wrote, “has written a
be required to fill up the region between the work of six books in which, in imitation of Ptolemy,
Earth and the Sun, a space that could not accom- he has embraced the whole of astronomy, stating
modate Venus’s epicycle, “which carries it 45 de- and proving individual propositions mathemati-
grees more or less to either side of the sun [and] cally and by the geometrical method.”174 Ptolemy,
must be six times longer than the line drawn as we have seen, did not treat astrological matters
from the Earth’s center to Venus’ perigee, as will in the Almagest—and neither did Regiomontanus
be demonstrated in the proper place.”171 in his Epitome—but had carefully reserved their
From Averroës, Copernicus moved to reject Ptol­ consideration to a separate work, the Tetrabiblos. It
emy’s use of the criterion of elongations (limited seems that Copernicus had in mind something
versus unlimited) for determining the planetary com­parable when, in a suppressed passage of
order. Once again, both the language and the con­ the autograph manuscript of De Revolutionibus,
clusion of book 1, chapter 10, strongly resembled he wrote: “I have also assumed that the Earth
those of Pico: “Ptolemy [Almagest, book 9, chap- moves in certain revolutions, on which, as the
ter 1] argues also that the Sun must move in the cornerstone, I strive to erect the entire science of
middle between the planets [medium ferri Solem] the stars.”175
which show every elongation from it and those If Copernicus ever intended to compose a com-
which do not. This argument carries no conviction panion astrological work based on heliocentric
because its error is revealed by the fact that the principles—no mean feat in its own right—one
Moon too shows every elongation from the Sun.” might expect that, “in imitation of Ptolemy,” he
Finally, Copernicus moved away from the Pico- would have followed the same classificatory prac-
nian text altogether. He used the Roman Martia- tice. Yet, in spite of his assisting Domenico Maria
nus Capella as an authority for what he took to be Novara in his prognosticatory undertakings, his
the correct ordering of Venus and Mercury but later medical training at Padua, and his own medi-
again encoded his discussion in the unmistakable cal practice in Varmia, we know of no horoscopes

104 Copernicus’s Space of Possibilities


that he cast, no prognostications that he issued, Still, these absences ought not to obscure the
and no orations in praise of astrology such as scope of Copernicus’s explanatory ambitions. At
were commonplace in his lifetime. And, of course, one stroke, by assuming the Earth’s annual revo-
these absences have only nurtured the image of lution, he had provided a single explanation for
Copernicus as immune from any interest or en- Peurbach’s puzzle concerning the Sun’s recur-
gagement with astrological practice. rent appearance in the planets’ motions and a so-
Copernicus might have believed that if astron- lution to the old controversy about the ordering of
omy’s foundations were reformed as he envi- Venus and Mercury, now forcefully energized by
sioned, then that change alone would be suffi­ Pico’s assault on the planetary ordering that un-
cient to sustain the traditional astrology found in derlay theoretical astrology. Yet, for that explana-
the Tetrabiblos. But following Pico’s critique of tion to carry weight, the Earth’s motion had to
the arbitrary association of elemental qualities be shown to be real. Because De Revolutionibus’s
and planetary order, it seems far more likely that manner of presentation hid much of its origins,
Copernicus would have recognized that a radical leaving only traces of the initial problem situa-
revision of the prevailing celestial arrangement tion, excavation of the original problematic from
would require a corresponding reform of astrolo- the surviving residues shows what the heliocen-
gy’s principles. Indeed, besides the reassignment tric hypothesis was initially intended to explain.177
of physical qualities made necessary by the plan- Once having posed the hypothesis, however, Co-
etary reordering, Pico’s other objections would pernicus gradually noticed other entailments—
need to be answered in a manner superior to that new explanations of phenomena for which he was
of Bellanti—for example, the house-division prob­ probably not even looking (such as why Mars, Ju-
lem and the uncertainty of the instruments and piter, and Saturn appear brightest at opposition
tables. We may well wonder whether he would but Mercury and Venus do so at inferior conjunc-
have turned to Regiomontanus’s astrology, as he tion) and, at the same time, new problems for
did with his planetary theory. In any case, just as which he did not have ready-made solutions (in-
a circularly moving Earth was incoherent with cluding the disordering of the planets’ elemental
Aristotle’s theory of the elements, so too the phys- attributes, the fall of heavy bodies to earth, the pre­
ics and meteorology underlying traditional astrol- cessional motion, and the size of the universe).
ogy would need to be rethought.176 Reformulat- The first group must have given him the confi­
ing Ptolemy’s Almagest was evidently more than dence that he had good reason to persevere as
enough for one man. Perhaps Copernicus believed much as the second must have given him serious
that he could leave to the young and astrologically pause about publishing before he could produce
skilled Rheticus the reconfiguring of the Tetra- credible solutions. The subsequent history of the
biblos, just as he had explicitly left debate about Copernican question would continue to mirror
the world’s infinitude to the philosophers. these early, unresolved tensions.

Crisis of the Bologna Prognosticators 105


andasse a di 26 de zugno, zoè sabato proximo che 1984b, 144. I have modified Rosen’s translation in
vene, V.S. haverla optima ellectione ad expugnandum order to bring out more precisely the legal terms:
inimicos et ad ottinere ogni victoria, et V.S. haveria “Statuimus, quod quilibet Canonicus de novo in-
optimo fine ne le sue facende, perche tunc la luna
trans, nisi in Sacra pagina Magister vel Baccalaureus
abraza Jupiter et Venus de aspecti beati, et ipsa luna
erit lumine crescens; et iddo V.S. ogni modo et omni- formatus, aut in Decretis, vel in iure civili, aut in me-
bus remotis pigli li predicti 26 dì et sera bon per lei, dicina seu physica Doctor aut Licenciatus exstiterit,
auxilliante deo. Fatilo, fatilo, fatilo. Io me arecomando post residentiam primi anni, si Capitulo visum et ex-
mille volte a V. Ill. S., la quale Dio conservi in stato pediens fuerit, teneatur ad triennium ad minus in
felicissimo. aliquo studio privilegiato in una dictarum faculta-
tum studere.” On the distinction between medicine
and physic, see Cook 1990, 398–99.
3. Copernicus and the Crisis of the
10. See Monfasani 1993, esp. 252–57.
Bologna Prognosticators, 1496 –1500
11. See Knoll 1975, 137–56.
1. Spellings of proper names were quite varied in 12. Prowe 1883–84, 1:73–82.
this period. Novara was also known as Dominicus 13. Rheticus 1971, 111.
Maria de Novaria Ferrariensis or Domenico Maria di 14. See Ady 1937, chaps. 6–7.
Novara. And for various prognostications, we find, 15. The result was a governo misto: “It pleases the
inter alia, Domenego Maria da Nouara (Italian, 1497), lord Pope that the statutes dealing with the authority,
Dominicho fer. da noara (Italian, 1492), Dominicus jurisdiction and powers of all the magistracies of the
Marie de Ferraria (Lat., 1490), and Dominici Marie said city shall be observed, and that none of the said
fer. de noaria (Latin, 1492). See also Rosen 1995a, magistracies shall have power to determine anything
129. without the consent of the [papal] Legate or governor,
2. Rosen 1995a has made much of this motion of and that, in like manner, the Legate governor shall
the pole; for useful references to the nineteenth- and not have power to determine anything without the
early-twentieth-century literature, see Rosen 1974. consent of the magistracies deputed to rule the city”
3. The existence of such an institution as a private (ibid., 39–40).
humanist school, a gathering of learned men of let- 16. Ibid., 90.
ters, or even a physical structure, such as a house or 17. Ibid., 132.
villa, has been called into serious question by Han- 18. Ibid., 132–33.
kins 1991. 19. See Watson 1993, 5.
4. See esp. Kuhn 1957, 129; Burtt 1932, 54–55; Stim­ 20. Christoph Scheurl, “Ad Sixtum Tucherum”
son 1917, 25. (November 22, 1506), in Knaake and Von Soden 1962,
5. Richard Lemay situates Copernicus in a Krakov- 1:39; quoted and trans. in Watson 1993, 157. The earth-
ian astrological context. He suggests that Coperni- quake occurred in 1505.
cus’s freedom from the need for patronage allowed 21. For brief but useful details on the pontificate of
him the unusual luxury of being able to attend di- the Borgia pope Alexander VI (1492–1503), see Kelly
rectly to theoretical astronomy: “To be able to indulge 1986, 252–54.
in the detached and independent pursuit of astro- 22. “Professor mathematum” is the somewhat am-
nomical studies goaded by nothing else than the love biguous phrase used by Rheticus to report what Co-
of truth, and furthermore to contemplate with seren- pernicus told him in 1539 (Narratio Prima in Prowe
ity a lifetime dedication to the realization of a single 1883–84, 2: pt. 1, 297). Edward Rosen’s “lectured in
major idea, was not given to the ordinary astronomer- mathematics” (Rheticus 1971, 111) and “lectured pub-
astrologer of Copernicus’ time” (Lemay 1978, 354). licly in Rome” (Rosen 1984b, 71) are helpful rendi-
6. John lectured from 1468 to 1507, Albert from tions. But note that Rheticus did not say that Coper-
1474 to 1495 (Birkenmajer 1900). nicus “disputed in Rome,” language that he might
7. See chapter 1. For a useful inventory of Krakow have used to signal the format of a philosophical dis-
prognostications, see Markowski 1992. putation. Further, he does not specify which of the
8. Abenragel 1485. Swerdlow and Neugebauer call several mathematical subjects Copernicus might have
this “one of the most comprehensive and influential been explaining. Rather, he seems to have lectured to
Arabic astrological treatises to be translated into a mixed audience that could have included prognosti-
Latin” (Swerdlow and Neugebauer 1984, 4). In addi- cators, painters, and instrument makers, students at
tion, Copernicus owned the 1492 Venice edition of the Roman Sapienza, and learned members of the
the Alfonsine tables and the 1490 Augsburg edition papal court.
of Regiomontanus’s Tabulae Directionum. The Euclid 23. This judgment is based on Bonney 1991, 88.
edition was published in Venice in 1482, with the 24. Ibid. For the wider historiographical issues in
commentary of Campanus of Novara (see Czarto- the international system of alliances of which Italy
ryski 1978, 365–66). was a part, see Marino 1994.
9. Prowe 1883–84, 2: pt. 2, 516–17; trans. Rosen 25. Guicciardini 1969, 48–49.

526 Notes to Pages 76 –81


26. Ibid. 44. Walker 1958, 54–59.
27. Phillips 1977, 122. 45. “Veniamus ad neotericos. Nicolaus Oresmius,
28. See Abulafia 1995, introduction, 48. et philosophus acutissimus et peritissimus mathe-
29. Guicciardini 1623, fol. 22r. Although science is maticus, astrologicam superstitionem peculiari com-
a possible translation, I avoid it. Guicciardini is menatrio indignabundus etiam insectatur” (Pico
clearly distinguishing between those who make their della Mirandola 1946–52, 1:58, bk. 1).
predictions employing certain acquired, intellectual 46. See Popkin 2003, 1993, 1996; Schmitt 1972a.
skills and those for whom knowledge of the future is In private conversations, Richard Popkin urged me to
somehow revealed. consider the possible influence of Sextus Empiricus
30. Guicciardini 1969, 43–45. on Pico; cf. Garin 1983, 87.
31. See esp. Niccoli 1990. I discuss this distinction 47. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 1:27.
in chapter 1. 48. Ibid., 29; see especially the helpful paraphrases
32. See Skinner 1978, 1:116–18. of Craven 1981, 131–55, and Parel 1992, 19. Other use-
33. Niccoli 1990, 163–66. Cuius, cuia, coioni, is a ful, although not always reliable, summaries of Pico
nonsensical declension with probable sexual conno- are Allen 1966, 19–34; Tester 1987, 207–13; and Thorn­-
tations: cuia = cuglia, a pinnacle or spire of a steeple; dike 1923–58, 4:531–39.
coioni = coglioni, testicles. 49. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 1:29.
34. A good example may be found in Giovanni 50. Ibid., 1:196, bk. 3, chap. 4. Cf. Ficino 1989, bk.
Garzoni’s “Laus Astrologie” (Biblioteca Universitaria 3, chap. 3, 257: “Spirit is a very tenuous body, as if
di Bologna: Garzoni 1500, fol. 207v). now it were soul and not body, and now body and not
35. See Bühler 1958, 45. Hectoris’s production may soul. In its power there is very little of the earthy na-
have exceeded Bühler’s estimates, however, as may ture, but more of the watery, more likewise of the
be seen by consulting the books listed under his airy, and again the greatest proportion of the stellar
name in the catalogue of printers of sixteenth-century fire. The very quantities of the stars and elements
books held by the Biblioteca Estense, Modena. have come into being according to the measures of
36. Discussed in chapter 2. On the Este astrologi- these degrees. This spirit assuredly lives in all as the
cal culture, see Biondi 1986; Lo Zodiaco del Principe proximate cause of all generation and motion, con-
1992. cerning which the poet said, ‘A Spirit nourishes
37. Savonarola 1497, 370, 339–40; quoted and within’ [Spiritus intus alit].” Walker (1958, 57), argues
trans. in Niccoli 1990, 165. Apparently without real- for a very close connection between Pico and Ficino:
izing it, Carl Sagan furthered the objection of Pico “The chapters in the Adversus Astrologiam on celestial
and Savonarola: “Despite the efforts of ancient as- and human spirit are so close to Ficino’s thought that
tronomers and astrologers to put pictures in the it seems highly probable they derive from him.”
skies, a constellation is nothing more than an arbi- 51. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 1:190, bk. 3,
trary grouping of stars, composed of intrinsically chap.3.
dim stars that seem to us bright because they are 52. Ibid., 1:516–18, bk. 4, chap. 16. The opponent was
nearby, and intrinsically brighter stars that are some- Pierre d’Ailly.
what more distant” (Sagan 1980, 196–97). 53. The best account is, in fact, Eugenio Garin’s ex-
38. See Weinstein 1970, 286–88. cellent critical apparatus to his edition of the Dis-
39. The 1502 edition (Venice: Bernardino Vitali) putationes; but the otherwise thorough and admira-
eliminated many of the wearisome abbreviations of bly reliable D.  P. Walker gives this section no
the first edition. The 1554 edition adjusted Bellanti’s consideration.
print identity to read “Mathematicus et Physicus;” all 54. On the problem of domification, see North
page references are to the 1554 edition. 1986a, 27–30; Vanden Broecke 2003. These two
40. Bellanti 1554, “Ad Lectorem,” fol. A1v. methods, like the others, involved dividing a circle
41. Here Bellanti was indebted to Marsilio Ficino chosen from one of the three major astronomical ref-
(“amico meo”; ibid., 171), whose De Triplici Vita (1489) erence frames—equatorial, ecliptic, and horizon—
was already causing a stir. into arcs or “houses”—not to be confused with the
42. Basel: Hervagius, 1553, 1554; Cologne, 1578, 1580. zodiacal signs. The method ascribed to Regiomonta-
See Vasoli 1965, 598. nus involved dividing the equatorial circle into twelve
43. He was, in fact, thirty-one at his death, al- parts, starting from the intersection of the equator
though his epitaph at San Marco in Florence gives his and horizon; the Campanus method divided the
age as thirty-two: “Johannes iacet hic Mirandula. / prime vertical, a great circle that joined the observer’s
Caetera norunt et Tagus et Ganges forsan et antipo- zenith to the equinoctial points, and then projected
des / Ob. an. sal. 1494. Vix. an. 32” (Rocca 1964, 19); these points into the ecliptic.
cf. Cardano 1547b, 162: “Vixit igitur annis XXXIII. 55. On this point, Pico confused the tropical with
cum eius obitum Astrologus eodem anno praedixis- the sidereal year, and the original printed text mis-
set, qui etiam aduersus illum scripsit.” takenly reads “12 degrees” instead of “12 seconds.”

Notes to Pages 81–86 527


Pico della Mirandola 1496, fol. Giii: “Thebit annum 73. Zambelli 1966b, 181.
constare dixit ccclxv. diebus horis sex. minutis ix. 74. Cattini-Marzio and Romani 1982, 60, 62; for
gra[dus] xii.” Although the published value may con- an illustration of the castle, see Portoghesi n.d., 8; cf.
tain a typographical error, Garin, who made a critical Prowe 1883–84, 1:236.
comparison with the original manuscript, makes no 75. See Ridolfi 1989; Frati 1908; cf. Nussdorfer
comment here. 1993, 103–18.
56. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 2:330, bk. 9, 76. Archivio di Stato di Bologna: Archivio del no-
chap. 9. taio Lorenzo Benazzi, 1459–1508.
57. Ibid., 2:322, bk. 9, chap. 8. 77. This situation is not unlike the problematic of
58. See Shapin and Schaffer 1985, esp. chaps. 2, 4, contemporary social scientists, as described by Clif-
and 5. ford Geertz: “Social events do have causes and social
59. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 2:334, bk. 9, institutions effects; but it just may be that the road to
chap. 10. discovering what we assert in asserting this lies less
60. Ibid., 2:354, bk. 9, chap. 12. through postulating forces and measuring them
61. Ibid., 2:370, bk. 10, chap. 4. than through noting expressions and inspecting
62. Ibid., 2:372, bk. 10, chap. 4: “Quam quod me- them” (Geertz 1983, 34).
diorum situs et ordo penitus in ambiguo.” 78. Novara 1492. There are some slight differ-
63. Ibid., 2:374, bk. 10, chap. 4. ences between the Italian (Iudicio) and the Latin
64. See Rocca 1964, 5, 7. (Pronosticon).
65. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 2:374, bk. 10, 79. See Niccoli 1990, 10. To my knowledge, the
chap. 4. A manuscript titled “Almagestus Auerois” question of notarial uses of astrological prognostica-
appears on the inventory of Pico’s library (Kibre 1966, tion has simply not been investigated. In addition
no. 626, 203–4). to the Bologna prognosticators who came from no-
66. Pico della Mirandola 1946–52, 2:374, bk. 10, tarial families, we might mention the great naturalist
chap. 4: “Quomodo vero tres aliae se habeant, Sol, Ulisse Aldrovandi (1522–65), whose father, Teseo, was
Venus, Mercurius, incertum.” both a notary and the secretary of the Bologna senate
67. “Vixerat cum Dominico Maria Bononiensi, (see Franchini et. al. 1979, 10).
cuius rationes plane cognoverat, et observationes adi- 80. Malagola 1878, 572–73.
uverat” (Rheticus 1550a in Prowe 1883–84, 2:390). 81. Biblioteca Universitaria di Bologna: de Fundis
68. Tabarroni 1987, 177; Biliński 1989, 38–39. At 1435, opening: “Altissimi dei nostri Ihesus Christi
the time, the via Galliera was one of the most impor- virtute chooperante primo in hoc meo iudiciolo.” The
tant and prestigious streets in the city; leaving the colophon reads: “Datum Bonon. die septima febr.
city, it pointed toward Ferrara, Domenico’s place of 1435 per doctorem artium Iohannem paulum de fun-
birth. dis actu legentem in astronomia et in medicina nos-
69. Sighinolfi 1920. Much of this information is tris studentibus et necnon inclite et excelse com(mun)
based, in fact, on Malagola 1878; see also Birkenmajer itatis Bonon. astrologum bene meritum.”
1900, chap. 19, s.v. “Dominicus Maria Novara,” 424– 82. For example, “Per mi Hieronimo di Manfredi
48; Birkenmajer 1975, 738–96. In the 1890s, Birken­ doctore de le arte & medicina nel studio famoso de
majer attempted to follow up on the fate of Domeni- bologna madre di studij, 1479” (Biblioteca Universita-
co’s library. He wrote to Antonio Favaro, who on ria di Bologna).
February 6, 1898, informed him, “Having examined 83. Novara 1500, fol. 96v (copy used: Biblioteca
in the two libraries—the University and the Commu- Universitaria di Bologna).
nal [in Bologna]—the books that could have belonged 84. For example, there are small differences for
to Domenico Maria, no signs of ownership were Novara 1492.
found in any of the respective copies” (Birkenmajer 85. The 1484 prognostication was published in
1975, 762–63). On November 29, 1994, I discovered Venice by Bernardino Benali: “Per me magistrum
the provenance of Domenico Maria Nouaria Ferra­ Domenicum mariam Ferrariensem. iudicium edi-
riensis in the 1493 edition of the Tetrabiblos at the Bi­ tum in almo ac inclito studio Bon. anno Domini m.
blioteca Universitaria, Bologna. cccc.lxxxiiii” (copy used: Herzog August Bibliothek,
70. Sighinolfi 1920, 235: “Item solvit ser Laurentio Wolfenbüttel). The 1497 prognostication was pub-
de Benatijs pro pensione domus duorum annorum lished in Rome (in Italian) by Stephan Plannck (copy
libras 100.” used: Biblioteca Colombina y Capitular, Seville).
71. He held the position perhaps until 1528. See 86. See Sorbelli 1938, 114; Thorndike 1923–58,
Zambelli 1966a, 180–81; Mazzetti 1988, 47. ­Mazzetti’s 5:234–51.
source was Fantuzzi 1781–84, 2: 62. 87. Pietramellara 1500. It was issued on January 18,
72. Benatius 1502 (Copy used: British Library): “Ex- two days before Novara’s (copy used: Biblioteca Uni-
quisitissimus praeceptor noster Dominicus Maria versitaria di Bologna).
Novari[a].” 88. Novara 1489 (copy used: Biblioteca Colombina

528 Notes to Pages 86 – 91


y Capitular, Seville). Magini 1585, 29–30. Magini was have seen those for 1484, 1487, 1489, 1490, 1492,
a rival of Galileo, an astrologer and mathematician at 1496, and 1497.
Bologna, and, effectively, a much later successor to 98. Benatius 1502.
Domenico Maria. William Gilbert, although critical 99. In the Italian universities, the connection be-
of Domenico’s judgment, lifted the same passage tween medicine and natural philosophy was well es-
from Magini without attribution (Gilbert 1958, bk. 4, tablished (Siraisi 1987, 221–23; Schmitt 1985); but the
chap. 2, 315–16). connection between astronomy and medicine has
89. The only prognostication that I have been unable been less well appreciated.
to find for Copernicus’s Bologna period is that of 1498. 100. See Kibre 1967; Lind 1993, 9. According to
90. Novara 1499 (copy used: Archiginnasio, Bologna): Nancy Siraisi, Avicenna’s canon concerned “parts of
the body with their anatomy, physiology, and dis-
We regard those judges as unjust who presume to eases, arranged from head to toe. Judging from the
judge something about which they know nothing. For content of the sections specified, the first year was de-
only the good man is a [true] judge among those who
voted to the head and brain; the second to the lungs,
do know. How many of these unfair judges there are
in our time [who classify] the science of the stars heart, and thoracic cavity; the third to the liver, stom-
among the other disciplines of the liberal arts. This is ach, and intestines; and the fourth to the urinary and
not a surprise. For it is the customary role, especially reproductive systems” (Siraisi 1987, 55–56).
among ignorant men, to criticize and revile because 101. See Ady 1937, 144–45; Raimondi 1950, 69–70;
they know nothing. Others believe this science of the Kibre 1967, 506.
stars [scientia astrorum] to be deceitful and worthless
102. Garzoni (Opusculum de Dignitate Urbis
and of no civil use. Still others, wearing the skull caps
of dark ignorance, declaim in their arrogant orations Bononiae), cited in Raimondi 1950, 71:
that astronomers argue for necessity in human affairs.
Ho sempre pensato che non vi sia alcuna scienza
Another group, on the other hand, argues against the
che possa essere messa a pari con l’astrologia perché
latter, appearing to dispute about everything. They
questa porta agli uomini un bene sommamente utile
compete in agonistic disputations and imitate certain
e onorevole. Coloro che ne sono esperti annunciano la
astronomical words, names and rhetorical styles.
morte dei principi e le mutazioni degli stati; predicono
Entirely forsaking the office of wise men, however,
le guerre, le pestilenze, le carestie; insegnano ciò che
they prefer to be seen as wise men rather than to be
bisogna fuggire o seguire. Quante sciagure si sareb-
[wise] and not to be seen. For, as Aristotle observes, the
bero potute evitare se si fosse ascoltato il consiglio degli
wise man’s work is the first of the two pearls: it con-
astrologi! Io credo che chi ignora l’astrologia, non possa
cerns the one who knows that he does not deceive. . . .
riuscire buon filosofo, medico e poeta. D’altra parte
Those accusing the astronomers do not understand
è quasi impossibile trovare un geografo che non pos-
astronomical matters. . . . they are only imitators of
sieda nozioni astrologiche, come attestano Claudio
the words compared to the beholding astronomer.
Tolomeo, Strabone, Gnosio e tutti gli altri. Che dire
The art of imitation, however, deceives many. As
poi della scienza militare, dell’agricoltura, della navi­
you know, the imitators stray far from the truth and
gazione, alle quali l’ausilio della astrologia è piú che
express with words and names a pretense [to under-
necessario?
stand] the individual arts when they understand
nothing at all about these arts. So, when they con­ 103. Quoted in Raimondi 1950, 65 (novella 65). The
template the words, at least let them be imitated in
recommendation that Gabriel should read both theo-
such a way that they appear to be well spoken and
so that these imitators may stroke the ears sweetly rica and practica underlines the complementarity of
in some natural way. the two genres.
104. Ady 1937, 162; Raimondi 1950, 54; Sighinolfi
91. Ptolemy 1493, comment on Tetrabiblos, “Prohe- 1914.
mium,” 3: “Et qui dixit in virtute fuit, quia iste dem- 105. Ady 1937, 144.
onstrationes firmiores et fortiores sunt illis quae sunt 106. For the display of Latinity as a sign of superi-
in arte iudiciorum et quas de geometria et arismetica ority and its use in academic games of dominance,
[sic] sunt accepte.” see Grafton and Jardine 1986, 92–94.
92. Ptolemy 1493, Centiloquium, “First Saying,” 107. 107. Zaccagnini 1930, 125; Ady 1937, 144.
93. Scientifica, in the sense of satisfying Aristotle’s 108. Raimondi 1950, 58.
requirements for apodictic knowledge. 109. Cayado 1501. Of two copies of the 1501 edition
94. The section begins: “In fact, he who thinks in the Biblioteca Estense, Modena (shelfmark α.H.7.15),
that astronomers reckon things by necessity is lost in one has extensive hand illuminations, suggesting
ignorance about the astronomical discipline. For that it was intended for presentation.
what astronomers say is that from a fixed position 110. For Cayado’s connection to Szdłowiecki, Be­
of the stars a fixed and necessary inclination follows” roaldo, and Copernicus, see Gorski 1978, 397–401.
(Novara 1499). 111. Pico della Mirandola 1496a; on the back appear
95. Aristotle 1966, bk. 1, chap. 2, 70b 20f., 31. Hectoris’s symbol and the date, March 6, 1496.
96. Novara 1499. 112. I translate the Latin titles thus: A Little Erudite
97. For the years preceding the 1499 forecast, I Work wherein Is Contained a Declamation on the Excel-

Notes to Pages 91– 94 529


lence of the Philosopher’s, Physician’s and Orator’s Dis- 126. The Venetian publisher and bookseller Otta-
putations; And a Little Book Concerning the Best State viano Scotto sold the 1471 and the 1496 editions of
and Prince (December 1497); On Happiness (April Pietro d’Abano’s Conciliator as well as the 1493 edi-
1499). These works exemplify Beroaldo’s classiciz- tion of the Tetrabiblos. As Martin Lowry (1991, 187)
ing spirit and his celebration of worldly values, such has observed, it was customary for scholars at the
as friendship. Beroaldo dedicates the Declamation to universities of Ferrara, Padua, Pavia, and Bologna to
Paul Szdłowiecki, described as a “Polish scholar” obtain their larger textbooks from Venice: thus it is
(Scholasticum Polonum) and “archigrammates, auric- not surprising that books like the Conciliator and the
ularius illustratissimi principis nuncuparis / Cancel- Tetrabiblos would also be found in this market.
larium uulgo nouitant.” 127. Salio was the “corrector” of Beroaldus 1488.
113. Ady 1937, 161. 128. Two transpositions are necessary to reach the
114. “Quo mihi homo nemo neque amicior neque proposed reading: The A and the n must first be ex-
carior neque coniunctior fuit”: Beroaldus n.d., sigs. b changed; then the a must be converted to an o. See
4r–c 2r; Malagola 1878, 275; “Mine mi eruditorum Ptolemy 1493, dedication: “Hieronymus salius fauen-
nobilissime: nobilium eruditissime” (Beroaldus 1488, tinus* artium et medicine doctor:dnico marie de an-
epistolary dedication). uaria ferrariensi artium et medicie doctori as-
115. Cayado 1931, 86. trologoque excellentissimo de nobilitate astrologie.”
116. Quoted in Lind 1993,1992. Cf. Birkenmajer 1975, 756–62. The several copies of
117. Malagola 1878, 275–76. All this information this rare edition that I have seen contain the same
based upon Archivio di Stato di Bologna: Liber Par­ uncorrected error.
titorum magnificorum dominorum Sedicem, vols. 129. “Mei Dominici Marie de Nouari Ferr[arien­
10–12. sis].” The provenance appears after the colophon of
118. Beroaldus 1500, bk. 5, fols. 100v–101r. See the last-bound work, Albubater 1492. I conjecture
Rhodes 1982b, 14–17. A copy of this edition was that Novara bundled together Eschenden 1489 and
owned by the Varmian canon Johann Langhenk; al- Albubater 1492 soon after he acquired Ptolemy 1493,
though Copernicus’s hand does not appear on this with its personal dedication. In a note beneath the
item, its presence in Varmia shows that Hectoris’s provenance, partially legible with the aid of ultravio-
productions were making their way into that region let light, Novara refers to the erroneous spelling of
(see Czartoryski 1978, no. 23, 374). his name in the published dedication and forgives
119. See Cayado 1931, 13. the editor for his human weakness (“Dedicatio uero
120. Pico della Mirandola 1496b (March), fol. YYiir: mei Ptolomei Faventino Bono: et [cur?] suo [rum?]
Beroaldus to Pico, April 10, 1486; see also Rhodes error[um?] vir humanum [?]”). The two additional
1982b, 14–17; Garin 1942, 588. Because these letters works are noted (by hand) in the table of contents,
were publicly available, both Copernicus and Novara also on the spine (perhaps by a librarian) and on the
could have read them. Beroaldus’s reference to din- top and outside of the volume. The entire collection is
ner with Pico and Mino Rossi also signals Pico’s im- bound in an early vellum binding. When the collec-
portance in Bolognese noble circles. tion was put together, the margins were cut down,
121. Rhodes 1982a, 17: “On 31 July 1502 Beroaldus partially slicing off some annotations. The name
had another book printed by Benedictus Hectoris, “Ul[isse] Aldr[ovandi]” is penciled in on the dorso
Orationes et carmina Beroaldi, in which he addressed of the front board, but Paula Findlen confirmed
an epistle and some verses to Roscius, and on S3 (personal communication) that there are no internal
recto he included a poem about a supper party given markings that correspond to Aldrovandi’s catalogu-
by Roscius to Prince Bentivoglio.” ing practices, that is, provenance and book number.
122. Dubium: a proposition of uncertain truth and Moreover, although the 1493 Tetrabiblos and Eschen-
suited for debate, examples of which are often to be den’s Summa do appear in Aldrovandi’s catalogue,
found listed in the practical medical manuals with the work by Albubater does not. This absence sug-
which Novara was well acquainted (e.g., Savonarola gests that an early librarian arbitrarily entered Aldro­
1502, Tabula, capitulum 3, “De pupilla”: “Whether vandi’s initials into the book.
dryness causes the pupil of the eye to narrow”). 130. Österreichische Nationalbibliothek: Novara,
123. Because the daily business of the Sedici was n.d., fol. 199r. As Ernst Zinner points out, this manu-
documented in standard, notarial Latin, Domenico script was kept from 1519 onward in the library of
must have intended the compliment as a sign that Johannes Schöner in Nuremberg. The amanuensis,
Rossi’s Latin was as learned as that used at the uni- one Johannes Michael Budorensis, had contacts with
versity (see Zaccagnini 1930, 124; Malagola 1878, Ratdolt’s publishing house in Venice and perhaps
275–76). also with Novara himself. Budorensis may have ac-
124. The only prognostications directed to Rossi quired papers of both Regiomontanus and Novara on
that I have found were authored by Novara. the latter’s death and transmitted them to Nurem-
125. Rhodes 1982c, 229–31. berg (Zinner 1990, 153–54).

530 Notes to Pages 94– 97


131. Novara probably meant “my teacher” in a liter- 147. Aristotle 1966, bk. 1, chap.10, 76b, 14–15. Some
ary rather than a literal sense, that is, from having further light might be thrown on this passage if it
read his books. Although it is just possible that No- could be established which edition and commentary
vara and Regiomontanus had met personally, I regard Copernicus was using.
such an encounter as unlikely. 148. “Omnes orbes ambire Solem, tanquam in
132. Copernicus 1978, 218. medio omnium existentem, ideoque circa Solem esse
133. Swerdlow and Neugebauer 1984, 66. centrum mundi” (Copernicus 1884, 186; cf. Swerd-
134. See Dobrzycki and Kremer 1996. low 1973, 436; Copernicus 1985, 81).
135. Copernicus 1978, bk. 4, chap. 14, 200. 149. “Quicquid nobis ex motibus circa Solem ap-
136. Swerdlow (1973, 456–63) and Swerdlow and paret, non esse occasione ipsius, sed telluris et nostri
Neugebauer (1984, 47–48) argue for the virtual iden- orbis, cum quo circa Solem volvimur ceu aliquot alio
tity of Copernicus’s lunar model with that of the sidere, sicque terram pluribus motibus ferri.” Coper-
“Maragha school” astronomer Ibn ash-Shatir. nicus 1884, 186; cf. Swerdlow 1973, 436; Copernicus
137. Rheticus 1971, 133. 1985, 81–82.
138. Tabarroni 1987, 184. 150. This important point, which allowed Coperni-
139. Achillini 1498, fol. 15r a: “tamen ipse 3º al- cus to sidestep the Aristotelian standard of demon-
magesti capitulo primo concedit Mercurium et Ve- stration, was later emphasized by Rheticus (1982, 58):
nerem cadere super eadem linea inter solem et ocu- “Cum autem tum in physicis, tum in astronomicis ab
lum nostri. et demonstrat quae necesse est sic esse et effectibus et observationibus ut plurimum ad prin-
Geber ibidem. et sic videtur contradictio in dictis cipia sit processus, ego quidem statuo Aristotelem,
ptolomei in hoc an venus et mercurius cadant in auditis novarum hypothesium rationibus, ut disputa-
eodem epipodo [periodo?] cum sole etc.” Because tiones de gravi, levi, circulari latione, motu et quiete
the Almagest has no such discussion of Mercury terrae diligentissime excussit, ita dubio procul can-
and Venus in book 3, chapter 1, Achillini might have dide confessurum, quid a se in his demonstratum sit,
been using Geber’s Correction of the Almagest (Islah et quid tanquam principium since demonstratione
al-Majisti). assumptum.”
140. Achillini 1498 (7 August), fol. 15r b. 151. “Proinde ne quis temere mobilitatem telluris
141. Bellanti 1498, bk. 10, 213: “Pariter de Mercurij asseverasse cum Pythagoricis nos arbitretur, mag-
et Veneris situ sub sole ignorat demonstrationem ap- num quoque et hic argumentum accipiet in circulo-
ertam, quae ex epicyclorum quantitate tantaque vel rum declaratione. Etenim quibus Physiologi stabilita-
tanta apparentia maioritatis corporis ipsorum elici- tem eius astruere potissime conantur, apparentiis
tur postquam sequaces hoc ignorant. Quae vero dicit plerumque innituntur; quae omnia hic in primis cor-
Auerrois nullius sunt momenti, asserit enim XII runt, cum etiam propter apparentiam versemus ean-
Metaph. erraticarum earum apparentias in eodem dem” (Copernicus 1884, 187–88). Copernicus’s refer-
orbe diuersis polis posse saluari, epicyclos negans ence to the Pythagoreans as “natural philosophers”
­ineptissime, qui etiam quandoque in philosophia shows that he associated them with Aristotle rather
­deceptus est, dolet tamen ob senium ne possit astro- than Ptolemy. Thus Copernicus’s reconsideration of
logiam discere, quam antiquorum & sui temporis Aristotle’s rejection of the Pythagorean position played
ignorabat.” an important part in Copernicus’s explanation of the
142. Because Bellanti’s book appeared in May and shared-motion problem. Cf. Swerdlow 1973, 439–40;
Achillini’s in August 1498, Copernicus would have Copernicus 1971a, 82; Bilińksi, 1977, 56–57.
had to draw the connections himself. For Achillini’s 152. Rheticus 1982, 55: “Quare, cum hoc unico
gloss on Averroës’ commentary on Aristotle’s Meta- terrae motus infinitis quasi apparentiis satisfieri
physics discussion, see Goldstein 2002, 225, and videremus”—echoing Copernicus 1543, bk. 1, chap. 10,
chapter 1, this volume. fol. 10: “Quae omnia ex eadem causa procedunt, quae
143. See Goddu 2004, 71 ff.; Hatfield 1990, in telluris est motu.”
93–166. 153. Rheticus 1982, 61:3–8. The passage explicitly
144. See Dobrzycki 2001. attributes to Aristotle the recognition that if one mo-
145. See Swerdlow 1973; Copernicus 1985, 3:75– tion was ascribed to the Earth, then other motions
126; Dobrzycki 1973. could equally well be assigned to it (cf. Aristotle 1939,
146. Copernicus 1884, 186: “Si nobis aliquae peti- 243; bk. 2, chap. 14, 296b, 1–5).
tiones, quas axiomata vocant, concedantur.” The date 154. Swerdlow 1973, 440.
of composition of this work, like so much else about 155. Copernicus produces values of nine months
this period of Copernicus’s life, is uncertain. Swerd- (Venus) and three months (Mercury): Copernicus
low (1973, 431) believes that “there is insufficient evi- 1884, 2:188.
dence to determine how long before 1514 Copernicus 156. Rheticus explicitly denies that a higher sphere
developed his new planetary theory,” whereas Rosen could cause any inequality in the motion of a lower
opts for 1508–15 (Copernicus 1985, 79–80). sphere: “Quilibet planetae orbis suo a natura sibi at-

Notes to Pages 97–102 531


tributo motu uniformiter incedens suam periodum 167. Another source from which Copernicus
conficit et nullam a superiori orbe vim patitur, ut could have drawn this information is Regiomontanus
in diversum rapiatur” (Rheticus 1982, 60; Rheticus 1496, book 9, prop. 1, fol. klv. Regiomontanus knew
1971, 146). al-Bitruji’s views directly from De Motibus Celorum,
157. Swerdlow 1973, 437; cf. Rosen 1985, 92; Dobr­ of which he owned a copy (see Shank 1992, 17).
zycki 2001. 168. To the best of my knowledge, Ludwik Birken­
158. For analysis of such textualities, see Hallyn majer was the first to point out that Copernicus had
1990, 60–61. found the passage in Pico 1984a (1900, 94). Ernst
159. See Matsen 1977, 1994. Zinner claimed that Copernicus had mistaken Aver-
160. See Westman 1980a. roës for Aven Rodan, based on a misreading of Pico
161. Zinner 1988, 186, basing his argument on (Zinner 1943, 510 n.: “Tatsächlich handelte es sich
Birkenmajer 1924, 199–224, notes that Miechow had um Aven Rodan [‘Ali ben Ridwān]; Coppernicus
many “astronomical” works in his library; but using hatte die Stelle wohl dem Werke des Pico della Mi­
“the science of the stars” as our classification, we randola wider die Sterndeutung entnommen und
can easily see that the sexternus found its place amid den Namen Aven Rodan in Averroes verschrieben”).
kindred books—for example, copies of Ptolemy’s Te­ Goldstein (1969, 58 n.) rightly called attention to
trabiblos and Stöffler’s Almanach. Rosen’s transla- Zinner’s error.
tion of Miechów’s entry is problematic (Copernicus 169. See Rosen’s note in Copernicus 1978, 356–57.
1985, 75). Beginning with Erasmus Reinhold, many sixteenth-
162. The designation sexternus undoubtedly comes century readers of this passage noted that the same
from Matthew of Miechów, as the term refers to the observation could also be found in another source:
size of the item and hence to a catalogue entry rather “Idem est in historia Carolj Magnj” (The same is [to
than to the subject matter. However, the term theor- be found] in the History of Charlemagne); cf. Gin­
ica is more problematic. In general, Matthew’s en- gerich 2002, Edinburgh 1, 268–78 (1543, fol. 8);
tries reflect accurate condensations of actual titles; Prague 3, 23–28 (1566, fol. 8). The source is the ninth-
hence, following this practice, he might have been century Abbot Einhard, and the earliest printed edi-
using a title that was part of the manuscript itself. On tion that I have found is Einhard 1532. This volume
the other hand, he already had two items with the also contains Vita et Gesta Caroli Cognomento Magni,
title theorica in his library, and he might simply have Francorum Regis Fortissimi, et Germaniae suae illus-
decided to assign this word of his own account. tratoris, autorisque optime meriti, per Eginhartum, il-
163. Copernicus 1884, 2:187. lius quandoque alumnum atque scribam adiuratum,
164. Aristotle 1966, bk. 1, chap. 1, 273. Germanum conscripta. On page 122, Einhard reports
165. See Goddu 2010, 275–300. Swerdlow also that Charlemagne had died in 814 but that afterward
wrestled with this question: “It could  .  .  . be intelli- it was said that the event had been presaged as fol-
gently argued that because Copernicus calls these lows: “Appropinquantis finis complura fuere praesa-
statements postulates (petitiones), he is therefore not gia, ut non solum alij, sed et ipse hoc minitari sen-
asserting that they are necessarily true. Yet, if he tiret. Per tres continuos, uitaque termino proximos
had any doubts about the truth of the heliocentric annos et solis et lunae creberrima defectio, ac in sole
theory, he probably would not have advanced it in the macula quaedam atri coloris septem dierum spatio
first place” (1973, 437 n.). Swerdlow’s first statement uisa.” It is clear that this description scarcely resem-
seems to me to be exactly right. Perhaps we might say bles the passage from Copernicus on Averroës. More-
that by leaving the Commentariolus as a sexternus, Co- over, even if Copernicus had known this book, it is
pernicus was not yet “advancing” it. In fact, Coperni- clearly not his original source, as he does not cite it.
cus’s argument with the natural philosophers was 170. Copernicus 1978, bk. 1, chap. 10, 19; Coperni-
that their claims “rest for the most part on appear- cus 1543, fol. 8: “Quamuis & Averroes in Ptolemaica
ances,” which they do not fully “save”; on the other paraphrasi, nigricans quiddam se uidisse meminit,
hand, Copernicus believed that from his postulates quando Solis & Mercurij copulam numeris inuenie-
“the motions can be saved in a systematic way.” Cf. bat expositam: & ita decernunt haec duo sydera sub
Swerdlow and Neugebauer 1984, 9: “The heliocentric solari circulo moueri.”
theory and the motion of the earth were presented 171. Ibid.
as a series of postulates, although there is no doubt 172. See Swerdlow 1976, 122. This language and
that Copernicus considered them true. This was not Swerdlow’s diagrammatic reconstructions make it
really objectionable, and was in fact entirely reason- quite plausible that Copernicus was allowing here for
able, because Copernicus knew that at the time he the existence of solid orbs, in the geometric sense,
had no way of proving that the earth in fact moves.” but without pronouncing in any way on their materi-
Cf. Rosen’s footnotes, Copernicus 1985, 38, 56, 66, ality or impenetrability.
83, 192. 173. Copernicus 1978, bk. 1, chap. 10, 22; cf. Gio­
166. Rheticus 1971, 126–27. vanni Gioviano Pontano (1429–1503) in Pontano 1512,

532 Notes to Pages 102–104


bk. 1, sig. A2. For further discussion, see also Trin­ July 1543; Prowe 1883–84, 2:420). However, Hooykaas
kaus 1985, 450–51. endorsed the view of Bruce Wrightsman that “Coper-
174. Rheticus 1971, 109–10, my italics. nicus shrewdly declined to name his Lutheran disci-
175. Copernicus 1972, fol. 13, my italics: “Assumpsi- ple, Rheticus, in his letter of dedication to the Pope,
mus extra quibusdam revolutionibus mobilem esse as one of those whose assistance and encouragement
tellurem quibus tamque primario lapidi totam astro- persuaded him to have the work published. What
rum scientiam instruere initiam”; Copernicus 1978, other possible reason could there be for such a
26; again, in the Letter against Werner (1524), he says significant omission?” (Hooykaas 1984, 38; Wrights-
that “the science of the stars is one of those subjects man 1975, 234). By the same token, Rheticus nowhere
which we learn in the order opposite to the natural mentions the pope in the Narratio Prima.
order” (Copernicus 1971c, 98; Copernicus 1985, 146). 9. Edward Grant concludes: “Astrologers and natu-
176. For Copernicus’s reconfiguring of gravity and ral philosophers may have shared the Aristotelian
the elements, see Knox 2002, 2005. conviction that celestial bodies were the ultimate
177. The manuscript of De Revolutionibus contains causes of terrestrial effects, but natural philosophers
a suppressed passage from Lysis’s letter to Hippar- largely excluded the prognosticative aspects of astrol-
chus, available to Copernicus both in Bessarion’s In ogy from their deliberations. Except for the attribu-
Calumniatorem Platonis, fols. 2v–3r, and in Epistolae tion of certain qualities to certain planets, astrologi-
Diversorum Philosophorum (Venice, 1499). Introduc- cal details and concepts are virtually ignored in
ing the text of the letter, Copernicus mentions that questions on Aristotle’s natural books, especially on
“Philolaus believed in the earth’s motion” and that De caelo. The properties, positions, and relationships
“Aristarchus of Samos too held the same view accord- of the planets used for astrological prognostication
ing to some people”; Copernicus also explains that were of little significance for the scholastic tradition
these views are not widely known because of the Py- in natural philosophy” (Grant 1994, 36 n. 66). Of
thagoreans’ practice of not committing “the secrets course, the general exclusion of astrology from natu-
of philosophy to writing” (see Rosen’s discussion in ral philosophy did not mean that specific churchmen
Copernicus 1978, 25–26, 361–63; Prowe 1883–84, 2:128– were averse to engaging in practical astrology.
31; Africa 1961). 10. Luther 1969; Ludolphy 1986; Barnes 1988,
46–53.
11. Caroti 1986, 120; Kusukawa 1991, 1995.
4. Between Wittenberg and Rome 12. Barnes 1988, 97; Bretschneider et al. 1834–,
1. See Barnes 1988. 20:677–85.
2. See Hammerstein 1986; Köhler 1986; Reeves 13. See, for example, Hammer 1951, 313: “At the
1969, v–vi. sight of these beautiful luminaries, they may medi-
3. Quoted in Rupp 1983, 257, and Bonney 1991, 21. tate upon the entire arrangement of the year and
Luther completed his translation of the Bible in 1534. upon the reason why God, the Author of all, created
4. See Dobrzycki and Szczucki 1989. differ­ences in seasons and annual cycles. And
5. The Commentariolus was not published until the finally, that at such contemplation they may ac-
nineteenth century (Copernicus 1884, 2:184–202); it knowledge God as the Creator and praise His wis-
lacked an explicit public strategy of persuasion and, dom and goodness shining forth from the infinite
therefore played a somewhat different role in promot- variety of blessings by which He shows His care for
ing Copernicus’s work. mankind. May they also realize that the wise and
6. He was known to his classmates as Hosen just Creator has shed the rays of His light upon us,
Enderle (see Swerdlow and Neugebauer 1984, 1:13.). namely, in order to distinguish between the con-
7. On Schöner, see Wrightsman 1970, 120. Coper- cepts of good and evil.”
nicus is not known to have had a mistress, but he did 14. Barnes 1988, 96–99; Caroti 1986, 109–21.
have a female housekeeper, whose presence in his 15. See Bretschneider et al. 1834–, 8:63, no. 5362;
house made him the subject of fairly strong censures Caroti 1986, 120. Of course, although Stöffler’s 1499
by the Varmia bishop (see Rosen 1984b, 149–57). Almanach had been a major resource in the flood pre-
8. Giese attributed Copernicus’s failure to mention dictions, he himself had thrown cold water on the ris-
Rheticus to a kind of absentmindedness about any- ing expectations as the time grew close (see Stöffler
thing that was not “philosophical”: “incommodi, quo 1523).
in praefatione operis praeceptor tuus tui mentionem 16. Quoted and trans. in Warburg 1999, 656–57.
omisit. quod ego non tui neglectu, sed lentitudine 17. Ludolphy 1986, 106.
et incuria quaedam (ut erat ad monia quae philo- 18. For an excellent analysis of the meaning of
sophical non essent, minus attentus), praesertim superstition in this period, see Clark 1991, 233–35.
iam languescenti evenisse interpretor, non ignarus, 19. See Caroti 1986, 118. On D’Ailly’s astrology, see
quanti facere solitus fuerit tuam in se adiuvando op- Smoller 1994.
eram et facilitatem” (Giese to Rheticus in Leipzig, 26 20. Cited by Barnes 1988, 97; the example comes

Notes to Pages 104–112 533

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi